PHILOSOPHY A.S. UNIT 2 PAPER, JUNE 2009 SUGGESTED ANSWERS TO SELECTED QUESTIONS

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "PHILOSOPHY A.S. UNIT 2 PAPER, JUNE 2009 SUGGESTED ANSWERS TO SELECTED QUESTIONS"

Transcription

1 PHILOSOPHY A.S. UNIT 2 PAPER, JUNE 2009 SUGGESTED ANSWERS TO SELECTED QUESTIONS In writing the answers to past exam questions, I have referred to AQA s mark schemes (available on their website) as far as possible. However, my answers should not be treated as carrying AQA s stamp of approval. They represent my considered opinion as to how these questions might reasonably be tackled. The BPA takes no responsibility for the examination performance of students who have used these answers. There are of course a range of valid ways of tackling most of these questions and mine represent, in each case, just one possible approach. Theme 1: Knowledge of the external world 1) Outline and illustrate the differences between sense data and physical objects. (15 marks) In the sense-datum theory of perception: Sense-data are considered as the immediate objects of perceptual awareness, in contrast to physical objects, which, it is claimed, are only perceived by the intermediary of sense-data. Sense-data only exist for as long as someone is actually aware of them, whereas the continued existence of physical objects is not normally dependent on perceptual awareness by anyone. A subject s having a sense-datum does not necessarily imply that there is any corresponding physical object present, as the subject may just be having a hallucination. The character of the sense-datum may not be a faithful reflection of the properties of the physical object, e.g. a straight stick in water may present to the subject a sense-datum that suggests a bent stick. This is how sense-datum theorists explain perceptual illusions. Sense-data are private objects. My sense-data cannot be known with any certainty by anyone but myself. In contrast, physical objects provide publicly accessible knowledge. My knowledge of my own (current) sense-data is often considered infallible I have a special first-person authority in relation to them that noone else can have. In the representative theory of perception, sense-data are correlated with the brain states which are the physical effects on my brain of the presence of the physical objects indirectly perceived by me. Sense-data are mental entities, unlike physical objects, which exist independently of the mind. N.B. There are obviously more points here than you need for full marks.

2 2) The existence of the external world is a reasonable hypothesis Consider what can be said both for and against this view. (30 marks) To common sense, the existence of the external world the world beyond one s own mind hardly seems like a hypothesis, as this would imply that it is subject to some degree of uncertainty. But according to the rigorous standards of traditional epistemology, only my own sense-data can be known to exist in the first instance. The claim that there exists an external, physical world must be considered a hypothesis, justified or not with reference to this core of personal, sensory knowledge. So, is it a reasonable hypothesis? Suppose (if it is possible to imagine) that we did not understand reality in terms of a stable and publicly observable system of physical entities, but instead as a series of unconnected and mostly short-lived sense-data. This would make it impossible to either predict or control our future sense-data, as we depend on our physical world-view for causal laws that make such prediction and control possible. We would be in psychological turmoil. However, while it may be granted that the physical world-view is an effective system for predicting and controlling our future sense-data, it does not necessarily follow from this that it is true. Might it not be that the totality of our sense-experience proceeds just as if physical objects were real, whereas in fact they are no more than mythical? Such a viewpoint would not imply that we ought to stop thinking in terms of physical objects. As already pointed out, it is scarcely possible for us to do that. It tells us rather that we should think of the physical world-view as a useful fiction. So-called realists about the physical world (which I guess includes most of us) would probably find such a view very strange. But how can it be avoided? How, in other words, can we bridge the gap between the idea of the physical world as a useful myth and the idea of it as something that is, in some sense, really there? One popular strategy is to argue that a belief in the literal truth of the physical hypothesis can be grounded on an inference to the best explanation. Both common sense and science provide plenty of examples of cases where we adopt a particular hypothesis because it is the one that seems to explain the totality of our evidence or experience better than any alternative. To see how this works in the present case, note firstly that there are alternative explanations of our sense-data besides the physical world-view. For example, there is the view (perhaps attributable to Berkeley) that we have the mental states we do because God has these mental states and he is letting us participate in his mental life. Now it will be argued by most philosophers that physical realism is a better explanation of our experiences than this one, presumably on the grounds of its greater simplicity. They will argue that the simplest explanation of the fact that the pattern of our sense-data is just as if physical things were real is that they are real. However, a difficulty can be raised for this strategy, which is as follows: how do we know that inference to the best explanation will lead to the truth? The reason we trust inference to the best explanation as a (generally) reliable method is that we have known it to work in many cases and rarely known it to fail, and so we infer from this that it will work in other cases too. This implies that we have been able to confirm independently in many cases that the explanation inferred using the method was the

3 correct one. In a sense, this is true, but the problem is that once the existence of the physical world is put in doubt, what we ought to say is that we have been able to confirm in such cases that our experience is just as if the explanation were true, not that the explanation actually is true. In that case, our backing for the method of inference to the best explanation only supports the thesis that explanations inferred using the method that are cast in purely experiential terms are likely to be true. Obviously, this will not do for the physical world hypothesis, since by its very nature, it cannot be cast in purely experiential terms it concerns what lies beyond experience. Perhaps we should have avoided going down this road in the first place. Perhaps it was wrong to talk about the hypothesis of the existence of an external world; in other words, it is an illusion to think that there is really anything to be uncertain about here. There are two main ways of supporting such a position. One is to suggest that the starting-point is wrong. It is simply incorrect to think that we are in the position of solitary minds with access only to private sense-data, from which we must either construct or infer a physical world. This is not the line I will pursue here. Instead I will briefly investigate a different approach. It is that the hypothesis idea is wrong because the distinction between everything s being just as if there were a physical world, on the one hand, and there being a physical world, on the other, is a false one. The suggestion here is that once we know that the overall pattern of our experience is such as to suggest a physical world, this in itself is all we need to confirm that precisely such a thing exists. The assumption, made throughout this essay up to now, that there is some kind of gap here is simply a mistake. This suggestion may seem like a non-starter. Surely, it will be said, the difference between the way things seem and the way they are is fundamental. But notice that whenever in everyday life we establish that things are not as they seem, we do so using evidence of some kind and this evidence comes to us ultimately in the form of sensations. The problem with the idea of a physical world hypothesis is that it is considered to be something that holds or does not hold independently of our sensations and this makes no sense. We cannot make sense of the idea that the physical world does or does not exist if that does not boil down to some difference in the sensations we have. It might be thought that this is just a form of phenomenalism, the view that the physical world is a construct from sense-data. But that would be a mistake. I am not saying that physical things are ultimately unreal or that they are in any sense created by our mental states. These are first order statements about the relationship between our mental states and the physical world. I am not making any specific claims of this sort here. I am only making a second order claim about our statements or thoughts regarding our mental states and those regarding physical things, which is that there is a tight logical relation between them, with the result that the statement There are no physical things, even though our mental states are just as if there were makes no sense. No doubt more needs to be said in order to be sure that this position does not collapse into phenomenalism, but there is insufficient space to do so here!

