Canadian Figure Skaters, French Judges, and Realism in Sport

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Canadian Figure Skaters, French Judges, and Realism in Sport"

Transcription

1 JOURNAL OF THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPORT, Realism 2003, XXX, in Sport by the International Association for the Philosophy of Sport Canadian Figure Skaters, French Judges, and Realism in Sport Nicholas Dixon Philosophers of sport often discuss controversial incidents on the playing field when it is unclear what decision the rules require referees, umpires, or judges to make. Such cases include a soccer player who ignores the convention that possession should be returned to the team whose player deliberately puts the ball into touch so that an injured player can receive treatment and a base runner in baseball who himself catches the ball in order to prevent a double play. 1 Hard cases that pose problems for popular theories are often a fertile ground for insights in philosophy in general, and hard cases that arise when the rules of a sport fail to provide clear guidance are no exception. In this article, however, I will adopt a very different strategy. I will try to derive some philosophical lessons from a recent incident in sport that, although it generated much controversy, appears amenable to quite simple analysis by reference to the pertinent rules. I refer to the decision by judges in the 2002 winter Olympic Games in Salt Lake City to award the gold medal in pairs figure skating to the Russian couple, even though it was widely believed by the skating community, journalists, and spectators that the Canadian pair, Jamie Salé and David Pelletier, had skated better. The IOC made a de facto admission that the judges had made a mistake when it decided several days after the event to enact the unusual remedy of awarding a second pair of gold medals to the Canadians while allowing the Russians to keep theirs. I will examine the implications of this incident for two philosophical questions: (a) the nature of decisions by referees, umpires, and judges in sport and (b) the more general issue of the nature of our judgments about sport (i.e., our views on debates about sport). I will assume for the sake of argument that the Canadians did indeed deserve to be the sole recipients of gold medals. In support of this assumption, even laypersons could see that the Russians stumbled several times during their routine, whereas the Canadians was faultless. Unless the Russians routine was more technically challenging or clearly superior in artistic merit which was patently not the case, in the opinion of nearly all observers the Canadians should have won. Perhaps even more telling than the nearly unanimous verdict of the skating community was the unguarded reaction of Salé when she and Pelletier had finished their routine. N. Dixon <dixon@alma.edu> is with the Philosophy Department at Alma College, Alma, MI This article was delivered as the presidential address at the 2002 meeting of the International Association for the Philosophy of Sport and underwent the same blind review process handled by the associate editor to avoid conflict of interest as other submissions to JPS. 103

2 104 DIXON She bent downward in stunned silence and only after a few seconds was she able to regain her composure to tearfully wave to the crowd. She knew that she and Pelletier had skated beautifully, with none of the errors that the Russian pair had committed, and she believed that winning the gold medal was a foregone conclusion. Most publicity surrounding this controversy has concerned allegations of corruption among judges and national skating federations, especially those from France. If it really exists, such corruption is reprehensible and merits the harsh criticism it has received, and the IOC urgently needs to take measures to eradicate it. Although the wrongness of this alleged corruption is so evident that it appears to require little philosophical argument, I propose to address two issues arising from this incident that have significant philosophical relevance: the status of the judges original decision and implications for rival theories on the nature of judgments about sport. The Status of the Judges Original Decision First, the innocuous-looking claim that the original decision to award the gold medal to the Russian skaters, rather than the Canadians, was unjust raises interesting questions about the general nature of decisions by referees, umpires, and judges in sport. The injustice remains, whether the decision was influenced by corruption or whether it was a simple error of judgment. In another article (2), I treated refereeing errors as one cause of unjust results, in which the better, more deserving team or athlete does not win. Some refereeing errors do not necessarily lead to unjust results, in that a superior team will often be able to overcome mistaken calls by the referee and win anyway. In figure skating, however, the judges verdict is the final word that determines the outcome, and the skaters have no opportunity to overcome judges errors. The claim that denying the Canadians the gold medal was unjust presupposes, of course, that we have a standard for judging skating contests independent of the actual decision made by the judges. As John Russell has shown in his illuminating discussion of calls in baseball (10), however, even this modest claim has been disputed by those who assert that the umpire s call creates the reality. If this is the case, no independent criterion exists by reference to which we can deem the umpire s call to be mistaken. As Russell perceptively responds, this view considers only the fact that umpires have the final word (which he calls the verdictive force of their calls) and neglects the fact that baseball calls are simultaneously descriptions, which can be true or false, of the events that the umpires saw (10: pp ). Because baseball calls are descriptions of physical events, we can easily accept that some calls are plain wrong. After all, television replays can conclusively prove that, for instance, contrary to the umpire s decision, the base runner beat the throw to first base. Similarly, replays can provide objective evidence of mistaken calls in other sports such as football, cricket, and tennis. Figure skating is more problematic in that it, like other judged performances, is judged in part on aesthetic criteria. Victory in skating is determined by adding two separate scores, one for technical and one for artistic merit. To show that any aesthetic judgment including the judgment that skater A s performance was more artistically or aesthetically worthy than skater B s is clearly mistaken is notoriously difficult. Even if

3 Realism in Sport 105 we can agree on common criteria for aesthetic judgments, two different works of art or athletic performances can qualify as aesthetically pleasing by virtue of different subsets of these criteria, making it difficult to make comparative judgments. In the case of Salé and Pelletier, however, we do not need to engage in arcane debate about the nature of aesthetic judgments to show that the judges made a bad decision. The reason for the widespread condemnation of their decision had nothing to do with the artistic merit of the two couples performance, which was widely viewed as comparable. Awarding the gold medal to the Russians created such controversy because the technical superiority of the Canadians, who did not once stumble, was evident for all to see. Marks for technical merit, in contrast to those for artistic merit, are more akin to the factual reports that baseball umpires make when they call a batter out on strikes or safe at home plate. It is, in other words, a matter of checkable, empirical fact whether skaters perform the required jumps and do so without falling or stumbling. We might go even further than the claim that the judges erred and assert that their decision to give the gold medals to the Russian skaters was so bad as to be null and void, with the Canadians being the real winners. I have elsewhere criticized the idea, which parallels the doctrine of natural law that an unjust law is no law at all, that those who secure victory by means of blatant refereeing errors are not really winners at all. My objection to this view is that we need to distinguish between the existence of a law or victory and, on the other hand, its justice. Moral problems need to be solved by argument, not by stipulation, and we should not try to deny a priori the very possibility of unjust laws and undeserved victories (2: pp ). Russell, however, has offered an ingenious interpretation of natural-law theory that avoids the paradoxical claim that no unjust laws exist. Russell argues, for instance, that the decisions of a corrupt judge, although he might have been duly appointed and although they are on the books, are actually perversions of legal judgments that have no authority. The judgments of a corrupt judge... are judgments in a merely technical and equivocal sense of the term. [I]t does not make sense to say they are genuine or true judicial judgments. We know this because a corrupt judge fails to perform a function that is essential to his role, that of being an impartial arbiter. (10: p. 26) Russell coins the term dismissive judgment to refer to the assertion that a purported instance of a concept is, despite its superficial authenticity, not a genuine one (10: p. 33). We use dismissive judgments not only to dismiss the rulings of corrupt judges but also in many other contexts, for instance to deny the worth of a degree awarded by a mail order university lacking accreditation despite the impressive stationery on which the certificate is printed. Russell argues that some instances of bad calls by baseball umpires such as those resulting from bias or incompetence merit the dismissive judgment That s no call! No doubt we recognize that even excellent umpires occasionally make bad calls without being tempted to regard the calls as lacking in authority. In the case of blatantly biased or incompetent officiating, however, we might justifiably abandon our usual respect for the authority of umpires and pursue various methods of protest to challenge the standing of their mistaken calls. As a practical expedient, Russell quite reasonably proposes that we minimize the need for

