Philosophical Writings Vol. 40 No.1

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Philosophical Writings Vol. 40 No.1"

Transcription

1 Philosophical Writings Vol. 40 No.1 1 University of Limerick Ludwig Wittgenstein s Tractatus has rightly been regarded as paramount to the rise of analytic philosophy and a dominant influence on the logical positivism of the Vienna Circle. Otto Neurath, however, and subsequently Ayer, did come to realise that Wittgenstein was not offering the positivist committal of metaphysics to the flames. Nevertheless, they regard his conception of the tautological necessity that is the mark of logical truths as exerting a positive influence on the development of their own thought. This paper maintains that Wittgenstein has here been misunderstood through excessively analytic readings of his text. The recontextualisation of Wittgenstein s Tractatus within the frame of the Kantian tradition, of which he is equally the inheritor, reveals a deep discrepancy between Wittgenstein and the positivists with regard to the nature of necessity. For Wittgenstein, it will be argued, unlike the positivists, extends necessity to the realm of ethical, as well as logical truths. Date Submitted: 10/10/2010 Date Accepted: 07/04/2011 Vol. 40 pp This paper is adapted from my PhD thesis, Tractarian Holism: Transcendental Solipsism in the Context of the Kantian Tradition (Mary Immaculate College, University of Limerick, 2005). Neither the paper nor the thesis could have been completed without the close supervision and expert guidance of Dr. Stephen Thornton, to whom I am indebted for the interest in Wittgenstein and much else besides. 1

2 Moritz Schlick s The Turning Point in Philosophy opened the first number of Erkenntnis Volume I. Schlick here expresses a confidence that we have reached a turning point in philosophy in which we can now, finally, consider ourselves as moving beyond the fruitless conflict of systems that has hitherto hindered philosophical progress. Schlick claims that the methods are already at hand to make such conflict unnecessary. What is required is the resolute application of these methods, and so firstly an acquaintance with the new philosophical paths. The paths have their origin in logic. Leibniz dimly saw their beginning. Bertrand Russell and Gottlob Frege have opened up important stretches in the last decades, but Ludwig Wittgenstein (in his Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus, 1922) is the first to have pushed forward to the decisive turning point.the insight into the nature of logic itself (Schlick 1959, pp ). The insight into the nature of logic itself is Wittgenstein s contention that the propositions of logic are tautological. For Schlick, this allowed a complete adherence to empiricism, to which logical necessity had provided the greatest previous stumbling block. Kant s notion of synthetic a priori propositions could finally be discarded and the members of the Vienna Circle could consistently cling to conventionalism with regard to necessary truth. With the rejection of Kant s notion of necessity thus comes a regression to Humean empiricism, and an equally Humean characterisation of the philosophical enterprise: Thus metaphysics collapses not because the solving of its tasks is an enterprise to which the human reason is unequal (as for example Kant thought) but because there is no such task (Schlick 1959, p. 57). A.J. Ayer initially consolidated the positivist conception of Wittgenstein s attitude to metaphysics (Ayer 1971, p. 9). But by the publication of Wittgenstein in 1985, he had formed a very different conception of his subject: His attitude was much more akin to that of Kant whose criticisms of metaphysics were intended to limit the scope of the understanding in the interests of faith (Ayer 1985, pp ). Otto Neurath was, from the outset, more perceptive than other members of the Vienna Circle in recognising the gulf between Wittgenstein s position and their own. In Sociology and Physicalism, appearing in Volume II of Erkenntnis, Neurath lists Wittgenstein along with Mach, Poincare and Frege as beginning the work which the Vienna Circle aim to continue (Neurath 1959, p. 284). While Wittgenstein s place within the analytic tradition thus remains assured, Neurath was nevertheless overtly critical of what he, like Ramsey, perceived to be Wittgenstein s inclinations towards 2

3 metaphysical assertion, conceived as something other than the plain nonsense that Hume or members of the Circle would have taken them for (Ramsey 1959, p. 321). The conclusion of the Tractatus, Whereof one cannot speak, thereof one must be silent, is, at least grammatically, misleading. It sounds as if there were a something of which one could not speak. We should rather say: if one really wishes to avoid the metaphysical attitude entirely, then one will be silent, but not about something. We have no need of any metaphysical ladder of elucidation. We cannot follow Wittgenstein in this matter, although his great significance for logic is not, for that reason, to be less highly valued. We owe him, among other things, the distinction between tautologies and statements about empirical events (Neurath 1959, p. 284). Such discrepancies between the thought of Wittgenstein and those analytic thinkers whom he both influenced and was influenced by have been well documented. And it has become clear that considering the Tractatus exclusively as a work in analytic philosophy, in the mould of Frege s Begriffsschrift or Russell s Principia, is highly problematic. The false construal of the Tractatus as offering the positivist committal of metaphysics to the flames is a much documented example of the problems thus created. In keeping with the dominant picture of the Tractatus as a work of analytic realism, however, it is equally evident that commentators have assumed that Schlick, Neurath, Ayer and others have at least remained faithful to Wittgenstein in construing the only true necessity as tautological in nature. It is my contention that such an assumption is misguided, and is, furthermore, based on excessively analytic readings of Wittgenstein s Tractatus. While it is difficult to overestimate Wittgenstein s early contribution to the rise of analytic philosophy, or the influence of the new logic of Frege and Russell on Wittgenstein s early thought, Wittgenstein is equally the inheritor of the linguistic and cultural discourse of a continental, Kantian tradition. It is a tradition which, although not entirely ignored in past scholarship, has been largely marginalised. Through the re-contextualisation of Wittgenstein s Tractarian account of necessity within the frame of this latter tradition, this paper will illustrate that any construal of the Tractatus as ridding us finally of the last vestiges of Kant s synthetic a priori is a flawed one. For both Frege and Russell logical propositions were conceived of as the most general of truths. Hacker, in Wittgenstein s Place in Twentieth Century Analytic Philosophy, remarks that Frege and Russell had given no satisfactory account of logical necessity. The question of necessity and contingency did not feature as a problem for either of them, although it was to become so for Wittgenstein. For him, 3

4 the mark of a logical proposition is not that it is an absolutely general truth, but that it is an absolutely essential, necessary one (Hacker 1996, p. 25). The common error of interpretation has been to posit conversely that all necessary truths are, for Wittgenstein, consequentially logical ones. Wittgenstein himself explicitly states, in Tractatus 6.37, that The only necessity that exists is logical necessity (Wittgenstein 1974, p. 85). This remark seems nothing more than a restatement of the earlier tautological necessity of logical deduction. Such a reading is implied in Schlick s contention that, in accepting Wittgenstein s conception of logical propositions as tautologies, one is finally rid of the final remnants of Kant s synthetic a priori. It was Schlick s acceptance of Wittgenstein s conception of the nature of logic which allowed him to cling consistently to an empirically grounded conventionalism as regards the nature of necessity. Even Neurath, we have seen, so quick to criticise Wittgenstein s silence directed towards some ineffable truth, is equally quick to cite the division between a tautology and an empirical fact as exerting a positive influence over members of the Circle. This paper deems it to be a misreading of the Tractatus to suppose, as such positivists as Schlick and Neurath subsequently did, that The only necessity that exists is logical necessity says nothing more or less than The only necessity that exists is tautological necessity. For Wittgenstein, it will become clear on a closer reading of the text, uses the term logical in more than one sense. G.E.M. Anscombe, in the introduction to her An Introduction to Wittgenstein s Tractatus, quite rightly says that: If we look for Wittgenstein s philosophical ancestry, we should look (rather) to Schopenhauer; specifically, his solipsism, his conception of the limit and his ideas on value will be better understood in the light of Schopenhauer than of any other philosopher (Anscombe 1971, p. 12). More specifically again, we can say that all of the above themes, as well as Wittgenstein s identification of ethics and aesthetics, are best understood when considered together as indicative of an early tendency towards the transcendental idealism that he had discovered in Schopenhauer. Indeed, the nature of a possible a priori order is, Wittgenstein states in the Notebooks, the fundamental question upon which his early philosophy is based: The great problem round which everything that I write turns is: Is there an order in the world a priori, and if so what does it consist in? (Wittgenstein 1979, p. 53e). Phillips Griffiths, in his article Wittgenstein and the Four-Fold Root of the Principle of Sufficient Reason, comments on the above quote as follows: For Wittgenstein, what 4