4 Theme 2: Tolerance 3) Explain and illustrate two reasons why tolerance should not rule out being offensive. (15 marks) Some people, following John Stuart Mill, would claim that we should not try to interfere with others freedom unless their behaviour is harmful to others. Offending other people could cause them real harm in extreme cases. For example, insulting Mohammed could traumatise a devout believer. The difficulty is in knowing whether that has indeed been the effect. One cannot necessarily take the believer s own claim at face value, as he/she might exaggerate the negative effect of the offence. One would be in danger of creating a situation where those who shout the loudest are able to exert control over what people can say, which would be extremely unfair. One of the main reasons for supposing that society should be tolerant of diverse opinions is that it is only through free, unfettered discussion that truth can ultimately be known. It might be thought that offensiveness would make no significant contribution to this process, since any particular opinion expressed in an offensive way could also be expressed without the offensive element with no loss to its cognitive content. However, this would be to take too narrow a view of the process of debate within a free society. It is not enough for certain views to be expressed: in order for them to make their contribution to the debate they must get noticed. One way of getting your ideas noticed is to express them in a lively, vigorous or humorous way. Satire directed at religion would be an example of this. While it may offend those who adhere to the religious beliefs in question, the irreverent expression of the ideas helps to gain them attention, without which they might perish. While this does not justify the most hurtful and vicious kinds of expression, it does justify an approach to the expression of certain ideas that is not overly sensitive to the views and feelings of those who are opposed to them. 4) Discuss the claim that society should be tolerant because the benefits of toleration outweigh the costs. (30 marks) We need to begin by clarifying what is meant by tolerance, as this is a very broad concept. What exactly does tolerance involve and what is it that society is required to tolerate? I shall defend the classical liberal answer: society should tolerate everything except the infliction of demonstrable harm on others. What tolerance of X involves is abstaining from any coercive action designed to prevent X and perhaps also abstaining from the active discouragement of X. These answers themselves no doubt raise many questions, but will suffice for the purposes of this essay. I shall consider first the costs of this policy. One is the fact that if society tolerates a wide range of (non-harmful) types of behaviour and the expression of a wide diversity of opinions, this may lead to many people being deeply offended by behaviour or opinions that they strongly disagree with. This in itself may be thought to be a bad thing, but there is the additional fact that it may lead to dangerous social conflict. Although the actions of individuals involved in this conflict are likely to be harmful to

5 others and therefore legitimately prohibited by the state, such prohibition may not be entirely successful and the acts of punishment that it involves may be considered additional costs to be set alongside the costs involved in the conflict itself. I shall refer to this type of cost of tolerance as its threat to social cohesion. A further type of cost will be experienced by people who have a richer conception of the good life than is embodied in the principle of non-harm. This applies to almost all of us, since nearly all of us think that we ought not only to desist from harming others, but also (other things being equal) to avoid upsetting them and in some cases to take positive steps to help them (to be a good Samaritan ). On the conception of the tolerant society that I have in mind (a fairly standard one), we are required to tolerate indifference or even unkindness to others if this falls short of actual harming and these may be considered to be, or to lead to, costs that we should be concerned about. Others with even richer conceptions of the good life (e.g., those dictated by various religious views) will find even more costs in this kind of tolerance, due to the fact that people will not be required to live their lives according to their particular standard. Obviously, though, there will be much more disagreement about these sorts of costs than about those already mentioned and little chance of obtaining a publicly acceptable way of resolving these disagreements. So much for the costs. What are the benefits of societal tolerance? One of these concerns specifically the consequences of tolerating a wide variety of ideas and opinions. It is argued that doing this assists discovery of the truth, since the only way of attaining truth is to allow the expression of the widest diversity of views, which can then be tested in the court of public opinion (or perhaps in more specialised arenas in the case of more technical matters). The widest diversity of views is needed, since we cannot rule out in advance what might turn out to be the case on any given matter. (That the world is a sphere must at some time have seemed an extraordinary idea that could not possibly be true, yet it turned out that it was.) There is also the tolerance of different lifestyles to consider. Here it is argued that such tolerance allows a range of experiments in living. As in the case of the truth of opinions, we cannot know in advance the best ways for human beings to live, so our only viable course as a society is to let people live the kinds of lives they want to (subject to the non-harm constraint) and examine the results to determine which is best. Identifying the main costs and benefits of tolerance is one thing, weighing them so as to reach a conclusion about its overall desirability is a more difficult matter. But perhaps the task can be made more manageable by noting that not all these costs are beyond our control. For example, we can perhaps minimise the costs in terms of the threat to social cohesion by instituting strong propaganda in favour of tolerance, promoting its virtues. This can be reinforced by introducing pro-tolerance ideas into the education of young people from the earliest opportunity. Additionally, the state can seek to reduce those factors that tend to exacerbate social conflict, e.g., poverty and lack of opportunity, employing such means as redistributive taxation and antidiscrimination laws. In such ways the cost to social cohesion can be reduced considerably. What of the costs relating to the thinness of the tolerant society s conception of the good life, its refusal to enforce a richer morality than that of mere non-harming? Notice that a refusal to enforce a morality is not the same as an