4 106 DIXON after-the-fact protests by giving baseball umpires far more opportunity than currently exists for correcting mistaken calls (10: pp ). If awarding the gold medal to the Russian skaters in Salt Lake City were just an innocent, if baffling, error on the part of otherwise competent judges, we would have to regard their judgment as legal positivists view bad laws: as mistaken but nonetheless binding and authoritative. The kind of gross corruption of which various figure-skating judges and federations in Salt Lake City are accused, however agreeing to give high marks for another country s skaters in return for reciprocal favors in future contests clearly falls within the ambit of Russell s argument. Although the judges did indeed have the power to award medals, their corruption, which led them to award medals on the basis of factors other than the skaters merits, invalidates their decision. When the IOC, in response to outrage at the original decision, took the unprecedented step of overruling it and awarding a second set of gold medals to the Canadians, it tacitly admitted that the judges initial verdict was not only mistaken but also invalid and lacking in authority. Implications for Rival Theories on the Nature of Judgments About Sport The second philosophical question on which the Olympic skating debacle sheds light is a far more general issue: the debate between rival theories on the general nature of judgments about sport. By judgments about sport I mean not the decisions made by judges but rather the beliefs that anyone holds on moral or nonmoral debates about sport. We can use the uncontroversial claim that the judges corruption was wrong as a test case for three different theories on the general nature of judgments about sport. Formalists, who believe that questions about sport can be answered by sole reference to the relevant rules, will condemn the judges actions because they brazenly violated the rules that govern the awarding of marks for skating performances. So-called conventionalists, such as adherents of the Rortyinspired belief that there is no deeper foundation to rationality than solidarity (1: p. 61), will condemn the judges actions precisely because of the strong negative reaction they provoked in the practice community of figure skating. And those whom Robert Simon has termed interpretive broad internalists, or just interpretivists (11), who hold that judgments about sport should be based in part on rationally grounded principles about the nature and purpose of sport whether or not the practice community or any other group happens to adhere to those principles will have no trouble in criticizing the judges. An uncontroversial principle underlying all sport is that victory should be determined by the relative merits of the competitors performances, which clearly rules out the kind of corruption alleged at Salt Lake City. So all three approaches pass the minimal test of concurring with the intuitive judgment that a gross injustice was done in Salt Lake City. Nonetheless, a better test of these rival theories on judgments about sport is provided by considering how they would deal with slightly changed circumstances and further questions related to the skating controversy. I hope to use these further considerations to show the inadequacy of formalism and conventionalism and to add my voice in support of interpretivism. What if, for instance, the skating community regarded quid pro quo arrangements among judges as an acceptable practice? (They might regard bias and secret deals as an inevitable fact among judges and hope that true

5 Realism in Sport 107 talent will still rise to the top in spite of these backroom machinations.) It is hard to see how a conventionalist, who regards the assent of the relevant athletic community as the ultimate standard for resolving disputes about sport, could consistently criticize a practice that was widely accepted. Interpretivists, in contrast, owe no such allegiance to the prevailing view and would cite the aforementioned principle that victory should be determined by merit in criticizing the corruption. Consider further the possibility of adopting rule changes that would reduce the likelihood of corruption in future skating contests. We could, for instance, require a more detailed accounting by judges of the specific number of points awarded or deducted for each jump. This expedient alone might have been sufficient to prevent the debacle in Salt Lake City. It was already difficult for the French and other judges to justify giving higher marks for overall technical merit to the Russian skaters, but it would have been practically impossible for them to conceal the corruption at work had they had to award higher points for visibly inferior individual jumps by the Russians. Now this proposed change in judging practices might turn out to be inadvisable. Requiring judges to award separate marks for each jump might make the marking process too time-consuming, and it could hamstring judges by not allowing them to use their discretion to make overall judgments about technical merit, something that might not be reducible to the merit of individual jumps. Nonetheless, we have seen enough to establish that the debate between the current judging system and the proposed reform requires the use of arguments to evaluate the rival systems, and the trouble with both formalism and conventionalism is that they are unable to account for the reasoning process that is necessary when debating not only this proposal but also, more generally, any proposal for any change in sport. I have elsewhere criticized Rorty-inspired conventionalism for its inadequate account of change in sport (3). The problem is that conventionalists can only describe what changes occur and lack the resources to evaluate the desirability of these changes. Thus, conventionalists would support the current judging system if the skating community favors it, but they would equally support the new status quo if the community decided to adopt a new system. What they are unable to do is provide reasons to defend one or the other system as superior. Robert Simon has leveled a similar criticism at formalism (11: p. 4). Formalism describes what actions are permitted and required by existing rules, but it lacks the resources to provide justifications for these rules or, consequently, to defend a position on proposed rule changes. In contrast, interpretivists are well positioned to formulate and defend positions on proposed rule changes. They can, that is, refer to principles about the nature and purpose of sport in order to determine whether a proposed change would constitute an improvement. Another issue arising from the Salt Lake City controversy that is pertinent to the debate between rival approaches to judgments about sport pertains to comparative judgments between sports. Although trying to rank-order sports in terms of their overall purity or desirability would be a futile task, it does make sense to compare different sports with respect to specific features. One scale on which figure skating scores quite badly is the heavy reliance of a just outcome on the competence and integrity of judges. Calls by umpires and referees can often have a significant impact on a contest s outcome, but in figure skating the judges marks are its sole determinant. In most sports, athletes have some opportunity to compensate on the playing field for bad decisions by referees and umpires, but in skating

6 108 DIXON this is impossible because the judges make their decision only when the performance is over. Furthermore, although judges in all sports have to make judgment calls, these are typically reports of observed events: whether the tennis ball landed out, whether the goal scorer was offside when the ball was passed, and so on. In contrast, even marks for the technical merit of a skating performance are an evaluation rather than a report, and marks for artistic merit are aesthetic judgments that are even further removed from mere reports of physical events. This added role for the discretion of judges in skating greatly increases the chance of unjust results, whether resulting from poor judgment or corruption. Of course, the very same dependence on judges discretion is a necessary consequence of the nature of skating as a graceful, aesthetically pleasing performance, and this prominent artistic component is also one of the strengths of the sport vis-à-vis sports with more functional goals such as advancing a ball over a goal line or hitting a ball into a designated fair playing area. Nonetheless, it still makes sense to say that the dependence of figure skating on the competence and integrity of judges for just outcomes is a prima facie disadvantage of the sport compared with those whose outcome is more immune to refereeing errors or bias. At the very least, we need to recognize that different sports have rival strengths and weaknesses. The problem for formalism and conventionalism is that they are both unable to support such comparative judgments. They are both descriptive theories that do not provide the resources for evaluating the sports that they explain. Formalism simply describes the rules that govern judging in figure skating, without providing a basis for assessing those rules. Conventionalism fares a little better, in that it can support the judgment that figure skating s enormous reliance on judges is a weakness, as long as the sporting community as a whole endorses this view. What conventionalism cannot do, though, is provide arguments to support the view that this is a weakness. According to conventionalism, what makes the status quo right is just that it is the status quo, not that it is supported by defensible reasons. In contrast, interpretivism can easily sustain the judgment that skating s vulnerability to judges errors and corruption is a prima facie weakness. It can do so precisely because it recognizes the role of principles about the value and purpose of sport in our deliberations about sport. The relevant principle here is the innocuous aforementioned claim that victory should be determined by the relative merits of the competitors performances. Sports that are vulnerable to judging errors and corruption in the way that skating is are more likely to have unjust outcomes than are sports that are more immune. Interpretivism and Realism in Sport Interpretivism has emerged as the most defensible theory on the nature of judgments about sport. The remainder of this article is a defense of interpretivism, reconceptualized to bring out its realist foundations. I begin by giving a more detailed analysis of the interpretivist views of Russell and Simon. The most sophisticated expression to date of interpretivism is John Russell s (9). In contrast with my goal in this article of discussing the more general question of how we resolve debates about sport, Russell s concern is more narrow: the nature of calls by baseball umpires. He focuses in particular on how umpires should resolve hard cases in which it is not clear how the rules of baseball apply. He

7 Realism in Sport 109 transposes to sport Ronald Dworkin s theory of judicial decision: The law consists not only of written statutes, constitutions, and precedents but also of moral and political principles. According to Dworkin, judges must use these principles to guide their decisions when the written law is indeterminate and sometimes even to overrule statutes whose literal application would result in injustice. These principles are binding parts of the law not merely personal preferences to which judges can refer, should they so desire that will often leave only one decision legally open to the judge, even though the written law might be inconclusive. Also, judges use of principles should not be random and piecemeal. On the contrary, judges should apply them consistently to like cases and ensure that different principles are applied consistently with each other, so that the end product is a coherent, just system of laws and decisions. 2 Applying Dworkin s analysis to umpires decisions, Russell suggests that umpires and participants in games lie under legal obligations to decide cases a particular way when the rules are significantly indeterminate.... [W]e might try to understand and interpret the rules of a game, say, baseball, using these principles, to generate a coherent and principled account of the point and purposes that underlie the game, attempting to show the game in its best light. (9: p. 35) To complete his account of calls in baseball, Russell proposes four principles to guide umpires when applying rules to borderline cases. Although Russell s four principles of rule interpretation are all intuitively plausible and persuasively defended, what matters for the purposes of this article is not the content of his principles but, rather, the more general interpretivist claim that we should use a coherent, consistent set of rationally defensible principles concerning the nature and purpose of sport to resolve debates about sport. In his 1999 IAPS presidential address (11), Robert L. Simon made the vital theoretical advance of recognizing and naming the general approach ( interpretivism ), of which Russell s work is one application, and proposing that we adopt it to guide our judgments on a variety of issues in sport. The questions on which, according to Simon, interpretivism can shed light include issues of sportspersonship that go beyond mere obedience to the rules of the game; the status of intentional, professional fouls; and debates about rule changes. Simon cites other work in philosophy of sport that falls into the interpretivist camp, and we can add yet more recent examples. For instance, my critique of Rortian antirealist approaches to change in sport, which I discussed briefly in the preceding section, presupposes the existence of criteria by which we can judge whether a proposed change is desirable. I criticize the Rortian approach for its inability to support criticisms of the status quo, despite the attempts of some of its adherents to propose innovation (3: pp ). In accordance with interpretivism, my arguments for some changes and against others are based on principles such as the claim that skill should play a central role in determining victory. Equally, Cesar Torres s recent critique of penalty shootouts in soccer (12) is based on a related principle about the fundamental purpose of sport: namely, that victory should be determined as far as possible by constitutive, not regulative, skills. Also, M. Andrew Holowchak s recent critique of steroid use in sport (5) cites a principle, which he calls aretism, about the nature of ideal athletic competition.

