KANT S EXPLANATION OF THE NECESSITY OF GEOMETRICAL TRUTHS. John Watling

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "KANT S EXPLANATION OF THE NECESSITY OF GEOMETRICAL TRUTHS. John Watling"

Transcription

1 KANT S EXPLANATION OF THE NECESSITY OF GEOMETRICAL TRUTHS John Watling Kant was an idealist. His idealism was in some ways, it is true, less extreme than that of Berkeley. He distinguished his own by calling it transcendental. It is less extreme than Berkeley s in two ways. First, Kant does not assert that everything which exists is essentially mental, as Berkeley does. Second, those things which he does hold to be essentially mental, he holds to be so in a weaker fashion. Nevertheless he was an idealist; he held that neither intuition nor thought could concern any object that was not essentially related to our minds. Since intuition and thought together provide knowledge, and since we can have no knowledge except through them, it follows that every object of which we have knowledge is essentially within our minds. Moreover, there is at least one respect in which his idealism is more extreme than that of Berkeley. He held that the objects of intuition were essentially within our minds, whereas Berkeley held only that they were essentially within some mind. Kant was led to his idealism by the desire to establish the possibility of knowledge in a sphere where it lay in doubt, and so to avoid scepticism. Berkeley, likewise, was led to his idealism by the wish to establish the possibility of knowledge, although knowledge in another sphere, and so to avoid scepticism. The scepticisms they sought to allay concerned propositions of different kinds, but their idealisms meet when they consider the nature of the objects of what Kant calls sensible intuition and Berkeley calls immediate perception. In sensible intuition and in immediate perception sensible objects are present to us. The scepticism which troubled Berkeley arises over our knowledge of those things which we believe ourselves to perceive. That which troubled Kant arises over propositions which involve, in one way or another, the idea of necessity. If we are to believe Kant himself, it was Hume s arguments concerning causation which first forced this problem upon Kant s attention. He seems to have considered that Hume s conclusion that we have no idea of necessity is not totally implausible to someone who takes no other example of necessity but that of causation. However, anyone who considers how necessity enters also into the propositions of arithmetic and of geometry must see that if we have no idea of necessity, then we have no understanding of these sciences. Had Hume widened his considerations in this way Kant erroneously implies that he did not his good sense would have 1

2 forced him to revise his views. Hume held that if causation implies necessary connection it is impossible to get an idea of causation or understand a causal proposition. His case against the idea of necessity, applied to mathematics, would show the impossibility of our understanding the necessary incompatibility between two lines both being straight lines and enclosing an area, or the necessary consequence between a closed figure having three straight sides and its included angles adding up to two right angles. However, Kant makes no attempt to show how we come to be able to grasp these ideas of incompatibility and consequence. He turns to the question of how it is that these geometrical theorems can be necessary and how we can know them to be so, leaving aside the question of how we can understand the necessity they involve. Kant agrees with Hume that no proposition which involves necessity can be established by experience. Propositions which cannot be established by experience he calls a priori. However, he held that although no proposition involving necessity could be established by experience alone, some of them could be established without experience at all, others only with the help of experience. Propositions of the former sort he calls pure a priori. The theorems of geometry are of this sort and so are such principles as that every event has a cause. Propositions concerning particular causal connections are of the latter sort. As I have just remarked, with geometrical theorems he neglects a task he should undertake, that of showing how we understand the necessity involved. With propositions concerning causal connections, such as scientific hypotheses, he concentrates on the problem of how we come by the idea of causal necessity and almost entirely neglects the problem of how we can know a particular scientific hypothesis to be a law of nature. The pure a priori principles which Kant held to stand at the head of natural science, such as that every event has a cause, or that matter can neither be created nor destroyed, are distinguished. Only with them does he take up both of the problems which necessity poses: that of understanding and that of knowledge. However, with neither science nor mathematics does Kant attempt to analyse the necessary connection involved. Perhaps he neglected the problem of our under standing of the necessity of geometrical theorems because of the view he took of the origin of that necessity. The origin lay, he held, not in concepts or our understanding of concepts, but in the relationship between our faculty of sensible intuition and the nature of the objects with which, by means of that faculty, we become acquainted. Perhaps, that is, he unconsciously argued that because the necessity of those propositions had a non-conceptual origin, so our knowledge of them demanded no understanding of the concept of necessity. If he did, he argued mistakenly. However that may be, he did neglect the problems of understanding and concentrate on the problem of knowledge. Besides truths which are ordinarily regarded as theorems of geometry Kant set out to explain the necessity of such properties of space as these. Space has three dimensions, no more and no less. 2

3 There is only one space. Divisions can be introduced into it, but the divisions do not result in parts which could exist independently. It is possible that a pair of things in space should be incongruent counterparts. Incongruent counterparts are pairs of things, such as a pair of gloves, which are incongruent, in that one of them will not always fit where the other will, yet exact counterparts, in that their parts are similar and similarly related among themselves. He also set out to explain why those things which are in space could not exist except in space. These examples show that he was not satisfied to explain only the relationships holding between the spatial properties of things, about which geometry informs us, but sought the origin of the most fundamental properties of space and even of the spatial nature of objects. Of course, it would be possible to seek an explanation of the necessity of the spatial relationships of which geometry informs us without raising the more fundamental questions. John Stuart Mill s theory of geometry is an example of such a more restricted inquiry. Kant held all these propositions to be synthetic, not analytic. Had he held the opposite view, the problem of the origin of their necessity and of how we can know them would scarcely have been, in his eyes, any problem at all. An analytic proposition, such as All cubes have six faces, cannot extend our knowledge. It merely serves to make more evident what it is to be a cube. In knowing it to be true we know nothing, and its necessity is not the necessity of anything. Of course, this account given by Kant of the nature of analytic propositions does raise problems. If, in knowing them to be true, we know nothing, how can we know them to be true? If their necessity is not the necessity of anything how can they be necessary propositions? However, since Kant denied the analyticity of most geometrical theorems, these problems are irrelevant to our purpose. Kant does indeed admit that some geometrical propositions, such as that the whole is greater than the part, are analytic; he argues for the synthetic character of the rest. That the straight line between two points is the shortest, is a synthetic proposition. For my concept of straight contains nothing of quantity, but only of quality. The concept of the shortest is wholly an addition, and cannot be derived, through any process of analysis, from the concept of the straight line. Intuition, therefore, must here be called in; only by its aid is synthesis possible. (CPR p. 53, B 17) 1 1 CPR = Immanuel Kant s Critique of Pure Reason, trans. Norman Kemp Smith (London: Macmillan, 1964) 3