6 indifference to whether it is realised. There are some aspects of rich morality that the state would do well to actively foster, even if (quite rightly) it does not attempt to enforce them. These include kindness to others and a willingness to help them, at least when the costs to oneself would be minimal. This should not be taken to imply that the state should support even by mere encouragement all elements that have ever been thought by anyone to be parts of morality. That would obviously lead to contradictions, as many moral systems are mutually inconsistent. (For example, one cannot simultaneously support a system that requires arranged marriages and denounces them.) In view of these considerations, it is plausible to suppose that the costs of the tolerant society can be reduced to such an extent that they are outweighed by its benefits in terms of enabling rational discussion and experiments in living. The argument can be further strengthened by noting that not only does tolerance have benefits, nontolerance has costs, namely those punitive actions that involve enforcement of whatever standard it is thought necessary to impose on people. Not only are these serious in themselves; they also risk, by a slippery slope effect, the emergence of a totalitarian state. Theme 5: Free will and determinism 9) Contrast determinism with fatalism, illustrating your answer. (15 marks) Suppose I consult a palm reader, who sees that my love line is rather short and tells me that I will always be unlucky in love. If I believe the palm reader, then I am a fatalist, at least about my love life. Fatalism is the view that what will be true is true now and has always been true and is thus incapable of being altered by human action. In my example, I will think that I am going to be unlucky in love whatever anybody does, including myself. Thus fatalists believe that certain things are inescapably destined to happen to us, and that human action cannot prevent them. In contrast with this, determinists will not think that human action is generally useless in affecting events in our lives. For determinism may be defined as the thesis that a determinate set of conditions can only produce one possible outcome given fixed laws of nature. In other words, the conditions, together with the laws of nature, fully determine the outcome via some set of causal processes. An example of a deterministic explanation would be the movements of the planets according to Newton s law of gravitation. However, there is no reason why the relevant causal processes should not sometimes involve human actions, and so the determinist is not committed to asserting that human action is never efficacious. 10) Explore the claim that We make the choices we do because of our nature. (30 marks) The claim can be interpreted as meaning that we make the choices we do only because we are the sorts of people we are genetically. According to this view, the circumstances of our lives, e.g., the way in which we were brought up (our nurture ), do not fundamentally affect what choices we make. Thus interpreted, the claim is an empirical one and almost certainly false. Both common sense and much research in

7 social psychology supports the view that the circumstances of our lives, such as our cultural inheritance and the influence of our parents, can profoundly affect what choices we subsequently go on to make. Of course, no-one would deny that our genetic nature has an important role to play. But the suggestion that it is only our genetic nature that is important is very implausible. Alternatively, the claim might be understood in a weakened way to mean that it is mainly our nature that determines our choices. In that case it is not obviously false, but it is still an empirical claim that can only be substantiated by empirical research. What is the connection between this claim and the issue of moral responsibility? There is an important argument (due to Galen Strawson) which tries to argue from the premise that all our choices are due to our nature to the conclusion that we are not morally responsible for them. It runs as follows: 1. All our choices are due to our individual natures. 2. We do not determine our individual natures. 3. Therefore, we are not morally responsible for our individual natures. 4. Therefore we are not morally responsible for our choices. However, for this argument to work, a person s nature must be understood in a broader sense than it has been so far in this essay, i.e., broader than it is in the nature vs. nurture debate. In this broader sense, my nature consists in everything that I intrinsically am at a given time, irrespective of whether it derives from my genes or the influences from my life so far. Let us examine each of the steps in turn. First: step 1, the premise that all our choices are due to our natures, i.e., the claim cited (in slightly different wording) in the exam question. It seems that when the term nature is understood in the broad way indicated, there is only one way that this premise could fail to be true, which is that there could be indeterminacy affecting our choices, i.e., that to some extent, our choices cannot be explained by anything at all. Of course this does not make them totally random. A person s choices must be affected by her nature to some extent, probably to a very large extent. The claim would only be that to some degree (perhaps so small as to be undetectable), there is pure randomness involved, e.g., there is a probability of a given individual with a given nature making a given choice in a given situation of 99.9% rather than 100%, and there simply is no deeper explanation for precisely why the choice goes one way rather than the other. This is conceivable, and in principle at least, science allows a way in which it could happen quantum indeterminacy. However, the importance of this should not be overestimated. If we were to appeal to this to save moral responsibility, we would be letting the latter depend on recognition of randomness in the world. This does not seem to make very much sense. For moral responsibility, we would surely need, not the absence or incompleteness of an explanation, but rather a particular kind of explanation, one that sees my choices as being due to me in some very deep sense. Of course, explaining my choices as being due to my nature could fit the bill if I can be identified with my nature. But if the rest of the argument goes through, this cannot be done without detriment to my moral responsibility.

8 Let us now turn to the second step in the argument, which is the statement that a person does not determine her own nature. Now clearly this must be true for the most part. My nature is basically my character and I did not form my own character. (It was formed by some combination of my genes and my environment.) However, it is not clear that I am completely impotent in the formation of my own character. For example, if I want to turn myself into a kinder person, perhaps I could start by forcing myself to perform some kind acts, in the hope that after a while such behaviour will become more habitual for me and thus capable of being considered part of my character. This may be possible, but it does not undermine the claim that I cannot form my own character. For what determines my decision to try to change my character? If the first step in the argument is correct, i.e., if all my choices are indeed due to my nature, it must be some part of my nature that determines this. We are back to where we were before, for the question then arises: how could I determine that part of my nature that determined this decision? An infinite regress threatens. It seems that this can only be avoided by conceding that I cannot in fact have any control over the development of my own nature. The third statement, that we are not responsible for our individual nature, seems to follow once the second is accepted. As I had ultimately no part in forming it, how could I be held responsible for it? How could I legitimately be blamed for any of its flaws or praised for any of its virtues? The fourth statement does appear to follow from the first and third. It implicitly appeals to the principle that if I am not responsible for X and Y is entirely due to X, then I cannot be held responsible for Y either. This appears to be a necessary truth and so, given the premises of the argument, the conclusion that we are not morally responsible for our choices, seems unassailable. The above argument provides an interesting alternative to the simple appeal to determinism for supporting the idea that we lack moral responsibility for our actions. Of course, acceptance of this conclusion remains hard, since the idea of moral responsibility seems to be deeply involved in almost everyone s moral understanding. Whether this points to a genuine conceptual connection is another matter, which cannot, however, be explored here.

Ayer on the argument from illusion

Ayer on the argument from illusion Ayer on the argument from illusion Jeff Speaks Philosophy 370 October 5, 2004 1 The objects of experience.............................. 1 2 The argument from illusion............................. 2 2.1

More information

SUPPORT MATERIAL FOR 'DETERMINISM AND FREE WILL ' (UNIT 2 TOPIC 5)

SUPPORT MATERIAL FOR 'DETERMINISM AND FREE WILL ' (UNIT 2 TOPIC 5) SUPPORT MATERIAL FOR 'DETERMINISM AND FREE WILL ' (UNIT 2 TOPIC 5) Introduction We often say things like 'I couldn't resist buying those trainers'. In saying this, we presumably mean that the desire to

More information

Perception and Mind-Dependence: Lecture 2

Perception and Mind-Dependence: Lecture 2 1 Recap Perception and Mind-Dependence: Lecture 2 (Alex Moran, apm60@ cam.ac.uk) According to naïve realism: (1) the objects of perception are ordinary, mindindependent things, and (2) perceptual experience

More information

Ethical non-naturalism

Ethical non-naturalism Michael Lacewing Ethical non-naturalism Ethical non-naturalism is usually understood as a form of cognitivist moral realism. So we first need to understand what cognitivism and moral realism is before

More information

Martin s case for disjunctivism

Martin s case for disjunctivism Martin s case for disjunctivism Jeff Speaks January 19, 2006 1 The argument from naive realism and experiential naturalism.......... 1 2 The argument from the modesty of disjunctivism.................