8 110 DIXON I very much endorse the interpretivist approach to questions about sport. My goal in the remainder of this article is to highlight its most important feature, which is already implicit in Simon s paper: realism in sport, or sporting realism. It is the belief that principles about the nature and purpose of sport (as posited by interpretivists), supplemented where applicable with other factors such as general moral principles and the pertinent rules, dictate the best answer to moral and nonmoral debates about sport. It also includes the belief that these fundamental principles themselves are amenable to rational argument. Realism in sport parallels realism in other areas of philosophy. Moral realists believe in moral truths that lay claim to our assent by virtue of the reasons that support them, not by virtue of being an expression of our personal feelings (subjectivism) or those of any particular group (relativism). Realists in philosophy of science believe that scientific hypotheses purport to give an accurate description of the way the world really is, in contrast to instrumentalists, who regard these hypotheses merely as useful tools for predicting and manipulating the world that make no claim to accurately represent it. Realists in sport believe, in contrast to conventionalists such as adherents of Rorty s approach, that whether a position on a debate about sport be it about a particular issue or about fundamental principles is defensible depends on the quality of the supporting arguments, not on whether it has the assent of the relevant athletic community. Many issues in sport are straightforwardly normative, and in debating them we can use the same moral principles that we apply in other areas of applied ethics, such as medical and business ethics. Issues that fall into this category include questions of gender equity in sport and whether we are justified in paternalistic legislation to protect athletes from danger in sport. Realism in sport includes moral realism, and its proponents believe that the pertinent moral principles often dictate a particular answer on ethical issues in sport. Other issues involve nonmoral value judgments such as whether various rule changes are desirable. Many issues will involve value judgments of both kinds. Consider the debate over the use of performance-enhancing drugs. One aspect of this debate involves purely moral values, in particular the conflict between respect for the autonomy of athletes who wish to use these substances to further their careers and, on the other hand, the paternalistic desire to protect them from harm. Another aspect of the debate, however, moves away from purely moral considerations and turns to questions about the fundamental nature and purpose of sport. This is the status of discussions about the objection that performance-enhancing drugs introduce a determinant of success that is irrelevant to the excellences that athletic competition is designed to measure. Realists in sport believe that relevant moral principles, principles about the nature and purpose of sport, and pertinent background information together determine the most reasonable positions in moral and nonmoral debate about sport. Realism as a Response to Externalism Simon s defense of interpretivism, reflected in his use of the expression interpretive broad internalism, stresses its contrast with externalism. Simon s internalist thesis is that sport has a kind of internal ethic, what might be called an internal morality of sport, that is tightly (some would say conceptually) connected with the idea of athletic competition (11: p. 2). More important, he states that sport has a significant degree of autonomy from the wider society and supports,

9 Realism in Sport 111 stands for, or expresses a set of values of its own which may run counter to the values dominant in the culture (11: p. 2). He contrasts this thesis with the externalist view that sport at best reflects and reinforces prevailing values in broader society. Put more simply, the debate between internalists and externalists is primarily over whether sport is an inherently valuable activity that, by its very nature, presupposes and promotes desirable values, whether or not these values are shared by society at large. Simon presents very persuasive arguments in favor of the internalist thesis that athletic competition is inherently valuable (11: pp. 9-11). Nonetheless, it is not clear that autonomy from the broader society is enough to distinguish Simon s interpretivism from conventionalism, an approach that he rejects. Even a conventionalist could allow for an internal morality of sport, independent of society s morality. This internal morality would be based, consistent with conventionalism s relativistic approach, on the prevailing view in the sporting practice community. So, although Simon identifies conventionalism as a form of externalism, it is actually consistent with internalism. Because conventionalism appears to be a paradigm case of externalism, this calls into question the value of the whole internalism versus externalism distinction. The problem is that the only type of internalism that is consistent with conventionalism is unacceptable. Although conventionalism might be able to sustain an athletic community s independence from the values of society at large, it is unable, as we have seen, to account for the possibility that the dominant view in an athletic community might be mistaken. A far better account of the autonomy of sport comes from the more fundamental autonomy of morality itself, which always provides the resources to criticize the status quo, whether that of society at large or that of an athletic (or any other) practice community. But the autonomy to make both kinds of critique can be explained only on the assumption of moral realism. Moral realism best accounts for the ability of any practice including law and medicine, and not only sport to deviate from the broader morality of society. More important, only moral realism can make sense of critiques (which would automatically be mistaken according to conventionalism) of the prevailing view in an athletic community. Moral realism is thus the key tenet of interpretivism s response to externalism. Indeed, my thesis is that the best form of interpretivism is tantamount to sporting realism. Stressing the realism that is central to and even constitutive of interpretivism puts the debate over interpretivism in the context of the broader realism versus antirealism debate. Especially in light of the doubts I have raised about the entire internalism versus externalism distinction, the most pertinent target for Simon s defense of interpretivism is antirealism, not externalism. Just as Simon generalized from Russell s work on baseball to a general approach (interpretivism) to a whole range of questions about sport, one can view this article as continuing the process of generalization by presenting Simon s view as taking a position on the perennial realism versus antirealism debate. 3 Showing the connection between the debate over interpretivism and this general philosophical issue might be particularly pertinent, given the popularity of the antirealist views of Rorty and MacIntyre in philosophy of sport. Dworkin, Moral Realism, and Sporting Realism The centrality of realism to interpretivism is further supported by the fact that moral realism is also fundamental to the jurisprudence of Ronald Dworkin,

10 112 DIXON whose views are cited extensively by Simon and, especially, by Russell in their defenses of interpretivism. Dworkin s moral realism is most explicit in his theory of constitutional interpretation. He states that U.S. constitutional law requires that judges formulate and apply conceptions of such moral concepts as cruel and unusual punishment, unreasonable search and seizure, and due process of law. These moral concepts are part of the law, and failure to give them due consideration results in mistaken decisions (4: ch. 5). Dworkin s approach, which leads inevitably to judicial activism, would make sense only on the assumption of moral realism. Only if we think that moral judgments can be supported by arguments whose status transcends mere subjective preferences would activism have any plausibility. Its opponents, who instead favor judicial restraint, criticize Dworkin s view precisely because they believe that it gives judges too much discretion in fact, a license to impose their own moral judgments in disregard of the law. One prominent opponent of judicial activism, William Rehnquist, explicitly cites a moral subjectivist view in complaining that moral views are unprovable personal preferences that should play no part in the decisions of an impartial judge (8). A full defense of moral realism is far beyond the scope of this article, but one particular response that Dworkin gives to the skeptical view that moral claims about legal rights are arbitrary is especially relevant for our concerns. Dworkin points out that the entire institution of constitutional law works in a way that appears to presuppose moral realism. High-court justices write detailed opinions to justify their decisions, and legal scholars write elaborate articles defending or criticizing decisions. If these justices and legal scholars believed that moral views are more or less arbitrary statements of individual preferences, why would they take the time to construct such elaborate moral justifications for their positions on issues of constitutional law (4: pp )? A parallel situation exists in philosophy of sport. Philosophers construct careful and detailed arguments to support their views on a variety of moral issues that arise in sport. Why would they bother to do so if they believed that moral judgments were merely subjective feelings? The fact that justices and scholars feel the need to provide arguments to support their positions on constitutional law and ethical issues in sport indicates that they are moral realists who believe that moral judgments, unlike subjective statements of taste, require justifications. Of course, a moral subjectivist could respond that these justices and scholars are, like everyone else who acts as if moral judgments were anything more than reports of subjective feelings, merely mistaken. Although challenging the status quo has been a venerable part of philosophy throughout its history, a heavy burden of proof lies on the shoulders of subjectivists who claim that so many people are victims of such a fundamental delusion. Moral realism is part of realism in sport, but sporting realism applies to all judgments about sport, moral and nonmoral. Just as Dworkin s insistence on the centrality of moral principles to law makes sense only on the assumption of moral realism, so interpretivism is plausible only if we adopt a realist stance toward nonmoral principles about the nature and purpose of sport. That is, those who advance such principles must believe that they are supported by arguments whose force is independent of whether any particular group of persons happens to endorse them. Consequently, they must believe that not all views on debates about sport are on an equal footing. The moral and nonmoral principles that interpretivists advance entail, in at least some cases, a particular position on various issues in sport.

