Is the Humean defeated by induction? A reply to Smart. (What is a Law of Nature? Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1983; Dialogue 30

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Is the Humean defeated by induction? A reply to Smart. (What is a Law of Nature? Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1983; Dialogue 30"

Transcription

1 This is a copy of the accepted manuscript for publication. Is the Humean defeated by induction? A reply to Smart Abstract: This paper is a reply to Benjamin Smart s (Philos Stud 162 (2): , 2013) recent objections to David Armstrong s solution to the problem of induction (What is a Law of Nature? Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1983; Dialogue 30 (4): , 1991). To solve the problem of induction, Armstrong contends that laws of nature are the best explanation of our observed regularities, where laws of nature are dyadic relations of necessitation holding between first-order universals. Smart raises three objections against Armstrong s pattern of inference. First, regularities can explain our observed regularities; that is, universally quantified conditionals are required for explanations. Second, if Humean s pattern of inference is irrational, then Armstrong s pattern of inference is also irrational. Third, universal regularities are the best explanation of our observed regularities. I defend Armstrong s solution of induction, arguing against these three claims. Key words: Armstrong, Explanation, Humeanism, Induction, Laws of Nature. 1 Introduction The problem of induction is the problem of justifying inductive inferences, such as the following: (1) All observed ravens are black. All ravens are black. David Armstrong (1983: cap. 4, 6; 1991) argues that the theory of nomic necessity 1

2 makes it possible to solve the problem of induction. To make this feasible, Armstrong follows Gilbert Harman s (1965) interpretation of induction. Induction is described as a special case of inference to the best explanation. (1) All observed ravens are black. (2) The best explanation for (1) is that it is a law of nature that all ravens are black. All ravens are black. According to Armstrong s proposal, laws of nature, symbolized by N(R,B), are firstorder universals, that is, laws of nature are dyadic relations of necessitation, N, holding between first-order universals (R and B). This natural necessitation between universals is the best explanation for our observed regularities. Recently, Armstrong s proposal has been challenged by some regularists. In general, the regularity theorist s strategy has two steps. First, the problem of induction is interpreted in a slightly different way from Armstrong s interpretation of the problem of induction. Second, an alleged missing link or extra step is inserted in Armstrong s solution to block Armstrong s justification of induction. For example, Beebee (2011) considers that what it is really required to explain is why all observed R s have been B s, so far. The expression so far is Beebee s new ingredient of the problem of induction. Then, she advances a competing explanation for this explanandum, a time-limited necessary connection. She argues that Armstrong s solution to the problem of induction, based on timeless necessity, is no longer valid because there is an alleged illicit inductive premise in Armstrong s solution, i.e., an extra step. (See Castro (2014) for a reply). 2

3 Smart follows this same strategy. Smart cooks up two universals: OR means observed-raven and OB means observed-black. For him, what it is really required to explain is why all observed-ravens are observed-black. These universals are Smart s new ingredient in the problem of induction. Three objections are raised from these cooked universals. First, Armstrong s solution to the problem of induction requires universally quantified conditionals to have explanatory value. Second, Armstrong s own pattern of inference fails by his own standards. Third, Armstrong s explanations are not the best explanations. This objection tries to argue that universal regularities are the best explanation of our observed regularities. Basically, Smart s ultimate claim is to show that Armstrong s inductive inferences are no better justified that the Humean s. The remainder of this paper is organised as follows. First, the solution of Armstrong to the problem of induction is presented. Second, the discussion follows. Smart s three objections to Armstrong s solution to the problem of induction are answered individually. 1 2 Armstrong s solution to the problem of induction Armstrong s solution to the problem of induction has two steps: the bottom-up step and the top-down step. The bottom-up step is a step of inference to the best explanation (IBE) that goes from the observational facts to laws. It is a law of nature that all Rs are Bs ; N(R,B) is the best explanation that all observed Rs are Bs. N(R,B) is the truthmaker of the law-statement that best explains our observations. The top-down step is an analytical or conceptual step. It goes from laws to observational facts. The law of nature that all Rs are Bs, N(R,B), entails and explains that all Rs are Bs, x(rx Bx), the law-statement, where all Rs are Bs is logically equivalent to all observed Rs are 1 I follow Smart s letters R and B instead of the traditional letters F and G. 3