4 Kant s point is that until we look at, or, what is just as good, imagine, a straight line we cannot see the proposition to be true. Gottfried Martin claims that there is historical evidence to show that Kant was aware of the failure of Saccheri s attempt to prove the inconsistency of a system of geometry which was exactly like that of Euclid except that the fifth axiom the parallels axiom was replaced by one which contradicted it. Martin argues that this failure convinced Kant that there could be a self-consistent system of geometry contradicting Euclid s, and hence that Euclid s geometry was not analytic. This explanation of Kant s rejection of the analytical character of geometric truths is plausible, but not entirely convincing. No systems of arithmetic were known which were self-consistent but inconsistent with ordinary arithmetic. Why did Kant accept the non-analytic character of both the theorems of geometry and those of arithmetic? Again, it is not clear that the mutual consistency of the axioms of Saccheri s non-euclidean system proves that the axiom which denied Euclid s parallels axiom was selfconsistent. It proves only that there is no inconsistency between that non-euclidean axiom and the rest of Euclid s assumptions. To put the same point another way round, it may be that Euclid s parallels axiom is analytic even though it does not follow from the rest of Euclid. The failure of the attempts to show Saccheri s system inconsistent was only the failure to prove Euclid s parallels axiom from the rest of Euclid s assumptions. Of course, even though this argument failed to show that the parallels axiom could be denied without contradiction, Kant may have believed that it did. What is more, if geometers were beginning to speak as if they found no contradiction in denying the axiom, that was quite good evidence that there was none. Kant held, then, that geometry was a body of propositions providing genuine knowledge about objects in space, which held for all of them, from atoms to stars, the smallest to the largest, the nearest to the furthest, but which stood in no danger of contradiction by experience and had no need of support from it. The explanation of these facts, and of our having knowledge of them, lay, for Kant, in the nature of our faculty of intuition: i.e. that faculty without which objects could not be present to us. Kant believed that perception, or experience, could he separated into two parts: sensible acquaintance with objects, on the one hand, and propositional thought about them, on the other. The former he called intuition, the latter, thought, and to each of them there corresponded a faculty, in the former case called the sensibility, in the latter, the understanding. There corresponds also, in the first part of The Critique of Pure Reason, a division to each: the aesthetic, where he discusses intuition and the sensibility, and the analytic, where he discusses thought and the understanding. Although it would be impossible for us to perceive, or have experience of, any object in space without the faculty of understanding, the necessity of the propositions of geometry, and the possibility of our knowledge of them, arise from our faculty of 4

5 intuition. It is from the character of that faculty, which might, Kant often stresses, have been different, and which may be different in other sentient beings, that geometrical facts and other facts about space arise. If we depart from the subjective condition under which alone we can have outer intuition, namely, liability to be affected by objects, the representation of space stands for nothing whatsoever. This predicate can be ascribed to things only in so far as they appear to us, that is, only to objects of sensibility. (CPR, p.71, B43) He speaks of outer intuition here to distinguish the faculty which presents objects in space to us from another faculty also a faculty of intuition which he believes we possess: that which presents to us inner states. Inner states were, for him, non-spatial states of ourselves, e.g. pains or other sensations. [Space] is the subjective condition of sensibility, under which alone outer intuition is possible for us. Since, then, the receptivity of the subject, its capacity to be affected by objects, must necessarily precede all intuitions of these objects, it can readily be understood how the form of all appearances can be given prior to all actual perceptions. (CPR, p. 71, B 42) But quite how did Kant suppose that the conditions imposed by our own nature, by the constitution of our own faculty, could explain the necessary facts of geometry, facts that concern the things we perceive? Obviously it might be that the character of our own faculty made us unable to intuit, and hence unable to perceive, any objects which were not spatial and which did not obey the laws of geometry. That is, the character of our own faculty might imply the truth of the proposition: If we can intuit a thing, it is in space and obeys the laws of geometry. This would mean that the character of our own faculty of intuition, which enables objects in space to be present to us, also imposes on us a disability: objects which are not in space, or which do not obey the laws of geometry, cannot be present to us. This would explain why we can intuit nothing which is not in space and does not obey the laws of geometry. The idealism it implies is a limited one. Such truth as it yielded to the laws of geometry would arise from the character of our minds, but the objects which we could intuit would be perfectly independent of our minds. They would exist whether or not we could intuit them and, although they would not lack spatial properties when we intuited them, they could lack spatial properties. In just the same way, the fact that if a fish can meet a thing, that thing is in water, explains the restricted nature of a fish s experience but does not imply the dependence of the things it can meet on the presence of water. However, such an 5

6 explanation could not have satisfied Kant. The facts he took geometry to express were stronger than such an explanation can explain. Kant did hold that geometry has a restricted subject-matter it deals only with things we can intuit but he did not hold that it has restricted implications concerning that subject-matter. He did not hold that it informs us only of the properties the things we can intuit have if we can intuit them, he held that it informs us of the properties the things we can intuit must have. Now the fact that if a fish can meet a thing, that thing is in water does not imply that if a fish can meet a thing, that thing is a thing which is necessarily in water, and so does not imply that the things a fish can meet are things which are necessarily in water. In just the same way, the explanation we have been considering does not imply that if we can intuit a thing, that thing is a thing which is necessarily in space and necessarily obeys the laws of geometry, and so does not imply that the things we can intuit are things which are necessarily in space and necessarily obey the laws of geometry. An obvious suggestion is to reinforce our explanation by declaring the connection between being a thing we can intuit and being in space to be one which holds necessarily. The objection to this reinforcement is that Kant stresses that our intuition might have been of a different type. However, by itself, the reinforcement fails to achieve what we require of it. It is a fact that necessarily, if a fish meets a thing, that thing is met by a fish, but it is not a fact, and so cannot follow, that necessarily, if a fish meets a thing, that thing is a thing which is necessarily met by a fish. I have been met by a fish, yet I am not a thing which was necessarily met by a fish. Similarly, our reinforced explanation does not have the consequence that, necessarily, if we can intuit a thing, that thing is a thing which is necessarily in space and necessarily obeys the laws of geometry. It is true that there is a passage in The Critique of Pure Reason which suggests that Kant did accept the validity of such inferences. Since we cannot treat the special conditions of sensibility as conditions of the possibility of things, but only of their appearances, we can indeed say that space comprehends all things that appear to us as external, but not all things in themselves, by whatever subject they are intuited, or whether they be intuited or not. For we cannot judge in regard to the intuitions of other thinking beings, whether they are bound by the same conditions as those which limit our intuition and which for us are universally valid. If we add to the concept of the subject of a judgment the limitation under which the judgment is made, the judgment is then unconditionally valid. The proposition, that all things are side by side in space, is valid under the limitation that these things are viewed as objects of our sensible intuition. If, now, I add the 6

7 condition to the concept, and say that all things, as outer appearances, are side by side in space, the rule is valid universally and without limitation. (CPR, p. 72, A 27) When, in this passage, Kant asserts the principle If we add to the concept of the subject of a judgment the limitation under which the judgment is made, the judgment is then unconditionally valid he seems to countenance the inference from If we can intuit a thing, it is in space to The things we intuit are in space. This is just the inference which leads to trouble when necessity enters the picture, as Kant requires. It is worth observing that the inference leads to trouble over universality as well as over necessity. Our explanation expressing the limitation of our faculty of intuition should take the form that if we can intuit a thing, then at that time it is in space. This does not imply that if we can intuit a thing, then it is a thing which is always in space. However, although this passage suggests that Kant accepted the inference, there is another, which I will quote presently, which strongly suggests that he did not. Whether or not he did accept the inference, it is in fact invalid, so that our reinforced explanation needs further reinforcement. It needs an addition which there is every reason to think Kant accepted. It is this, that if we can intuit a thing, then it is a thing which necessarily can be intuited by us. With this addition our explanation entails, what it did not entail before, that if we can intuit a thing, then it is a thing which is necessarily in space and necessarily obeys the laws of geometry. It entails that the things we can intuit are necessarily in space and necessarily obey the laws of geometry. Two things stand in the way of regarding this explanation of the necessity of geometry as the one Kant intended. First, what I have already pointed out, that Kant explicitly rejects the necessity of our having the faculty of intuition which, as a matter of fact, we have. Second, the fear that the explanation proves that the conclusion that the things we intuit obey the laws of geometry is an analytic proposition, and so perhaps proves what Kant denied. To take the second difficulty first: what Kant denied was the analyticity of the theorems themselves. He denied, for example, that being a straight line analytically involved being the shortest distance between any two points on that line. Perhaps he would not have denied that being a straight line on a thing we can intuit analytically involved this. After all, although he insists that intuition is necessary to establish geometrical truths, he does not rely on intuition in the explanation of the necessity of geometrical truths which he argues for in the Critique. The first difficulty is more troublesome, but there is one way of overcoming it. Before explaining what that way is, I must say a little more about the addition which completed our explanation. It could be expressed as: The things we can intuit are things which, necessarily, can be intuited by us. Again, it could be put as: It is true of the things we can intuit that to be is to be intuitable by us. I 7