5 the order a priori might consist in seems to be what Schopenhauer said it did consist in (Phillips Griffiths 1976, p. 4). For Schopenhauer, The Principle of Sufficient Reason has four basic forms, which are differentiated by virtue of the four classes of objects which may be subject to necessity. These are: Knowledge, which gives rise to logical necessity; Change, giving rise to physical necessity; Being in general (time and space), giving rise to mathematical necessity; and finally, Motivation, which gives rise to moral necessity. For Phillips Griffiths, Wittgenstein allows only logical necessity (Phillips Griffiths 1976, p. 5). Tractatus seemingly leads one inexorably to this conclusion: Just as the only necessity that exists is logical necessity, so too the only impossibility that exists is logical impossibility (Wittgenstein 1974, p. 85). Phillips Griffiths conception of Tractarian necessity above ought to be construed as emblematic of a more generally held view which found its inception in the earliest interpretations of Wittgenstein s analytic contemporaries. Both Russell s introduction to the Tractatus and the aforementioned accounts of the Logical Positivists have fashioned Wittgenstein as something of an empiricist, with an analogously empirical conception of necessity as strictly tautological in nature. It is a view of necessity that is, of course, at odds with the a priori necessity that we find grounded in the conceptual framework of the metaphysical subject of the Kantian tradition. Monk relates that Wittgenstein had read Kant s Kritik, whilst in prison during the First World War (Monk 1991, p. 158). To some degree at least, tales of Wittgenstein s inability to acquire insight into the ideas of Kant, Spinoza and others are explicable by virtue of a seemingly conscious effort on Wittgenstein s part to disassociate himself from the philosophical tradition. Wittgenstein himself stated in the preface to the Tractatus that he is not concerned with the extent to which his efforts coincide with those of other philosophers but continues nonetheless to mention that he remains indebted to Frege and Russell. Their influence on the Tractatus, however, has been painstakingly recounted in the past and need not be repeated here. Our starting point is instead what Magee confidently refers to as the fact that the philosophy of the young Wittgenstein was to an important degree an attempt to revise and correct Schopenhauer (Magee 1983, p. 288). In keeping with Anscombe s remark that Schopenhauer then struck him (Wittgenstein) as fundamentally right, if only a few adjustments and clarifications were made (Anscombe 1971, pp ) We may add that these revisions were not as extensive as Magee seems to suggest. Like Phillips Griffiths, Magee fails to see that the philosophy of the young 5

6 Wittgenstein was to a greater extent a straightforward acceptance of the philosophy of Schopenhauer, with corrections largely confined to incidentals as opposed to fundamentals. In exploring just one aspect of this influence here, I confine myself to the last class of objects that can be subject to necessity in Schopenhauer s Principle of Sufficient Reason: Motivation, giving rise to moral necessity. This ought to suffice to diffuse the traditional assumption that Wittgenstein accepts only that form of necessity which derives from objects of Knowledge, that is to say, logical necessity. That Wittgenstein accepts logical necessity is not at issue. On this fact commentators are unanimous. Tractatus 6.375, quoted above, assures us that they are right. What does remain at issue, however, is precisely to what Wittgenstein is referring when he speaks of logical necessity. The confusion arises due to Phillips Griffiths exaggerated attempt to explain the Tractatus always within the confines of Schopenhauer s Four-Fold Root of theprinciple of Sufficient Reason. Phillips Griffiths reason for suggesting that Wittgenstein had encountered this work at all is extremely tenuous. At the beginning of The World as Will and Representation, Schopenhauer recommends that one has read his former treatise. Phillips Griffiths continues, I cannot believe that Wittgenstein could have read these words and then ignored the implied injunction (Phillips Griffiths 1976, p. 4). Assuming that Wittgenstein had ignored the implied injunction, the fact would amount to little. The a priori nature of the various forms of causality is equally evident in The World as Will and Representation. They are not, however, presented in so systematic a format as to imply that Wittgenstein, when considering the possibility of an a priori order at the time of the Tractatus, had Schopenhauer s four classes of objects subject to necessity specifically in mind. It is this unsubstantiated premise that causes Phillips Griffiths to construe Wittgenstein s declaration that the only necessity that exists is logical necessity as a rebuttal of the other forms of necessity, as found in the Four-fold Root and equally in The World as Will and Representation. The argument breaks down when we consider that Wittgenstein uses the term logic in at least three distinct senses. Tractatus 6.22 serves to illustrate our point: The logic of the world, which is shown in tautologies by the propositions of logic, is shown in equations by mathematics (Wittgenstein 1974, p. 79). The logic that is presented in propositions is a form of expression for the logic of the world. It is the logic of the world that is referred to in 6.13 when Wittgenstein says that Logic is not a body of doctrine, but a mirror-image of the world. Logic is transcendental (Wittgenstein 1974, p. 78). 6

7 Wittgenstein s early views on logic are perhaps best expressed by the Wittgenstein of the Philosophical Investigations, who makes it clear again that at the time of the Tractatus, Wittgenstein did not construe logic primarily as comprising the study of deductive logic. These considerations bring us up to the problem: In what sense is logic something sublime? For there seemed to pertain to logic a peculiar depth a universal significance. Logic lay, it seemed, at the bottom of all the sciences. For logical investigation explores the nature of all things. It seeks to see to the bottom of things and is not meant to concern itself whether what actually happens is this or that. It takes its rise, not from an interest in the facts of nature, nor from a need to grasp causal connexions: but from an urge to understand the basis, or essence, of everything empirical (Wittgenstein 1967, p. 42). Logic, for Schopenhauer, remained what Wittgenstein terms a body of doctrine. He is concerned with logic as the study of deductive arguments and as such, the logic of his logical necessity is not comparable to logic as the transcendental mirrorimage of the world accounted in the Investigations above. Tractatus the statement that the only necessity is logical necessity no longer appears as a rebuttal of Schopenhauer s other forms of necessity, not at least without further investigation. Continuing then with Wittgenstein s Tractarian conception of logic, its description in the Investigations above makes it clear that it is not comparable to Schopenhauer s conception of logic as a body of doctrine. Wittgenstein is thus not so easily aligned to the thematic confines of Schopenhauer s Four-fold Root. Tractatus ought not to be construed then as a rejection of the other forms of necessity as they appear in the philosophy of Schopenhauer. In fact, in this instance, Wittgenstein is utilising logic in a third and more causal sense of the word (the previous two being the logic of the proposition and logic as the mirror image of the world), to mean the inescapable relationship between two objects is a part of the discussion on the relationship between the will and the world. It uses the term logical in the same sense as 6.374, which precedes it immediately: Even if all that we wish for were to happen, still this would only be a favour granted by fate, so to speak: for there is no logical connexion between the will and the world, which would guarantee it, and the supposed physical connexion itself is surely not something that we could will (Wittgenstein 1974, p. 85). 7

8 Tractatus 6.375, which Phillips Griffiths confidently cites as the answer to the question of what, for Wittgenstein, does the a priori order consist in, is not a commentary on logic, in Schopenhauer s sense. It points rather to the fact that, for Wittgenstein, a logical fact is that which excludes the possibility of its contradictory. Logical impossibility is elaborated on in as follows: For example, the simultaneous presence of two colours at the same place in the visual field is impossible, in fact logically impossible, since it is ruled out by the logical structure of colour (Wittgenstein 1974, p. 85). That this explanation of the impossibility of any necessity bar the logical kind does not in fact exclude the possibility of moral necessity will become more apparent later. For now, let it suffice to say that Wittgenstein, because he is not consciously tied to the rigid consideration of the a priori as they appear in Schopenhauer s Fourfold Root, refers to logical necessity in a much broader sense than Phillips Griffiths supposes. If applied to the classes of objects which Schopenhauer deems subject to necessity, then Wittgenstein s logical necessity does not serve to permit only logical necessity as this appears in Schopenhauer. It acts rather as a blanket term under the rubric of which all of Schopenhauer s forms may be placed. Within the narrow confines of this paper, however, I will focus exclusively on how the moral necessity of the Tractatus serves to dismantle the empirically grounded, analytic conception of Tractarian necessity. There has been large disagreement between commentators as to the location (if any) of Wittgenstein s early ethical remarks within a Western philosophical tradition. For Phillips Griffiths, discussion of Wittgenstein and ethics requires the stipulation that Wittgenstein s conception of ethics is far removed from what tradition would normally associate with the word. Diane Collinson, in a paper entitled Ethics and Aesthetics are One, aligns herself with the opposing strand which conceives of Wittgenstein s ethics as belonging to the mainstream (Collinson 1985, p. 266). John Churchill is one who agrees with Phillips Griffiths that there is some peculiarity in the Tractatus as to what Wittgenstein takes ethics to be about (Churchill 1983, p. 493). He goes on however to point at a possible bridge to Collinson s position by adding the following, This peculiarity is soon explained, as Russell Goodman has further shown, by comparing the conception of ethics in Schopenhauer with Wittgenstein s thoughts (Churchill 1983, p. 493). Russell Goodman himself concludes the paper in question, Schopenhauer and Wittgenstein on Ethics, by stating that Wittgenstein is an ethical writer whose views place him firmly within the Western ethical tradition (Goodmann 1979, p. 447). As 8