11 Realism in Sport 113 Clarifications About Sporting Realism It is also important to understand what realists in sport do not claim. First, they do not propose that we clumsily impose a single, universal, unchanging view on sporting issues that ignores vital differences between different places and different eras. The analogy with moral realism is again instructive. Moral realists can quite consistently condone the same action in some circumstances while condemning it in others, because the same general moral principles can require different actions in different circumstances. 4 For instance, an austerity program that imposes considerable hardships on people who are dependent on government programs might be justified in times of national emergency such as wars but would be cruel and unjust during times of prosperity. Likewise, strict population controls, with each couple being restricted to one child, might possibly be a justified response to China s population problem, but it would be an unjust restriction of reproductive freedom in countries with sustainable, stable populations. Similarly, sporting realists can take into account relevant differences between countries and periods of history when making moral and nonmoral judgments about sport. Adhering to general moral principles and general principles about the nature and purpose of sport does not prevent sporting realists from judging the same practice differently when the circumstances are significantly different. Second, sporting realists do not believe in the fiction that applying the relevant moral principles and principles about the nature and purpose of sport will produce a clearly correct answer to all debates about sport. Doing justice to all the competing principles, which sometimes pull us in opposite directions, can be an enormously complex task. Yet again, the analogy with moral realism is helpful. Philosophers are only too familiar with perennial moral dilemmas in which compelling moral arguments lead to contradictory conclusions. Think of the abortion debate, in which we must try to simultaneously do justice to respect for reproductive freedom and respect for potential persons. Moral realists do not react to moral dilemmas by throwing up their hands, renouncing the need for principled arguments to support their views, and arbitrarily choosing their positions based on a whim. On the contrary, they realize that it is unsurprising that complex moral debates that have long taxed our limited human understanding continue to resist easy resolution. This complexity, if anything, magnifies the need for carefully constructed arguments, all the while recognizing that strong and persuasive arguments are available to support opposing positions. Realists hope that continuing the dialectic of debate at a high level of argumentation will permit the emergence of increasingly defensible views, ideally (though in practice rarely) culminating in arguments so cogent that they win almost universal allegiance. Similarly, sporting realists are well aware of persistent dilemmas that tax our intellectual resources. A familiar example is the debate over the use of performance-enhancing drugs: Many philosophers have a persistent intuition that it subverts the purpose of athletic competition, but specifying how it differs from other, widely accepted training methods has proven enormously tricky. Like moral realists, though, sporting realists, although they are sanguine about the possibility of ever coming up with solutions to such dilemmas so plausible that they will persuade everyone, react to these dilemmas by trying even harder to construct cogent, principled arguments. They see the dialectic of debate as resulting in increasingly informed, principled, and defensible positions.

12 114 DIXON Third, and finally, sporting realists, although they believe that debate about sport aims at the truth, or at least the most reasonable position, do not claim that they have privileged access to this truth. On the contrary, realism in sport, just like moral realism, is often motivated in part by a painful awareness of the fallibility of our views. It is precisely the realist view that morality is based on principles that are independent of the status quo in any given society that permits moral realists to condemn such practices as slavery, even though during its heyday it quite likely was supported by a majority of people in countries in which it was practiced. Sporting realists are also quite willing to retroactively condemn practices, such as the long exclusion of African American players from Major League Baseball, that at the time were very likely condoned by the majority of the sporting community. Awareness of our past errors tends to instill a sense of humility and the realization that further reflection on moral principles and principles about the nature and purpose of sport might reveal some of our current practices to be unjust or imprudent and some of our current views to be mistaken. In fact, realism, which makes us appeal to external standards to support our views, provides the best possible defense against arrogance, because we cannot retreat to our own incorrigible feelings (subjectivism) or the uncontestable prevailing view in our community or society (relativism). Realism in sport is a theory about the general nature of truth in judgments about sport. It is not a theory about the content of true judgments about sport. Just as two moral realists might support very different normative principles for instance Kantianism and utilitarianism two fellow sporting realists might defend different views on particular issues in sport and even different principles on the nature and purpose of sport. What makes them both realists is their belief that some views and principles are more defensible than others and that what makes some views and principles more defensible than others is the quality of the supporting arguments, not whether they happen to be endorsed by the athletic community, society at large, or any other group of people. Conclusion This article began with a discussion of the judging controversy in the Salt Lake City Olympic figure skating contest. The first philosophical lesson that we derived pertains to the nature of decisions by judges in sport. Drawing on Russell s analogy with judicial decision in law, we saw that we do indeed have good reason to criticize bad decisions, even to the point of considering them null and void in extreme cases. Second, we used the scandal as a test case for deciding among three different theories on our judgments about sport: formalism, conventionalism, and interpretivism. All three easily support the view that the judges decision was unjust, but consideration of two hypothetical extensions of the Salt Lake City controversy and related features the approval of the skating community of the judges decision, proposed changes in the way that scores are awarded, and comparative judgments about different sports revealed the inadequacy of formalism and conventionalism. Only interpretivism provides the resources to challenge the status quo and evaluate proposed changes in sport and comparative judgments about sports. The remainder of this article consisted of the articulation and defense of realism in sport, which is the vital tenet and even the essence of interpretivism.

13 Realism in Sport 115 Only on the assumption of realism can we give our moral and nonmoral judgments about sport the warrant that is lacking in formalism and conventionalism. Indeed, interpretivism, like Dworkin s jurisprudence, lacks any plausibility unless we adopt a realist approach to its moral and nonmoral principles and the judgments we base on them. Whereas Simon presents his defense of interpretivism as a response to externalism, I suggest that interpretivists would do better to regard themselves as realists lined up in opposition to antirealists in sport influenced by Rorty and MacIntyre. Sporting realists must have the courage of their convictions and be prepared to assert that the positions entailed by the most defensible moral principles and principles about the nature and purpose of sport are indeed, to the best of their knowledge, the correct ones, whether or not the majority of the relevant sporting community shares these views. Notes 1 These examples are discussed, respectively, in Loland and McNamee (6: p. 63) and Russell (9: pp ). 2 Dworkin has offered increasingly sophisticated defenses of his theory of judicial decision in several books and numerous articles, but the best source for a succinct account of his position can be found in two chapters ( The Model of Rules and Hard Cases ) of his seminal book Taking Rights Seriously (4). 3 Simon himself is clearly a realist, as evidenced by the following passage: We agree to [principles, premises, or other justifiers] because of the intellectual considerations in their favor rather than find them intellectually favored because we agree. The alternative is simply to privilege the belief of existing communities because they are believed (11: p. 14). My approach differs only in the far greater emphasis I place on realism, which I consider to be fundamental to and even constitutive of interpretivism. 4 See Rachels (7: pp ) for more detail on this defense of moral realism against relativism. As Rachels argues, very different practices in different cultures might result from different factual beliefs or vastly different circumstances, not from different basic moral principles. References 1. Burke, M.D. Drugs in Sport: Have They Practiced Too Hard? A Response to Schneider and Butcher. Journal of the Philosophy of Sport. XXIV, 1997, Dixon, N. On Winning and Athletic Superiority. Journal of the Philosophy of Sport. XXVI, 1999, Dixon, N. Rorty, Performance-Enhancing Drugs, and Change in Sport. Journal of the Philosophy of Sport. XXVIII (1), 2001, Dworkin, R. Taking Rights Seriously. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1977, Holowchak, M.A. Aretism and Pharmacological Ergogenic Aids in Sport: Taking a Shot at the Use of Steroids. Journal of the Philosophy of Sport. XXVII, 2000, Loland, S., and McNamee, M. Fair Play and the Ethos of Sports: An Eclectic Philosophical Framework. Journal of the Philosophy of Sport. 27, 2000, Rachels, J. The Elements of Moral Philosophy. 3rd ed. Boston, MA: McGraw-Hill College, 1999.