8 believe it is this which Kant expresses when he asserts that the things we intuit are appearances, not things in themselves. Space does not represent any property of things in themselves, nor does it represent them [things in themselves] in their relation to one another Space is nothing but the form of all appearances of outer sense. (CPR, p. 71, A 26) He is speaking of the things we intuit when he says. As appearances, they cannot exist in themselves, but only in us (CPR, p. 82, A 42). There are passages, it is true, which suggest, at least in Kemp Smith s translation, that the things we intuit have some properties in themselves. A few sentences before the sentence I last quoted, he says: The things which we intuit are not in themselves what we intuit them as being (CPR, p. 82, A 42). This does seem to suggest that they are something in themselves and so exist in themselves and not merely in us. That suggestion is, however. immediately contradicted in the earlier quotation: As appearances, they cannot exist in themselves, but only in us. Moreover, a little further on in the Critique, a passage occurs which indicates fairly conclusively that Kant saw that without the premise that the things we can intuit are necessarily intuitable by us, he could never prove that geometry holds necessarily of those things. He is discussing how this might be proved in a particular example, Given three straight lines, a figure is possible. He mentions various ways in which it cannot be done and goes on: If there did not exist in you a power of a priori intuition; and if that subjective condition were not also at the same time, as regards its form, the universal a priori condition under which alone the object of this outer intuition is itself possible; if the object (the triangle) were something in itself, apart from any relation to you, the subject, how could you say that what necessarily exist in you as subjective conditions for the construction of a triangle, must of necessity belong to the triangle itself? (CPR, p. 86, A 48) I think that this passage clinches my interpretation of Kant s explanation of the necessity belonging to geometrical laws. It also suggests a short way with the first of the two difficulties which that interpretation faces, for in it Kant speaks of what exist necessarily in you as subjective conditions for the construction of a triangle in contradiction to what he says elsewhere. My other suggestion for resolving the first difficulty is that we might weaken the first part of our explanation, so that it implies only a contingent connection between our being able to intuit a thing and that thing being in space, and 8

9 strengthen the second part, so that it implies that if a thing can be intuited by us, then it is a thing which is not only necessarily intuitable by us, but necessarily intuitable by us with the faculty of intuition we now have. That strengthening would mean that appearances were things that, necessarily, can be perceived with the faculty of intuition we have. It would mean that appearances were not only in us, but in our faculty of intuition. Perhaps Kant did not distinguish these alternatives clearly. He speaks most often of appearances being necessarily in us, but one passage, which I will quote later, suggests that they are in our faculty of intuition. The passage I quoted last mentions something upon which depends Kant s explanation of how, independently of experience, we can know the laws of geometry to be true. This is what he calls the power of a priori intuition. The properties of a thing in space divide, according to Kant, into two: those which it has essentially, and could not lack, which he calls its form, and those which it might have lacked, which he calls its matter. That the path of the planets is an ellipse is not, paradoxically, part of its form. That, if the path of the planets is an ellipse traversed at constant speed, then the radii sweep out equal areas in equal times, is part of its form. Since this latter fact is necessarily true, no experience of the planetary orbits can refute it. The question remains why we can get to know this geometrical fact without experience of the planetary orbits? Kant might have replied, but did not, Because experience of any other elliptical thing would do as well. In investigating these questions concerning any object of intuition you are in fact investigating your own faculty of intuition, your own sensibility; you can do this as well with one object of intuition as another. However, Kant must have felt that this allowed experience a larger place than it deserved. He considers that this investigation of your own faculty, which you do when you investigate an object of intuition, can be done without investigating any object. It can be done in an a priori intuition. I take it that you have an a priori intuition when you imagine an object. Kant speaks not only of the power of a priori intuition, but also of things which are intuited when we exercise that power. These he calls a priori intuitions ; his view that here are such things comes close to being a contradiction in terms. As I explained at the beginning of the lecture, the term pure a priori means without experience so that pure a priori knowledge is knowledge that can be got without experience and a pure a priori intuition is an intuition which one can have without having any experience. In Kant s usage the view that there are pure a priori intuitions was not a contradiction in terms because he took the term experience to mean perception of objects which exist in space and time, rather than perception of anything whatever. There can be pure a priori intuitions because there are things we can intuit which do not exist in space and time. These things we intuit when we imagine objects in space and time. They are space and time themselves. 9

10 Kant s idealism is well summed up in his contention that the things in space which we intuit cannot exist in themselves, but only in us (CPR, p. 82, A 42). Berkeley and Kant share the view that any drop of rain we perceive is in our minds. However, whereas Berkeley holds, of such a rain drop, that to be is to be perceived, Kant holds of it, that to be is to be perceivable by us. Since being perceived entails being perceivable, while being perceivable does not entail being perceived, it may seem that Berkeley s idealism comprises Kant s, but that Kant s does not comprise Berkeley s. The latter, indeed, is obviously true. Kant allowed that things in space could exist unperceived. However, I think it equally true that Berkeley would have agreed, had the question occurred to him, that things which could not exist unperceived could exist although they were unperceivable by us. His idealism does not comprise Kant s. I do not know whether it occurred to Berkeley that something which was perceivable to a being of one kind, for example, a creator, might not be perceivable to a being of another kind, for example, a created being. If it did, he must, I think, have held that to be is to be perceived entails to be is to be perceivable to a being of some kind and denied that it entails to be is to be perceivable by us. Berkeley himself produces arguments for his idealism which are not easily set aside but, it seems to me, they go for nothing in the face of the arguments against it. The arguments I mean consist in showing what implausible consequences it has for the nature of perception. Does Kant s idealism escape such implausibilities? G. E. Moore s article The Refutation of Idealism contains an argument which, it seems to me, does refute Berkeley s idealism. Perhaps it is not quite that which Moore himself employs. The argument is this. The principle that to be is to be perceived entails the identity of whatever is perceived and the perception of it. Things which are perceived are, therefore, perceptions or, perhaps more explicitly, perceivings. But some perceivings are perceivings of one thing and others are perceivings of other things. If the things perceived are the perceivings of them, then the difference between perceivings which differ must lie in the perceivings having different properties. For the perceivings are their own objects and so can only differ in their objects if they themselves differ. Therefore two perceivings which we might regard as differing in respect of their objects differ only, according to this p in that one is of one kind and one of another. But this consequence is absurd. How could it be that the difference be tween perceiving the colour green and perceiving the colour red was a difference between two kinds of perceiving? This absurd conclusion must arise from an absurdity in our premisses, These were, first, that to be is to be perceived, second, that some perceivings are of one thing, others of another. The second premise is not absurd, therefore the first is. Moore put forward a view of the nature of sensation according to which it is not true even of sensations that to be is to be perceived. He suggested that a sensation of blue is an awareness of blue, so 10