More information

Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000)

Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000) Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000) One of the advantages traditionally claimed for direct realist theories of perception over indirect realist theories is that the

More information

Are There Reasons to Be Rational?

Are There Reasons to Be Rational? Are There Reasons to Be Rational? Olav Gjelsvik, University of Oslo The thesis. Among people writing about rationality, few people are more rational than Wlodek Rabinowicz. But are there reasons for being

More information

The Qualiafications (or Lack Thereof) of Epiphenomenal Qualia

The Qualiafications (or Lack Thereof) of Epiphenomenal Qualia Francesca Hovagimian Philosophy of Psychology Professor Dinishak 5 March 2016 The Qualiafications (or Lack Thereof) of Epiphenomenal Qualia In his essay Epiphenomenal Qualia, Frank Jackson makes the case

More information

Ethics is subjective.

Ethics is subjective. Introduction Scientific Method and Research Ethics Ethical Theory Greg Bognar Stockholm University September 22, 2017 Ethics is subjective. If ethics is subjective, then moral claims are subjective in

More information

Naturalized Epistemology. 1. What is naturalized Epistemology? Quine PY4613

Naturalized Epistemology. 1. What is naturalized Epistemology? Quine PY4613 Naturalized Epistemology Quine PY4613 1. What is naturalized Epistemology? a. How is it motivated? b. What are its doctrines? c. Naturalized Epistemology in the context of Quine s philosophy 2. Naturalized

More information

Foundationalism Vs. Skepticism: The Greater Philosophical Ideology

Foundationalism Vs. Skepticism: The Greater Philosophical Ideology 1. Introduction Ryan C. Smith Philosophy 125W- Final Paper April 24, 2010 Foundationalism Vs. Skepticism: The Greater Philosophical Ideology Throughout this paper, the goal will be to accomplish three

More information

Consciousness might be defined as the perceiver of mental phenomena. We might say that there are no differences between one perceiver and another, as

Consciousness might be defined as the perceiver of mental phenomena. We might say that there are no differences between one perceiver and another, as 2. DO THE VALUES THAT ARE CALLED HUMAN RIGHTS HAVE INDEPENDENT AND UNIVERSAL VALIDITY, OR ARE THEY HISTORICALLY AND CULTURALLY RELATIVE HUMAN INVENTIONS? Human rights significantly influence the fundamental

More information

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology. Topic 6: Theories of Justification: Foundationalism versus Coherentism. Part 2: Susan Haack s Foundherentist Approach

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology. Topic 6: Theories of Justification: Foundationalism versus Coherentism. Part 2: Susan Haack s Foundherentist Approach Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 6: Theories of Justification: Foundationalism versus Coherentism Part 2: Susan Haack s Foundherentist Approach Susan Haack, "A Foundherentist Theory of Empirical Justification"

More information

EPISTEMOLOGY for DUMMIES

EPISTEMOLOGY for DUMMIES EPISTEMOLOGY for DUMMIES Cary Cook 2008 Epistemology doesn t help us know much more than we would have known if we had never heard of it. But it does force us to admit that we don t know some of the things

More information

Introduction to Cognitivism; Motivational Externalism; Naturalist Cognitivism

Introduction to Cognitivism; Motivational Externalism; Naturalist Cognitivism Introduction to Cognitivism; Motivational Externalism; Naturalist Cognitivism Felix Pinkert 103 Ethics: Metaethics, University of Oxford, Hilary Term 2015 Cognitivism, Non-cognitivism, and the Humean Argument

More information

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 4: Skepticism. Part 1: The Scope of Skepticism and Two Main Types of Skeptical Argument

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 4: Skepticism. Part 1: The Scope of Skepticism and Two Main Types of Skeptical Argument 1. The Scope of Skepticism Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 4: Skepticism Part 1: The Scope of Skepticism and Two Main Types of Skeptical Argument The scope of skeptical challenges can vary in a number

More information

Chapter 2 Reasoning about Ethics

Chapter 2 Reasoning about Ethics Chapter 2 Reasoning about Ethics TRUE/FALSE 1. The statement "nearly all Americans believe that individual liberty should be respected" is a normative claim. F This is a statement about people's beliefs;

More information

PHILOSOPHY A.S. UNIT 2 PAPER, JANUARY 2009 SUGGESTED ANSWERS TO SELECTED QUESTIONS

PHILOSOPHY A.S. UNIT 2 PAPER, JANUARY 2009 SUGGESTED ANSWERS TO SELECTED QUESTIONS PHILOSOPHY A.S. UNIT 2 PAPER, JANUARY 2009 SUGGESTED ANSWERS TO SELECTED QUESTIONS In writing the answers to past exam questions, I have referred to AQA s mark schemes (available on their website) as far

More information

Class #14: October 13 Gödel s Platonism

Class #14: October 13 Gödel s Platonism Philosophy 405: Knowledge, Truth and Mathematics Fall 2010 Hamilton College Russell Marcus Class #14: October 13 Gödel s Platonism I. The Continuum Hypothesis and Its Independence The continuum problem

More information

TWO ACCOUNTS OF THE NORMATIVITY OF RATIONALITY

TWO ACCOUNTS OF THE NORMATIVITY OF RATIONALITY DISCUSSION NOTE BY JONATHAN WAY JOURNAL OF ETHICS & SOCIAL PHILOSOPHY DISCUSSION NOTE DECEMBER 2009 URL: WWW.JESP.ORG COPYRIGHT JONATHAN WAY 2009 Two Accounts of the Normativity of Rationality RATIONALITY

More information

General Philosophy. Dr Peter Millican,, Hertford College. Lecture 4: Two Cartesian Topics

General Philosophy. Dr Peter Millican,, Hertford College. Lecture 4: Two Cartesian Topics General Philosophy Dr Peter Millican,, Hertford College Lecture 4: Two Cartesian Topics Scepticism, and the Mind 2 Last Time we looked at scepticism about INDUCTION. This Lecture will move on to SCEPTICISM

More information

Philosophy Epistemology. Topic 3 - Skepticism

Philosophy Epistemology. Topic 3 - Skepticism Michael Huemer on Skepticism Philosophy 3340 - Epistemology Topic 3 - Skepticism Chapter II. The Lure of Radical Skepticism 1. Mike Huemer defines radical skepticism as follows: Philosophical skeptics