14 116 DIXON 8. Rehnquist, W. The Notion of a Living Constitution. Texas Law Review. 54, 1976, Russell, J.S. Are Rules All an Umpire Has to Work With? Journal of the Philosophy of Sport. XXVI, 1999, Russell, J.S. The Concept of a Call in Baseball. Journal of the Philosophy of Sport. XXIV, 1997, Simon, R.L. Internalism and Internal Values in Sport. Journal of the Philosophy of Sport. XXVII, Torres, C. What Counts as Part of a Game? A Look at Skill. Journal of the Philosophy of Sport. XXVII, 2000,

Utilitarianism: For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), pp Reprinted in Moral Luck (CUP, 1981).

Utilitarianism: For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), pp Reprinted in Moral Luck (CUP, 1981). Draft of 3-21- 13 PHIL 202: Core Ethics; Winter 2013 Core Sequence in the History of Ethics, 2011-2013 IV: 19 th and 20 th Century Moral Philosophy David O. Brink Handout #14: Williams, Internalism, and

More information

Positivism A Model Of For System Of Rules

Positivism A Model Of For System Of Rules Positivism A Model Of For System Of Rules Positivism is a model of and for a system of rules, and its central notion of a single fundamental test for law forces us to miss the important standards that

More information

Chapter 2 Ethical Concepts and Ethical Theories: Establishing and Justifying a Moral System

Chapter 2 Ethical Concepts and Ethical Theories: Establishing and Justifying a Moral System Chapter 2 Ethical Concepts and Ethical Theories: Establishing and Justifying a Moral System Ethics and Morality Ethics: greek ethos, study of morality What is Morality? Morality: system of rules for guiding

More information

In Epistemic Relativism, Mark Kalderon defends a view that has become

In Epistemic Relativism, Mark Kalderon defends a view that has become Aporia vol. 24 no. 1 2014 Incoherence in Epistemic Relativism I. Introduction In Epistemic Relativism, Mark Kalderon defends a view that has become increasingly popular across various academic disciplines.

More information

Dworkin on the Rufie of Recognition

Dworkin on the Rufie of Recognition Dworkin on the Rufie of Recognition NANCY SNOW University of Notre Dame In the "Model of Rules I," Ronald Dworkin criticizes legal positivism, especially as articulated in the work of H. L. A. Hart, and

More information

No Love for Singer: The Inability of Preference Utilitarianism to Justify Partial Relationships

No Love for Singer: The Inability of Preference Utilitarianism to Justify Partial Relationships No Love for Singer: The Inability of Preference Utilitarianism to Justify Partial Relationships In his book Practical Ethics, Peter Singer advocates preference utilitarianism, which holds that the right

More information

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View Chapter 98 Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View Lars Leeten Universität Hildesheim Practical thinking is a tricky business. Its aim will never be fulfilled unless influence on practical

More information

Rawls s veil of ignorance excludes all knowledge of likelihoods regarding the social

Rawls s veil of ignorance excludes all knowledge of likelihoods regarding the social Rawls s veil of ignorance excludes all knowledge of likelihoods regarding the social position one ends up occupying, while John Harsanyi s version of the veil tells contractors that they are equally likely

More information

Does the Skeptic Win? A Defense of Moore. I. Moorean Methodology. In A Proof of the External World, Moore argues as follows:

Does the Skeptic Win? A Defense of Moore. I. Moorean Methodology. In A Proof of the External World, Moore argues as follows: Does the Skeptic Win? A Defense of Moore I argue that Moore s famous response to the skeptic should be accepted even by the skeptic. My paper has three main stages. First, I will briefly outline G. E.

More information

(i) Morality is a system; and (ii) It is a system comprised of moral rules and principles.

(i) Morality is a system; and (ii) It is a system comprised of moral rules and principles. Ethics and Morality Ethos (Greek) and Mores (Latin) are terms having to do with custom, habit, and behavior. Ethics is the study of morality. This definition raises two questions: (a) What is morality?

More information

2 FREE CHOICE The heretical thesis of Hobbes is the orthodox position today. So much is this the case that most of the contemporary literature

2 FREE CHOICE The heretical thesis of Hobbes is the orthodox position today. So much is this the case that most of the contemporary literature Introduction The philosophical controversy about free will and determinism is perennial. Like many perennial controversies, this one involves a tangle of distinct but closely related issues. Thus, the

More information

REASON AND PRACTICAL-REGRET. Nate Wahrenberger, College of William and Mary

REASON AND PRACTICAL-REGRET. Nate Wahrenberger, College of William and Mary 1 REASON AND PRACTICAL-REGRET Nate Wahrenberger, College of William and Mary Abstract: Christine Korsgaard argues that a practical reason (that is, a reason that counts in favor of an action) must motivate

More information

Well-Being, Time, and Dementia. Jennifer Hawkins. University of Toronto

Well-Being, Time, and Dementia. Jennifer Hawkins. University of Toronto Well-Being, Time, and Dementia Jennifer Hawkins University of Toronto Philosophers often discuss what makes a life as a whole good. More significantly, it is sometimes assumed that beneficence, which is

More information

A Case against Subjectivism: A Reply to Sobel

A Case against Subjectivism: A Reply to Sobel A Case against Subjectivism: A Reply to Sobel Abstract Subjectivists are committed to the claim that desires provide us with reasons for action. Derek Parfit argues that subjectivists cannot account for

More information

Are There Reasons to Be Rational?

Are There Reasons to Be Rational? Are There Reasons to Be Rational? Olav Gjelsvik, University of Oslo The thesis. Among people writing about rationality, few people are more rational than Wlodek Rabinowicz. But are there reasons for being

More information

Rawls, rationality, and responsibility: Why we should not treat our endowments as morally arbitrary

Rawls, rationality, and responsibility: Why we should not treat our endowments as morally arbitrary Rawls, rationality, and responsibility: Why we should not treat our endowments as morally arbitrary OLIVER DUROSE Abstract John Rawls is primarily known for providing his own argument for how political

More information

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism Mathais Sarrazin J.L. Mackie s Error Theory postulates that all normative claims are false. It does this based upon his denial of moral

More information

-- The search text of this PDF is generated from uncorrected OCR text.

-- The search text of this PDF is generated from uncorrected OCR text. Citation: 21 Isr. L. Rev. 113 1986 Content downloaded/printed from HeinOnline (http://heinonline.org) Sun Jan 11 12:34:09 2015 -- Your use of this HeinOnline PDF indicates your acceptance of HeinOnline's

More information

Chapter 3 PHILOSOPHICAL ETHICS AND BUSINESS CHAPTER OBJECTIVES. After exploring this chapter, you will be able to:

Chapter 3 PHILOSOPHICAL ETHICS AND BUSINESS CHAPTER OBJECTIVES. After exploring this chapter, you will be able to: Chapter 3 PHILOSOPHICAL ETHICS AND BUSINESS MGT604 CHAPTER OBJECTIVES After exploring this chapter, you will be able to: 1. Explain the ethical framework of utilitarianism. 2. Describe how utilitarian

More information

Zdenko Kodelja HOW TO UNDERSTAND EQUITY IN HIGHER EDUCATION? (Draft)

Zdenko Kodelja HOW TO UNDERSTAND EQUITY IN HIGHER EDUCATION? (Draft) Zdenko Kodelja HOW TO UNDERSTAND EQUITY IN HIGHER EDUCATION? (Draft) The question How to understand equity in higher education? presupposes that it is not clear enough what exactly equity means. If this

More information

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy Res Cogitans Volume 5 Issue 1 Article 20 6-4-2014 Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy Kevin Harriman Lewis & Clark College Follow this and additional works at: http://commons.pacificu.edu/rescogitans

More information

R. Keith Sawyer: Social Emergence. Societies as Complex Systems. Cambridge University Press

R. Keith Sawyer: Social Emergence. Societies as Complex Systems. Cambridge University Press R. Keith Sawyer: Social Emergence. Societies as Complex Systems. Cambridge University Press. 2005. This is an ambitious book. Keith Sawyer attempts to show that his new emergence paradigm provides a means

More information

In Defense of Pure Reason: A Rationalist Account of A Priori Justification, by Laurence BonJour. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,

In Defense of Pure Reason: A Rationalist Account of A Priori Justification, by Laurence BonJour. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, Book Reviews 1 In Defense of Pure Reason: A Rationalist Account of A Priori Justification, by Laurence BonJour. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998. Pp. xiv + 232. H/b 37.50, $54.95, P/b 13.95,

More information

2014 Examination Report 2014 Extended Investigation GA 2: Critical Thinking Test GENERAL COMMENTS

2014 Examination Report 2014 Extended Investigation GA 2: Critical Thinking Test GENERAL COMMENTS 2014 Extended Investigation GA 2: Critical Thinking Test GENERAL COMMENTS The Extended Investigation Critical Thinking Test assesses the ability of students to produce arguments, and to analyse and assess

More information

Brian Leiter (ed), Objectivity in Law and Morals, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001, xi pp, hb

Brian Leiter (ed), Objectivity in Law and Morals, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001, xi pp, hb Brian Leiter (ed), Objectivity in Law and Morals, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001, xi + 354 pp, hb 42.50. Legal philosophy since the 1960s has been gradually moving away from discussion of

More information

Law and Authority. An unjust law is not a law

Law and Authority. An unjust law is not a law Law and Authority An unjust law is not a law The statement an unjust law is not a law is often treated as a summary of how natural law theorists approach the question of whether a law is valid or not.