11 that a sensation of green differs from a sensation of blue, not in the element of awareness, for exactly the same kind of awareness is present in both instances, but in the colour which is the object of the sensations. Blue is as much an object, and as little a mere content, of my experience, when I experience it, as the most exalted and independent real thing of which I am ever aware. There is, therefore, no question of how we are to get outside the circle of our own ideas and sensations. Merely to have a sensation is already to be outside that circle. It is to know something which is as truly and really not a part of my experience, as anything I can ever know. (Philosophical Studies, p.27) Moore came later to reject this account of the nature of sensation. He did so because he came to reject the possibility of a person being aware of a colour except by being aware of something which is that colour. It was for that reason that he introduced the notion of sense-data, the things which we are aware of in sensation; some are things which are blue, others things which are green. I do not myself see why he came to this view. No doubt when we perceive things in space we perceive things which are blue, but often when we have a sensation of blue, or imagine the colour, the truth seems to me to be that we sense, or imagine, the colour without perceiving or imagining anything which has the colour. I have mentioned this change of mind on Moore s part because it raises another possibility for the interpretation of what Berkeley intended by the principle that to be is to be perceived. It is an interpretation which contradicts the view Moore came to hold. It is certainly one thing Berkeley intended by his principle. The only question is whether he also held the view against which Moore s argument in The Refutation of Idealism is directed. Berkeley often argues for the view that colours cannot be exemplified in things as their qualities, except by exemplification in minds by being perceived. That is, Berkeley might have meant no more by the principle that to be is to be perceived than that colours cannot be qualities of non-mental things but can only be things perceived by minds. This principle would be better expressed as the principle that to be exemplified is to be perceived; or that being perceived is the only way in which a quality can be exemplified the only way in which a quality can be directly related to a particular. If Berkeley held no more than this, then Moore s refutation is misdirected and the relation between his philosophy and that of Kant is very different from the one I have depicted. Kant s principle that to be is to be intuitable by us cannot be given a corresponding interpretation, since he held that we intuit particular objects, not qualities. Moore s refutation of idealism does not depend on the verbal point that whenever a term seems to indicate a relation of a person to an object, as the term perception does, then there must be such a 11

12 relation. That point is shown to be false by an example given by Ducasse in a discussion of Moore s refutation. Ducasse points out that the difference between dancing a waltz and dancing a foxtrot does consist in a difference between two ways of dancing. However, the example does no damage to Moore s argument for there is no plausibility in the interpretation of He perceived the colour blue as He perceived bluely. What sort of activity could this objectless perception be, and how could it be performed bluely? This example of Ducasse s points to a general conclusion concern ing the conditions under which what is spoken of as the object of an activity can be identical with that activity: it can be so only if it either is the activity itself or is a mode in which the activity can be carried on. How else could what a man x-ed be his x-ing of it? Now, just as Berkeley s idealism committed him to the identity of what is perceived and the perceiving of it, so Kant s commits him to the identity of what we can intuit and our ability to intuit it. If my general conclusion is right, then this identity could only hold if an object we can intuit were a mode of the ability to intuit. There is a passage in which Kant speaks of objects of intuition in this way. We then realise that not only are the drops of rain mere appearances, but that even their round shape, nay even the space in which they fall, are nothing in themselves, but merely modifications or fundamental forms of our sensible intuition.... (CPR, p. 85, A 46) This consequence of Kant s idealism is, if anything, more absurd than the corresponding consequence of Berkeley s, for blue, an object of sensation, is at least a mode of something, although it is difficult to see how it can be a mode of whatever non-relational activity or state sensation might be. A raindrop, an object of the ability to intuit, being a particular thing, cannot be a mode at all. 12

Philosophy of Mathematics Kant

Philosophy of Mathematics Kant Philosophy of Mathematics Kant Owen Griffiths oeg21@cam.ac.uk St John s College, Cambridge 20/10/15 Immanuel Kant Born in 1724 in Königsberg, Prussia. Enrolled at the University of Königsberg in 1740 and

More information

The CopernicanRevolution

The CopernicanRevolution Immanuel Kant: The Copernican Revolution The CopernicanRevolution Immanuel Kant (1724-1804) The Critique of Pure Reason (1781) is Kant s best known work. In this monumental work, he begins a Copernican-like

More information

Kant s Critique of Pure Reason1 (Critique) was published in For. Learning to Count Again: On Arithmetical Knowledge in Kant s Prolegomena

Kant s Critique of Pure Reason1 (Critique) was published in For. Learning to Count Again: On Arithmetical Knowledge in Kant s Prolegomena Aporia vol. 24 no. 1 2014 Learning to Count Again: On Arithmetical Knowledge in Kant s Prolegomena Charles Dalrymple - Fraser One might indeed think at first that the proposition 7+5 =12 is a merely analytic

More information

Kant s Transcendental Exposition of Space and Time in the Transcendental Aesthetic : A Critique

Kant s Transcendental Exposition of Space and Time in the Transcendental Aesthetic : A Critique 34 An International Multidisciplinary Journal, Ethiopia Vol. 10(1), Serial No.40, January, 2016: 34-45 ISSN 1994-9057 (Print) ISSN 2070--0083 (Online) Doi: http://dx.doi.org/10.4314/afrrev.v10i1.4 Kant

More information

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras Module - 21 Lecture - 21 Kant Forms of sensibility Categories

More information

1/12. The A Paralogisms

1/12. The A Paralogisms 1/12 The A Paralogisms The character of the Paralogisms is described early in the chapter. Kant describes them as being syllogisms which contain no empirical premises and states that in them we conclude

More information

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras Module - 20 Lecture - 20 Critical Philosophy: Kant s objectives

More information

1/7. The Postulates of Empirical Thought

1/7. The Postulates of Empirical Thought 1/7 The Postulates of Empirical Thought This week we are focusing on the final section of the Analytic of Principles in which Kant schematizes the last set of categories. This set of categories are what

More information

Think by Simon Blackburn. Chapter 7c The World

Think by Simon Blackburn. Chapter 7c The World Think by Simon Blackburn Chapter 7c The World Idealism Despite the power of Berkeley s critique, his resulting metaphysical view is highly problematic. Essentially, Berkeley concludes that there is no

More information

1/10. The Fourth Paralogism and the Refutation of Idealism

1/10. The Fourth Paralogism and the Refutation of Idealism 1/10 The Fourth Paralogism and the Refutation of Idealism The Fourth Paralogism is quite different from the three that preceded it because, although it is treated as a part of rational psychology, it main

More information

Kant Lecture 4 Review Synthetic a priori knowledge

Kant Lecture 4 Review Synthetic a priori knowledge Kant Lecture 4 Review Synthetic a priori knowledge Statements involving necessity or strict universality could never be known on the basis of sense experience, and are thus known (if known at all) a priori.

