SCHLEIERMACHER'S HERMENEUTICS AND THE MYTH OF THE GIVEN

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "SCHLEIERMACHER'S HERMENEUTICS AND THE MYTH OF THE GIVEN"

Transcription

1 Vol. XXXIV No. 2, Winter, SCHLEIERMACHER'S HERMENEUTICS AND THE MYTH OF THE GIVEN CORNEL WEST Friedrich Schleiermacher is the father of modern philosophical hermeneutics. His Copernican Revolution in hermeneutics shifted the focus from understanding texts to the process of understanding itself. Instead of providing general rules for biblical and philological exegesis, he asked a more fundamental question: How is understanding possible? By separating the applicatory function of interpretation from the act of understanding, Schleiermacher created the new, independent domain of theoretical inquiry into the necessary and sufficient conditions for the possibility of understanding. In this essay, I shall argue that Schleiermacher's valiant attempt to provide an acceptable hermeneutical theory to overcome the distance between speakers and listeners, readers and authors is unsuccessful owing to his acceptance of The Myth of the Given. The Myth of the Given is a philosophical doctrine held most notably by Cartesian and Kantian thinkers. Its rests upon a particular view of langauge and the relation of language to consciousness and awareness. I will try to show that The Myth of the Given is untenable by sketching three contemporary attacks on it-those of Martin Heidegger, Jacques Derrida and Ludwig Wittgenstein. Lastly, I will suggest implications these attacks have for the future of philosophy and theology. A. The Myth of the Given in Modern Philosophy Before we examine the role of The Myth of the Given in Schleiermacher's hermeneutics, it is essential to put forward a clear definition of this Myth and illustrate briefly how it functions in the epistemologica! viewpoints of Cartesian and Kantian thinkers. The Myth of the Given consists of the following epistemologica! assumption: the justification of our employment of concepts, utterance of sentences, or intelligent use of words rests on nonlinguistic awareness, that is, on special, felt, incommunicable qualities. The Myth of the Given is based on the privileged status of certain states of consciousness, representations or assertions as species of knowledge unmediated by language. Descartes is an appropriate thinker to begin with in order to see the modern philosophical legitimation of The Myth of the Given. Descartes' breakthrough was neither, as is commonly believed, to establish the cogito as axiomatic evidence for the certainty of knowledgeclaims, not to prove indubitability as the mark of self-consciousness. Rather, his innovation -and the initiation of his version of The Myth of the Given-was to transform what previous philosophers had meant by sensations and to widen the scope of what they believed the notion of thought to be. Descartes writes, Thought (cogitatio) is a word that covers everything that exists in us in such a way that we are immediately aware of it. Thus, ail the operations of will, intellect, imagination, and of the sense are thoughts.^ By subsuming sensations and ideas under the rubric, cogitatio, he represents the assimilationist tradition, namely, the assimilation of ideas to sensations, language to consciousness, and words to experience, giving privileged status to the latter as well as the basis for the former. Cornel West is Assistant Professor of Philosophy of Religion at Union Theological Seminary, New York.

2 72 UNION SEMINARY QUARTERLY REVIEW This privileged status and basis are seen clearly in Descartes' perennial attempt to distinguish between ideas and the sensory stimulus which activate them. In his famous arguments with Hobbes and Gassendi, he distinguishes between ideas and mental images, concepts and mere pictures in the brain-all viewed as species of cogitatio. For Descartes, rational defense of our employment of concepts, utterance of sentences or intelligent use of words presupposes mental images, pictures in the brain, or similar kinds of special, felt, incommunicable qualities. Cartesian epistemology rests on this kind of pre-linguistic, preconceptual consciousness which supports valid knowledge-claims. In this way, it thus subscribes to The Myth of the Given. The empiricists-locke, Berkeley and Hume-are Cartesian thinkers to the extent that they assume people have self-authenticating nonlinguistic episodes of knowledge. These episodes consists of primordial, non-problematic features of immediate experience, such as Lockean ideas of sensation and Humean impressions. Such features constitute, for them, a kind of awareness which is prior to, and basis for, our ability to employ concepts, utter sentences or intelligently use words. Kant succumbs to The Myth of the Given and upholds the assimilationist tradition by distinguishing between intuitions given by sense and concepts contributed by intellect. Kant calls both "representations" (Vorstellungen). Intuitions are more immediate and privileged than concepts since, he implies, we can intuit a manifold of diversity in need of conceptual unity. But how do we know that a manifold is one of diversity without concepts? Kant claims that we are conscious only of synthesized intuitions, therefore we can know only a synthesized, unified manifold. On what grounds, then, can we hold that a manifold is one of diversity prior to our ability to employ concepts, utter sentences, or intelligently use words? Kant says that "intuitions without concepts are blind," yet it seems that they manage to "see" enough to inform us about that upon which concepts work, namely manifolds of diversity. This intuitive information can be attributed only to a kind of immediate awareness or privileged representation without concepts - a possibility Kant cannot, yet would like to, avoid. The central fault of the Cartesian and Kantian traditions of assimilationism is that they permit the existence of knowledge unmediated by the employment of concepts, utterance of sentences, or intelligent use of words. They support The Myth of the Given because they hold that this employment, utterance, or use can be learned and practiced only by calling on an awareness or immediate knowledge of pre-linguistic qualities such as Lockean ideas of sensation, Humean impressions, or Kantian intuitions. ft Schleiermacher's Hermeneutics and Language For our purposes, it is best to understand Schleiermacher's hermeneutics by juxtaposing it to the Cartesian and Kantian epistemologica! perspective. The crucial questions we will keep in the background are: Is Schleiermacher an assimilationist? Is a version of The Myth of the Given operative in his hermeneutics? If so, in what form does it appear? For Schleiermacher, hermeneutics is concerned with the phenomenon of understanding. It tries to discover the universal laws or general principles which state the requisite conditions for the possibility of human understanding. Only by satisfying such conditions can we make intelligible what others have said in speech or written in texts, and thereby avoid misunderstanding. Schleiermacher conceives of hermeneutics as a doctrine of art {Kunstlehre) or a technique (Technik). It is a science and an art; it consists of scientific investigation and artistic skill. It provides rational guidelines which regulate interpretive activity; it also depends, however, on specific talents acquired and refined only by actual practice.

3 SCHLEIERMACHER'S HERMENEUTICS 73 This twofold defintion of hermeneutics roughly corresponds to the two kinds of interpretations which comprise Schleiermacher's hermeneutics: the grammatical and psychological interpretations. These two interpretations are two moments of reconstruction (Nachbildung). And as he notes, "Understanding takes place only in the comherence of these two moments." 2 The grammatical interpretation is a reconstruction of the historical context, linguistic discourse and word-meanings of an author (or speaker). This interpretation probes into the Zeitgeist of the period in which the author writes; the intellectual, emotional and personal stage of the author's development; the literary genre which the author adopts; and the semantic possibilities of the words that the author employs. The grammatical interpretation contains two canons. The aim of the first canon is to determine, as precisely as possible, claims, insights, and statements in the author's text "on the basis of the use of language common to the author and his original public." 3 The goal of the second canon is to ascertain the single meaning of words in the author's text "by the context in which it occurs." 4 In short, the first canon reconstructs the historical context and linguistic discourse of the author; the second canon, the word-meanings in the text. The psychological interpretation is Schleiermacher's original contribution to hermeneutics. It is a reconstruction of the author's style, subjectivity, individuality and uniqueness. This interpretation delves deep into the inner chambers of the author, viewing the author's text as an expression and manifestation of what goes on within these inner chambers. The psychological interpretation contains two kinds of interpretations: the technical and psychological-proper interpretations. The former interpretation tries to reconstruct the particular circumstances and details which have direct bearing on the uniqueness of the author's text. The latter consist of two interpretative procedures the comparative and divinatory procedures. The psychological-proper interpretation reconstructs the text as an event which serves as the outward expression of a free-flowing, meaning-producing, creative process within the author. At this point, Schleiermacher reveals his romanticism by permitting the interpreter to participate in the creative process initiated by the author. The interpreter can be more creative than the author since, aside from this participation, he or she can unearth elements in the text unknown to the author. Such understanding can be viewed as the goal of hermeneutics. "The task is to be formulated as follows: To understand the text at first as well as and then even better than its author.' " 5 Understanding can be achieved, and the superiority of the interpreter over any self-interpretation by the author established, only by employing the comparative and divinatory procedures in conjunction with one another (along with the grammatical and technical interpretations). The comparative procedure entails "subsuming the author under a general type" and discovering the author's unique characteristics "by comparing him with the others of the same general type." 6 This comparison makes possible the necessary point of contact for an act of understanding to occur between interpreter and author only if the interpreter is able to recognize within him/herself similar characteristics to those of the author. For Schleiermacher, this point of contact consists of a fundamental identity and commonality between interpreter and author. The divinatory procedure tries to make possible this identity and commonality "by leading the interpreter to transform himself, so to speak, into the author." 7 And what are the grounds for this possible identity and commonality? A pre-existing connection of all individuals, an omnipresent stream which