More information

Philosophical Perspectives, 16, Language and Mind, 2002 THE AIM OF BELIEF 1. Ralph Wedgwood Merton College, Oxford

Philosophical Perspectives, 16, Language and Mind, 2002 THE AIM OF BELIEF 1. Ralph Wedgwood Merton College, Oxford Philosophical Perspectives, 16, Language and Mind, 2002 THE AIM OF BELIEF 1 Ralph Wedgwood Merton College, Oxford 0. Introduction It is often claimed that beliefs aim at the truth. Indeed, this claim has

More information

KANT S EXPLANATION OF THE NECESSITY OF GEOMETRICAL TRUTHS. John Watling

KANT S EXPLANATION OF THE NECESSITY OF GEOMETRICAL TRUTHS. John Watling KANT S EXPLANATION OF THE NECESSITY OF GEOMETRICAL TRUTHS John Watling Kant was an idealist. His idealism was in some ways, it is true, less extreme than that of Berkeley. He distinguished his own by calling

More information

George Berkeley. The Principles of Human Knowledge. Review

George Berkeley. The Principles of Human Knowledge. Review George Berkeley The Principles of Human Knowledge Review To be is to be perceived Obvious to the Mind all those bodies which compose the earth have no subsistence without a mind, their being is to be perceived

More information

Title II: The CAPE International Conferen Philosophy of Time )

Title II: The CAPE International Conferen Philosophy of Time ) Against the illusion theory of temp Title (Proceedings of the CAPE Internatio II: The CAPE International Conferen Philosophy of Time ) Author(s) Braddon-Mitchell, David Citation CAPE Studies in Applied

More information

Chapter 5: Freedom and Determinism

Chapter 5: Freedom and Determinism Chapter 5: Freedom and Determinism At each time t the world is perfectly determinate in all detail. - Let us grant this for the sake of argument. We might want to re-visit this perfectly reasonable assumption

More information

THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE

THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE Diametros nr 29 (wrzesień 2011): 80-92 THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE Karol Polcyn 1. PRELIMINARIES Chalmers articulates his argument in terms of two-dimensional

More information

(i) Morality is a system; and (ii) It is a system comprised of moral rules and principles.

(i) Morality is a system; and (ii) It is a system comprised of moral rules and principles. Ethics and Morality Ethos (Greek) and Mores (Latin) are terms having to do with custom, habit, and behavior. Ethics is the study of morality. This definition raises two questions: (a) What is morality?

More information

Hume s emotivism. Michael Lacewing

Hume s emotivism. Michael Lacewing Michael Lacewing Hume s emotivism Theories of what morality is fall into two broad families cognitivism and noncognitivism. The distinction is now understood by philosophers to depend on whether one thinks

More information

Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Introduction

Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Introduction 24 Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Abstract: In this paper, I address Linda Zagzebski s analysis of the relation between moral testimony and understanding arguing that Aquinas

More information

Philosophy 428M Topics in the History of Philosophy: Hume MW 2-3:15 Skinner Syllabus

Philosophy 428M Topics in the History of Philosophy: Hume MW 2-3:15 Skinner Syllabus 1 INSTRUCTOR: Mathias Frisch OFICE ADDRESS: Skinner 1108B PHONE: (301) 405-5710 E-MAIL: mfrisch@umd.edu OFFICE HOURS: Tuesday 10-12 Philosophy 428M Topics in the History of Philosophy: Hume MW 2-3:15 Skinner

More information

Russell s Problems of Philosophy

Russell s Problems of Philosophy Russell s Problems of Philosophy IT S (NOT) ALL IN YOUR HEAD J a n u a r y 1 9 Today : 1. Review Existence & Nature of Matter 2. Russell s case against Idealism 3. Next Lecture 2.0 Review Existence & Nature

More information

2014 Examination Report 2014 Extended Investigation GA 2: Critical Thinking Test GENERAL COMMENTS

2014 Examination Report 2014 Extended Investigation GA 2: Critical Thinking Test GENERAL COMMENTS 2014 Extended Investigation GA 2: Critical Thinking Test GENERAL COMMENTS The Extended Investigation Critical Thinking Test assesses the ability of students to produce arguments, and to analyse and assess

More information

Unit VI: Davidson and the interpretational approach to thought and language

Unit VI: Davidson and the interpretational approach to thought and language Unit VI: Davidson and the interpretational approach to thought and language October 29, 2003 1 Davidson s interdependence thesis..................... 1 2 Davidson s arguments for interdependence................

More information

Final Paper. May 13, 2015

Final Paper. May 13, 2015 24.221 Final Paper May 13, 2015 Determinism states the following: given the state of the universe at time t 0, denoted S 0, and the conjunction of the laws of nature, L, the state of the universe S at

More information

PHL340 Handout 8: Evaluating Dogmatism

PHL340 Handout 8: Evaluating Dogmatism PHL340 Handout 8: Evaluating Dogmatism 1 Dogmatism Last class we looked at Jim Pryor s paper on dogmatism about perceptual justification (for background on the notion of justification, see the handout

More information

Reason and Explanation: A Defense of Explanatory Coherentism. BY TED POSTON (Basingstoke,

Reason and Explanation: A Defense of Explanatory Coherentism. BY TED POSTON (Basingstoke, Reason and Explanation: A Defense of Explanatory Coherentism. BY TED POSTON (Basingstoke, UK: Palgrave Macmillan, 2014. Pp. 208. Price 60.) In this interesting book, Ted Poston delivers an original and

More information

Précis of Empiricism and Experience. Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh

Précis of Empiricism and Experience. Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh Précis of Empiricism and Experience Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh My principal aim in the book is to understand the logical relationship of experience to knowledge. Say that I look out of my window

More information

Russell s Problems of Philosophy

Russell s Problems of Philosophy Russell s Problems of Philosophy KNOWLEDGE: A CQUAINTANCE & DESCRIPTION J a n u a r y 2 4 Today : 1. Review Russell s against Idealism 2. Knowledge by Acquaintance & Description 3. What are we acquianted

More information

Rule-Following and the Ontology of the Mind Abstract The problem of rule-following

Rule-Following and the Ontology of the Mind Abstract The problem of rule-following Rule-Following and the Ontology of the Mind Michael Esfeld (published in Uwe Meixner and Peter Simons (eds.): Metaphysics in the Post-Metaphysical Age. Papers of the 22nd International Wittgenstein Symposium.