4 Bs and all unobserved Rs are Bs. Here is a reconstruction of Armstrong s chain of explanation, where O refers to the predicate O_:_is observed. Bottom-up: Top-down: x((ox Rx) Bx) IBE N(R,B) N(R,B) x(rx Bx) where x(rx Bx) [ x((ox Rx) Bx) x(( Ox Rx) Bx)]. 3 First objection Let R, OR, B and OB be universals. R means raven, OR means observed-raven, B means black and OB means observed-black. Three relations may then be established: (1) N(OR,OB) x(orx OBx). (2) N(R,B) x(rx Bx). (3) N(R,B) x(orx OBx). According to Smart, propositions (1) and (2) follow Armstrongian logic, that is, a necessitation relation between two universals entails the universally quantified conditional between those two universals. However, proposition (3) does not follow Armstrongian logic, that is, a necessitation relation between two universals cannot entail the universally quantified conditional between two completely distinct universals (Smart 2013: 323). OR and OB are not subsets of the properties R and B, respectively. 2 2 Supposedly, for the Humean (or at least, for the nominalist Humean), OR and OB are subsets of R and B. 4

5 Armstrong s solution to the problem of induction fails because x(orx OBx) does not follow from N(R,B). That is, from it is a law of nature that all ravens are black, it cannot be deduced that all observed-ravens are observed-black. According to Smart, the necessitarian may try to solve this issue by suggesting that N(R,B) explains x(orx OBx). Smart justifies this explanation by claiming that N(R,B) does necessitate (in Armstrong s contingent necessitation sense) x(rx Bx). Thus, actually, there is a missing link between N(R,B) and x(orx OBx): it is missing x(rx Bx). At the end of the day, the necessitarian is committed to the following chain of explanation: 1. N(R,B) 2. x(rx Bx) 3. x(orx OBx) To explain our observations, Smart confronts the necessitarian with the dilemma: [The necessitarian] needs either to accept OR and OB as natural properties, and claim the natural necessitation relation stands between these universals at our world, or that regularities can bridge the gap between the proposed explanand and the explanandum. (Smart 2013: 324) 3 It is widely assumed that for an Armstrongian (and surely for anyone), OR and OB are inacceptable as natural properties. Thus, the necessitarian should follow the second horn of the dilemma. If this is the case, actually, x(rx Bx) explains (ORx OBx). Smart 3 There is a typo in the original paper. I wrote OB instead of BR. 5

6 (2013: 324) concludes that without accepting that universally quantified statements have explanatory value, there can be no explanatory relation between N(R,B) and the colour of observed ravens. 4 Reply to the first objection My reply has three points. First, I discuss the relations of explanation between N(R,B) and x(orx OBx) and between x(rx Bx) and x(orx OBx). I argue that neither N(R,B) nor x(rx Bx) explains x(orx OBx). Second, I discuss the entailment between N(R,B) and x(orx OBx). Third, I argue against the existence of the putative universals observed-raven and observed-black. 4 Thus, our explanandum is all observed ravens are black, x((ox Rx) Bx), instead of all observed-ravens are observed-black, x(orx OBx). In this section, to make the discussion more intelligible, I need to introduce a character, a particular sort of idealized necessitarian called absurd necessitarian. The absurd necessitarian accepts Smart s challenge. He wants to explain why all observedravens are observed-black, x(orx OBx). At the end of the discussion, the absurd necessitarian will be discarded, as all observed-ravens are observed-black, x(orx OBx), is an absurd explanandum. 4.1 either (R,B) nor x(rx Bx) explains x(orx OBx) Smart claims that N(R,B) indirectly explains x(orx OBx), via x(rx Bx). That is: (1) N(R,B) entails x(rx Bx); (2) x(rx Bx) explains x(orx OBx); thus, N(R,B) (indirectly) explains x(orx OBx). This reasoning seems to be incorrect for 4 In this paper, natural properties and universals are interchangeable terms. 6