More information

From Transcendental Logic to Transcendental Deduction

From Transcendental Logic to Transcendental Deduction From Transcendental Logic to Transcendental Deduction Let me see if I can say a few things to re-cap our first discussion of the Transcendental Logic, and help you get a foothold for what follows. Kant

More information

Kant s Misrepresentations of Hume s Philosophy of Mathematics in the Prolegomena

Kant s Misrepresentations of Hume s Philosophy of Mathematics in the Prolegomena Kant s Misrepresentations of Hume s Philosophy of Mathematics in the Prolegomena Mark Steiner Hume Studies Volume XIII, Number 2 (November, 1987) 400-410. Your use of the HUME STUDIES archive indicates

More information

Excerpt from J. Garvey, The Twenty Greatest Philosophy Books (Continuum, 2007): Immanuel Kant s Critique of Pure Reason

Excerpt from J. Garvey, The Twenty Greatest Philosophy Books (Continuum, 2007): Immanuel Kant s Critique of Pure Reason Excerpt from J. Garvey, The Twenty Greatest Philosophy Books (Continuum, 2007): Immanuel Kant s Critique of Pure Reason In a letter to Moses Mendelssohn, Kant says this about the Critique of Pure Reason:

More information

Kant and his Successors

Kant and his Successors Kant and his Successors G. J. Mattey Winter, 2011 / Philosophy 151 The Sorry State of Metaphysics Kant s Critique of Pure Reason (1781) was an attempt to put metaphysics on a scientific basis. Metaphysics

More information

24.01 Classics of Western Philosophy

24.01 Classics of Western Philosophy 1 Plan: Kant Lecture #2: How are pure mathematics and pure natural science possible? 1. Review: Problem of Metaphysics 2. Kantian Commitments 3. Pure Mathematics 4. Transcendental Idealism 5. Pure Natural

More information

It is not at all wise to draw a watertight

It is not at all wise to draw a watertight The Causal Relation : Its Acceptance and Denial JOY BHATTACHARYYA It is not at all wise to draw a watertight distinction between Eastern and Western philosophies. The causal relation is a serious problem

More information

WHAT IS HUME S FORK? Certainty does not exist in science.

WHAT IS HUME S FORK?  Certainty does not exist in science. WHAT IS HUME S FORK? www.prshockley.org Certainty does not exist in science. I. Introduction: A. Hume divides all objects of human reason into two different kinds: Relation of Ideas & Matters of Fact.

More information

Ayer s linguistic theory of the a priori

Ayer s linguistic theory of the a priori Ayer s linguistic theory of the a priori phil 43904 Jeff Speaks December 4, 2007 1 The problem of a priori knowledge....................... 1 2 Necessity and the a priori............................ 2

More information

Ayer and Quine on the a priori

Ayer and Quine on the a priori Ayer and Quine on the a priori November 23, 2004 1 The problem of a priori knowledge Ayer s book is a defense of a thoroughgoing empiricism, not only about what is required for a belief to be justified

More information

On the epistemological status of mathematical objects in Plato s philosophical system

On the epistemological status of mathematical objects in Plato s philosophical system On the epistemological status of mathematical objects in Plato s philosophical system Floris T. van Vugt University College Utrecht University, The Netherlands October 22, 2003 Abstract The main question

More information

Today we turn to the work of one of the most important, and also most difficult, philosophers: Immanuel Kant.

Today we turn to the work of one of the most important, and also most difficult, philosophers: Immanuel Kant. Kant s antinomies Today we turn to the work of one of the most important, and also most difficult, philosophers: Immanuel Kant. Kant was born in 1724 in Prussia, and his philosophical work has exerted

More information

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy Res Cogitans Volume 5 Issue 1 Article 20 6-4-2014 Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy Kevin Harriman Lewis & Clark College Follow this and additional works at: http://commons.pacificu.edu/rescogitans

More information

Class #14: October 13 Gödel s Platonism

Class #14: October 13 Gödel s Platonism Philosophy 405: Knowledge, Truth and Mathematics Fall 2010 Hamilton College Russell Marcus Class #14: October 13 Gödel s Platonism I. The Continuum Hypothesis and Its Independence The continuum problem

More information

Logic: Deductive and Inductive by Carveth Read M.A. CHAPTER IX CHAPTER IX FORMAL CONDITIONS OF MEDIATE INFERENCE

Logic: Deductive and Inductive by Carveth Read M.A. CHAPTER IX CHAPTER IX FORMAL CONDITIONS OF MEDIATE INFERENCE CHAPTER IX CHAPTER IX FORMAL CONDITIONS OF MEDIATE INFERENCE Section 1. A Mediate Inference is a proposition that depends for proof upon two or more other propositions, so connected together by one or

More information

1/9. The First Analogy

1/9. The First Analogy 1/9 The First Analogy So far we have looked at the mathematical principles but now we are going to turn to the dynamical principles, of which there are two sorts, the Analogies of Experience and the Postulates

More information

Chapter 18 David Hume: Theory of Knowledge

Chapter 18 David Hume: Theory of Knowledge Key Words Chapter 18 David Hume: Theory of Knowledge Empiricism, skepticism, personal identity, necessary connection, causal connection, induction, impressions, ideas. DAVID HUME (1711-76) is one of the

More information

From Necessary Truth to Necessary Existence

From Necessary Truth to Necessary Existence Prequel for Section 4.2 of Defending the Correspondence Theory Published by PJP VII, 1 From Necessary Truth to Necessary Existence Abstract I introduce new details in an argument for necessarily existing

More information

Immanuel Kant, Analytic and Synthetic. Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics Preface and Preamble

Immanuel Kant, Analytic and Synthetic. Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics Preface and Preamble + Immanuel Kant, Analytic and Synthetic Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics Preface and Preamble + Innate vs. a priori n Philosophers today usually distinguish psychological from epistemological questions.

More information

1/8. The Schematism. schema of empirical concepts, the schema of sensible concepts and the

1/8. The Schematism. schema of empirical concepts, the schema of sensible concepts and the 1/8 The Schematism I am going to distinguish between three types of schematism: the schema of empirical concepts, the schema of sensible concepts and the schema of pure concepts. Kant opens the discussion

More information

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori PHIL 83104 November 2, 2011 Both Boghossian and Harman address themselves to the question of whether our a priori knowledge can be explained in

More information

1/6. The Second Analogy (2)

1/6. The Second Analogy (2) 1/6 The Second Analogy (2) Last time we looked at some of Kant s discussion of the Second Analogy, including the argument that is discussed most often as Kant s response to Hume s sceptical doubts concerning

More information

Perception and Mind-Dependence: Lecture 2

Perception and Mind-Dependence: Lecture 2 1 Recap Perception and Mind-Dependence: Lecture 2 (Alex Moran, apm60@ cam.ac.uk) According to naïve realism: (1) the objects of perception are ordinary, mindindependent things, and (2) perceptual experience

More information

Kant s Copernican Revolution

Kant s Copernican Revolution Kant s Copernican Revolution While the thoughts are still fresh in my mind, let me try to pick up from where we left off in class today, and say a little bit more about Kant s claim that reason has insight

More information

III Knowledge is true belief based on argument. Plato, Theaetetus, 201 c-d Is Justified True Belief Knowledge? Edmund Gettier

III Knowledge is true belief based on argument. Plato, Theaetetus, 201 c-d Is Justified True Belief Knowledge? Edmund Gettier III Knowledge is true belief based on argument. Plato, Theaetetus, 201 c-d Is Justified True Belief Knowledge? Edmund Gettier In Theaetetus Plato introduced the definition of knowledge which is often translated

More information

HUME'S THEORY. THE question which I am about to discuss is this. Under what circumstances

HUME'S THEORY. THE question which I am about to discuss is this. Under what circumstances Chapter V HUME'S THEORY THE question which I am about to discuss is this. Under what circumstances (if any) does a man, when he believes a proposition, not merely believe it but also absolutely know that

More information

KANT S PHILOSOPHY OF MATHEMATICS

KANT S PHILOSOPHY OF MATHEMATICS KANT S PHILOSOPHY OF MATHEMATICS By Dr. Marsigit, M.A. Yogyakarta State University, Yogyakarta, Indonesia Email: marsigitina@yahoo.com, Web: http://powermathematics.blogspot.com HomePhone: 62 274 886 381;

More information

Think by Simon Blackburn. Chapter 7b The World

Think by Simon Blackburn. Chapter 7b The World Think by Simon Blackburn Chapter 7b The World Kant s metaphysics rested on identifying a kind of truth that Hume and other did not acknowledge. It is called A. synthetic a priori B. analytic a priori C.