4 74 UNION SEMINARY QUARTERLY REVIEW flows from person to person. Despite the uniqueness of individuals, Schleiermacher must assume that there is a universal element implicit in every human expression which enables understanding to take place. The divinatory is based on the assumption that each person is not only a unique individual in his own right, but that he has a receptivity to the uniqueness of every other person. This assumption in turn seems to presuppose that each person contains a minimum of everyone else, and so divination is aroused by comparison with oneself. 8 Schleiermacher's hermeneutics rest on establishing the fundamental identity and commonality between people, e.g., interpreter and author, speaker and listener. According to this viewpoint, understanding is possible only by justifying the fundamental identity and commonality of people. I shall now try to show that Schleiermacher's justification appeals to a version of The Myth of the Given. This can be illustrated by examining how he conceives the relation of langauge to consciousness and awareness. In recent years, there has been much controversy concerning the "early" and "late" Schleiermacher's views on language. Heinz Kimmerle, in his famous introduction to his 1959 edition of Schleiermacher's Hermeneutik, claims that the "early" Schleiermacher held a "language-centered" hermeneutics, identifying thought with language, thinking with speaking. By attempting to incorporate his hermeneutical theory into scientific disciplines which distinguish the ideal, inner essence from the empirical, external appearance, the "late" Schleiermacher moved toward a "subjectivity-centered" hermeneutics, separating the mental process of thought from language. 9 This distinction between the "early" and "late" Schleiermacher, however, misses the point. The issue is not the relation of language to thought or thinking to speaking, but rather the status of pre-linguistic consciousness or non-linguistic qualities in Schleiermacher's perspective. The Kimmerle controversy focuses on the scope of such consciousness and the broadening of this scope from the "early" to the "late" Schleiermacher. We are concerned with the fact that a pre-linguistic consciousness is posited, as well as with the epistomological status of this fact, and how this fact becomes the basis of the fundamental identity and commonality needed to support his hermeneutics. It is undeniable that the "early" Schleiermacher allowed for, indeed, lauded, prelinguistic consciousness. This consciousness is discussed, not only in the "early" Schleiermacher's hermeneutical reflections in the "Aphorisms" of 1805 and , but also in the "young" Schleiermacher in his classic work, On Religion: Speeches to its Cultured Despisers (1799) and his Soliloquies (1800). In On Religion, pre-linguistic consciousness (or non-linguistic experience) is depicted as immediate awareness of our relationship with the Infinite and the Eternal. Schleiermacher describes this awareness as "the immediate consciousness of the universal existence of all finite things in and through the Infinite, and of all temporal things in and through the Eternal." 1 Schleiermacher separates this immediate consciousness from knowledge, e.g., ideas, concepts, language, and holds that "In itself it is an affection, a revelation of the Infinite in the finite, God being seen in it and it in God." 1 λ The key word in this passage is "seen." God is somehow "seen." But, who "sees"? Surely the person or individual affected. But isn't this "seeing" a species of knowledge; a knowledge of one's true self and of a relationship which makes known one's true self? This seems to be what he meant when Schleiermacher beckons his opponents to, descend into the inmost sanctuary of life... There alone you discover the original relation of intuition and feeling from which alone this identity and difference is to be understood. But I must direct you to your own selves. You must apprehend a living moment... What you are to notice is the rise of vour consciousness and not to reflect upon something already there. Your thought can only embrace what is sundered. ' 2 In captivating prose, Schleiermacher portrays this immediate consciousness as, fleeting and transparent as the vapour which the dew breathes on blossom and fruit, it is bashful and tender as a maiden's kiss, it is holy and fruitful as a bridal embrace. Nor is it merely like, it is all this. It is the first contact of the universal life with an individual.

5 SCHLEIERMACHER'S HERMENEUTICS It fills no time and fashions nothing palpable. It is the holy wedlock of the Universe with the incarnated Reason for a creative, productive embrace. It is immediate, raised above all error and misunderstanding.^ At this point, Schleiermacher's intuitions resemble those of Kant's in that both are "blind," i.e., pre-conceptual and pre-linguistic, yet still manage to "see" quite a bit. Just as Kant's intuitions "see" a manifold of diversity, so Schleiermacher's intuitions "see" an original unity of the self and the Infinite. In one passage, Schleiermacher equates this "seeing" with a species of knowledge, At length your consciousness is finally determined as one or other, as intuition or feeling. Then even though you have not quite surrendered to this division and lost consciousness of your life as a unity, there remains nothing but the knowledge that they were,4 originally one And immediately after this equation of intuitive insight and a kind of knowledge, Schleiermacher reveals his assimilationist position by further defining immediate consciousness and feelings, intuitive insight and "privileged" knowledge, as a series of sensations and nothing else. The chief point in my Speech is now uttered. This is the peculiar sphere which I» would assign to religion the whole of it, and nothing more Your feeling is piety in so far as it is the result of the operation of God in you by means of the operation of the world upon you. This series is not made up either of perceptions or of objects of perception, either of works or operations or of different spheres of operation, but purely ot sensations and the influences of all that lives and moves around, which accompanies them and conditions them: These feelings are exclusively the elements of religion, and none are excluded. There is no sensation that is not pious, except it indicate some diseased and impaired state of the life, the influence of which will not be confined to religion. Wherefore, it follows that ideas and principles are all foreign to religion... If ideas and principles are to be anything, they must belong to knowledge which is a different department of life from religion.^ From our reading of On Religion, we can conclude that for the "young" Schleiermacher immediate consciousness or non-linguistic (non-conceptual) awareness consists of feelings and intuitions which yield a "seeing" of the original unity of the self and God. This "seeing" is unmediated by ideas, concepts or words. It is a "privileged" knowledge which rests on a series of sensations activated by the presence of the Infinite. Somehow therefore these sensations ground an immediate knowledge without the help of ideas, concepts, or words. In this way, the "young" Schleiermacher subscribes to The Myth of the Given and upholds assimilationism. In Soliloquies (1800), Schleiermacher draws a connection between his version of The Myth of the Given, his assimilationism and the universal element in human expressions which will undergird his hermeneutics in the future. Thus there dawned upon me what is now my highest intuition. I saw clearly that each man is meant to represent humanity in his own way, combining its elements uniquely, so that it may reveal itself in every mode, and all that can issue from its womb be made actual in the fullness of unending space and time J 6 The universal element in human expressions is posited owing to our ability to "see" or "know" the life-unity of the self. This life-unity establishes one's membership in a community of spiritual individuals. In Schleiermacher's hermeneutics, this pantheistic metaphysics of individuality is the foundation for the identity and commonality of human beings. This identity and commonality makes understanding possible. Without non-linguistic consciousness or immediate awareness of the life-unity of the self-schleiermacher's version of The Myth of the Given -there is no pantheistic metaphysics of individuality. Without his pantheistic metaphysics of individuality, there is no identity and commonality of human beings, hence no grounds for human understanding. So we are forced to conclude that without The Myth of the Given, Schleiermacher's hermeneutics is in deep trouble. G Attacking The Myth of the Given Schleiermacher's hermeneutics is in jeopardy because it relies on an unacceptable

6 76 UNION SEMINARY QUARTERLY REVIEW epistemologica! viewpoint. This viewpoint, commonly held by Cartesian and Kantian thinkers, gives privileged epistemic status to certain intuitions, feelings and sensations, or immediate consciousness and awareness. It can account for this "knowledge" only by appealing to the Myth of the Given. I shall argue that The Myth of the Given is untenable. This argument will take the form of examining three trenchant critiques of The Myth of the Given: those of Martin Heidegger, Jacques Derrida and Ludwig Wittgenstein. These critiques constitute the most challenging philosophical viewpoints in the twentieth century. Thev not only call into question The Myth of the Given (any versions of it), but also the conception of philosophy (and theology) which rests upon The Myth of the Given. It is significant to note that these three thinkers represent three distinct philosophical traditions and backgrounds. Heidegger is rooted in classical thought and German hermeneutics; Derrida, in French phenomenology and Saussurean linguistics; Wittgenstein, in British analytic philosophy and his own brand of Viennese-baked existentialism. The common consensus of these three giants in contemporary philosophy against The Myth of the Given should cast some suspicion on this Myth. D. Heidegger's Critique We shall begin with Heidegger since he directly confronts and transforms the hermeneutic tradition initiated by Schleiermacher. For Heidegger, the locus of hermeneutics is not the phenomenon ot understanding, but rather what it means to be. By directing hermeneutics to the meaning of Being (the Seinsfrage), Heidegger discards Schleiermacher's conception of understanding. Understanding is no longer a cognitive act which occurs when there is a point of contact between speaker and listener, interpreter and author; rather it is a mode of existence which reveals the ontological structure of human existence. The phenomenology of Dasein is a hermeneutic in the primordial signification of this word, where it designates this business of interpreting. But to the extent that by uncovering the meaning of Being and the basic structures of Dasein in general we may exhibit the horizon for any further ontological study of those entities which do not have the character of Dasein, this hermeneutic also becomes a 'hermeneutic' in the sense of workingout the conditions on which the possibility of any ontological investigation depends. ' ' Heidegger holds understanding to be a mode of existence which enables self-reflective human beings to be aware of the existential "fact" that they have possibilities. And understanding itself is one of these possibilities. Understanding, as an existence-possibility, projects potentiality-for-being (Seinkönnen). As Heidegger states, "The kind of Being which Dasein has, as potentiality-for-being, lies existentially in understanding." 1 8 The projection or throwing forward (Entwurf) of possibilities before human beings does not occur in a historical vacuum. Rather it is colored by Dasein's (or self-reflective individuals') Being-in-the-world. To-be-in-the-world is first and foremost to view the world as ready-at-hand (Zuhanden), as available for human use. All projections are limited by the range of service possibilities the world presents to Dasein', all understanding occurs within a matrix of potentiality dictated by Dasein's situation and environment. As a disclosure, understanding always pertains to the whole basic state of Being-in-theworld. As a potentiality-for-being, any Being-in is a potentiality-for-being-in-the-world. Not only is the world,.qua world, disclosed as possible significance, but when that which is within-the-world is itself freed, this entity is freed for its own possibilities. That which is ready-at-hand is discovered as such in its serviceability, its usability, and its detrimento//^. For Heidegger, interpretation presupposes understanding in that it tries to shed light on or lay bare certain possibilities projected by understanding. All interpretation or attempts to illuminate particular possibilités proceeds from a fore-having (Vorhabe), fore-sight (Vorsicht), and fore-conception (Vorgriff), from something we have, see and grasp prior to the act of interpretation.