More information

KANTIAN ETHICS (Dan Gaskill)

KANTIAN ETHICS (Dan Gaskill) KANTIAN ETHICS (Dan Gaskill) German philosopher Immanuel Kant (1724-1804) was an opponent of utilitarianism. Basic Summary: Kant, unlike Mill, believed that certain types of actions (including murder,

More information

* Dalhousie Law School, LL.B. anticipated Interpretation and Legal Theory. Andrei Marmor Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992, 193 pp.

* Dalhousie Law School, LL.B. anticipated Interpretation and Legal Theory. Andrei Marmor Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992, 193 pp. 330 Interpretation and Legal Theory Andrei Marmor Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992, 193 pp. Reviewed by Lawrence E. Thacker* Interpretation may be defined roughly as the process of determining the meaning

More information

The Paradox of the stone and two concepts of omnipotence

The Paradox of the stone and two concepts of omnipotence Filo Sofija Nr 30 (2015/3), s. 239-246 ISSN 1642-3267 Jacek Wojtysiak John Paul II Catholic University of Lublin The Paradox of the stone and two concepts of omnipotence Introduction The history of science

More information

A Contractualist Reply

A Contractualist Reply A Contractualist Reply The Harvard community has made this article openly available. Please share how this access benefits you. Your story matters Citation Scanlon, T. M. 2008. A Contractualist Reply.

More information

If Everyone Does It, Then You Can Too Charlie Melman

If Everyone Does It, Then You Can Too Charlie Melman 27 If Everyone Does It, Then You Can Too Charlie Melman Abstract: I argue that the But Everyone Does That (BEDT) defense can have significant exculpatory force in a legal sense, but not a moral sense.

More information

PHL271 Handout 2: Hobbes on Law and Political Authority. Many philosophers of law treat Hobbes as the grandfather of legal positivism.

PHL271 Handout 2: Hobbes on Law and Political Authority. Many philosophers of law treat Hobbes as the grandfather of legal positivism. PHL271 Handout 2: Hobbes on Law and Political Authority 1 Background: Legal Positivism Many philosophers of law treat Hobbes as the grandfather of legal positivism. Legal Positivism (Rough Version): whether

More information

Is euthanasia morally permissible? What is the relationship between patient autonomy,

Is euthanasia morally permissible? What is the relationship between patient autonomy, Course Syllabus PHILOSOPHY 433 Instructor: Doran Smolkin, Ph. D. doran.smolkin@kpu.ca or doran.smolkin@ubc.ca Course Description: Is euthanasia morally permissible? What is the relationship between patient

More information

CONVENTIONALISM AND NORMATIVITY

CONVENTIONALISM AND NORMATIVITY 1 CONVENTIONALISM AND NORMATIVITY TORBEN SPAAK We have seen (in Section 3) that Hart objects to Austin s command theory of law, that it cannot account for the normativity of law, and that what is missing

More information

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006 In Defense of Radical Empiricism Joseph Benjamin Riegel A thesis submitted to the faculty of the University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of

More information

Positivism, Natural Law, and Disestablishment: Some Questions Raised by MacCormick's Moralistic Amoralism

Positivism, Natural Law, and Disestablishment: Some Questions Raised by MacCormick's Moralistic Amoralism Valparaiso University Law Review Volume 20 Number 1 pp.55-60 Fall 1985 Positivism, Natural Law, and Disestablishment: Some Questions Raised by MacCormick's Moralistic Amoralism Joseph M. Boyle Jr. Recommended

More information

What should I believe? What should I believe when people disagree with me?

What should I believe? What should I believe when people disagree with me? What should I believe? What should I believe when people disagree with me? Imagine that you are at a horse track with a friend. Two horses, Whitey and Blacky, are competing for the lead down the stretch.

More information

Legal positivism represents a view about the nature of law. It states that

Legal positivism represents a view about the nature of law. It states that Legal Positivism A N I NTRODUCTION Polycarp Ikuenobe Legal positivism represents a view about the nature of law. It states that there is no necessary or conceptual connection between law and morality and

More information

Andrea Westlund, in Selflessness and Responsibility for Self, argues

Andrea Westlund, in Selflessness and Responsibility for Self, argues Aporia vol. 28 no. 2 2018 Phenomenology of Autonomy in Westlund and Wheelis Andrea Westlund, in Selflessness and Responsibility for Self, argues that for one to be autonomous or responsible for self one

More information

EXECUTION AND INVENTION: DEATH PENALTY DISCOURSE IN EARLY RABBINIC. Press Pp $ ISBN:

EXECUTION AND INVENTION: DEATH PENALTY DISCOURSE IN EARLY RABBINIC. Press Pp $ ISBN: EXECUTION AND INVENTION: DEATH PENALTY DISCOURSE IN EARLY RABBINIC AND CHRISTIAN CULTURES. By Beth A. Berkowitz. Oxford University Press 2006. Pp. 349. $55.00. ISBN: 0-195-17919-6. Beth Berkowitz argues

More information

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism? Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism? Author: Terence Rajivan Edward, University of Manchester. Abstract. In the sixth chapter of The View from Nowhere, Thomas Nagel attempts to identify a form of idealism.

More information

1) What is the universal structure of a topicality violation in the 1NC, shell version?

1) What is the universal structure of a topicality violation in the 1NC, shell version? Varsity Debate Coaching Training Course ASSESSMENT: KEY Name: A) Interpretation (or Definition) B) Violation C) Standards D) Voting Issue School: 1) What is the universal structure of a topicality violation

More information

A Review on What Is This Thing Called Ethics? by Christopher Bennett * ** 1

A Review on What Is This Thing Called Ethics? by Christopher Bennett * ** 1 310 Book Review Book Review ISSN (Print) 1225-4924, ISSN (Online) 2508-3104 Catholic Theology and Thought, Vol. 79, July 2017 http://dx.doi.org/10.21731/ctat.2017.79.310 A Review on What Is This Thing

More information

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory Western University Scholarship@Western 2015 Undergraduate Awards The Undergraduate Awards 2015 Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory David Hakim Western University, davidhakim266@gmail.com

More information

Class #14: October 13 Gödel s Platonism

Class #14: October 13 Gödel s Platonism Philosophy 405: Knowledge, Truth and Mathematics Fall 2010 Hamilton College Russell Marcus Class #14: October 13 Gödel s Platonism I. The Continuum Hypothesis and Its Independence The continuum problem

More information

AN OUTLINE OF CRITICAL THINKING

AN OUTLINE OF CRITICAL THINKING AN OUTLINE OF CRITICAL THINKING LEVELS OF INQUIRY 1. Information: correct understanding of basic information. 2. Understanding basic ideas: correct understanding of the basic meaning of key ideas. 3. Probing:

More information

Templates for Research Paper

Templates for Research Paper Templates for Research Paper Templates for introducing what they say A number of have recently suggested that. It has become common today to dismiss. In their recent work, have offered harsh critiques

More information

Philosophy of Science. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

Philosophy of Science. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology Philosophy of Science Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology Philosophical Theology 1 (TH5) Aug. 15 Intro to Philosophical Theology; Logic Aug. 22 Truth & Epistemology Aug. 29 Metaphysics

More information

Notes on Moore and Parker, Chapter 12: Moral, Legal and Aesthetic Reasoning

Notes on Moore and Parker, Chapter 12: Moral, Legal and Aesthetic Reasoning Notes on Moore and Parker, Chapter 12: Moral, Legal and Aesthetic Reasoning The final chapter of Moore and Parker s text is devoted to how we might apply critical reasoning in certain philosophical contexts.