More information

1/10. The Fourth Paralogism and the Refutation of Idealism

1/10. The Fourth Paralogism and the Refutation of Idealism 1/10 The Fourth Paralogism and the Refutation of Idealism The Fourth Paralogism is quite different from the three that preceded it because, although it is treated as a part of rational psychology, it main

More information

Why I Am Not a Property Dualist By John R. Searle

Why I Am Not a Property Dualist By John R. Searle 1 Why I Am Not a Property Dualist By John R. Searle I have argued in a number of writings 1 that the philosophical part (though not the neurobiological part) of the traditional mind-body problem has a

More information

Logic, Truth & Epistemology. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

Logic, Truth & Epistemology. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology Logic, Truth & Epistemology Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology Philosophical Theology 1 (TH5) Aug. 15 Intro to Philosophical Theology; Logic Aug. 22 Truth & Epistemology Aug. 29 Metaphysics

More information

Is there a good epistemological argument against platonism? DAVID LIGGINS

Is there a good epistemological argument against platonism? DAVID LIGGINS [This is the penultimate draft of an article that appeared in Analysis 66.2 (April 2006), 135-41, available here by permission of Analysis, the Analysis Trust, and Blackwell Publishing. The definitive

More information

CAUSATION 1 THE BASICS OF CAUSATION

CAUSATION 1 THE BASICS OF CAUSATION CAUSATION 1 A founder of the study of international relations, E. H. Carr, once said: The study of history is a study of causes. 2 Because a basis for thinking about international affairs is history, he

More information

Three Fundamentals of the Introceptive Philosophy

Three Fundamentals of the Introceptive Philosophy Three Fundamentals of the Introceptive Philosophy Part 9 of 16 Franklin Merrell-Wolff January 19, 1974 Certain thoughts have come to me in the interim since the dictation of that which is on the tape already

More information

Bertrand Russell Proper Names, Adjectives and Verbs 1

Bertrand Russell Proper Names, Adjectives and Verbs 1 Bertrand Russell Proper Names, Adjectives and Verbs 1 Analysis 46 Philosophical grammar can shed light on philosophical questions. Grammatical differences can be used as a source of discovery and a guide

More information

Are Practical Reasons Like Theoretical Reasons?

Are Practical Reasons Like Theoretical Reasons? Are Practical Reasons Like Theoretical Reasons? Jordan Wolf March 30, 2010 1 1 Introduction Particularism is said to be many things, some of them fairly radical, but in truth the position is straightforward.

More information

Positivism A Model Of For System Of Rules

Positivism A Model Of For System Of Rules Positivism A Model Of For System Of Rules Positivism is a model of and for a system of rules, and its central notion of a single fundamental test for law forces us to miss the important standards that

More information

proper construal of Davidson s principle of rationality will show the objection to be misguided. Andrew Wong Washington University, St.

proper construal of Davidson s principle of rationality will show the objection to be misguided. Andrew Wong Washington University, St. Do e s An o m a l o u s Mo n i s m Hav e Explanatory Force? Andrew Wong Washington University, St. Louis The aim of this paper is to support Donald Davidson s Anomalous Monism 1 as an account of law-governed

More information

Epistemological Externalism and the Project of Traditional Epistemology. Contemporary philosophers still haven't come to terms with the project of

Epistemological Externalism and the Project of Traditional Epistemology. Contemporary philosophers still haven't come to terms with the project of Epistemological Externalism and the Project of Traditional Epistemology 1 Epistemological Externalism and the Project of Traditional Epistemology Contemporary philosophers still haven't come to terms with

More information

KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST. Arnon Keren

KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST. Arnon Keren Abstracta SPECIAL ISSUE VI, pp. 33 46, 2012 KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST Arnon Keren Epistemologists of testimony widely agree on the fact that our reliance on other people's testimony is extensive. However,

More information

Think by Simon Blackburn. Chapter 7c The World

Think by Simon Blackburn. Chapter 7c The World Think by Simon Blackburn Chapter 7c The World Idealism Despite the power of Berkeley s critique, his resulting metaphysical view is highly problematic. Essentially, Berkeley concludes that there is no

More information

Essay Discuss Both Sides and Give your Opinion

Essay Discuss Both Sides and Give your Opinion Essay Discuss Both Sides and Give your Opinion Contents: General Structure: 2 DOs and DONTs 3 Example Answer One: 4 Language for strengthening and weakening 8 Useful Structures 11 What is the overall structure

More information

Chapter 2 Ethical Concepts and Ethical Theories: Establishing and Justifying a Moral System

Chapter 2 Ethical Concepts and Ethical Theories: Establishing and Justifying a Moral System Chapter 2 Ethical Concepts and Ethical Theories: Establishing and Justifying a Moral System Ethics and Morality Ethics: greek ethos, study of morality What is Morality? Morality: system of rules for guiding

More information

Saul Kripke, Naming and Necessity

Saul Kripke, Naming and Necessity 24.09x Minds and Machines Saul Kripke, Naming and Necessity Excerpt from Saul Kripke, Naming and Necessity (Harvard, 1980). Identity theorists have been concerned with several distinct types of identifications:

More information

Realism and instrumentalism

Realism and instrumentalism Published in H. Pashler (Ed.) The Encyclopedia of the Mind (2013), Thousand Oaks, CA: SAGE Publications, pp. 633 636 doi:10.4135/9781452257044 mark.sprevak@ed.ac.uk Realism and instrumentalism Mark Sprevak

More information

What one needs to know to prepare for'spinoza's method is to be found in the treatise, On the Improvement

What one needs to know to prepare for'spinoza's method is to be found in the treatise, On the Improvement SPINOZA'S METHOD Donald Mangum The primary aim of this paper will be to provide the reader of Spinoza with a certain approach to the Ethics. The approach is designed to prevent what I believe to be certain

More information

Causation and Free Will

Causation and Free Will Causation and Free Will T L Hurst Revised: 17th August 2011 Abstract This paper looks at the main philosophic positions on free will. It suggests that the arguments for causal determinism being compatible

More information

From: Michael Huemer, Ethical Intuitionism (2005)

From: Michael Huemer, Ethical Intuitionism (2005) From: Michael Huemer, Ethical Intuitionism (2005) 214 L rsmkv!rs ks syxssm! finds Sally funny, but later decides he was mistaken about her funniness when the audience merely groans.) It seems, then, that