7 SCHLEIERMACHER'S HERMENEUTICS 77 Whenever something is interpreted as something, the interpretation will be founded essentially upon fore-having, foresight, and fore-conception. An interpretation is never a presuppositionless apprehending of something presented to us.20 Since all interpretation operates within a specific set of presuppositions, prejudgments, and prejudices, it is circular. But it is not a vicious circularity, capriciously arriving at preconceived results. Instead it is a productive and unavoidable circularity making explicit what was implicit, obvious what was obscure, familiar what was strange without ever completely removing what is implicit, obscure and strange. This circularity characterizes the conditions under which interpretation takes place, thereby creating the possibility of self-conscious interpretations and nonarbitrary conclusions. If the basic conditions which make interpretation possible are to be fulfilled, this must rather be done by not failing to recognize beforehand the essential conditions under which it can be performed. What is decisive is not to get out of the circle but to come into it in the right way. This circle of understanding is not an orbit in which any random kind of knowledge may move; it is the expression of the existential fore-structure of Dasein itself. It is not to be reduced to the level of a Vicious circle, or even of a circle which is merely tolerated. In the circle is hidden a positive possibility of the most primordial kind of knowing. 21 Heidegger's conception of understanding and the fore-structure of interpretation rules out The Myth of the Given. His emphasis on the Dasein's Being-in-the-world as the context of all knowledge does not permit the epistemic status of immediate awareness or privileged assertions, representations or states of consciousness. The "given" for Heidegger is the radical historicity of human existence, the perennial entrapment of human beings in particular circumstances and situations to which they must respond. He attacks The Myth of the Given by trying to show, on ontological grounds, that all knowledge is mediated by history. According to his view, Schleiermacher's attempt to ground the fundamental identity and commonality of people in a pantheistic metaphysics of individuality and to base this metaphysics on immediate awareness of the life-unity of the self is not only epistemologically misguided, but, more importantly, ontologically impossible. E. Derrida's Critique Jacques Derrida, a leading French philosopher, attacks The Myth of the Given from another angle. Instead of claiming that all knowledge is mediated by history, he holds that all knowledge is mediated by texts. His famous slogan, "There is nothing outside the text" (il n'y a pas de hors-texte)? 2 roughly summarizes his viewpoint. For Derrida, The Myth of the Given is at the core of the Western metaphysical tradition which gives priority (or privilege) to speech over texts, voice over writing. This metaphysics of presence or epiphany constitutes Western logocentrism, namely, the belief that the origin and telos of things are the Logos, the Word, the creative subject, or the selfpresence in consciousness. This metaphysical tradition rests upon a human desire to posit a privileged reference, fixed origin, absolute arche or unchanging center upon which to ground knowledge-claims. Successively, and in a regulated fashion, the center receives different forms and names. The history of metaphysics, like the history of the West, is the history of these metaphors and metonymies. Its matrix if you will pardon me for demonstrating so little and for being so elliptical in order to bring me more quickly to my principal theme is the determination of being as presence in all the senses of this word. It would be possible to show that all the names related to fundamentals, to principles, or to the center have always designated the constant of a presence eidos, arche, telos, energeia, ousia (essence, existence, substance, subject) aletheia, transcendentality, consciousness, or conscience, God, man, and so forth.23 Derrida's famous deconstruction program is an attempt to reveal the illusory status of the center and dissolve The Myth of the Given in texts. This program discovers that in place of a necessary center, we find contingent "traces". These "traces" are not the result of a previous presence or loss of center, but rather of the linguistic play of differ-

8 78 UNION SEMINARY QUARTERLY REVIEW enees (of sounds and meanings), of irreducible aftereffects and delayed effects of a perennially deferred presence or postponed center. The trace is not a presence but is rather the simulacrum of a presence that dislocates, displaces, and refers beyond itself. The trace has, properly speaking, no place, for effacement belongs to the very structure of the trace. Effacement must always be able to overtake the trace; otherwise it would not be a trace but an indestructible and monumental substance.24 This play of differences forever holding "presence" at arm's length is made possible by what Derrida calls "differance." It is neither a word nor a concept. Instead, it is "the movement by which language or any code, any system of reference in general, becomes 'historically constituted as a fabric of differences." 25 Derrida opposes the privileged status of speech over texts and voice over writing because this status assumes that the spoken voice insures the intuitive presence of the speaking subject. He argues that since a spoken sentence must have universal application in order to be understood (that is, understood by someone presently absent) it presupposes the absence of the speaker. Therefore its status is the same as a written sentence. In his lengthy argument against Husserl 's conception of presence (as the phenomenological structure of the voice), Derrida writes, When I say "I" even in solitary speech, can I give my statement meaning without implying, there as always, the possible absence of the object of speech in this case, myself? When I tell myself "I am," this expression, like any other according to Husserl, has the status of speech only if it is intelligible in the absence of its object, in the absence of intuitive presence here, in the absence of myself. Moreover, it is in this way that the ergo sum is introduced into the philosophical tradition and that a discourse about the transcendental ego is possible. 26 Derrida's attack on The Myth of the Given takes the form of an all-out assault on not only the priority of the spoken word, but also the speaking subject. His attack cuts at the very roots of Schleiermacher's version of The Myth of the Given: the intuitive awareness of the life-unity of the self. Like the French structuralists (whom he often criticizes), Derrida holds that the subject is a function of language in that he or she becomes a speaking subject only by conforming his or her speech to an already given linguistic code or system. This system is a play of differences which precludes the self-presence of the subject prior to speech or its signs. We thus come to posit presence and, in particular, consciousness, the beingnext-to-itself of consciousness no longer as the absolutely matrical form of being but as a "determination" and an "effect". Presence is a determination and effect within a system which is no longer that of presence but that of differance Despite his hostility to The Myth of the Given, Derrida's ambitions are much less than those of Heidegger. Whereas Heidegger wants to overcome and "destroy" Western metaphysics, replacing it with a new philosophical epoch in which we wait and harken for "the first word of Being," Derrida only wants to show that the logocentrism of the Western metaphysical tradition is an integral and inescapable part of our language. For him, the task is not to initiate a new non-metaphysical discourse, but rather to reveal the untenable, yet necessary, participation in a metaphysics of presence. In response to critics on this point, he states, Here and there I have used the word deconstruct/on. which has nothing to do with destruction. That is to say, it is simply a question of (and this is a necessity of criticism in the classical sense of the word) being alert to the implications, to the historical sedimentation of the language which we use and that is not destruction... First of all, I didn't say that there was no center, that we could get along without the center. I believe that the center is a function, not a being a reality, but a function. And this function is absolutely indispensable. The subject is absolutely indispensable. I don't destroy the subject; I situate it.28 Derrida believes that some version of The Myth of the Given is necessary for languageusage. Yet, it is unexcusable for one to be unaware of the groundlessness of any version. This unawareness bespeaks a philosophical false consciousness and reflects a yearning for security and certainty. It results in an "ethic of presence, an ethic of nostalgia for origins,