More information

III. RULES OF POLICY (TEAM) DEBATE. A. General

III. RULES OF POLICY (TEAM) DEBATE. A. General III. RULES OF POLICY (TEAM) DEBATE A. General 1. All debates must be based on the current National High School Debate resolution chosen under the auspices of the National Topic Selection Committee of the

More information

Final Paper. May 13, 2015

Final Paper. May 13, 2015 24.221 Final Paper May 13, 2015 Determinism states the following: given the state of the universe at time t 0, denoted S 0, and the conjunction of the laws of nature, L, the state of the universe S at

More information

The Conflict Between Authority and Autonomy from Robert Wolff, In Defense of Anarchism (1970)

The Conflict Between Authority and Autonomy from Robert Wolff, In Defense of Anarchism (1970) The Conflict Between Authority and Autonomy from Robert Wolff, In Defense of Anarchism (1970) 1. The Concept of Authority Politics is the exercise of the power of the state, or the attempt to influence

More information

Stem Cell Research on Embryonic Persons is Just

Stem Cell Research on Embryonic Persons is Just Stem Cell Research on Embryonic Persons is Just Abstract: I argue that embryonic stem cell research is fair to the embryo even on the assumption that the embryo has attained full personhood and an attendant

More information

Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000)

Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000) Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000) One of the advantages traditionally claimed for direct realist theories of perception over indirect realist theories is that the

More information

Luck, Rationality, and Explanation: A Reply to Elga s Lucky to Be Rational. Joshua Schechter. Brown University

Luck, Rationality, and Explanation: A Reply to Elga s Lucky to Be Rational. Joshua Schechter. Brown University Luck, Rationality, and Explanation: A Reply to Elga s Lucky to Be Rational Joshua Schechter Brown University I Introduction What is the epistemic significance of discovering that one of your beliefs depends

More information

Shafer-Landau's defense against Blackburn's supervenience argument

Shafer-Landau's defense against Blackburn's supervenience argument University of Gothenburg Department of Philosophy, Linguistics and Theory of Science Shafer-Landau's defense against Blackburn's supervenience argument Author: Anna Folland Supervisor: Ragnar Francén Olinder

More information

What is the "Social" in "Social Coherence?" Commentary on Nelson Tebbe's Religious Freedom in an Egalitarian Age

What is the Social in Social Coherence? Commentary on Nelson Tebbe's Religious Freedom in an Egalitarian Age Journal of Civil Rights and Economic Development Volume 31 Issue 1 Volume 31, Summer 2018, Issue 1 Article 5 June 2018 What is the "Social" in "Social Coherence?" Commentary on Nelson Tebbe's Religious

More information

Panel: Mr. Peter Leaver QC (United Kingdom), President; Mr. Hans Nater (Switzerland); Mr. Olli Rauste (Finland)

Panel: Mr. Peter Leaver QC (United Kingdom), President; Mr. Hans Nater (Switzerland); Mr. Olli Rauste (Finland) Tribunal Arbitral du Sport Court of Arbitration for Sport Arbitration CAS ad hoc Division (O.G. Salt Lake City) 02/007, Korean Olympic Committee (KOC) / International Skating Union (ISU), Panel: Mr. Peter

More information

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology. Topic 6: Theories of Justification: Foundationalism versus Coherentism. Part 2: Susan Haack s Foundherentist Approach

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology. Topic 6: Theories of Justification: Foundationalism versus Coherentism. Part 2: Susan Haack s Foundherentist Approach Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 6: Theories of Justification: Foundationalism versus Coherentism Part 2: Susan Haack s Foundherentist Approach Susan Haack, "A Foundherentist Theory of Empirical Justification"

More information

Louisiana Law Review. Cheney C. Joseph Jr. Louisiana State University Law Center. Volume 35 Number 5 Special Issue Repository Citation

Louisiana Law Review. Cheney C. Joseph Jr. Louisiana State University Law Center. Volume 35 Number 5 Special Issue Repository Citation Louisiana Law Review Volume 35 Number 5 Special Issue 1975 ON GUILT, RESPONSIBILITY AND PUNISHMENT. By Alf Ross. Translated from Danish by Alastair Hannay and Thomas E. Sheahan. London, Stevens and Sons

More information

What Lurks Beneath the Integrity Objection. Bernard Williams s alienation and integrity arguments against consequentialism have

What Lurks Beneath the Integrity Objection. Bernard Williams s alienation and integrity arguments against consequentialism have What Lurks Beneath the Integrity Objection Bernard Williams s alienation and integrity arguments against consequentialism have served as the point of departure for much of the most interesting work that

More information

1 Hans Jonas, The Imperative of Responsibility: In Search of an Ethics for the Technological Age (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984), 1-10.

1 Hans Jonas, The Imperative of Responsibility: In Search of an Ethics for the Technological Age (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984), 1-10. Introduction This book seeks to provide a metaethical analysis of the responsibility ethics of two of its prominent defenders: H. Richard Niebuhr and Emmanuel Levinas. In any ethical writings, some use

More information

A theory of adjudication is a theory primarily about what judges do when they decide cases in courts of law.

A theory of adjudication is a theory primarily about what judges do when they decide cases in courts of law. SLIDE 1 Theories of Adjudication: Legal Formalism A theory of adjudication is a theory primarily about what judges do when they decide cases in courts of law. American legal realism was a legal movement,

More information

Deontology, Rationality, and Agent-Centered Restrictions

Deontology, Rationality, and Agent-Centered Restrictions Florida Philosophical Review Volume X, Issue 1, Summer 2010 75 Deontology, Rationality, and Agent-Centered Restrictions Brandon Hogan, University of Pittsburgh I. Introduction Deontological ethical theories

More information

Common Morality: Deciding What to Do 1

Common Morality: Deciding What to Do 1 Common Morality: Deciding What to Do 1 By Bernard Gert (1934-2011) [Page 15] Analogy between Morality and Grammar Common morality is complex, but it is less complex than the grammar of a language. Just

More information

Legal Positivism: the Separation and Identification theses are true.

Legal Positivism: the Separation and Identification theses are true. PHL271 Handout 3: Hart on Legal Positivism 1 Legal Positivism Revisited HLA Hart was a highly sophisticated philosopher. His defence of legal positivism marked a watershed in 20 th Century philosophy of

More information

From: Michael Huemer, Ethical Intuitionism (2005)

From: Michael Huemer, Ethical Intuitionism (2005) From: Michael Huemer, Ethical Intuitionism (2005) 214 L rsmkv!rs ks syxssm! finds Sally funny, but later decides he was mistaken about her funniness when the audience merely groans.) It seems, then, that

More information

Freedom's Law: The Moral Reading of the American Constitution.

Freedom's Law: The Moral Reading of the American Constitution. Freedom's Law: The Moral Reading of the American Constitution. By Ronald Dworkin. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1996.389 pp. Kenneth Einar Himma University of Washington In Freedom's Law, Ronald

More information

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg 1 In Search of the Ontological Argument Richard Oxenberg Abstract We can attend to the logic of Anselm's ontological argument, and amuse ourselves for a few hours unraveling its convoluted word-play, or

More information

Well-Being, Disability, and the Mere-Difference Thesis. Jennifer Hawkins Duke University

Well-Being, Disability, and the Mere-Difference Thesis. Jennifer Hawkins Duke University This paper is in the very early stages of development. Large chunks are still simply detailed outlines. I can, of course, fill these in verbally during the session, but I apologize in advance for its current

More information

THE SEPARATION OF LAW AND MORALS

THE SEPARATION OF LAW AND MORALS Brigham Young University BYU ScholarsArchive All Faculty Publications 1986-11-28 THE SEPARATION OF LAW AND MORALS Noel B. Reynolds Brigham Young University - Provo, nbr@byu.edu Follow this and additional

More information

ALTERNATIVE SELF-DEFEAT ARGUMENTS: A REPLY TO MIZRAHI

ALTERNATIVE SELF-DEFEAT ARGUMENTS: A REPLY TO MIZRAHI ALTERNATIVE SELF-DEFEAT ARGUMENTS: A REPLY TO MIZRAHI Michael HUEMER ABSTRACT: I address Moti Mizrahi s objections to my use of the Self-Defeat Argument for Phenomenal Conservatism (PC). Mizrahi contends

More information

PRESS DEFINITION AND THE RELIGION ANALOGY

PRESS DEFINITION AND THE RELIGION ANALOGY PRESS DEFINITION AND THE RELIGION ANALOGY RonNell Andersen Jones In her Article, Press Exceptionalism, 1 Professor Sonja R. West urges the Court to differentiate a specially protected sub-category of the

More information

TWO APPROACHES TO INSTRUMENTAL RATIONALITY

TWO APPROACHES TO INSTRUMENTAL RATIONALITY TWO APPROACHES TO INSTRUMENTAL RATIONALITY AND BELIEF CONSISTENCY BY JOHN BRUNERO JOURNAL OF ETHICS & SOCIAL PHILOSOPHY VOL. 1, NO. 1 APRIL 2005 URL: WWW.JESP.ORG COPYRIGHT JOHN BRUNERO 2005 I N SPEAKING

More information

APPENDIX A NOTE ON JOHN PAUL II, VERITATIS SPLENDOR (1993) The Encyclical is primarily a theological document, addressed to the Pope's fellow Roman

APPENDIX A NOTE ON JOHN PAUL II, VERITATIS SPLENDOR (1993) The Encyclical is primarily a theological document, addressed to the Pope's fellow Roman APPENDIX A NOTE ON JOHN PAUL II, VERITATIS SPLENDOR (1993) The Encyclical is primarily a theological document, addressed to the Pope's fellow Roman Catholics rather than to men and women of good will generally.