More information

Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000)

Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000) Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000) One of the advantages traditionally claimed for direct realist theories of perception over indirect realist theories is that the

More information

1/5. The Critique of Theology

1/5. The Critique of Theology 1/5 The Critique of Theology The argument of the Transcendental Dialectic has demonstrated that there is no science of rational psychology and that the province of any rational cosmology is strictly limited.

More information

Spinoza, Ethics 1 of 85 THE ETHICS. by Benedict de Spinoza (Ethica Ordine Geometrico Demonstrata) Translated from the Latin by R. H. M.

Spinoza, Ethics 1 of 85 THE ETHICS. by Benedict de Spinoza (Ethica Ordine Geometrico Demonstrata) Translated from the Latin by R. H. M. Spinoza, Ethics 1 of 85 THE ETHICS by Benedict de Spinoza (Ethica Ordine Geometrico Demonstrata) Translated from the Latin by R. H. M. Elwes PART I: CONCERNING GOD DEFINITIONS (1) By that which is self-caused

More information

PHI2391: Logical Empiricism I 8.0

PHI2391: Logical Empiricism I 8.0 1 2 3 4 5 PHI2391: Logical Empiricism I 8.0 Hume and Kant! Remember Hume s question:! Are we rationally justified in inferring causes from experimental observations?! Kant s answer: we can give a transcendental

More information

PHILOSOPHY OF LOGIC AND LANGUAGE OVERVIEW FREGE JONNY MCINTOSH 1. FREGE'S CONCEPTION OF LOGIC

PHILOSOPHY OF LOGIC AND LANGUAGE OVERVIEW FREGE JONNY MCINTOSH 1. FREGE'S CONCEPTION OF LOGIC PHILOSOPHY OF LOGIC AND LANGUAGE JONNY MCINTOSH 1. FREGE'S CONCEPTION OF LOGIC OVERVIEW These lectures cover material for paper 108, Philosophy of Logic and Language. They will focus on issues in philosophy

More information

To appear in The Journal of Philosophy.

To appear in The Journal of Philosophy. To appear in The Journal of Philosophy. Lucy Allais: Manifest Reality: Kant s Idealism and his Realism. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2015, pp. xi + 329. 40.00 (hb). ISBN: 9780198747130. Kant s doctrine

More information

It doesn t take long in reading the Critique before we are faced with interpretive challenges. Consider the very first sentence in the A edition:

It doesn t take long in reading the Critique before we are faced with interpretive challenges. Consider the very first sentence in the A edition: The Preface(s) to the Critique of Pure Reason It doesn t take long in reading the Critique before we are faced with interpretive challenges. Consider the very first sentence in the A edition: Human reason

More information

CHAPTER III KANT S APPROACH TO A PRIORI AND A POSTERIORI

CHAPTER III KANT S APPROACH TO A PRIORI AND A POSTERIORI CHAPTER III KANT S APPROACH TO A PRIORI AND A POSTERIORI Introduction One could easily find out two most influential epistemological doctrines, namely, rationalism and empiricism that have inadequate solutions

More information

Class #9: Kant Our in class discussion of these notes will be lamentably abbreviated, focused on the first three sections.

Class #9: Kant Our in class discussion of these notes will be lamentably abbreviated, focused on the first three sections. Philosophy 405: Knowledge, Truth and Mathematics Fall 2014 Hamilton College Russell Marcus Class #9: Kant Our in class discussion of these notes will be lamentably abbreviated, focused on the first three

More information

Absolute Totality, Causality, and Quantum: The Problem of Metaphysics in the Critique of Pure Reason. Kazuhiko Yamamoto, Kyushu University, Japan

Absolute Totality, Causality, and Quantum: The Problem of Metaphysics in the Critique of Pure Reason. Kazuhiko Yamamoto, Kyushu University, Japan Absolute Totality, Causality, and Quantum: The Problem of Metaphysics in the Critique of Pure Reason Kazuhiko Yamamoto, Kyushu University, Japan The Asian Conference on Ethics, Religion & Philosophy 2017

More information

10 CERTAINTY G.E. MOORE: SELECTED WRITINGS

10 CERTAINTY G.E. MOORE: SELECTED WRITINGS 10 170 I am at present, as you can all see, in a room and not in the open air; I am standing up, and not either sitting or lying down; I have clothes on, and am not absolutely naked; I am speaking in a

More information

Spinoza and the Axiomatic Method. Ever since Euclid first laid out his geometry in the Elements, his axiomatic approach to

Spinoza and the Axiomatic Method. Ever since Euclid first laid out his geometry in the Elements, his axiomatic approach to Haruyama 1 Justin Haruyama Bryan Smith HON 213 17 April 2008 Spinoza and the Axiomatic Method Ever since Euclid first laid out his geometry in the Elements, his axiomatic approach to geometry has been

More information

Class 2 - Foundationalism

Class 2 - Foundationalism 2 3 Philosophy 2 3 : Intuitions and Philosophy Fall 2011 Hamilton College Russell Marcus Class 2 - Foundationalism I. Rationalist Foundations What follows is a rough caricature of some historical themes

More information

Important dates. PSY 3360 / CGS 3325 Historical Perspectives on Psychology Minds and Machines since David Hume ( )

Important dates. PSY 3360 / CGS 3325 Historical Perspectives on Psychology Minds and Machines since David Hume ( ) PSY 3360 / CGS 3325 Historical Perspectives on Psychology Minds and Machines since 1600 Dr. Peter Assmann Spring 2018 Important dates Feb 14 Term paper draft due Upload paper to E-Learning https://elearning.utdallas.edu

More information

Today we turn to the work of one of the most important, and also most difficult, philosophers: Immanuel Kant.

Today we turn to the work of one of the most important, and also most difficult, philosophers: Immanuel Kant. Kant s antinomies Today we turn to the work of one of the most important, and also most difficult, philosophers: Immanuel Kant. Kant was born in 1724 in Prussia, and his philosophical work has exerted

More information

Summary of Kant s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals

Summary of Kant s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals Summary of Kant s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals Version 1.1 Richard Baron 2 October 2016 1 Contents 1 Introduction 3 1.1 Availability and licence............ 3 2 Definitions of key terms 4 3

More information

Selections from Aristotle s Prior Analytics 41a21 41b5

Selections from Aristotle s Prior Analytics 41a21 41b5 Lesson Seventeen The Conditional Syllogism Selections from Aristotle s Prior Analytics 41a21 41b5 It is clear then that the ostensive syllogisms are effected by means of the aforesaid figures; these considerations

More information

First Truths. G. W. Leibniz

First Truths. G. W. Leibniz Copyright Jonathan Bennett 2017. All rights reserved [Brackets] enclose editorial explanations. Small dots enclose material that has been added, but can be read as though it were part of the original text.

More information

By submitting this essay, I attest that it is my own work, completed in accordance with University regulations. Minh Alexander Nguyen

By submitting this essay, I attest that it is my own work, completed in accordance with University regulations. Minh Alexander Nguyen DRST 004: Directed Studies Philosophy Professor Matthew Noah Smith By submitting this essay, I attest that it is my own work, completed in accordance with University regulations. Minh Alexander Nguyen

More information

Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible?

Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible? Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible? Anders Kraal ABSTRACT: Since the 1960s an increasing number of philosophers have endorsed the thesis that there can be no such thing as

More information

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory Western University Scholarship@Western 2015 Undergraduate Awards The Undergraduate Awards 2015 Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory David Hakim Western University, davidhakim266@gmail.com

More information

The Ontological Argument for the existence of God. Pedro M. Guimarães Ferreira S.J. PUC-Rio Boston College, July 13th. 2011

The Ontological Argument for the existence of God. Pedro M. Guimarães Ferreira S.J. PUC-Rio Boston College, July 13th. 2011 The Ontological Argument for the existence of God Pedro M. Guimarães Ferreira S.J. PUC-Rio Boston College, July 13th. 2011 The ontological argument (henceforth, O.A.) for the existence of God has a long

More information

Philosophy 203 History of Modern Western Philosophy. Russell Marcus Hamilton College Spring 2014

Philosophy 203 History of Modern Western Philosophy. Russell Marcus Hamilton College Spring 2014 Philosophy 203 History of Modern Western Philosophy Russell Marcus Hamilton College Spring 2014 Class #26 Kant s Copernican Revolution The Synthetic A Priori Forms of Intuition Marcus, Modern Philosophy,

More information

Russell s Problems of Philosophy

Russell s Problems of Philosophy Russell s Problems of Philosophy UNIVERSALS & OUR KNOWLEDGE OF THEM F e b r u a r y 2 Today : 1. Review A Priori Knowledge 2. The Case for Universals 3. Universals to the Rescue! 4. On Philosophy Essays

More information

Understanding How we Come to Experience Purposive. Behavior. Jacob Roundtree. Colby College Mayflower Hill, Waterville, ME USA

Understanding How we Come to Experience Purposive. Behavior. Jacob Roundtree. Colby College Mayflower Hill, Waterville, ME USA Understanding How we Come to Experience Purposive Behavior Jacob Roundtree Colby College 6984 Mayflower Hill, Waterville, ME 04901 USA 1-347-241-4272 Ludwig von Mises, one of the Great 20 th Century economists,

More information

- We might, now, wonder whether the resulting concept of justification is sufficiently strong. According to BonJour, apparent rational insight is

- We might, now, wonder whether the resulting concept of justification is sufficiently strong. According to BonJour, apparent rational insight is BonJour I PHIL410 BonJour s Moderate Rationalism - BonJour develops and defends a moderate form of Rationalism. - Rationalism, generally (as used here), is the view according to which the primary tool

More information

Notes on Bertrand Russell s The Problems of Philosophy (Hackett 1990 reprint of the 1912 Oxford edition, Chapters XII, XIII, XIV, )

Notes on Bertrand Russell s The Problems of Philosophy (Hackett 1990 reprint of the 1912 Oxford edition, Chapters XII, XIII, XIV, ) Notes on Bertrand Russell s The Problems of Philosophy (Hackett 1990 reprint of the 1912 Oxford edition, Chapters XII, XIII, XIV, 119-152) Chapter XII Truth and Falsehood [pp. 119-130] Russell begins here

More information

VI. CEITICAL NOTICES.

VI. CEITICAL NOTICES. VI. CEITICAL NOTICES. Our Knowledge of the External World. By BBBTBAND RUSSELL. Open Court Co. Pp. ix, 245. THIS book Mr. Russell's Lowell Lectures though intentionally somewhat popular in tone, contains

More information

THE STUDY OF UNKNOWN AND UNKNOWABILITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY

THE STUDY OF UNKNOWN AND UNKNOWABILITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY THE STUDY OF UNKNOWN AND UNKNOWABILITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY Subhankari Pati Research Scholar Pondicherry University, Pondicherry The present aim of this paper is to highlights the shortcomings in Kant

More information

The British Empiricism

The British Empiricism The British Empiricism Locke, Berkeley and Hume copyleft: nicolazuin.2018 nowxhere.wordpress.com The terrible heritage of Descartes: Skepticism, Empiricism, Rationalism The problem originates from the

More information

Copyright 2000 Vk-Cic Vahe Karamian

Copyright 2000 Vk-Cic Vahe Karamian Kant In France and England, the Enlightenment theories were blueprints for reforms and revolutions political and economic changes came together with philosophical theory. In Germany, the Enlightenment

More information

Absolute Totality, Causality, and Quantum: The Problem of Metaphysics in the Critique of Pure Reason

Absolute Totality, Causality, and Quantum: The Problem of Metaphysics in the Critique of Pure Reason International Journal of Humanities Social Sciences and Education (IJHSSE) Volume 4, Issue 4, April 2017, PP 72-81 ISSN 2349-0373 (Print) & ISSN 2349-0381 (Online) http://dx.doi.org/10.20431/2349-0381.0404008

More information

PHILOSOPHY OF KNOWLEDGE & REALITY W E E K 7 : E P I S T E M O L O G Y - K A N T

PHILOSOPHY OF KNOWLEDGE & REALITY W E E K 7 : E P I S T E M O L O G Y - K A N T PHILOSOPHY OF KNOWLEDGE & REALITY W E E K 7 : E P I S T E M O L O G Y - K A N T AGENDA 1. Review of Epistemology 2. Kant Kant s Compromise Kant s Copernican Revolution 3. The Nature of Truth REVIEW: THREE

More information

Kant On The A Priority of Space: A Critique Arjun Sawhney - The University of Toronto pp. 4-7

Kant On The A Priority of Space: A Critique Arjun Sawhney - The University of Toronto pp. 4-7 Issue 1 Spring 2016 Undergraduate Journal of Philosophy Kant On The A Priority of Space: A Critique Arjun Sawhney - The University of Toronto pp. 4-7 For details of submission dates and guidelines please

More information

Reid Against Skepticism

Reid Against Skepticism Thus we see, that Descartes and Locke take the road that leads to skepticism without knowing the end of it, but they stop short for want of light to carry them farther. Berkeley, frightened at the appearance

More information

This is a repository copy of Making Modal Distinctions: Kant on the possible, the actual, and the intuitive intellect..

This is a repository copy of Making Modal Distinctions: Kant on the possible, the actual, and the intuitive intellect.. This is a repository copy of Making Modal Distinctions: Kant on the possible, the actual, and the intuitive intellect.. White Rose Research Online URL for this paper: http://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/81838/

More information

The Kripkenstein Paradox and the Private World. In his paper, Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Languages, Kripke expands upon a conclusion

The Kripkenstein Paradox and the Private World. In his paper, Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Languages, Kripke expands upon a conclusion 24.251: Philosophy of Language Paper 2: S.A. Kripke, On Rules and Private Language 21 December 2011 The Kripkenstein Paradox and the Private World In his paper, Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Languages,

More information

Concerning God Baruch Spinoza

Concerning God Baruch Spinoza Concerning God Baruch Spinoza Definitions. I. BY that which is self-caused, I mean that of which the essence involves existence, or that of which the nature is only conceivable as existent. II. A thing

More information

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW DISCUSSION NOTE BY CAMPBELL BROWN JOURNAL OF ETHICS & SOCIAL PHILOSOPHY DISCUSSION NOTE MAY 2015 URL: WWW.JESP.ORG COPYRIGHT CAMPBELL BROWN 2015 Two Versions of Hume s Law MORAL CONCLUSIONS CANNOT VALIDLY

More information

Mary Shepherd's Two Senses of Necessary Connection

Mary Shepherd's Two Senses of Necessary Connection Mary Shepherd's Two Senses of Necessary Connection Mary Shepherd's proof of external existence rests on an account of cause and effect. At the same time, ideas of cause and effect are explained in terms

More information

5 A Modal Version of the

5 A Modal Version of the 5 A Modal Version of the Ontological Argument E. J. L O W E Moreland, J. P.; Sweis, Khaldoun A.; Meister, Chad V., Jul 01, 2013, Debating Christian Theism The original version of the ontological argument

More information

In The California Undergraduate Philosophy Review, vol. 1, pp Fresno, CA: California State University, Fresno.