More information

GREAT PHILOSOPHERS: Thomas Reid ( ) Peter West 25/09/18

GREAT PHILOSOPHERS: Thomas Reid ( ) Peter West 25/09/18 GREAT PHILOSOPHERS: Thomas Reid (1710-1796) Peter West 25/09/18 Some context Aristotle (384-322 BCE) Lucretius (c. 99-55 BCE) Thomas Reid (1710-1796 AD) 400 BCE 0 Much of (Western) scholastic philosophy

More information

16 Free Will Requires Determinism

16 Free Will Requires Determinism 16 Free Will Requires Determinism John Baer The will is infinite, and the execution confined... the desire is boundless, and the act a slave to limit. William Shakespeare, Troilus and Cressida, III. ii.75

More information

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea. Book reviews World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Naturalism, by Michael C. Rea. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2004, viii + 245 pp., $24.95. This is a splendid book. Its ideas are bold and

More information

How Not to Defend Metaphysical Realism (Southwestern Philosophical Review, Vol , 19-27)

How Not to Defend Metaphysical Realism (Southwestern Philosophical Review, Vol , 19-27) How Not to Defend Metaphysical Realism (Southwestern Philosophical Review, Vol 3 1986, 19-27) John Collier Department of Philosophy Rice University November 21, 1986 Putnam's writings on realism(1) have

More information

III Knowledge is true belief based on argument. Plato, Theaetetus, 201 c-d Is Justified True Belief Knowledge? Edmund Gettier

III Knowledge is true belief based on argument. Plato, Theaetetus, 201 c-d Is Justified True Belief Knowledge? Edmund Gettier III Knowledge is true belief based on argument. Plato, Theaetetus, 201 c-d Is Justified True Belief Knowledge? Edmund Gettier In Theaetetus Plato introduced the definition of knowledge which is often translated

More information

A Studying of Limitation of Epistemology as Basis of Toleration with Special Reference to John Locke

A Studying of Limitation of Epistemology as Basis of Toleration with Special Reference to John Locke A Studying of Limitation of Epistemology as Basis of Toleration with Special Reference to John Locke Roghieh Tamimi and R. P. Singh Center for philosophy, Social Science School, Jawaharlal Nehru University,

More information

Review of Nathan M. Nobis s Truth in Ethics and Epistemology

Review of Nathan M. Nobis s Truth in Ethics and Epistemology Review of Nathan M. Nobis s Truth in Ethics and Epistemology by James W. Gray November 19, 2010 (This is available on my website Ethical Realism.) Abstract Moral realism is the view that moral facts exist

More information

1/10. Primary and Secondary Qualities and the Ideas of Substance

1/10. Primary and Secondary Qualities and the Ideas of Substance 1/10 Primary and Secondary Qualities and the Ideas of Substance This week I want to return to a topic we discussed to some extent in the first year, namely Locke s account of the distinction between primary

More information

1/8. Descartes 3: Proofs of the Existence of God

1/8. Descartes 3: Proofs of the Existence of God 1/8 Descartes 3: Proofs of the Existence of God Descartes opens the Third Meditation by reminding himself that nothing that is purely sensory is reliable. The one thing that is certain is the cogito. He

More information

On Liberty by John Stuart Mill

On Liberty by John Stuart Mill Sparks Notes Summary of Mills Sparks Notes Summary of Mills On Liberty, Chapter 2 1 On Liberty by John Stuart Mill From http://www.sparknotes.com/philosophy/onliberty/index.html Context John Stuart Mill

More information

UC Berkeley UC Berkeley Previously Published Works

UC Berkeley UC Berkeley Previously Published Works UC Berkeley UC Berkeley Previously Published Works Title Disaggregating Structures as an Agenda for Critical Realism: A Reply to McAnulla Permalink https://escholarship.org/uc/item/4k27s891 Journal British

More information

Relativism and Subjectivism. The Denial of Objective Ethical Standards

Relativism and Subjectivism. The Denial of Objective Ethical Standards Relativism and Subjectivism The Denial of Objective Ethical Standards Starting with a counter argument 1.The universe operates according to laws 2.The universe can be investigated through the use of both

More information

Intro to Philosophy. Review for Exam 2

Intro to Philosophy. Review for Exam 2 Intro to Philosophy Review for Exam 2 Epistemology Theory of Knowledge What is knowledge? What is the structure of knowledge? What particular things can I know? What particular things do I know? Do I know

More information

The belief in the existence of an omniscient, omnipotent and benevolent God is inconsistent with the existence of human suffering. Discuss.

The belief in the existence of an omniscient, omnipotent and benevolent God is inconsistent with the existence of human suffering. Discuss. The belief in the existence of an omniscient, omnipotent and benevolent God is inconsistent with the existence of human suffering. Discuss. Is he willing to prevent evil, but not able? Then he is not omnipotent.

More information

ALTERNATIVE SELF-DEFEAT ARGUMENTS: A REPLY TO MIZRAHI

ALTERNATIVE SELF-DEFEAT ARGUMENTS: A REPLY TO MIZRAHI ALTERNATIVE SELF-DEFEAT ARGUMENTS: A REPLY TO MIZRAHI Michael HUEMER ABSTRACT: I address Moti Mizrahi s objections to my use of the Self-Defeat Argument for Phenomenal Conservatism (PC). Mizrahi contends

More information

Jeu-Jenq Yuann Professor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy, National Taiwan University,

Jeu-Jenq Yuann Professor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy, National Taiwan University, The Negative Role of Empirical Stimulus in Theory Change: W. V. Quine and P. Feyerabend Jeu-Jenq Yuann Professor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy, National Taiwan University, 1 To all Participants

More information

THE CONCEPT OF OWNERSHIP by Lars Bergström

THE CONCEPT OF OWNERSHIP by Lars Bergström From: Who Owns Our Genes?, Proceedings of an international conference, October 1999, Tallin, Estonia, The Nordic Committee on Bioethics, 2000. THE CONCEPT OF OWNERSHIP by Lars Bergström I shall be mainly

More information

HOW TO BE (AND HOW NOT TO BE) A NORMATIVE REALIST:

HOW TO BE (AND HOW NOT TO BE) A NORMATIVE REALIST: 1 HOW TO BE (AND HOW NOT TO BE) A NORMATIVE REALIST: A DISSERTATION OVERVIEW THAT ASSUMES AS LITTLE AS POSSIBLE ABOUT MY READER S PHILOSOPHICAL BACKGROUND Consider the question, What am I going to have

More information

Chapter 3 PHILOSOPHICAL ETHICS AND BUSINESS CHAPTER OBJECTIVES. After exploring this chapter, you will be able to:

Chapter 3 PHILOSOPHICAL ETHICS AND BUSINESS CHAPTER OBJECTIVES. After exploring this chapter, you will be able to: Chapter 3 PHILOSOPHICAL ETHICS AND BUSINESS MGT604 CHAPTER OBJECTIVES After exploring this chapter, you will be able to: 1. Explain the ethical framework of utilitarianism. 2. Describe how utilitarian

More information

Realism and the success of science argument. Leplin:

Realism and the success of science argument. Leplin: Realism and the success of science argument Leplin: 1) Realism is the default position. 2) The arguments for anti-realism are indecisive. In particular, antirealism offers no serious rival to realism in

More information

out in his Three Dialogues and Principles of Human Knowledge, gives an argument specifically

out in his Three Dialogues and Principles of Human Knowledge, gives an argument specifically That Thing-I-Know-Not-What by [Perm #7903685] The philosopher George Berkeley, in part of his general thesis against materialism as laid out in his Three Dialogues and Principles of Human Knowledge, gives

More information

Well-Being, Disability, and the Mere-Difference Thesis. Jennifer Hawkins Duke University

Well-Being, Disability, and the Mere-Difference Thesis. Jennifer Hawkins Duke University This paper is in the very early stages of development. Large chunks are still simply detailed outlines. I can, of course, fill these in verbally during the session, but I apologize in advance for its current

More information

On Some Alleged Consequences Of The Hartle-Hawking Cosmology. In [3], Quentin Smith claims that the Hartle-Hawking cosmology is inconsistent with

On Some Alleged Consequences Of The Hartle-Hawking Cosmology. In [3], Quentin Smith claims that the Hartle-Hawking cosmology is inconsistent with On Some Alleged Consequences Of The Hartle-Hawking Cosmology In [3], Quentin Smith claims that the Hartle-Hawking cosmology is inconsistent with classical theism in a way which redounds to the discredit

More information

Searle vs. Chalmers Debate, 8/2005 with Death Monkey (Kevin Dolan)

Searle vs. Chalmers Debate, 8/2005 with Death Monkey (Kevin Dolan) Searle vs. Chalmers Debate, 8/2005 with Death Monkey (Kevin Dolan) : Searle says of Chalmers book, The Conscious Mind, "it is one thing to bite the occasional bullet here and there, but this book consumes

More information

Property Dualism and the Knowledge Argument: Are Qualia Really a Problem for Physicalism? Ronald Planer Rutgers Univerity

Property Dualism and the Knowledge Argument: Are Qualia Really a Problem for Physicalism? Ronald Planer Rutgers Univerity Property Dualism and the Knowledge Argument: Are Qualia Really a Problem for Physicalism? Ronald Planer Rutgers Univerity Abstract: Where does the mind fit into the physical world? Not surprisingly, philosophers

More information

Intro. The need for a philosophical vocabulary

Intro. The need for a philosophical vocabulary Critical Realism & Philosophy Webinar Ruth Groff August 5, 2015 Intro. The need for a philosophical vocabulary You don t have to become a philosopher, but just as philosophers should know their way around

More information

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg 1 In Search of the Ontological Argument Richard Oxenberg Abstract We can attend to the logic of Anselm's ontological argument, and amuse ourselves for a few hours unraveling its convoluted word-play, or

More information

Charles Saunders Peirce ( )

Charles Saunders Peirce ( ) Charles Saunders Peirce (1839-1914) Few persons care to study logic, because everybody conceives himself to be proficient enough in the art of reasoning already. But I observe that this satisfaction is

More information

Cartesian Rationalism

Cartesian Rationalism Cartesian Rationalism René Descartes 1596-1650 Reason tells me to trust my senses Descartes had the disturbing experience of finding out that everything he learned at school was wrong! From 1604-1612 he

More information

The Question of Metaphysics

The Question of Metaphysics The Question of Metaphysics metaphysics seriously. Second, I want to argue that the currently popular hands-off conception of metaphysical theorising is unable to provide a satisfactory answer to the question

More information

1/12. The A Paralogisms

1/12. The A Paralogisms 1/12 The A Paralogisms The character of the Paralogisms is described early in the chapter. Kant describes them as being syllogisms which contain no empirical premises and states that in them we conclude

More information

24.02 Moral Problems and the Good Life

24.02 Moral Problems and the Good Life MIT OpenCourseWare http://ocw.mit.edu 24.02 Moral Problems and the Good Life Fall 2008 For information about citing these materials or our Terms of Use, visit: http://ocw.mit.edu/terms. Three Moral Theories

More information

Today s Lecture. René Descartes W.K. Clifford Preliminary comments on Locke

Today s Lecture. René Descartes W.K. Clifford Preliminary comments on Locke Today s Lecture René Descartes W.K. Clifford Preliminary comments on Locke René Descartes: The First There are two motivations for his method of doubt that Descartes mentions in the first paragraph of

More information

Scanlon on Double Effect

Scanlon on Double Effect Scanlon on Double Effect RALPH WEDGWOOD Merton College, University of Oxford In this new book Moral Dimensions, T. M. Scanlon (2008) explores the ethical significance of the intentions and motives with

More information

PHI 1700: Global Ethics

PHI 1700: Global Ethics PHI 1700: Global Ethics Session 3 February 11th, 2016 Harman, Ethics and Observation 1 (finishing up our All About Arguments discussion) A common theme linking many of the fallacies we covered is that

More information

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy Res Cogitans Volume 5 Issue 1 Article 20 6-4-2014 Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy Kevin Harriman Lewis & Clark College Follow this and additional works at: http://commons.pacificu.edu/rescogitans

More information

The Conflict Between Authority and Autonomy from Robert Wolff, In Defense of Anarchism (1970)

The Conflict Between Authority and Autonomy from Robert Wolff, In Defense of Anarchism (1970) The Conflict Between Authority and Autonomy from Robert Wolff, In Defense of Anarchism (1970) 1. The Concept of Authority Politics is the exercise of the power of the state, or the attempt to influence

More information

Biola University: An Ontology of Knowledge Course Points discussed 5/27/97

Biola University: An Ontology of Knowledge Course Points discussed 5/27/97 Biola University: An Ontology of Knowledge Course Points discussed 5/27/97 1. Formal requirements of the course. Prepared class participation. 3 short (17 to 18 hundred words) papers (assigned on Thurs,

More information

CONVENTIONALISM AND NORMATIVITY

CONVENTIONALISM AND NORMATIVITY 1 CONVENTIONALISM AND NORMATIVITY TORBEN SPAAK We have seen (in Section 3) that Hart objects to Austin s command theory of law, that it cannot account for the normativity of law, and that what is missing

More information