9 the title of Goodman s paper indicates, we find with ethics as we find with his treatment of solipsism and the subject that it is through his familiarity with the writings of Schopenhauer (who is in turn so influenced by Kant) that Wittgenstein finds himself as inheritor of a long philosophical lineage. Goodman, in comparing Schopenhauer and Wittgenstein, focuses on three of Wittgenstein s claims. Considered broadly, it is within these three themes that commentators are limited in the attempt to affirm or deny a link between Wittgenstein, via Schopenhauer, to a wider ethical tradition. As such, the Tractarian claims on which Goodman chooses to focus will serve loosely enough to provide us with a working structure. (1) Ethics has nothing to do with punishment and reward in the usual sense of the terms, but there is rather a kind of ethical reward and punishment that reside in the action itself (6.422); (2) The good or bad exercise of the will alters the world s limits, not the world, so that it can be said to wax and wane (6.43); (3) If we take eternity to mean not infinite temporal duration but timelessness, then eternal life belongs to those who live in the present (6.4311) (Goodmann 1979, p. 437). Firstly then, we find in Schopenhauer the notion that any ethical action is its own reward. His starting point in ethics is a sense of disillusionment with what he believed to be the loss of ethics in a philosophical climate so influenced by Hegel. For Schopenhauer, the time in which he lived was marked by a renewed Spinozism, and with it an acceptance of the world itself as a theophany. The difference between good and evil becomes merely conventional, given that every action is to be considered equally divine. Ethics had thus been largely ignored and had, under the guidance of Hegel, sunk to the point where it was nothing more than a set of instructions for proper public life. It is against this possibility of an objective ethical code that Schopenhauer rebels in his rejection of Hegel s conception of ethics, which asserted that ethics ought to have for its material not the conduct of individuals, but that of masses of people, and that this alone was a theme worthy of it (Schopenhauer 1966b, p. 590). For a fuller account of Schopenhauer s ethics, and in order to locate the proposed source of Wittgenstein s assertion that ethical reward resides in the action itself, we must return to Die Welt alswille und Vorstellung, Volume 1, Chapter 63. Here we find, firstly, that Schopenhauer draws a distinction between temporal justice and eternal 9

10 justice. Temporal justice is concerned with the requiting or punishing of a past outrage. This form of justice has its seat in the State, and acquires its name from the fact that justice is reached only upon punishment at some future time. While temporal justice is required for the ruling of a State, eternal justice is responsible for the ruling of the world. Furthermore, eternal justice exists always in the present, and so does not require any lapse of time in order to take effect: Here the punishment must be so linked with the offence that the two are one (Schopenhauer 1966a, pp ). Whether the punishment and the offence can be viewed as one seems to rest upon whether one accepts Schopenhauer s metaphysical belief in the single world Will. If one does, then every act of injustice becomes an offence of the Will upon itself. The egoistic man has failed to see beyond the principium individuationis, and remains unaware that the forms of phenomena space, time and causality do not apply to the thing-in-itself. The thing-in-itself, (for Schopenhauer) the Will, is indivisible and is not subject to the form of time. What appears to the person who has failed to grasp this as the conflict between one man and another, is, in actuality, the conflict of Will with itself, as it buries its teeth in its own flesh, not knowing that it injures always only itself (Schopenhauer 1966a, pp ). For Schopenhauer, then, ethics is not concerned with reward or punishment, it is concerned always with the individual, and furthermore with the individual as will rather than the individual as idea. The seeming disparity between the claims that ethics is concerned always with the individual and furthermore, that knowledge of eternal justice requires the complete elevation above individuality is explicable as follows. Where ethics resides is, in fact, in the will. That is, will as it is known in the individual and again as the metaphysical Will that permeates all nature. As will is recognizable firstly in oneself, it is with the individual that ethics is concerned. The recognition that this will is synonymous with the world Will requires elevation above the principium individuationis, and consequently, above individuality. Ethics, concerned with the will, is thus equally concerned with the individual and the elevation above individuality. Neither instance of the will (individual will and world Will) caters for the social ethics of Hegel. For Wittgenstein too, the Notebooks make clear, ethics is not concerned with reward or punishment as events that take place in time. Rather, as with Schopenhauer, we will see again that Der Quäler und der Gequälte sind Eines (Schopenhauer 1988a, p. 459). It is clear that ethics has nothing to do with punishment and reward.there must be a kind of ethical reward and of ethical punishment but these must be involved in the action itself (Wittgenstein 1979, p. 78e). 10

11 Goodman s second Tractarian reference, 6.43, follows 6.423, which itself has as its immediate predecessor the restatement of the above excerpt from the Notebooks. Having stated then that ethics is not about consequences as temporally sequential to action, Wittgenstein continues: (6.423) It is impossible to speak about the will in so far as it is the subject of ethical attributes. And the will as a phenomenon is of interest only to psychology. (6.43) If the good or bad exercise of the will does alter the world, it can alter only the limits of the world, not the facts not what can be expressed by means of language. In short the effect must be that it becomes an altogether different world. It must, so to speak wax and wane as whole. The world of the happy man is a different one from that of the unhappy man (Wittgenstein 1974, p. 87). Goodman invites us to consider 6.43 above in the light of Schopenhauer s description, in The World as Will and Representation, of the good conscience, which arises with every disinterested deed: It springs from the fact that such a deed, as arising from the direct recognition of our own inner being-in-itself in the phenomenon of another, again affords us the verification of this knowledge, of the knowledge that our true self exists not only in our own person, in this particular phenomenon, but in everything that lives. In this way the heart feels itself enlarged, just as by egoism it feels contracted (Goodman 1979, p. 444). The metaphors of expansion and contraction, Goodman points out, parallel Wittgenstein s use of waxing and waning Sie muβ sozusagen als Ganzes abnehmen oder zunehmen (Wittgenstein 1971, p. 146). Schopenhauer s passage, Goodman continues, provides a means of understanding Wittgenstein s claim that it is the world s limits (Grenzen), and not the facts (Tatsachen), which are altered by virtue of the good or bad exercise of the will: Egoists and altruists are still, for Schopenhauer, phenomenal; the latter are more or less ordinary human beings, not sages who have completely escaped the world of space, time, and the principle of sufficient reason. Facts such as that one s home is at a given location, that one ate this or that for breakfast, that an acquaintance insulted one, do not change when one adopts either an egoic or an altruistic attitude. Rather, one s attitude towards those facts changes (Goodmann 1979, p. 444). 11

12 The claim that we cannot speak about the will in so far as it is the bearer of ethical attributes, of course implies that this is precisely what the philosophical will, for Wittgenstein, is. Notebooks ( ) offers confirmation of this. What really is the situation of the human will? I will call will first and foremost the bearer of good and evil (Wittgenstein 1979, p. 76). It is the subject of willing (a la Schopenhauer) which is the bearer of good and evil. Like Kant s unity of apperception, we cannot speak about Wittgenstein s willing subject, we can stipulate only that it does exist. The will as a phenomenon, that is, the will as an empirically knowable object, is of no philosophical worth. The willing subject for Wittgenstein is still the transcendental subject of the Kantian tradition. Like Kant s subject, it is to be located at the limits of the world, never as an object in the world. And so ethics (good and evil), while not belonging to the empirical world of facts, nonetheless possess grounding in the Kantian, unknown subject that acts as its bearer. Diane Collinson cites the aforementioned fact that ethics, for Wittgenstein, is not about ends or goals, as one route to the further identification of ethics and aesthetics (Collinson 1985, p. 267). This identification finds its place in Tractatus 6.421: It is clear that ethics cannot be put into words. Ethics is transcendental. (Ethics and aesthetics are one and the same) (Wittgenstein 1974, p.86). The idea that Ethik und Ästhetik sind Eins first appeared in the Notebooks on , presented together with the notion that ethics is not concerned with the facts of the world: The World and Life are one. Physiological life is of course not Life. And neither is psychological life. Life is the world. Ethics does not treat of the world. Ethics must be a condition of the world, like logic. Ethics and aesthetics are one (Wittgenstein 1979, p. 77). We could not, for example, make an analogy between an ethical system such as utilitarianism, which places the value of an action in its eventual consequence, and the traditional view of aesthetic enjoyment as its own reward. It is because Wittgenstein s conception of ethics is now located in the Kantian strand (Schopenhauer, again, providing the link between the two) that Collinson finds fault with Phillips removal of Wittgenstein from the ethical tradition. In her paper Ethics and Aesthetics are One, Collinson proceeds to link Wittgenstein s ethics with a mainstream on the following accounts. (1) It is concerned with the contemplative apprehension of the Good. (2) It requires a metaphysical, nonempirical subject as the logical condition of this apprehension. (3) A certain necessity 12