9 SCHLEIERMACHER'S HERMENEUTICS 79 an ethic of archaic and natural innocence of a purity of presence and self-presence in speech." 29 In its place he offers a kind of tragicomic alternative, a celebration of one's freedom while succumbing to one's linguistic fate. He recommends, the joyous affirmation of the freeplay of the world and without truth, without origin... This affirmation then determines the non-center otherwise than as loss of the center. And it plays the game without security.30 The "given" for Derrida is the radical textuality of human existence, the continuous play of differences of already-existing marks (déjà écrit) on paper. Derrida's viewpoint deems Schleiermacher's version of The Myth of the Given as philosophically groundless, like his own, but unlike his own in that Schleiermacher is unaware of this status. Schleiermacher, like Derrida, participates in a metaphysics of presence or epiphany. But, for Derrida, only his deconstruction program frees one from its "spirit of gravity" and permits one to no longer take The Myth of the Given seriously. F. Wittgenstein's Critique Wittgenstein's attack on The Myth of the Given is, I believe, more profound and persuasive than those of Heidegger and Derrida. Instead of embarking on an ontologica! investigation to defend the claim that all knowledge is mediated by history or engaging in an ironic deconstruction program to show that all knowledge is mediated by texts, Wittgenstein describes ordinary language-usage in order to illustrate that all knowledge is mediated by linguistic, intersubjective agreement. In short, Wittgenstein criticizes The Myth of the Given by viewing epistemology as social practice. Wittgenstein discards The Myth of the Given by highlighting the fact that special, felt, incommunicable qualities of immediate experience play no role whatsoever in justifying our employment of concepts, utterance of sentences, or intelligent use of words. He does not deny the existence of such qualities, (e.g., thoughts and sensations) but he claims that the "innerness" of these qualities or our special accessibility to them does not give them privileged status as the basis of our employment of concepts, utterance of sentences, or intelligent use of words. There is no need to draw a philosophical line of demarcation between objects in the external world and special qualities (or mental states) in the human mind. Our attempts to justify both rest on public conventions or social practices. The criteria for such justification consists of the circumstances, behavior and utterances of human beings. Wittgenstein's viewpoint can be best illustrated by examining his famous treatment of how we justify the use of "mental state" words, e.g., "pain" in association with the behavior of other people. For Cartesians, this justification can never be certain since only immediate experience yields certainty and we can never "feel" the mental states of others. In reply to Cartesians (or supporters of The Myth of the Given), Wittgenstein proposes to provide public standards for justifying mental states in people. His slogans are, "... justification consists in appeal to something independent," ana, "... an 'inner process' stands in need of outward criteria." Wittgenstein begins by trying to characterize what it would be like to be caught in the Cartesian view of immediate experience (or the cogitatici). Let us imagine the following case. I want to keep a diary about the recurrence of a certain sensation. To this end I associate it with the sign "S" and write this sign in a calendar for every day on which I have the sensation. L will remark first of all that a definition cannot be formulated. But still I can give myself a kind of ostensive definition. How? Can I point to the sensation? Not in the ordinary sense. But I speak, or write the sign down, and at the same time I concentrate my attention on the sensation and so, as it were, point to it inwardly. But what is this ceremony for? for that is all it seems to be! A definition surely serves to establish the meaning of a sign. Well, that is done precisely by the concentration of my attention; for in this way I impress on myself the connection between the sign and the sensation. But "I impress it on myself" can only mean: this process brings it about that I remember the connection right in the future. But in the present case I have no criterion of correctness. One would Jike to sav: whatever is goine to seem right to me is right. And that only means that here we can't talk about 'right.' 33

10 80 UNION SEMINARY QUARTERLY REVIEW Cartesians would reply that Wittgenstein is correct to say that any private ostensive definition is objectionable if we cannot act in accordance with it. But Wittgenstein has provided no reasons for denying that we cannot rely upon memory as the basis for such a definition. Wittgenstein would quickly answer,... But what do we regard as the criterion for remembering it right? When we work with a sample instead of our memory there are circumstances in which we say that the sample has changed color and we judge of this by memory. But can we not sometimes speak of a darkening (for example) of our memory-image? Aren't we as much at the mercy of memory as of a sample? Suppose that the color struck you as brighter on one day than on another; would you not sometimes say: "I must be wrong, the color is certainly the same as yesterday?" This shows that we do not always resort to what memory tells us as the verdict of the highest court of appeal. 3^ Cartesians are forced to account for public knowledge of mental states in other people by arguing that since we have mental states justified by our immediate experience of them it is probable that persons with bodies like our own also have them. Since it is impossible to have direct evidence for (or immediate experience of) the mental states of other people, we can only rely on an analogy argument to establish the existence of such mental states. Wittgenstein wants to show that The Myth of the Given, or justifying the intelligent use of words by appealing to immediate experience, would lead one to think that knowledge of mental states in other people can be arrived at only by inferring from the unwarranted assumption that what holds true for one's own case must hold true for other persons or other bodies. The essential thing about private experience is really not that each person possesses his own exemplar, but that nobody knows whether other people also have this or something else. The assumption would thus be possible though unverifiable that one section of mankind had one sensation of red and another section another. 3^ In his particular argument for public criteria for the existence of pain-events in other people, Wittgenstein can be viewed as refuting Cartesians as well as undermining The Myth of the Given. For him, the meaning of the word "pain" in our language does not derive from pain being an entity, a stuff or a something in the minds of others; rather its meaning can be ascertained by examining its place in the language game of pain, by describing the linguistic practics which involve the use of the word "pain." This is the only way to escape Cartesian agnosticism about the existence of mental states (in this case, pain-events) in other people. If I say of myself that it is only from my own case that I know what the word "pain" means must I not say the same of other people too? And how can I generalize the one case so irresponsibly? Now someone tells me that he knows what pain is only from his own case! Suppose everyone had a box with something in it: we call it a "beetle". No one can look into anyone else's box, and everyone says he knows what a beetle is only by looking at his beetle. Here it would be quite possible for everyone to have something different in his box. One might even imagine such a thing constantly changing. But suppose the word "beetle" had a use in these people's language? If so it would not be used as the name of a thing. The thing in the box has no place in the language-game at all; not even as a something: for the box might even be empty. No, one can 'divide thought' by the thing in the box; it cancels out, whatever it is. That is to say: if we construe the grammar of the expression of sensation on the model of 'object and designation' the object drops out of consideration as irrelevant. 36 In disregarding the notion that the only way knowledge of mental states in other people is acquired is by our being acquainted with special, felt, incommunicable qualities, Wittgenstein allows the possibility of our having direct access to our mental states without relying on this access as the sole basis of our knowledge of mental states in other people. He notes that if we investigate the langauge-game of pain, we discover that the expression of doubt doubt generated by Cartesians and The Myth of the Given has no place in it. This doubt arises only if we talk about pain independent of human behavior and in terms of immediate experience.... expression of doubt has no place in the language-game; but if we cut out human behavior, which is the expression of sensation, it looks as if I might legitimately begin to doubt afresh. My temptation to say that one might take a sensation for something other

11 SCHLEIERMACHER'S HERMENEUTICS 81 than what it is arises from this: if I assume the abrogation of the normal language-game with the expression of a sensation. I need a criterion of identity for the sensation; and then the possibility of error also exists. 3? Once we make this Cartesian move, the identification of the sensation as pain becomes an intermediate step between the occurrence of pain and the expression of it in the words, "I am in pain." But this intermediate step is superfluous; pain is self-intimating to have it is to know it! And people's behavior shows it. "Imagine a person whose memory could not retain what the word 'pain' meant so that he constantly called different things by that name but nevertheless used the word in a way fitting in with the usual symptoms and presuppositions of pain" in short he uses it as we all do. Here I should like to say: a wheel that can be turned though nothing else moves with it, is not part of the mechan ism. 3^ Wittgenstein believes that a public language which describes and reports presupposes general agreement in judgments. Judgments involve the "correct" application of a word or phrase in association with shared experiences. The "correct" use of the word "pain" is connected with the shared experience of observing pain-behavior. This renders the status of pain-events irrelevant when trying to justify our knowledge of them in other people. "But you will surely admit that there is a difference between pain-behavior accompanied by pain and pain-behavior without pain?" admit it? What greater difference could there be? "And yet you again and again reach the conclusion that the sensation itself is a nothing"r Not at all. It is not a something but not a nothing either! The conclusion was only that a nothing would serve just as well as a something about which nothing co'ild be said. 39 It follows from Wittgenstein's view that mental states are distinct from physical objects, not because they are different sorts of things or inhabit two separate realms, e.g., inner/outer, subjective/objective, but because it is publicly accepted that certain knowledge-claims about them cannot be overridden.40 People engage in the language-game of mental states, making claims about the mental states of others, by following the particular social practice or public linguistic convention that first-person present-tense reports of mental states are taken as the most reliable evidence for their own truth. It is difficult to acknowledge this convention as contingent and subject to the social practices in the culture because it is rarely questioned and has a long history of acceptance. The contingent character of this convention can be brought to light by drawing an analogy between unobservable mental states in people and unobservable molecules. Just as Brownian motion serves as evidence in the current scientific community for the existence of molecules, so first-person present-tense reports of mental states serve as evidence in the present linguistic community for the existence of mental states in people. And just as Brownian motion might turn out to be the result of certain newly discovered forces which have nothing to do with molecules, so cerebroscopes might come to override tirst-person present-tense reports of mental states. In each case, new conventions arise owing to more reliable evidence. Therefore the justification of our knowledge of mental states (as well as physical objects) is based on the state of scientific inquiry (especially neurology and physics) and our linguistic practices. Wittgenstein demythologizes The Myth of the Given by showing that its most cherished qualities (e.g., thoughts and sensations) are best understood by describing how words which refer to them, e.g., pain, are used in our language. This usage, like any other social practice, is révisable and replaceable, e.g., by brain-state words, neurological-state words. In this way, Wittgenstein deciphers Cartesian hieroglyphics and dissolves the pseudo-problems generated by The Myth of the Given. It is the uncovering of ever-changing social practices by his brand of philosophy, concealed by Cartesian and Kantian thinkers, which Wittgenstein refers to in this metaphilosophical passage: Philosophy simply puts everything before us, and neither explains nor deduces anything. Since everything lies open to view there is nothing to explain One might also give the name "philosophy" to what is possible before all new discoveries and inventions. 41