More information

Course Syllabus. Course Description: Objectives for this course include: PHILOSOPHY 333

Course Syllabus. Course Description: Objectives for this course include: PHILOSOPHY 333 Course Syllabus PHILOSOPHY 333 Instructor: Doran Smolkin, Ph. D. doran.smolkin@ubc.ca or doran.smolkin@kpu.ca Course Description: Is euthanasia morally permissible? What is the relationship between patient

More information

PROSPECTS FOR A JAMESIAN EXPRESSIVISM 1 JEFF KASSER

PROSPECTS FOR A JAMESIAN EXPRESSIVISM 1 JEFF KASSER PROSPECTS FOR A JAMESIAN EXPRESSIVISM 1 JEFF KASSER In order to take advantage of Michael Slater s presence as commentator, I want to display, as efficiently as I am able, some major similarities and differences

More information

This document consists of 10 printed pages.

This document consists of 10 printed pages. Cambridge International Examinations Cambridge International Advanced Level THINKING SKILLS 9694/43 Paper 4 Applied Reasoning MARK SCHEME imum Mark: 50 Published This mark scheme is published as an aid

More information

RESPONSE TO ADAM KOLBER S PUNISHMENT AND MORAL RISK

RESPONSE TO ADAM KOLBER S PUNISHMENT AND MORAL RISK RESPONSE TO ADAM KOLBER S PUNISHMENT AND MORAL RISK Chelsea Rosenthal* I. INTRODUCTION Adam Kolber argues in Punishment and Moral Risk that retributivists may be unable to justify criminal punishment,

More information

Relativism and Subjectivism. The Denial of Objective Ethical Standards

Relativism and Subjectivism. The Denial of Objective Ethical Standards Relativism and Subjectivism The Denial of Objective Ethical Standards Starting with a counter argument 1.The universe operates according to laws 2.The universe can be investigated through the use of both

More information

To link to this article:

To link to this article: This article was downloaded by: [University of Chicago Library] On: 24 May 2013, At: 08:10 Publisher: Routledge Informa Ltd Registered in England and Wales Registered Number: 1072954 Registered office:

More information

Practical Rationality and Ethics. Basic Terms and Positions

Practical Rationality and Ethics. Basic Terms and Positions Practical Rationality and Ethics Basic Terms and Positions Practical reasons and moral ought Reasons are given in answer to the sorts of questions ethics seeks to answer: What should I do? How should I

More information

Consider... Ethical Egoism. Rachels. Consider... Theories about Human Motivations

Consider... Ethical Egoism. Rachels. Consider... Theories about Human Motivations Consider.... Ethical Egoism Rachels Suppose you hire an attorney to defend your interests in a dispute with your neighbor. In a court of law, the assumption is that in pursuing each client s interest,

More information

Attraction, Description, and the Desire-Satisfaction Theory of Welfare

Attraction, Description, and the Desire-Satisfaction Theory of Welfare Attraction, Description, and the Desire-Satisfaction Theory of Welfare The desire-satisfaction theory of welfare says that what is basically good for a subject what benefits him in the most fundamental,

More information

CHAPTER 2 Test Bank MULTIPLE CHOICE

CHAPTER 2 Test Bank MULTIPLE CHOICE CHAPTER 2 Test Bank MULTIPLE CHOICE 1. A structured set of principles that defines what is moral is referred to as: a. a norm system b. an ethical system c. a morality guide d. a principled guide ANS:

More information

Philosophy of Ethics Philosophy of Aesthetics. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

Philosophy of Ethics Philosophy of Aesthetics. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology Philosophy of Ethics Philosophy of Aesthetics Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology Philosophical Theology 1 (TH5) Aug. 15 Intro to Philosophical Theology; Logic Aug. 22 Truth & Epistemology

More information

World Religions. These subject guidelines should be read in conjunction with the Introduction, Outline and Details all essays sections of this guide.

World Religions. These subject guidelines should be read in conjunction with the Introduction, Outline and Details all essays sections of this guide. World Religions These subject guidelines should be read in conjunction with the Introduction, Outline and Details all essays sections of this guide. Overview Extended essays in world religions provide

More information

FIRST STUDY. The Existential Dialectical Basic Assumption of Kierkegaard s Analysis of Despair

FIRST STUDY. The Existential Dialectical Basic Assumption of Kierkegaard s Analysis of Despair FIRST STUDY The Existential Dialectical Basic Assumption of Kierkegaard s Analysis of Despair I 1. In recent decades, our understanding of the philosophy of philosophers such as Kant or Hegel has been

More information

Faults and Mathematical Disagreement

Faults and Mathematical Disagreement 45 Faults and Mathematical Disagreement María Ponte ILCLI. University of the Basque Country mariaponteazca@gmail.com Abstract: My aim in this paper is to analyse the notion of mathematical disagreements

More information

BELIEF POLICIES, by Paul Helm. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, Pp. xiii and 226. $54.95 (Cloth).

BELIEF POLICIES, by Paul Helm. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, Pp. xiii and 226. $54.95 (Cloth). BELIEF POLICIES, by Paul Helm. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1994. Pp. xiii and 226. $54.95 (Cloth). TRENTON MERRICKS, Virginia Commonwealth University Faith and Philosophy 13 (1996): 449-454

More information

The Oxford Handbook of Epistemology

The Oxford Handbook of Epistemology Oxford Scholarship Online You are looking at 1-10 of 21 items for: booktitle : handbook phimet The Oxford Handbook of Epistemology Paul K. Moser (ed.) Item type: book DOI: 10.1093/0195130057.001.0001 This

More information

Ayer and Quine on the a priori

Ayer and Quine on the a priori Ayer and Quine on the a priori November 23, 2004 1 The problem of a priori knowledge Ayer s book is a defense of a thoroughgoing empiricism, not only about what is required for a belief to be justified

More information

Henrik Ahlenius Department of Philosophy ETHICS & RESEARCH

Henrik Ahlenius Department of Philosophy ETHICS & RESEARCH Henrik Ahlenius Department of Philosophy henrik.ahlenius@philosophy.su.se ETHICS & RESEARCH Why a course like this? Tell you what the rules are Tell you to follow these rules Tell you to follow some other

More information

Writing Module Three: Five Essential Parts of Argument Cain Project (2008)

Writing Module Three: Five Essential Parts of Argument Cain Project (2008) Writing Module Three: Five Essential Parts of Argument Cain Project (2008) Module by: The Cain Project in Engineering and Professional Communication. E-mail the author Summary: This module presents techniques

More information

Index of Templates from They Say, I Say by Gerald Graff and Cathy Birkenstein. Introducing What They Say. Introducing Standard Views

Index of Templates from They Say, I Say by Gerald Graff and Cathy Birkenstein. Introducing What They Say. Introducing Standard Views Index of Templates from They Say, I Say by Gerald Graff and Cathy Birkenstein. Introducing What They Say A number of sociologists have recently suggested that X s work has several fundamental problems.

More information

Religious Assent in Roman Catholicism. One of the many tensions in the Catholic Church today, and perhaps the most

Religious Assent in Roman Catholicism. One of the many tensions in the Catholic Church today, and perhaps the most One of the many tensions in the Catholic Church today, and perhaps the most fundamental tension, is that concerning whether when and how the Church manifests her teaching authority in such a way as to

More information

Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly *

Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly * Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly * Ralph Wedgwood 1 Two views of practical reason Suppose that you are faced with several different options (that is, several ways in which you might act in a

More information

Plantinga, Pluralism and Justified Religious Belief

Plantinga, Pluralism and Justified Religious Belief Plantinga, Pluralism and Justified Religious Belief David Basinger (5850 total words in this text) (705 reads) According to Alvin Plantinga, it has been widely held since the Enlightenment that if theistic

More information

Explanatory Indispensability and Deliberative Indispensability: Against Enoch s Analogy Alex Worsnip University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill

Explanatory Indispensability and Deliberative Indispensability: Against Enoch s Analogy Alex Worsnip University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill Explanatory Indispensability and Deliberative Indispensability: Against Enoch s Analogy Alex Worsnip University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill Forthcoming in Thought please cite published version In

More information

Ethics is subjective.

Ethics is subjective. Introduction Scientific Method and Research Ethics Ethical Theory Greg Bognar Stockholm University September 22, 2017 Ethics is subjective. If ethics is subjective, then moral claims are subjective in

More information