13 of action is connected with the apprehension of the Good. It is this third point that is paramount to our attempted demarcation of Tractarian necessity from the tautological necessity of Logical Positivism. And as a belief in moral necessity may not be particularly obvious in Wittgenstein s case, it is worth following Collinson in quoting his Lecture on Ethics where this receives its clearest expression. Of the absolutely right road, Wittgenstein there says, I think it would be a road which everybody on seeing it would, with logical necessity, have to go, or be ashamed for not going (Collinson 1985, p. 270). Here we can see Wittgenstein s acceptance of the fourth form of The Four-Fold Root, namely, Motivation, giving rise to moral necessity. This offers further confirmation, if such was needed, that ethics, like logic, remains for Wittgenstein a necessary condition of the world and not merely a category devoid of any cognitive content. Phillips Griffiths, it will be recalled, allowed only that Wittgenstein accepted logical necessity. In a certain sense, this is true. The moral high road, once seen, would, with logical necessity, be taken. Now, if we are to say that Wittgenstein allows only logical necessity, then we must stipulate that logical necessity, for Wittgenstein, is not to be contrasted with moral necessity. As moral necessity, for Wittgenstein, is clearly one form of logical necessity, his consideration of the a priori simply cannot be so readily forced into the categories of Schopenhauer s Four-Fold Root namely, Knowledge, Change, Being and Motivation. Wittgenstein has been previously quoted to the effect that it is logically impossible for two colours to be present at the same time in the same place, as this is ruled out by the logical structure of colour. Now, we are forced to concede that ethics too may have its own logical necessity. As it was for Plato, so it seems to be for Wittgenstein, that to know the good is to do the good. That ethics should exhibit logical necessity is hardly surprising given the characterisation of what logical necessity is not in Tractatus 6.37, of which the remark regarding the simultaneous presence of two colours is an elaboration: There is no compulsion making one thing happen because another has happened. The only necessity that exists is logical necessity (Wittgenstein 1974, p. 84) , immediately preceding this reads, It is an hypothesis that the sun will rise tomorrow: and this means that we do not know whether it will rise (Wittgenstein 1974, p. 84). There is no logical necessity in the sun s not rising tomorrow, as it does not violate the logical structure of the sun for this to be the case. Although we may with certainty say that the sun will rise, it is not inconceivable that it would not. The 13

14 presence of two colours in the same place at the same time is, by contrast, logically inconceivable contrasts logical necessity with the compulsion which one thing happening causes another thing to happen. That this paves the way for a logical necessity with regards to morality is evident in that first Tractarian reference (6.422) which Russell Goodman had foreseen as indicative of Schopenhauer s influence on the ethics of the Tractatus. This stated that ethical reward and punishment are not correctly considered in the usual sense of the terms but instead, must have a reward and punishment that reside in the action itself. Reward and punishment, as normally understood, are in the sense of Schopenhauer s temporal justice reward and punishment at a future date. Because, however, there is no compulsion making one thing happen because another thing has happened (6.37), thus understood, moral necessity cannot be of the logical variety. In accepting Schopenhauer s eternal justice, in which reward or punishment reside in the action itself, Wittgenstein has already paved the way for the belief, not explicitly asserted until his Lecture on Ethics, that the absolutely right road, once seen, must, of logical necessity, be taken. Thus, in Wittgenstein s case, citing his belief that the only necessity that exists is logical necessity is not reason at all to exclude him from proposing necessity under the form of Motivation. This is to break with an account of logical necessity that is a staple of traditional Wittgenstein scholarship. But it is not to subvert the methodology of traditional scholarship after the fashion of the Diamond-Conant inspired New Wittgenstein movement. The central assumptions of Old scholarship, both the positive metaphysical doctrine of the Tractatus and its subsequent rejection by the therapeutic Wittgenstein of the Investigations period, are hereby upheld. What is altered in this reading is precisely what such metaphysical doctrine consists in, on this account a Schopenhauerian ethics (and mysticism) in addition to a somewhat modified New Logic. The transcendence of the realist/idealist dichotomy that Wittgenstein encountered in Schopenhauer is here applicable, more pointedly, to the question of ethical truths. Wittgenstein, on this account, belongs neither to the realist camp exemplified by the ethical non-naturalism of Moore, nor with anti-realist counterpoints such as Ayer s emotivism and the prescriptivism of Hare. In the case of the latter non-cognitivists, their moral anti-realism is evidenced in the belief that ethical sentences, because they do not assert genuine propositions, cannot be classified as true or false. While the same attribution might be made of Wittgenstein, this does not negate the possibility that, for him, ethical attitudes can yet be wrong or right, or that there can be an absolutely right road. The New movement presents a picture of the Tractatus which is effectively identical to Neurath s contention that in 14

15 order to avoid the metaphysical attitude entirely, we must indeed remain silent, but not about anything. However, where Neurath s remark was intended as a criticism of Wittgenstein s metaphysical endeavours, proponents of the Diamond-Conant reading view Wittgenstein himself as espousing this very anti-metaphysical attitude. Despite Ramsey, Ayer, Engelmann and Russell all upholding Neurath s picture of a Tractarian ineffable realm, New Wittgensteinians maintain that this separate stratum of ineffable truth also pertains to the philosophical confusions from which Wittgenstein is attempting to extricate us. Consequently, for them there can be no ethical doctrine of the early Wittgenstein. One aim of this Continental reading of the Tractatus is to preclude the New Wittgenstein movement from capitalising upon the inability of excessively analytic interpretations to explain from whence Wittgenstein derives his metaphysical tendencies. This author not only upholds the ineffability readings that New scholarship rejects, but views Wittgenstein s ethical ineffable as fundamental to his philosophical enterprise, and a pre-requisite for the possibility of any genuinely holistic account of the seemingly disparate elements of the Tractatus (Crary 2007, p. 8). This thesis does not, however, take the New reading as its sole or even primary target. Nor is its significance to traditional scholarship restricted to a commentary on the single commentator who has featured most heavily above. For Phillips Griffiths account of necessity is functionally identical to the account propagated by Russell, the Logical Positivists and innumerable commentators since who would consider the Tractatus exclusively against the background of the analytic tradition. An exploration of his continental inheritance, however, exposes a certain necessity of moral action in the thought of the early Wittgenstein. It was natural for Ayer to confuse Wittgenstein s metaphysical silence about something with his own committal of metaphysics to the flames. From the standpoint of a staunchly analytic empiricism, it has been equally easy to confuse statements denying that ethics can be put into words with an outright denial of all ethical value. For Wittgenstein, it remains the case that the point of the Tractatus is an ethical one. And far from ridding us of the last vestiges of Kant s synthetic a priori, the Tractatus, in removing ethical value from the world of facts, was rather involved in the attempt to salvage a place for ethics in the transcendental plane. It is an attempt that is also consistent with the Kantian enterprise of limiting the understanding in the interests of faith, and entirely at odds with the positivist denial of all forms of necessity but the empty tautologies of logic. Steven.Bond@mic.ul.ie 15

16 REFERENCES Anscombe, Gertrude, 1971: An Introduction to Wittgenstein s Tractatus. London: Hutchinson University Library. Ayer, Alfred, 1971: Language, Truth and Logic. London: Penguin Books. Ayer, Alfred, 1985: Wittgenstein. London: Weidenfeld and Nicolson. Churchill, John, 1983: Wittgenstein s adaptation of Schopenhauer in Southern Journal of Philosophy, 21, pp Collinson, Diane, 1985: Ethics and Aesthetics are One in British Journal of Aesthetics, 25(3), pp Crary, Alice, 2007: Introduction in Crary, Alice (ed.), Wittgenstein and the Moral Life. London: MIT Press, pp Goodman, Russell, 1979: Schopenhauer and Wittgenstein on Ethics in Journal of the History of Philosophy, 17(4), pp Hacker, Peter, 1996: Wittgenstein s Place in Twentieth-Century Analytic Philosophy. Oxford: Blackwell. Magee, Bryan, 2000: The Philosophy of Schopenhauer. New York: Oxford University Press. Monk, Ray, 1991: Ludwig Wittgenstein: The Duty of Genius. London: Vintage Books. Neurath, Otto, 1959: Sociology and Physicalism in Ayer, Alfred (ed.), Logical Positivism. New York: The Free Press, pp Phillips Griffiths, A., 1976: Wittgenstein and the Four-Fold Root of the Principle of Sufficient Reason in Aristotelian Society, 50, pp Ramsey, Frank, 1959: Philosophy in Ayer, Alfred (ed.), Logical Positivism. New York: The Free Press, pp Schlick, Moritz, 1959: The Turning Point in Philosophy in Ayer, Alfred (ed.), Logical Positivism. New York: The Free Press, pp