12 82 UNION SEMINARY QUARTERLY REVIEW The "given" for Wittgenstein is the radical intersubjectivity of human existence, especially the various agreements on rules of language and their interpretation. These agreements occur most often in homogeneous linguistic communities, forms of life (lebensformen), or cultures. What has to be accepted, the given, is so one can say forms of life. Wittgenstein's viewpoint holds that Schleiermacher's version of The Myth of the Given is not only philosophically untenable; it is also itself a social practice which philosophers and theologians must overcome. G. Philosophy and Theology Without The Myth of the Given: Historical Limits and Existential Leaps The critiques of The Myth of the Given by Heidegger, Derrida and Wittgenstein share one common theme: the radical finitude and sheer contingency of human existence. Human beings are trapped in either a historical, textual or intersubjective web from which there is no escape. By discarding The Myth of the Given, the quest for certainty and security comes to an end. Philosophy's grand search for the invariable, immutable categories in human experience, expressions and language and theology's bold attempt to establish veridical reference to a transcendent God must surrender and succumb to the ebb and flow of history, the freeplay of infinite substitutions in the confines of texts, and the transient character of intersubjective agreements. Two lines of theoretical inquiry remain after the end of modern philosophy and theology: theories of historical limits and theories of existential leaps. The former are required in order to provide accounts as to why and how each generation bequeaths what it does to the subsequent generation (e.g., conflict-ridden systems of production, social and political arrangements, beliefs about the self, world and God, values for conduct, attitudes toward particular artifacts). The latter are needed in order to view ourselves as active historical persons consciously engaged in the difficult business of coping with the vertiginous character of human life. Both kinds of theories, working in conjunction with one another, allow us to weigh historically possible and potent allegiances to particular religious, political and/or moral traditions and communities which evolve around specific types of existential valuing and, most importantly, enable us to make choices in regard to joining ranks with certain traditions and communities, regardless of the risk and insecurity this commitment involves. Without The Myth of the Given, philosophers and theologians are forced to adopt simultaneously a theory of historical and social change which explains the limits of the past and present and a theory of existential valuing that illuminates the depths of our capacity to love, hate, hope and despair and our inescapable need to make leaps of faith. In this way, the attacks of Heidegger, Derrida and Wittgenstein on The Myth of the Given may be seen as preparing the way for a creative synthesis of two disparate, yet complementary thinkers--marx and Kierkegaard.

1/12. The A Paralogisms

1/12. The A Paralogisms 1/12 The A Paralogisms The character of the Paralogisms is described early in the chapter. Kant describes them as being syllogisms which contain no empirical premises and states that in them we conclude

More information

Introductory Kant Seminar Lecture

Introductory Kant Seminar Lecture Introductory Kant Seminar Lecture Intentionality It is not unusual to begin a discussion of Kant with a brief review of some history of philosophy. What is perhaps less usual is to start with a review

More information

1/10. The Fourth Paralogism and the Refutation of Idealism

1/10. The Fourth Paralogism and the Refutation of Idealism 1/10 The Fourth Paralogism and the Refutation of Idealism The Fourth Paralogism is quite different from the three that preceded it because, although it is treated as a part of rational psychology, it main

More information

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras Module - 21 Lecture - 21 Kant Forms of sensibility Categories

More information

Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics 1. By Tom Cumming

Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics 1. By Tom Cumming Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics 1 By Tom Cumming Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics represents Martin Heidegger's first attempt at an interpretation of Kant's Critique of Pure Reason (1781). This

More information

Kant and his Successors

Kant and his Successors Kant and his Successors G. J. Mattey Winter, 2011 / Philosophy 151 The Sorry State of Metaphysics Kant s Critique of Pure Reason (1781) was an attempt to put metaphysics on a scientific basis. Metaphysics

More information

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg 1 In Search of the Ontological Argument Richard Oxenberg Abstract We can attend to the logic of Anselm's ontological argument, and amuse ourselves for a few hours unraveling its convoluted word-play, or

More information

The CopernicanRevolution

The CopernicanRevolution Immanuel Kant: The Copernican Revolution The CopernicanRevolution Immanuel Kant (1724-1804) The Critique of Pure Reason (1781) is Kant s best known work. In this monumental work, he begins a Copernican-like

More information

1/8. The Schematism. schema of empirical concepts, the schema of sensible concepts and the

1/8. The Schematism. schema of empirical concepts, the schema of sensible concepts and the 1/8 The Schematism I am going to distinguish between three types of schematism: the schema of empirical concepts, the schema of sensible concepts and the schema of pure concepts. Kant opens the discussion

More information

Chapter 18 David Hume: Theory of Knowledge

Chapter 18 David Hume: Theory of Knowledge Key Words Chapter 18 David Hume: Theory of Knowledge Empiricism, skepticism, personal identity, necessary connection, causal connection, induction, impressions, ideas. DAVID HUME (1711-76) is one of the

More information

INVESTIGATING THE PRESUPPOSITIONAL REALM OF BIBLICAL-THEOLOGICAL METHODOLOGY, PART II: CANALE ON REASON

INVESTIGATING THE PRESUPPOSITIONAL REALM OF BIBLICAL-THEOLOGICAL METHODOLOGY, PART II: CANALE ON REASON Andrews University Seminary Studies, Vol. 47, No. 2, 217-240. Copyright 2009 Andrews University Press. INVESTIGATING THE PRESUPPOSITIONAL REALM OF BIBLICAL-THEOLOGICAL METHODOLOGY, PART II: CANALE ON REASON

More information

Rationalism. A. He, like others at the time, was obsessed with questions of truth and doubt

Rationalism. A. He, like others at the time, was obsessed with questions of truth and doubt Rationalism I. Descartes (1596-1650) A. He, like others at the time, was obsessed with questions of truth and doubt 1. How could one be certain in the absence of religious guidance and trustworthy senses

More information

THE STUDY OF UNKNOWN AND UNKNOWABILITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY

THE STUDY OF UNKNOWN AND UNKNOWABILITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY THE STUDY OF UNKNOWN AND UNKNOWABILITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY Subhankari Pati Research Scholar Pondicherry University, Pondicherry The present aim of this paper is to highlights the shortcomings in Kant

More information

"Can We Have a Word in Private?": Wittgenstein on the Impossibility of Private Languages

Can We Have a Word in Private?: Wittgenstein on the Impossibility of Private Languages Macalester Journal of Philosophy Volume 14 Issue 1 Spring 2005 Article 11 5-1-2005 "Can We Have a Word in Private?": Wittgenstein on the Impossibility of Private Languages Dan Walz-Chojnacki Follow this

More information

The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel s Idealism

The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel s Idealism The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel s Idealism What is a great mistake? Nietzsche once said that a great error is worth more than a multitude of trivial truths. A truly great mistake

More information

From Transcendental Logic to Transcendental Deduction

From Transcendental Logic to Transcendental Deduction From Transcendental Logic to Transcendental Deduction Let me see if I can say a few things to re-cap our first discussion of the Transcendental Logic, and help you get a foothold for what follows. Kant

More information

1/8. Introduction to Kant: The Project of Critique

1/8. Introduction to Kant: The Project of Critique 1/8 Introduction to Kant: The Project of Critique This course is focused on the interpretation of one book: The Critique of Pure Reason and we will, during the course, read the majority of the key sections

More information

Some Notes Toward a Genealogy of Existential Philosophy Robert Burch

Some Notes Toward a Genealogy of Existential Philosophy Robert Burch Some Notes Toward a Genealogy of Existential Philosophy Robert Burch Descartes - ostensive task: to secure by ungainsayable rational means the orthodox doctrines of faith regarding the existence of God

More information

A Philosophical Critique of Cognitive Psychology s Definition of the Person

A Philosophical Critique of Cognitive Psychology s Definition of the Person A Philosophical Critique of Cognitive Psychology s Definition of the Person Rosa Turrisi Fuller The Pluralist, Volume 4, Number 1, Spring 2009, pp. 93-99 (Article) Published by University of Illinois Press

More information

It doesn t take long in reading the Critique before we are faced with interpretive challenges. Consider the very first sentence in the A edition:

It doesn t take long in reading the Critique before we are faced with interpretive challenges. Consider the very first sentence in the A edition: The Preface(s) to the Critique of Pure Reason It doesn t take long in reading the Critique before we are faced with interpretive challenges. Consider the very first sentence in the A edition: Human reason

More information

1/9. The Second Analogy (1)

1/9. The Second Analogy (1) 1/9 The Second Analogy (1) This week we are turning to one of the most famous, if also longest, arguments in the Critique. This argument is both sufficiently and the interpretation of it sufficiently disputed