In The California Undergraduate Philosophy Review, vol. 1, pp Fresno, CA: California State University, Fresno. A Distinction Without a Difference? The Analytic-Synthetic Distinction and Immanuel Kant s Critique of Metaphysics Brandon Clark Cal Poly, San Luis Obispo Abstract: In this paper I pose and answer the

More information

Conventionalism and the linguistic doctrine of logical truth

Conventionalism and the linguistic doctrine of logical truth 1 Conventionalism and the linguistic doctrine of logical truth 1.1 Introduction Quine s work on analyticity, translation, and reference has sweeping philosophical implications. In his first important philosophical

More information

David Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature ( ), Book I, Part III.

David Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature ( ), Book I, Part III. David Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature (1739 1740), Book I, Part III. N.B. This text is my selection from Jonathan Bennett s paraphrase of Hume s text. The full Bennett text is available at http://www.earlymoderntexts.com/.

More information

PHILOSOPHICAL RAMIFICATIONS: THEORY, EXPERIMENT, & EMPIRICAL TRUTH

PHILOSOPHICAL RAMIFICATIONS: THEORY, EXPERIMENT, & EMPIRICAL TRUTH PHILOSOPHICAL RAMIFICATIONS: THEORY, EXPERIMENT, & EMPIRICAL TRUTH PCES 3.42 Even before Newton published his revolutionary work, philosophers had already been trying to come to grips with the questions

More information

CONTENTS A SYSTEM OF LOGIC

CONTENTS A SYSTEM OF LOGIC EDITOR'S INTRODUCTION NOTE ON THE TEXT. SELECTED BIBLIOGRAPHY XV xlix I /' ~, r ' o>

More information

DESCARTES ONTOLOGICAL PROOF: AN INTERPRETATION AND DEFENSE

DESCARTES ONTOLOGICAL PROOF: AN INTERPRETATION AND DEFENSE DESCARTES ONTOLOGICAL PROOF: AN INTERPRETATION AND DEFENSE STANISŁAW JUDYCKI University of Gdańsk Abstract. It is widely assumed among contemporary philosophers that Descartes version of ontological proof,

More information

Meditations on Knowledge, Truth, and Ideas

Meditations on Knowledge, Truth, and Ideas 1 Copyright Jonathan Bennett [Brackets] enclose editorial explanations. Small dots enclose material that has been added, but can be read as though it were part of the original text. Occasional bullets,

More information

Wright on response-dependence and self-knowledge

Wright on response-dependence and self-knowledge Wright on response-dependence and self-knowledge March 23, 2004 1 Response-dependent and response-independent concepts........... 1 1.1 The intuitive distinction......................... 1 1.2 Basic equations

More information

Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods

Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods delineating the scope of deductive reason Roger Bishop Jones Abstract. The scope of deductive reason is considered. First a connection is discussed between the

More information

Introduction to Philosophy PHL 221, York College Revised, Spring 2017

Introduction to Philosophy PHL 221, York College Revised, Spring 2017 Introduction to Philosophy PHL 221, York College Revised, Spring 2017 Beginnings of Philosophy: Overview of Course (1) The Origins of Philosophy and Relativism Knowledge Are you a self? Ethics: What is

More information

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras Module - 22 Lecture - 22 Kant The idea of Reason Soul, God

More information

Treatise I,iii,14: Hume offers an account of all five causes: matter, form, efficient, exemplary, and final cause.

Treatise I,iii,14: Hume offers an account of all five causes: matter, form, efficient, exemplary, and final cause. HUME Treatise I,iii,14: Hume offers an account of all five causes: matter, form, efficient, exemplary, and final cause. Beauchamp / Rosenberg, Hume and the Problem of Causation, start with: David Hume

More information

A Priori Knowledge: Analytic? Synthetic A Priori (again) Is All A Priori Knowledge Analytic?

A Priori Knowledge: Analytic? Synthetic A Priori (again) Is All A Priori Knowledge Analytic? A Priori Knowledge: Analytic? Synthetic A Priori (again) Is All A Priori Knowledge Analytic? Recap A Priori Knowledge Knowledge independent of experience Kant: necessary and universal A Posteriori Knowledge

More information

1.2. What is said: propositions

1.2. What is said: propositions 1.2. What is said: propositions 1.2.0. Overview In 1.1.5, we saw the close relation between two properties of a deductive inference: (i) it is a transition from premises to conclusion that is free of any

More information

It Ain t What You Prove, It s the Way That You Prove It. a play by Chris Binge

It Ain t What You Prove, It s the Way That You Prove It. a play by Chris Binge It Ain t What You Prove, It s the Way That You Prove It a play by Chris Binge (From Alchin, Nicholas. Theory of Knowledge. London: John Murray, 2003. Pp. 66-69.) Teacher: Good afternoon class. For homework

More information

PHILOSOPHY OF KNOWLEDGE & REALITY W E E K 7 : E P I S T E M O L O G Y - K A N T

PHILOSOPHY OF KNOWLEDGE & REALITY W E E K 7 : E P I S T E M O L O G Y - K A N T PHILOSOPHY OF KNOWLEDGE & REALITY W E E K 7 : E P I S T E M O L O G Y - K A N T AGENDA 1. Review of Epistemology 2. Kant Kant s Compromise Kant s Copernican Revolution 3. The Nature of Truth KNOWLEDGE:

More information

What God Could Have Made

What God Could Have Made 1 What God Could Have Made By Heimir Geirsson and Michael Losonsky I. Introduction Atheists have argued that if there is a God who is omnipotent, omniscient and omnibenevolent, then God would have made

More information

Charles Hartshorne argues that Kant s criticisms of Anselm s ontological

Charles Hartshorne argues that Kant s criticisms of Anselm s ontological Aporia vol. 18 no. 2 2008 The Ontological Parody: A Reply to Joshua Ernst s Charles Hartshorne and the Ontological Argument Charles Hartshorne argues that Kant s criticisms of Anselm s ontological argument

More information

Ethics Demonstrated in Geometrical Order

Ethics Demonstrated in Geometrical Order Ethics Demonstrated in Geometrical Order Benedict Spinoza Copyright Jonathan Bennett 2017. All rights reserved [Brackets] enclose editorial explanations. Small dots enclose material that has been added,

More information

Lonergan on General Transcendent Knowledge. In General Transcendent Knowledge, Chapter 19 of Insight, Lonergan does several things:

Lonergan on General Transcendent Knowledge. In General Transcendent Knowledge, Chapter 19 of Insight, Lonergan does several things: Lonergan on General Transcendent Knowledge In General Transcendent Knowledge, Chapter 19 of Insight, Lonergan does several things: 1-3--He provides a radical reinterpretation of the meaning of transcendence

More information

THE FREEDOM OF THE WILL By Immanuel Kant From Critique of Pure Reason (1781)

THE FREEDOM OF THE WILL By Immanuel Kant From Critique of Pure Reason (1781) THE FREEDOM OF THE WILL By Immanuel Kant From Critique of Pure Reason (1781) From: A447/B475 A451/B479 Freedom independence of the laws of nature is certainly a deliverance from restraint, but it is also

More information