17 Schopenhauer, Arthur, 1966a: The World as Will and Representation I. Tr. Payne, Eric. New York: Dover Publications. Schopenhauer, Arthur, 1966b: The World as Will and Representation II. Tr. Payne, Eric. New York: Dover Publications. Schopenhauer, Arthur, 1988a: Die Welt als Wille und Vorstellung I. Ulm: Haffmans Verlag. Schopenhauer, Arthur, 1988b: Die Welt als Wille und Vorstellung II. Ulm: Haffmans Verlag. Wittgenstein, Ludwig, 1967: Philosophical Investigations. Tr. Anscombe, Gertrude. Oxford: Blackwell. Wittgenstein, Ludwig, 1971: Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul. Wittgenstein, Ludwig, 1974: Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus. Tr. David Pears and Brian McGuinness. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul. Wittgenstein, Ludwig, 1979: Notebooks Tr. Anscombe, Gertrude. Oxford: Blackwell. 17

Wittgenstein on The Realm of Ineffable

Wittgenstein on The Realm of Ineffable Wittgenstein on The Realm of Ineffable by Manoranjan Mallick and Vikram S. Sirola Abstract The paper attempts to delve into the distinction Wittgenstein makes between factual discourse and moral thoughts.

More information

Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus (abridged version) Ludwig Wittgenstein

Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus (abridged version) Ludwig Wittgenstein Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus (abridged version) Ludwig Wittgenstein PREFACE This book will perhaps only be understood by those who have themselves already thought the thoughts which are expressed in

More information

Has Logical Positivism Eliminated Metaphysics?

Has Logical Positivism Eliminated Metaphysics? International Journal of Humanities and Social Science Invention ISSN (Online): 2319 7722, ISSN (Print): 2319 7714 Volume 3 Issue 11 ǁ November. 2014 ǁ PP.38-42 Has Logical Positivism Eliminated Metaphysics?

More information

The New Wittgenstein, ed. Alice Crary and Rupert Read, London and New York, 2000, pp. v + 403, no price.

The New Wittgenstein, ed. Alice Crary and Rupert Read, London and New York, 2000, pp. v + 403, no price. Philosophical Investigations 24:2 April 2001 ISSN 0190-0536 critical notice The New Wittgenstein, ed. Alice Crary and Rupert Read, London and New York, 2000, pp. v + 403, no price. H. O. Mounce, University

More information

Chapter 31. Logical Positivism and the Scientific Conception of Philosophy

Chapter 31. Logical Positivism and the Scientific Conception of Philosophy Chapter 31 Logical Positivism and the Scientific Conception of Philosophy Key Words: Vienna circle, verification principle, positivism, tautologies, factual propositions, language analysis, rejection of

More information

145 Philosophy of Science

145 Philosophy of Science Logical empiricism Christian Wüthrich http://philosophy.ucsd.edu/faculty/wuthrich/ 145 Philosophy of Science Vienna Circle (Ernst Mach Society) Hans Hahn, Otto Neurath, and Philipp Frank regularly meet

More information

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras Module - 28 Lecture - 28 Linguistic turn in British philosophy

More information

PHI2391: Logical Empiricism I 8.0

PHI2391: Logical Empiricism I 8.0 1 2 3 4 5 PHI2391: Logical Empiricism I 8.0 Hume and Kant! Remember Hume s question:! Are we rationally justified in inferring causes from experimental observations?! Kant s answer: we can give a transcendental

More information

Conceivability and Possibility Studies in Frege and Kripke. M.A. Thesis Proposal. Department of Philosophy, CSULB. 25 May 2006

Conceivability and Possibility Studies in Frege and Kripke. M.A. Thesis Proposal. Department of Philosophy, CSULB. 25 May 2006 1 Conceivability and Possibility Studies in Frege and Kripke M.A. Thesis Proposal Department of Philosophy, CSULB 25 May 2006 Thesis Committee: Max Rosenkrantz (chair) Bill Johnson Wayne Wright 2 In my

More information

1/9. The First Analogy

1/9. The First Analogy 1/9 The First Analogy So far we have looked at the mathematical principles but now we are going to turn to the dynamical principles, of which there are two sorts, the Analogies of Experience and the Postulates

More information

Philosophy A465: Introduction to Analytic Philosophy Loyola University of New Orleans Ben Bayer Spring 2011

Philosophy A465: Introduction to Analytic Philosophy Loyola University of New Orleans Ben Bayer Spring 2011 Philosophy A465: Introduction to Analytic Philosophy Loyola University of New Orleans Ben Bayer Spring 2011 Course description At the beginning of the twentieth century, a handful of British and German

More information

University of Alberta. The Status of Aesthetics in Wittgenstein s Tractatus. Morteza Abedinifard

University of Alberta. The Status of Aesthetics in Wittgenstein s Tractatus. Morteza Abedinifard University of Alberta The Status of Aesthetics in Wittgenstein s Tractatus by Morteza Abedinifard A thesis submitted to the Faculty of Graduate Studies and Research in partial fulfillment of the requirements

More information

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. Tractatus 6.3751 Author(s): Edwin B. Allaire Source: Analysis, Vol. 19, No. 5 (Apr., 1959), pp. 100-105 Published by: Oxford University Press on behalf of The Analysis Committee Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/3326898

More information

Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics 1. By Tom Cumming

Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics 1. By Tom Cumming Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics 1 By Tom Cumming Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics represents Martin Heidegger's first attempt at an interpretation of Kant's Critique of Pure Reason (1781). This

More information

Verificationism. PHIL September 27, 2011

Verificationism. PHIL September 27, 2011 Verificationism PHIL 83104 September 27, 2011 1. The critique of metaphysics... 1 2. Observation statements... 2 3. In principle verifiability... 3 4. Strong verifiability... 3 4.1. Conclusive verifiability

More information

Ayer and Quine on the a priori

Ayer and Quine on the a priori Ayer and Quine on the a priori November 23, 2004 1 The problem of a priori knowledge Ayer s book is a defense of a thoroughgoing empiricism, not only about what is required for a belief to be justified

More information

1/7. The Postulates of Empirical Thought

1/7. The Postulates of Empirical Thought 1/7 The Postulates of Empirical Thought This week we are focusing on the final section of the Analytic of Principles in which Kant schematizes the last set of categories. This set of categories are what

More information

Denis Seron. Review of: K. Mulligan, Wittgenstein et la philosophie austro-allemande (Paris: Vrin, 2012). Dialectica

Denis Seron. Review of: K. Mulligan, Wittgenstein et la philosophie austro-allemande (Paris: Vrin, 2012). Dialectica 1 Denis Seron. Review of: K. Mulligan, Wittgenstein et la philosophie austro-allemande (Paris: Vrin, 2012). Dialectica, Volume 70, Issue 1 (March 2016): 125 128. Wittgenstein is usually regarded at once

More information

1/12. The A Paralogisms

1/12. The A Paralogisms 1/12 The A Paralogisms The character of the Paralogisms is described early in the chapter. Kant describes them as being syllogisms which contain no empirical premises and states that in them we conclude

More information

The Metaphysical Status of Tractarian Objects 1

The Metaphysical Status of Tractarian Objects 1 Philosophical Investigations 24:4 October 2001 ISSN 0190-0536 The Metaphysical Status of Tractarian Objects 1 Chon Tejedor I The aim of this paper is to resolve an ongoing controversy over the metaphysical

More information

Death and Immortality (by D Z Phillips) Introductory Remarks

Death and Immortality (by D Z Phillips) Introductory Remarks Death and Immortality (by D Z Phillips) Introductory Remarks Ben Bousquet 24 January 2013 On p.15 of Death and Immortality Dewi Zephaniah Phillips states the following: If we say our language as such is

More information

III Knowledge is true belief based on argument. Plato, Theaetetus, 201 c-d Is Justified True Belief Knowledge? Edmund Gettier

III Knowledge is true belief based on argument. Plato, Theaetetus, 201 c-d Is Justified True Belief Knowledge? Edmund Gettier III Knowledge is true belief based on argument. Plato, Theaetetus, 201 c-d Is Justified True Belief Knowledge? Edmund Gettier In Theaetetus Plato introduced the definition of knowledge which is often translated

More information

J. L. Mackie The Subjectivity of Values

J. L. Mackie The Subjectivity of Values J. L. Mackie The Subjectivity of Values The following excerpt is from Mackie s The Subjectivity of Values, originally published in 1977 as the first chapter in his book, Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong.