More information

Resolutio of Idealism into Atheism in Fichte

Resolutio of Idealism into Atheism in Fichte Maria Pia Mater Thomistic Week 2018 Resolutio of Idealism into Atheism in Fichte Introduction Cornelio Fabro s God in Exile, traces the progression of modern atheism from its roots in the cogito of Rene

More information

24.01 Classics of Western Philosophy

24.01 Classics of Western Philosophy 1 Plan: Kant Lecture #2: How are pure mathematics and pure natural science possible? 1. Review: Problem of Metaphysics 2. Kantian Commitments 3. Pure Mathematics 4. Transcendental Idealism 5. Pure Natural

More information

Consciousness might be defined as the perceiver of mental phenomena. We might say that there are no differences between one perceiver and another, as

Consciousness might be defined as the perceiver of mental phenomena. We might say that there are no differences between one perceiver and another, as 2. DO THE VALUES THAT ARE CALLED HUMAN RIGHTS HAVE INDEPENDENT AND UNIVERSAL VALIDITY, OR ARE THEY HISTORICALLY AND CULTURALLY RELATIVE HUMAN INVENTIONS? Human rights significantly influence the fundamental

More information

A HOLISTIC VIEW ON KNOWLEDGE AND VALUES

A HOLISTIC VIEW ON KNOWLEDGE AND VALUES A HOLISTIC VIEW ON KNOWLEDGE AND VALUES CHANHYU LEE Emory University It seems somewhat obscure that there is a concrete connection between epistemology and ethics; a study of knowledge and a study of moral

More information

Copyright 2000 Vk-Cic Vahe Karamian

Copyright 2000 Vk-Cic Vahe Karamian Kant In France and England, the Enlightenment theories were blueprints for reforms and revolutions political and economic changes came together with philosophical theory. In Germany, the Enlightenment

More information

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View Chapter 98 Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View Lars Leeten Universität Hildesheim Practical thinking is a tricky business. Its aim will never be fulfilled unless influence on practical

More information

Ayer and Quine on the a priori

Ayer and Quine on the a priori Ayer and Quine on the a priori November 23, 2004 1 The problem of a priori knowledge Ayer s book is a defense of a thoroughgoing empiricism, not only about what is required for a belief to be justified

More information

Naturalized Epistemology. 1. What is naturalized Epistemology? Quine PY4613

Naturalized Epistemology. 1. What is naturalized Epistemology? Quine PY4613 Naturalized Epistemology Quine PY4613 1. What is naturalized Epistemology? a. How is it motivated? b. What are its doctrines? c. Naturalized Epistemology in the context of Quine s philosophy 2. Naturalized

More information

Craig on the Experience of Tense

Craig on the Experience of Tense Craig on the Experience of Tense In his recent book, The Tensed Theory of Time: A Critical Examination, 1 William Lane Craig offers several criticisms of my views on our experience of time. The purpose

More information

K.V. LAURIKAINEN EXTENDING THE LIMITS OF SCIENCE

K.V. LAURIKAINEN EXTENDING THE LIMITS OF SCIENCE K.V. LAURIKAINEN EXTENDING THE LIMITS OF SCIENCE Tarja Kallio-Tamminen Contents Abstract My acquintance with K.V. Laurikainen Various flavours of Copenhagen What proved to be wrong Revelations of quantum

More information

This handout follows the handout on The nature of the sceptic s challenge. You should read that handout first.

This handout follows the handout on The nature of the sceptic s challenge. You should read that handout first. Michael Lacewing Three responses to scepticism This handout follows the handout on The nature of the sceptic s challenge. You should read that handout first. MITIGATED SCEPTICISM The term mitigated scepticism

More information

Heidegger Introduction

Heidegger Introduction Heidegger Introduction G. J. Mattey Spring, 2011 / Philosophy 151 Being and Time Being Published in 1927, under pressure Dedicated to Edmund Husserl Initially rejected as inadequate Now considered a seminal

More information

! Jumping ahead 2000 years:! Consider the theory of the self.! What am I? What certain knowledge do I have?! Key figure: René Descartes.

! Jumping ahead 2000 years:! Consider the theory of the self.! What am I? What certain knowledge do I have?! Key figure: René Descartes. ! Jumping ahead 2000 years:! Consider the theory of the self.! What am I? What certain knowledge do I have?! What is the relation between that knowledge and that given in the sciences?! Key figure: René

More information

New Chapter: Epistemology: The Theory and Nature of Knowledge

New Chapter: Epistemology: The Theory and Nature of Knowledge Intro to Philosophy Phil 110 Lecture 12: 2-15 Daniel Kelly I. Mechanics A. Upcoming Readings 1. Today we ll discuss a. Descartes, Meditations on First Philosophy (full.pdf) 2. Next week a. Locke, An Essay

More information

ABSTRACT of the Habilitation Thesis

ABSTRACT of the Habilitation Thesis ABSTRACT of the Habilitation Thesis The focus on the problem of knowledge was in the very core of my researches even before my Ph.D thesis, therefore the investigation of Kant s philosophy in the process

More information

- We might, now, wonder whether the resulting concept of justification is sufficiently strong. According to BonJour, apparent rational insight is

- We might, now, wonder whether the resulting concept of justification is sufficiently strong. According to BonJour, apparent rational insight is BonJour I PHIL410 BonJour s Moderate Rationalism - BonJour develops and defends a moderate form of Rationalism. - Rationalism, generally (as used here), is the view according to which the primary tool

More information

Reid Against Skepticism

Reid Against Skepticism Thus we see, that Descartes and Locke take the road that leads to skepticism without knowing the end of it, but they stop short for want of light to carry them farther. Berkeley, frightened at the appearance

More information

THE CRISIS OF THE SCmNCES AS EXPRESSION OF THE RADICAL LIFE-CRISIS OF EUROPEAN HUMANITY

THE CRISIS OF THE SCmNCES AS EXPRESSION OF THE RADICAL LIFE-CRISIS OF EUROPEAN HUMANITY Contents Translator's Introduction / xv PART I THE CRISIS OF THE SCmNCES AS EXPRESSION OF THE RADICAL LIFE-CRISIS OF EUROPEAN HUMANITY I. Is there, in view of their constant successes, really a crisis

More information

the notion of modal personhood. I begin with a challenge to Kagan s assumptions about the metaphysics of identity and modality.

the notion of modal personhood. I begin with a challenge to Kagan s assumptions about the metaphysics of identity and modality. On Modal Personism Shelly Kagan s essay on speciesism has the virtues characteristic of his work in general: insight, originality, clarity, cleverness, wit, intuitive plausibility, argumentative rigor,

More information

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras Module - 22 Lecture - 22 Kant The idea of Reason Soul, God

More information

Does Deduction really rest on a more secure epistemological footing than Induction?

Does Deduction really rest on a more secure epistemological footing than Induction? Does Deduction really rest on a more secure epistemological footing than Induction? We argue that, if deduction is taken to at least include classical logic (CL, henceforth), justifying CL - and thus deduction

More information

In Defense of Pure Reason: A Rationalist Account of A Priori Justification, by Laurence BonJour. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,

In Defense of Pure Reason: A Rationalist Account of A Priori Justification, by Laurence BonJour. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, Book Reviews 1 In Defense of Pure Reason: A Rationalist Account of A Priori Justification, by Laurence BonJour. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998. Pp. xiv + 232. H/b 37.50, $54.95, P/b 13.95,

More information

Process Thought and Bridge Building: A Response to Stephen K. White. Kevin Schilbrack

Process Thought and Bridge Building: A Response to Stephen K. White. Kevin Schilbrack Archived version from NCDOCKS Institutional Repository http://libres.uncg.edu/ir/asu/ Schilbrack, Kevin.2011 Process Thought and Bridge-Building: A Response to Stephen K. White, Process Studies 40:2 (Fall-Winter

More information

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006 In Defense of Radical Empiricism Joseph Benjamin Riegel A thesis submitted to the faculty of the University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of

More information

Thought is Being or Thought and Being? Feuerbach and his Criticism of Hegel's Absolute Idealism by Martin Jenkins

Thought is Being or Thought and Being? Feuerbach and his Criticism of Hegel's Absolute Idealism by Martin Jenkins Thought is Being or Thought and Being? Feuerbach and his Criticism of Hegel's Absolute Idealism by Martin Jenkins Although he was once an ardent follower of the Philosophy of GWF Hegel, Ludwig Feuerbach

More information

How Trustworthy is the Bible? (1) Written by Cornelis Pronk

How Trustworthy is the Bible? (1) Written by Cornelis Pronk Higher Criticism of the Bible is not a new phenomenon but a problem that has plagued the church for over a century and a-half. Spawned by the anti-supernatural spirit of the eighteenth century movement,

More information

III Knowledge is true belief based on argument. Plato, Theaetetus, 201 c-d Is Justified True Belief Knowledge? Edmund Gettier