More information

Comments on Scott Soames, Philosophical Analysis in the Twentieth Century, volume I

Comments on Scott Soames, Philosophical Analysis in the Twentieth Century, volume I Comments on Scott Soames, Philosophical Analysis in the Twentieth Century, volume I (APA Pacific 2006, Author meets critics) Christopher Pincock (pincock@purdue.edu) December 2, 2005 (20 minutes, 2803

More information

1/6. The Resolution of the Antinomies

1/6. The Resolution of the Antinomies 1/6 The Resolution of the Antinomies Kant provides us with the resolutions of the antinomies in order, starting with the first and ending with the fourth. The first antinomy, as we recall, concerned the

More information

Kant Lecture 4 Review Synthetic a priori knowledge

Kant Lecture 4 Review Synthetic a priori knowledge Kant Lecture 4 Review Synthetic a priori knowledge Statements involving necessity or strict universality could never be known on the basis of sense experience, and are thus known (if known at all) a priori.

More information

Foundations of Analytic Philosophy

Foundations of Analytic Philosophy Foundations of Analytic Philosophy Foundations of Analytic Philosophy (2016-7) Mark Textor Lecture Plan: We will look at the ideas of Frege, Russell and Wittgenstein and the relations between them. Frege

More information

From Transcendental Logic to Transcendental Deduction

From Transcendental Logic to Transcendental Deduction From Transcendental Logic to Transcendental Deduction Let me see if I can say a few things to re-cap our first discussion of the Transcendental Logic, and help you get a foothold for what follows. Kant

More information

1/8. The Third Analogy

1/8. The Third Analogy 1/8 The Third Analogy Kant s Third Analogy can be seen as a response to the theories of causal interaction provided by Leibniz and Malebranche. In the first edition the principle is entitled a principle

More information

Contemporary Theology I: Hegel to Death of God Theologies

Contemporary Theology I: Hegel to Death of God Theologies Contemporary Theology I: Hegel to Death of God Theologies ST503 LESSON 19 of 24 John S. Feinberg, Ph.D. Experience: Professor of Biblical and Systematic Theology, Trinity Evangelical Divinity School. In

More information

Rorty on Language and Social Practices

Rorty on Language and Social Practices Rorty on Language and Social Practices Michele Marsonet, Prof.Dr Dean, School of Humanities Chair of Philosophy of Science University of Genoa, Italy Abstract Richard Rorty wrote on many occasions that

More information

A Priori Knowledge: Analytic? Synthetic A Priori (again) Is All A Priori Knowledge Analytic?

A Priori Knowledge: Analytic? Synthetic A Priori (again) Is All A Priori Knowledge Analytic? A Priori Knowledge: Analytic? Synthetic A Priori (again) Is All A Priori Knowledge Analytic? Recap A Priori Knowledge Knowledge independent of experience Kant: necessary and universal A Posteriori Knowledge

More information

WITTGENSTEIN ON EPISTEMOLOGICAL STATUS OF LOGIC 1

WITTGENSTEIN ON EPISTEMOLOGICAL STATUS OF LOGIC 1 FILOZOFIA Roč. 68, 2013, č. 4 WITTGENSTEIN ON EPISTEMOLOGICAL STATUS OF LOGIC 1 TOMÁŠ ČANA, Katedra filozofie FF UCM, Trnava ČANA, T.: Wittgenstein on Epistemological Status of Logic FILOZOFIA 68, 2013,

More information

MY PURPOSE IN THIS BOOK IS TO PRESENT A

MY PURPOSE IN THIS BOOK IS TO PRESENT A I Holistic Pragmatism and the Philosophy of Culture MY PURPOSE IN THIS BOOK IS TO PRESENT A philosophical discussion of the main elements of civilization or culture such as science, law, religion, politics,

More information

WHAT DOES KRIPKE MEAN BY A PRIORI?

WHAT DOES KRIPKE MEAN BY A PRIORI? Diametros nr 28 (czerwiec 2011): 1-7 WHAT DOES KRIPKE MEAN BY A PRIORI? Pierre Baumann In Naming and Necessity (1980), Kripke stressed the importance of distinguishing three different pairs of notions:

More information

PHILOSOPHY IAS MAINS: QUESTIONS TREND ANALYSIS

PHILOSOPHY IAS MAINS: QUESTIONS TREND ANALYSIS VISION IAS www.visionias.wordpress.com www.visionias.cfsites.org www.visioniasonline.com Under the Guidance of Ajay Kumar Singh ( B.Tech. IIT Roorkee, Director & Founder : Vision IAS ) PHILOSOPHY IAS MAINS:

More information

UNITY OF KNOWLEDGE (IN TRANSDISCIPLINARY RESEARCH FOR SUSTAINABILITY) Vol. I - Philosophical Holism M.Esfeld

UNITY OF KNOWLEDGE (IN TRANSDISCIPLINARY RESEARCH FOR SUSTAINABILITY) Vol. I - Philosophical Holism M.Esfeld PHILOSOPHICAL HOLISM M. Esfeld Department of Philosophy, University of Konstanz, Germany Keywords: atomism, confirmation, holism, inferential role semantics, meaning, monism, ontological dependence, rule-following,

More information

Divisibility, Logic, Radical Empiricism, and Metaphysics

Divisibility, Logic, Radical Empiricism, and Metaphysics Abstract: Divisibility, Logic, Radical Empiricism, and Metaphysics We will explore the problem of the manner in which the world may be divided into parts, and how this affects the application of logic.

More information

1/8. Introduction to Kant: The Project of Critique

1/8. Introduction to Kant: The Project of Critique 1/8 Introduction to Kant: The Project of Critique This course is focused on the interpretation of one book: The Critique of Pure Reason and we will, during the course, read the majority of the key sections

More information

To appear in The Journal of Philosophy.

To appear in The Journal of Philosophy. To appear in The Journal of Philosophy. Lucy Allais: Manifest Reality: Kant s Idealism and his Realism. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2015, pp. xi + 329. 40.00 (hb). ISBN: 9780198747130. Kant s doctrine

More information

Ayer s linguistic theory of the a priori

Ayer s linguistic theory of the a priori Ayer s linguistic theory of the a priori phil 43904 Jeff Speaks December 4, 2007 1 The problem of a priori knowledge....................... 1 2 Necessity and the a priori............................ 2

More information

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg 1 In Search of the Ontological Argument Richard Oxenberg Abstract We can attend to the logic of Anselm's ontological argument, and amuse ourselves for a few hours unraveling its convoluted word-play, or

More information

1/9. The Second Analogy (1)

1/9. The Second Analogy (1) 1/9 The Second Analogy (1) This week we are turning to one of the most famous, if also longest, arguments in the Critique. This argument is both sufficiently and the interpretation of it sufficiently disputed

More information

Ayer and the Vienna Circle

Ayer and the Vienna Circle Ayer and the Vienna Circle Richard Zach October 29, 2010 1/20 Richard Zach Ayer and the Vienna Circle Outline 1 The Vienna Circle 2 Ayer s Logical Positivism 3 Truth and Analyticity 4 Language, Truth and

More information

Cory Juhl, Eric Loomis, Analyticity (New York: Routledge, 2010).

Cory Juhl, Eric Loomis, Analyticity (New York: Routledge, 2010). Cory Juhl, Eric Loomis, Analyticity (New York: Routledge, 2010). Reviewed by Viorel Ţuţui 1 Since it was introduced by Immanuel Kant in the Critique of Pure Reason, the analytic synthetic distinction had

More information

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori PHIL 83104 November 2, 2011 Both Boghossian and Harman address themselves to the question of whether our a priori knowledge can be explained in

More information

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras Module - 21 Lecture - 21 Kant Forms of sensibility Categories

More information

NORTON ANTHOLOGY OF WESTERN PHILOSOPHY: AFTER KANT TABLE OF CONTENTS. Volume 2: The Analytic Tradition. Preface Acknowledgments GENERAL INTRODUCTION

NORTON ANTHOLOGY OF WESTERN PHILOSOPHY: AFTER KANT TABLE OF CONTENTS. Volume 2: The Analytic Tradition. Preface Acknowledgments GENERAL INTRODUCTION NORTON ANTHOLOGY OF WESTERN PHILOSOPHY: AFTER KANT TABLE OF CONTENTS Volume 2: The Analytic Tradition Preface Acknowledgments GENERAL INTRODUCTION I. THE 19 TH CENTURY AND EARLY 20 TH CENTURY BACKGROUND

More information

It doesn t take long in reading the Critique before we are faced with interpretive challenges. Consider the very first sentence in the A edition:

It doesn t take long in reading the Critique before we are faced with interpretive challenges. Consider the very first sentence in the A edition: The Preface(s) to the Critique of Pure Reason It doesn t take long in reading the Critique before we are faced with interpretive challenges. Consider the very first sentence in the A edition: Human reason

More information

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras Module - 22 Lecture - 22 Kant The idea of Reason Soul, God

More information

Remarks on the philosophy of mathematics (1969) Paul Bernays

Remarks on the philosophy of mathematics (1969) Paul Bernays Bernays Project: Text No. 26 Remarks on the philosophy of mathematics (1969) Paul Bernays (Bemerkungen zur Philosophie der Mathematik) Translation by: Dirk Schlimm Comments: With corrections by Charles

More information

The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel s Idealism

The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel s Idealism The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel s Idealism What is a great mistake? Nietzsche once said that a great error is worth more than a multitude of trivial truths. A truly great mistake

More information

Think by Simon Blackburn. Chapter 7c The World

Think by Simon Blackburn. Chapter 7c The World Think by Simon Blackburn Chapter 7c The World Idealism Despite the power of Berkeley s critique, his resulting metaphysical view is highly problematic. Essentially, Berkeley concludes that there is no

More information

PHILOSOPHICAL RAMIFICATIONS: THEORY, EXPERIMENT, & EMPIRICAL TRUTH

PHILOSOPHICAL RAMIFICATIONS: THEORY, EXPERIMENT, & EMPIRICAL TRUTH PHILOSOPHICAL RAMIFICATIONS: THEORY, EXPERIMENT, & EMPIRICAL TRUTH PCES 3.42 Even before Newton published his revolutionary work, philosophers had already been trying to come to grips with the questions

More information

Philosophy and Logical Syntax (1935)

Philosophy and Logical Syntax (1935) Rudolf Carnap: Philosophy and Logical Syntax (1935) Chap. "The Rejection of Metaphysics" 1.Verifiability The problems of philosophy as usually dealt with are of very different kinds. From the point of

More information

Analyticity, Reductionism, and Semantic Holism. The verification theory is an empirical theory of meaning which asserts that the meaning of a

Analyticity, Reductionism, and Semantic Holism. The verification theory is an empirical theory of meaning which asserts that the meaning of a 24.251: Philosophy of Language Paper 1: W.V.O. Quine, Two Dogmas of Empiricism 14 October 2011 Analyticity, Reductionism, and Semantic Holism The verification theory is an empirical theory of meaning which

More information

Introductory Kant Seminar Lecture

Introductory Kant Seminar Lecture Introductory Kant Seminar Lecture Intentionality It is not unusual to begin a discussion of Kant with a brief review of some history of philosophy. What is perhaps less usual is to start with a review

More information

Wilhelm Dilthey and Rudolf Carnap on the Foundation of the Humanities. Christian Damböck Institute Vienna Circle University of Vienna

Wilhelm Dilthey and Rudolf Carnap on the Foundation of the Humanities. Christian Damböck Institute Vienna Circle University of Vienna Wilhelm Dilthey and Rudolf Carnap on the Foundation of the Humanities Christian Damböck Institute Vienna Circle University of Vienna This talk is part of an ongoing research project on Wilhelm Dilthey

More information

24.01 Classics of Western Philosophy

24.01 Classics of Western Philosophy 1 Plan: Kant Lecture #2: How are pure mathematics and pure natural science possible? 1. Review: Problem of Metaphysics 2. Kantian Commitments 3. Pure Mathematics 4. Transcendental Idealism 5. Pure Natural

More information

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras Module - 20 Lecture - 20 Critical Philosophy: Kant s objectives

More information

1/8. The Schematism. schema of empirical concepts, the schema of sensible concepts and the

1/8. The Schematism. schema of empirical concepts, the schema of sensible concepts and the 1/8 The Schematism I am going to distinguish between three types of schematism: the schema of empirical concepts, the schema of sensible concepts and the schema of pure concepts. Kant opens the discussion

More information

LENT 2018 THEORY OF MEANING DR MAARTEN STEENHAGEN

LENT 2018 THEORY OF MEANING DR MAARTEN STEENHAGEN LENT 2018 THEORY OF MEANING DR MAARTEN STEENHAGEN HTTP://MSTEENHAGEN.GITHUB.IO/TEACHING/2018TOM THE EINSTEIN-BERGSON DEBATE SCIENCE AND METAPHYSICS Henri Bergson and Albert Einstein met on the 6th of

More information

Ethical non-naturalism

Ethical non-naturalism Michael Lacewing Ethical non-naturalism Ethical non-naturalism is usually understood as a form of cognitivist moral realism. So we first need to understand what cognitivism and moral realism is before

More information

Fundamentals of Metaphysics

Fundamentals of Metaphysics Fundamentals of Metaphysics Objective and Subjective One important component of the Common Western Metaphysic is the thesis that there is such a thing as objective truth. each of our beliefs and assertions

More information

ON NONSENSE IN THE TRACTATUS LOGICO-PHILOSOPHICUS: A DEFENSE OF THE AUSTERE CONCEPTION

ON NONSENSE IN THE TRACTATUS LOGICO-PHILOSOPHICUS: A DEFENSE OF THE AUSTERE CONCEPTION Guillermo Del Pinal* Most of the propositions to be found in philosophical works are not false but nonsensical (4.003) Philosophy is not a body of doctrine but an activity The result of philosophy is not

More information

1/10. The Fourth Paralogism and the Refutation of Idealism

1/10. The Fourth Paralogism and the Refutation of Idealism 1/10 The Fourth Paralogism and the Refutation of Idealism The Fourth Paralogism is quite different from the three that preceded it because, although it is treated as a part of rational psychology, it main

More information

The Representation of Logical Form: A Dilemma

The Representation of Logical Form: A Dilemma The Representation of Logical Form: A Dilemma Benjamin Ferguson 1 Introduction Throughout the Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus and especially in the 2.17 s and 4.1 s Wittgenstein asserts that propositions

More information

Wittgenstein and Moore s Paradox

Wittgenstein and Moore s Paradox Wittgenstein and Moore s Paradox Marie McGinn, Norwich Introduction In Part II, Section x, of the Philosophical Investigations (PI ), Wittgenstein discusses what is known as Moore s Paradox. Wittgenstein

More information

The Copernican Shift and Theory of Knowledge in Immanuel Kant and Edmund Husserl.

The Copernican Shift and Theory of Knowledge in Immanuel Kant and Edmund Husserl. The Copernican Shift and Theory of Knowledge in Immanuel Kant and Edmund Husserl. Matthew O Neill. BA in Politics & International Studies and Philosophy, Murdoch University, 2012. This thesis is presented

More information

Moral Objectivism. RUSSELL CORNETT University of Calgary

Moral Objectivism. RUSSELL CORNETT University of Calgary Moral Objectivism RUSSELL CORNETT University of Calgary The possibility, let alone the actuality, of an objective morality has intrigued philosophers for well over two millennia. Though much discussed,

More information

The Coherence of Kant s Synthetic A Priori

The Coherence of Kant s Synthetic A Priori The Coherence of Kant s Synthetic A Priori Simon Marcus October 2009 Is there synthetic a priori knowledge? The question can be rephrased as Sellars puts it: Are there any universal propositions which,

More information

Rationalism. A. He, like others at the time, was obsessed with questions of truth and doubt

Rationalism. A. He, like others at the time, was obsessed with questions of truth and doubt Rationalism I. Descartes (1596-1650) A. He, like others at the time, was obsessed with questions of truth and doubt 1. How could one be certain in the absence of religious guidance and trustworthy senses

More information

What is the Nature of Logic? Judy Pelham Philosophy, York University, Canada July 16, 2013 Pan-Hellenic Logic Symposium Athens, Greece

What is the Nature of Logic? Judy Pelham Philosophy, York University, Canada July 16, 2013 Pan-Hellenic Logic Symposium Athens, Greece What is the Nature of Logic? Judy Pelham Philosophy, York University, Canada July 16, 2013 Pan-Hellenic Logic Symposium Athens, Greece Outline of this Talk 1. What is the nature of logic? Some history

More information

Naturalized Epistemology. 1. What is naturalized Epistemology? Quine PY4613

Naturalized Epistemology. 1. What is naturalized Epistemology? Quine PY4613 Naturalized Epistemology Quine PY4613 1. What is naturalized Epistemology? a. How is it motivated? b. What are its doctrines? c. Naturalized Epistemology in the context of Quine s philosophy 2. Naturalized

More information

Kant s Critique of Pure Reason1 (Critique) was published in For. Learning to Count Again: On Arithmetical Knowledge in Kant s Prolegomena