III Knowledge is true belief based on argument. Plato, Theaetetus, 201 c-d Is Justified True Belief Knowledge? Edmund Gettier III Knowledge is true belief based on argument. Plato, Theaetetus, 201 c-d Is Justified True Belief Knowledge? Edmund Gettier In Theaetetus Plato introduced the definition of knowledge which is often translated

More information

Broad on Theological Arguments. I. The Ontological Argument

Broad on Theological Arguments. I. The Ontological Argument Broad on God Broad on Theological Arguments I. The Ontological Argument Sample Ontological Argument: Suppose that God is the most perfect or most excellent being. Consider two things: (1)An entity that

More information

On the epistemological status of mathematical objects in Plato s philosophical system

On the epistemological status of mathematical objects in Plato s philosophical system On the epistemological status of mathematical objects in Plato s philosophical system Floris T. van Vugt University College Utrecht University, The Netherlands October 22, 2003 Abstract The main question

More information

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras Module - 20 Lecture - 20 Critical Philosophy: Kant s objectives

More information

What one needs to know to prepare for'spinoza's method is to be found in the treatise, On the Improvement

What one needs to know to prepare for'spinoza's method is to be found in the treatise, On the Improvement SPINOZA'S METHOD Donald Mangum The primary aim of this paper will be to provide the reader of Spinoza with a certain approach to the Ethics. The approach is designed to prevent what I believe to be certain

More information

Christian Lotz, Commentary, SPEP 2009 Formal Indication and the Problem of Radical Philosophy in Heidegger

Christian Lotz, Commentary, SPEP 2009 Formal Indication and the Problem of Radical Philosophy in Heidegger Christian Lotz, Commentary, SPEP 2009 Formal Indication and the Problem of Radical Philosophy in Heidegger Introduction I would like to begin by thanking Leslie MacAvoy for her attempt to revitalize the

More information

The British Empiricism

The British Empiricism The British Empiricism Locke, Berkeley and Hume copyleft: nicolazuin.2018 nowxhere.wordpress.com The terrible heritage of Descartes: Skepticism, Empiricism, Rationalism The problem originates from the

More information

Kant and the Problem of Personal Identity Jacqueline Mariña

Kant and the Problem of Personal Identity Jacqueline Mariña Jacqueline Mariña 1 Kant and the Problem of Personal Identity Jacqueline Mariña How do I know that I am the same I today as the person who first conceived of this specific project over two years ago? The

More information

Projection in Hume. P J E Kail. St. Peter s College, Oxford.

Projection in Hume. P J E Kail. St. Peter s College, Oxford. Projection in Hume P J E Kail St. Peter s College, Oxford Peter.kail@spc.ox.ac.uk A while ago now (2007) I published my Projection and Realism in Hume s Philosophy (Oxford University Press henceforth abbreviated

More information

Jeu-Jenq Yuann Professor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy, National Taiwan University,

Jeu-Jenq Yuann Professor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy, National Taiwan University, The Negative Role of Empirical Stimulus in Theory Change: W. V. Quine and P. Feyerabend Jeu-Jenq Yuann Professor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy, National Taiwan University, 1 To all Participants

More information

PHILOSOPHY AND THEOLOGY

PHILOSOPHY AND THEOLOGY PHILOSOPHY AND THEOLOGY Paper 9774/01 Introduction to Philosophy and Theology Key Messages Most candidates gave equal treatment to three questions, displaying good time management and excellent control

More information

FIRST STUDY. The Existential Dialectical Basic Assumption of Kierkegaard s Analysis of Despair

FIRST STUDY. The Existential Dialectical Basic Assumption of Kierkegaard s Analysis of Despair FIRST STUDY The Existential Dialectical Basic Assumption of Kierkegaard s Analysis of Despair I 1. In recent decades, our understanding of the philosophy of philosophers such as Kant or Hegel has been

More information

Important dates. PSY 3360 / CGS 3325 Historical Perspectives on Psychology Minds and Machines since David Hume ( )

Important dates. PSY 3360 / CGS 3325 Historical Perspectives on Psychology Minds and Machines since David Hume ( ) PSY 3360 / CGS 3325 Historical Perspectives on Psychology Minds and Machines since 1600 Dr. Peter Assmann Spring 2018 Important dates Feb 14 Term paper draft due Upload paper to E-Learning https://elearning.utdallas.edu

More information

Descartes to Early Psychology. Phil 255

Descartes to Early Psychology. Phil 255 Descartes to Early Psychology Phil 255 Descartes World View Rationalism: the view that a priori considerations could lay the foundations for human knowledge. (i.e. Think hard enough and you will be lead

More information

Phenomenal Knowledge, Dualism, and Dreams Jesse Butler, University of Central Arkansas

Phenomenal Knowledge, Dualism, and Dreams Jesse Butler, University of Central Arkansas Phenomenal Knowledge, Dualism, and Dreams Jesse Butler, University of Central Arkansas Dwight Holbrook (2015b) expresses misgivings that phenomenal knowledge can be regarded as both an objectless kind

More information

Response to Gregory Floyd s Where Does Hermeneutics Lead? Brad Elliott Stone, Loyola Marymount University ACPA 2017

Response to Gregory Floyd s Where Does Hermeneutics Lead? Brad Elliott Stone, Loyola Marymount University ACPA 2017 Response to Gregory Floyd s Where Does Hermeneutics Lead? Brad Elliott Stone, Loyola Marymount University ACPA 2017 In his paper, Floyd offers a comparative presentation of hermeneutics as found in Heidegger

More information

Rethinking Knowledge: The Heuristic View

Rethinking Knowledge: The Heuristic View http://www.springer.com/gp/book/9783319532363 Carlo Cellucci Rethinking Knowledge: The Heuristic View 1 Preface From its very beginning, philosophy has been viewed as aimed at knowledge and methods to

More information

BonJour Against Materialism. Just an intellectual bandwagon?

BonJour Against Materialism. Just an intellectual bandwagon? BonJour Against Materialism Just an intellectual bandwagon? What is physicalism/materialism? materialist (or physicalist) views: views that hold that mental states are entirely material or physical in

More information

Introduction to Philosophy PHL 221, York College Revised, Spring 2017

Introduction to Philosophy PHL 221, York College Revised, Spring 2017 Introduction to Philosophy PHL 221, York College Revised, Spring 2017 Beginnings of Philosophy: Overview of Course (1) The Origins of Philosophy and Relativism Knowledge Are you a self? Ethics: What is

More information

On the intentionality-relative features of the world

On the intentionality-relative features of the world Filosofia Unisinos Unisinos Journal of Philosophy 17(2):149-154, may/aug 2016 Unisinos doi: 10.4013/fsu.2016.172.09 PHILOSOPHY SOUTH On the intentionality-relative features of the world Rodrigo A. dos

More information

STANISŁAW BRZOZOWSKI S CRITICAL HERMENEUTICS

STANISŁAW BRZOZOWSKI S CRITICAL HERMENEUTICS NORBERT LEŚNIEWSKI STANISŁAW BRZOZOWSKI S CRITICAL HERMENEUTICS Understanding is approachable only for one who is able to force for deep sympathy in the field of spirit and tragic history, for being perturbed

More information

Excerpt from J. Garvey, The Twenty Greatest Philosophy Books (Continuum, 2007): Immanuel Kant s Critique of Pure Reason

Excerpt from J. Garvey, The Twenty Greatest Philosophy Books (Continuum, 2007): Immanuel Kant s Critique of Pure Reason Excerpt from J. Garvey, The Twenty Greatest Philosophy Books (Continuum, 2007): Immanuel Kant s Critique of Pure Reason In a letter to Moses Mendelssohn, Kant says this about the Critique of Pure Reason:

More information

Heidegger's What is Metaphysics?

Heidegger's What is Metaphysics? Heidegger's What is Metaphysics? Heidegger's 1929 inaugural address at Freiburg University begins by posing the question 'what is metaphysics?' only to then immediately declare that it will 'forgo' a discussion

More information

Philosophy 203 History of Modern Western Philosophy. Russell Marcus Hamilton College Spring 2014

Philosophy 203 History of Modern Western Philosophy. Russell Marcus Hamilton College Spring 2014 Philosophy 203 History of Modern Western Philosophy Russell Marcus Hamilton College Spring 2014 Class #26 Kant s Copernican Revolution The Synthetic A Priori Forms of Intuition Marcus, Modern Philosophy,

More information

MY PURPOSE IN THIS BOOK IS TO PRESENT A

MY PURPOSE IN THIS BOOK IS TO PRESENT A I Holistic Pragmatism and the Philosophy of Culture MY PURPOSE IN THIS BOOK IS TO PRESENT A philosophical discussion of the main elements of civilization or culture such as science, law, religion, politics,

More information

Previous Final Examinations Philosophy 1

Previous Final Examinations Philosophy 1 Previous Final Examinations Philosophy 1 For each question, please write a short answer of about one paragraph in length. The answer should be written out in full sentences, not simple phrases. No books,

More information

Intro. The need for a philosophical vocabulary

Intro. The need for a philosophical vocabulary Critical Realism & Philosophy Webinar Ruth Groff August 5, 2015 Intro. The need for a philosophical vocabulary You don t have to become a philosopher, but just as philosophers should know their way around

More information

Strange bedfellows or Siamese twins? The search for the sacred in practical theology and psychology of religion

Strange bedfellows or Siamese twins? The search for the sacred in practical theology and psychology of religion Strange bedfellows or Siamese twins? The search for the sacred in practical theology and psychology of religion R.Ruard Ganzevoort A paper for the Symposium The relation between Psychology of Religion

More information

Ayer s linguistic theory of the a priori

Ayer s linguistic theory of the a priori Ayer s linguistic theory of the a priori phil 43904 Jeff Speaks December 4, 2007 1 The problem of a priori knowledge....................... 1 2 Necessity and the a priori............................ 2

More information

Think by Simon Blackburn. Chapter 7c The World

Think by Simon Blackburn. Chapter 7c The World Think by Simon Blackburn Chapter 7c The World Idealism Despite the power of Berkeley s critique, his resulting metaphysical view is highly problematic. Essentially, Berkeley concludes that there is no

More information

Lecture 38 CARTESIAN THEORY OF MIND REVISITED Overview. Key words: Cartesian Mind, Thought, Understanding, Computationality, and Noncomputationality.

Lecture 38 CARTESIAN THEORY OF MIND REVISITED Overview. Key words: Cartesian Mind, Thought, Understanding, Computationality, and Noncomputationality. Lecture 38 CARTESIAN THEORY OF MIND REVISITED Overview Descartes is one of the classical founders of non-computational theories of mind. In this paper my main argument is to show how Cartesian mind is

More information

Ludwig Wittgenstein: Philosophical Investigations

Ludwig Wittgenstein: Philosophical Investigations Ludwig Wittgenstein: Philosophical Investigations Published posthumously in 1953 Style and method Style o A collection of 693 numbered remarks (from one sentence up to one page, usually one paragraph long).

More information

Ludwig Feuerbach The Essence of Christianity (excerpts) 1 PHIL101 Prof. Oakes updated: 10/23/13 9:10 AM. Section III: How do I know? Reading III.

Ludwig Feuerbach The Essence of Christianity (excerpts) 1 PHIL101 Prof. Oakes updated: 10/23/13 9:10 AM. Section III: How do I know? Reading III. Ludwig Feuerbach The Essence of Christianity (excerpts) 1 PHIL101 Prof. Oakes updated: 10/23/13 9:10 AM Section III: How do I know? Reading III.6 The German philosopher, Ludwig Feuerbach, develops a humanist

More information

From Brains in Vats.

From Brains in Vats. From Brains in Vats. To God; And even to Myself, To a Malicious Demon; But, with I am, I exist (or Cogito ergo sum, i.e., I think therefore I am ), we have found the ultimate foundation. The place where

More information

THE REFUTATION OF PHENOMENALISM

THE REFUTATION OF PHENOMENALISM The Isaiah Berlin Virtual Library THE REFUTATION OF PHENOMENALISM A draft of section I of Empirical Propositions and Hypothetical Statements 1 The rights and wrongs of phenomenalism are perhaps more frequently

More information

Lonergan on General Transcendent Knowledge. In General Transcendent Knowledge, Chapter 19 of Insight, Lonergan does several things:

Lonergan on General Transcendent Knowledge. In General Transcendent Knowledge, Chapter 19 of Insight, Lonergan does several things: Lonergan on General Transcendent Knowledge In General Transcendent Knowledge, Chapter 19 of Insight, Lonergan does several things: 1-3--He provides a radical reinterpretation of the meaning of transcendence

More information

A Fundamental Thinking Error in Philosophy

A Fundamental Thinking Error in Philosophy Friedrich Seibold A Fundamental Thinking Error in Philosophy Abstract The present essay is a semantic and logical analysis of certain terms which coin decisively our metaphysical picture of the world.

More information

The Middle Path: A Case for the Philosophical Theologian. Leo Strauss roots the vitality of Western civilization in the ongoing conflict between

The Middle Path: A Case for the Philosophical Theologian. Leo Strauss roots the vitality of Western civilization in the ongoing conflict between Lee Anne Detzel PHI 8338 Revised: November 1, 2004 The Middle Path: A Case for the Philosophical Theologian Leo Strauss roots the vitality of Western civilization in the ongoing conflict between philosophy

More information

Scripture: Authority, Canon & Criticism Final Exam Sample Questions

Scripture: Authority, Canon & Criticism Final Exam Sample Questions Scripture: Authority, Canon & Criticism Final Exam Sample Questions 1. (T/F) A Worldview is a conceptual scheme by which we consciously or unconsciously place or fit everything we believe and by which

More information

Phil 114, Wednesday, April 11, 2012 Hegel, The Philosophy of Right 1 7, 10 12, 14 16, 22 23, 27 33, 135, 141

Phil 114, Wednesday, April 11, 2012 Hegel, The Philosophy of Right 1 7, 10 12, 14 16, 22 23, 27 33, 135, 141 Phil 114, Wednesday, April 11, 2012 Hegel, The Philosophy of Right 1 7, 10 12, 14 16, 22 23, 27 33, 135, 141 Dialectic: For Hegel, dialectic is a process governed by a principle of development, i.e., Reason

More information

Do we have knowledge of the external world?

Do we have knowledge of the external world? Do we have knowledge of the external world? This book discusses the skeptical arguments presented in Descartes' Meditations 1 and 2, as well as how Descartes attempts to refute skepticism by building our

More information

1/7. The Postulates of Empirical Thought

1/7. The Postulates of Empirical Thought 1/7 The Postulates of Empirical Thought This week we are focusing on the final section of the Analytic of Principles in which Kant schematizes the last set of categories. This set of categories are what

More information

1/5. The Critique of Theology

1/5. The Critique of Theology 1/5 The Critique of Theology The argument of the Transcendental Dialectic has demonstrated that there is no science of rational psychology and that the province of any rational cosmology is strictly limited.

More information

Notes on Hume and Kant

Notes on Hume and Kant Notes on Hume and Kant Daniel Bonevac, The University of Texas at Austin 1 Hume on Identity Hume, an empiricist, asks the question that his philosophical stance demands: nor have we any idea of self, after

More information

Saul Kripke, Naming and Necessity

Saul Kripke, Naming and Necessity 24.09x Minds and Machines Saul Kripke, Naming and Necessity Excerpt from Saul Kripke, Naming and Necessity (Harvard, 1980). Identity theorists have been concerned with several distinct types of identifications:

More information

Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Introduction

Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Introduction 24 Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Abstract: In this paper, I address Linda Zagzebski s analysis of the relation between moral testimony and understanding arguing that Aquinas

More information

Edmund Husserl s Transcendental Phenomenology by Wendell Allan A. Marinay

Edmund Husserl s Transcendental Phenomenology by Wendell Allan A. Marinay Edmund Husserl s Transcendental Phenomenology by Wendell Allan A. Marinay We remember Edmund Husserl as a philosopher who had a great influence on known phenomenologists like Max Scheler, Edith Stein,

More information

PART FOUR: CATHOLIC HERMENEUTICS

PART FOUR: CATHOLIC HERMENEUTICS PART FOUR: CATHOLIC HERMENEUTICS 367 368 INTRODUCTION TO PART FOUR The term Catholic hermeneutics refers to the understanding of Christianity within Roman Catholicism. It differs from the theory and practice

More information

Richard L. W. Clarke, Notes REASONING

Richard L. W. Clarke, Notes REASONING 1 REASONING Reasoning is, broadly speaking, the cognitive process of establishing reasons to justify beliefs, conclusions, actions or feelings. It also refers, more specifically, to the act or process

More information

Putnam: Meaning and Reference

Putnam: Meaning and Reference Putnam: Meaning and Reference The Traditional Conception of Meaning combines two assumptions: Meaning and psychology Knowing the meaning (of a word, sentence) is being in a psychological state. Even Frege,

More information

Søren Kierkegaard Philosophical Fragments, Concluding Scientific Postscript excerpts 1 PHIL101 Prof. Oakes updated: 10/10/13 12:03 PM

Søren Kierkegaard Philosophical Fragments, Concluding Scientific Postscript excerpts 1 PHIL101 Prof. Oakes updated: 10/10/13 12:03 PM Søren Kierkegaard Philosophical Fragments, Concluding Scientific Postscript excerpts 1 PHIL101 Prof. Oakes updated: 10/10/13 12:03 PM Section III: How do I know? Reading III.5 Søren Kierkegaard (1813-1855)

More information

The Supplement of Copula

The Supplement of Copula IRWLE Vol. 4 No. I January, 2008 69 The Quasi-transcendental as the condition of possibility of Linguistics, Philosophy and Ontology A Review of Derrida s The Supplement of Copula Chung Chin-Yi In The

More information

MODELS CLARIFIED: RESPONDING TO LANGDON GILKEY. by David E. Klemm and William H. Klink

MODELS CLARIFIED: RESPONDING TO LANGDON GILKEY. by David E. Klemm and William H. Klink MODELS CLARIFIED: RESPONDING TO LANGDON GILKEY by David E. Klemm and William H. Klink Abstract. We respond to concerns raised by Langdon Gilkey. The discussion addresses the nature of theological thinking

More information