Kant s Critique of Pure Reason1 (Critique) was published in For. Learning to Count Again: On Arithmetical Knowledge in Kant s Prolegomena Aporia vol. 24 no. 1 2014 Learning to Count Again: On Arithmetical Knowledge in Kant s Prolegomena Charles Dalrymple - Fraser One might indeed think at first that the proposition 7+5 =12 is a merely analytic

More information

Twentieth-Century Analytic Philosophy by Avrum Stroll

Twentieth-Century Analytic Philosophy by Avrum Stroll Twentieth-Century Analytic Philosophy by Avrum Stroll Columbia University Press: New York, 2000. 302pp, Hardcover, $32.50. Brad Majors University of Kansas The history of analytic philosophy is a troubled

More information

Conventionalism and the linguistic doctrine of logical truth

Conventionalism and the linguistic doctrine of logical truth 1 Conventionalism and the linguistic doctrine of logical truth 1.1 Introduction Quine s work on analyticity, translation, and reference has sweeping philosophical implications. In his first important philosophical

More information

Philosophy Courses-1

Philosophy Courses-1 Philosophy Courses-1 PHL 100/Introduction to Philosophy A course that examines the fundamentals of philosophical argument, analysis and reasoning, as applied to a series of issues in logic, epistemology,

More information

Ayer on the criterion of verifiability

Ayer on the criterion of verifiability Ayer on the criterion of verifiability November 19, 2004 1 The critique of metaphysics............................. 1 2 Observation statements............................... 2 3 In principle verifiability...............................

More information

"Can We Have a Word in Private?": Wittgenstein on the Impossibility of Private Languages

Can We Have a Word in Private?: Wittgenstein on the Impossibility of Private Languages Macalester Journal of Philosophy Volume 14 Issue 1 Spring 2005 Article 11 5-1-2005 "Can We Have a Word in Private?": Wittgenstein on the Impossibility of Private Languages Dan Walz-Chojnacki Follow this

More information

Metaphysical Problems and Methods

Metaphysical Problems and Methods Metaphysical Problems and Methods Roger Bishop Jones Abstract. Positivists have often been antipathetic to metaphysics. Here, however. a positive role for metaphysics is sought. Problems about reality

More information

A Defence of Kantian Synthetic-Analytic Distinction

A Defence of Kantian Synthetic-Analytic Distinction A Defence of Kantian Synthetic-Analytic Distinction Abstract: Science is organized knowledge. Wisdom is organized life. Immanuel Kant Dr. Rajkumar Modak Associate Professor Department of Philosophy Sidho-Kanho-Birsha

More information

Philosophy 3100: Ethical Theory

Philosophy 3100: Ethical Theory Philosophy 3100: Ethical Theory Topic 2 - Non-Cognitivism: I. What is Non-Cognitivism? II. The Motivational Judgment Internalist Argument for Non-Cognitivism III. Why Ayer Is A Non-Cognitivist a. The Analytic/Synthetic

More information

Philosophy Courses-1

Philosophy Courses-1 Philosophy Courses-1 PHL 100/Introduction to Philosophy A course that examines the fundamentals of philosophical argument, analysis and reasoning, as applied to a series of issues in logic, epistemology,

More information

Projection in Hume. P J E Kail. St. Peter s College, Oxford.

Projection in Hume. P J E Kail. St. Peter s College, Oxford. Projection in Hume P J E Kail St. Peter s College, Oxford Peter.kail@spc.ox.ac.uk A while ago now (2007) I published my Projection and Realism in Hume s Philosophy (Oxford University Press henceforth abbreviated

More information

Rule-Following and the Ontology of the Mind Abstract The problem of rule-following

Rule-Following and the Ontology of the Mind Abstract The problem of rule-following Rule-Following and the Ontology of the Mind Michael Esfeld (published in Uwe Meixner and Peter Simons (eds.): Metaphysics in the Post-Metaphysical Age. Papers of the 22nd International Wittgenstein Symposium.

More information

Kantian Deontology. A2 Ethics Revision Notes Page 1 of 7. Paul Nicholls 13P Religious Studies

Kantian Deontology. A2 Ethics Revision Notes Page 1 of 7. Paul Nicholls 13P Religious Studies A2 Ethics Revision Notes Page 1 of 7 Kantian Deontology Deontological (based on duty) ethical theory established by Emmanuel Kant in The Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals. Part of the enlightenment

More information

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy Res Cogitans Volume 5 Issue 1 Article 20 6-4-2014 Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy Kevin Harriman Lewis & Clark College Follow this and additional works at: http://commons.pacificu.edu/rescogitans

More information

Holtzman Spring Philosophy and the Integration of Knowledge

Holtzman Spring Philosophy and the Integration of Knowledge Holtzman Spring 2000 Philosophy and the Integration of Knowledge What is synthetic or integrative thinking? Of course, to integrate is to bring together to unify, to tie together or connect, to make a

More information

Philosophy of Mathematics Kant

Philosophy of Mathematics Kant Philosophy of Mathematics Kant Owen Griffiths oeg21@cam.ac.uk St John s College, Cambridge 20/10/15 Immanuel Kant Born in 1724 in Königsberg, Prussia. Enrolled at the University of Königsberg in 1740 and

More information

Introduction to Philosophy

Introduction to Philosophy 1 Introduction to Philosophy What is Philosophy? It has many different meanings. In everyday life, to have a philosophy means much the same as having a specified set of attitudes, objectives or values

More information

The Human Science Debate: Positivist, Anti-Positivist, and Postpositivist Inquiry. By Rebecca Joy Norlander. November 20, 2007

The Human Science Debate: Positivist, Anti-Positivist, and Postpositivist Inquiry. By Rebecca Joy Norlander. November 20, 2007 The Human Science Debate: Positivist, Anti-Positivist, and Postpositivist Inquiry By Rebecca Joy Norlander November 20, 2007 2 What is knowledge and how is it acquired through the process of inquiry? Is

More information

Issues in Thinking about God. Michaelmas Term 2008 Johannes Zachhuber

Issues in Thinking about God. Michaelmas Term 2008 Johannes Zachhuber Issues in Thinking about God Michaelmas Term 2008 Johannes Zachhuber http://users.ox.ac.uk/~trin1631 Week 6: God and Language J. Macquarrie, God-Talk, London 1967 F. Kerr, Theology after Wittgenstein,

More information

Issue 4, Special Conference Proceedings Published by the Durham University Undergraduate Philosophy Society

Issue 4, Special Conference Proceedings Published by the Durham University Undergraduate Philosophy Society Issue 4, Special Conference Proceedings 2017 Published by the Durham University Undergraduate Philosophy Society An Alternative Approach to Mathematical Ontology Amber Donovan (Durham University) Introduction

More information

Ibn Sina on Substances and Accidents

Ibn Sina on Substances and Accidents Ibn Sina on Substances and Accidents ERWIN TEGTMEIER, MANNHEIM There was a vivid and influential dialogue of Western philosophy with Ibn Sina in the Middle Ages; but there can be also a fruitful dialogue

More information

Wittgenstein s The First Person and Two-Dimensional Semantics

Wittgenstein s The First Person and Two-Dimensional Semantics Wittgenstein s The First Person and Two-Dimensional Semantics ABSTRACT This essay takes as its central problem Wittgenstein s comments in his Blue and Brown Books on the first person pronoun, I, in particular

More information

Critique of Cosmological Argument

Critique of Cosmological Argument David Hume: Critique of Cosmological Argument Critique of Cosmological Argument DAVID HUME (1711-1776) David Hume is one of the most important philosophers in the history of philosophy. Born in Edinburgh,

More information

Book Reviews 427. University of Manchester Oxford Rd., M13 9PL, UK. doi: /mind/fzl424

Book Reviews 427. University of Manchester Oxford Rd., M13 9PL, UK. doi: /mind/fzl424 Book Reviews 427 Whatever one might think about the merits of different approaches to the study of history of philosophy, one should certainly admit that Knuutilla s book steers with a sure hand over the

More information

Junior Research Fellow and Lecturer in Philosophy Worcester College, University of Oxford Walton Street Oxford OX1 2HB Great Britain

Junior Research Fellow and Lecturer in Philosophy Worcester College, University of Oxford Walton Street Oxford OX1 2HB Great Britain Essay Title: Author: Meaning (verification theory) Markus Schrenk Junior Research Fellow and Lecturer in Philosophy Worcester College, University of Oxford Walton Street Oxford OX1 2HB Great Britain ESSAY

More information

From Theory to Mysticism

From Theory to Mysticism From Theory to Mysticism From Theory to Mysticism: The Unclarity of the Notion Object in Wittgenstein s Tractatus By Andreas Georgallides From Theory to Mysticism: The Unclarity of the Notion Object in

More information