7 several reasons. If it is argued that N(R,B) explains x(orx OBx), then, on the contrary to Smart, that relation of explanation cannot be a relation of explanation simpliciter. 5 The absurd necessitarian searches for the best explanation of our observed regularities. The Armstrong s down-up step is a step of inference to the best explanation. The down-up step is not a chain of explanation simpliciter. To justify induction, inference to the best explanation cannot be discarded. Otherwise, we are left with the classical enumerative induction, before Harman: all observed-ravens are observed-black; thus, all ravens are black. An obvious reply is to claim that N(R,B) is the best explanation of x(orx OBx). However, this claim is highly controversial. For the absurd necessitarian N(R,B) would be, at most, a potential explanation of x(orx OBx). However, N(R,B) would not be the best explanation of x(orx OBx). Clearly, N(OR,OB), instead of N(R,B), would be the best explanation of x(orx OBx). The best inference to laws must be about the types of universals that were observed. If it is alleged that we observed ORs constantly conjoined with OBs, then the absurd necessitarian would infer a relation between ORs and OBs. According to this reasoning, there would no longer be a missing link, x(rx Bx), between N(OR,OB) and x(orx OBx). N(OR,OB) would not entail x(rx Bx). The relation of explanation between N(OR,OB) and x(orx OBx) would be a direct relation. There is an additional issue regarding the claim that N(R,B) is the best explanation of x(orx OBx). Let us take a closer look at Smart s chain of explanation: (1) N(R,B) entails x(rx Bx); (2) x(rx Bx) explains x(orx OBx); 5 Smart s argumentation for the chain of explanation is silent about the best explanation. For instance, N(R,B) explains x(orx OBx) Smart (2011: 323) 7

8 thus, N(R,B) (indirectly) best explains x(orx OBx). Arguably, it is not clear that the second step of this chain of explanation is true. The problem here lies on the flawed Smart s support for his chain of explanation. That is, if N(R,B) is the best explanation of x(orx OBx) and N(R,B) entails x(rx Bx), it does not straightforwardly follow that x(rx Bx) explains x(orx OBx). This is what Lipton (2004: 63) calls the deductive consequence condition on inference. Observational data may be relevant to a hypothesis, but that hypothesis may not explain the observational data. Here is an example from physics. Newton s dynamical theory explains body dynamics. Newton s dynamical theory was an inference to the best explanation of the dynamics of observed bodies on Earth. It turns out that Newton s dynamical theory entails a lower level theory concerning laws of planetary orbit. These laws are a deductive consequence of Newton s dynamical theory. However, it is implausible to claim that the laws of planetary orbit also explain the dynamics of the observed bodies on Earth. It seems to me that, for the absurd necessitarian N(R,B) is not even a potential explanation of x(orx OBx). In light of Smart s grammar (with four distinct universals, R, B, OR and OB), it is implausible to claim that N(R,B) may explain x(orx OBx). Smart s objection against the entailment between N(R,B) and x(orx OBx) can be used against the alleged explanation relation between N(R,B) and x(orx OBx). It is implausible to claim that N(R,B) may explain x(orx OBx), as Smart (2013: 323) states, because this is similar to asserting that all massive objects curve spacetime may be explained by it is contingently necessary that electrons have charge 1. In other words, for the absurd necessitarian, N(R,B) would not be part of the pool of his potential explanations. Surprisingly, Smart does not commit to the idea that N(R,B) explains x(rx Bx): [t]hat all ravens are black is just an implication of his explanation 8

9 [N(R,B)] (Smart 2013: 322 my italic); a perfectly good explanation for this [our observations] might not serve as an explanation for why ravens in general are black (Smart 2013: 323); N(R,B) does not explain why whenever we observe a raven it will be observed to be black (Smart 2013: 324). Smart (2013: 322) speculates that the necessitarian might have a better chance of explaining this phenomenon [all ravens are black] than the Humean (although this is not obviously true). This position is very unusual in the literature. Armstrong (1983: 41; 1988: 225; 1993: 422) and several authors (Mumford 2004: 88; Beebee 2011: 507) consider that N(R,B) explains x(rx Bx). That is, N(R,B) entails and explains the law-statement, x(rx Bx). I believe that providing explanations for law-statements is a basic desideratum for any metaphysical theory of laws of nature. Let us assume that N(R,B) explains x(rx Bx). Then Smart s chain of explanation can be rewritten in the following terms: (1) N(R,B) explains x(rx Bx); (2) x(rx Bx) explains x(orx OBx); thus, by transitivity, N(R,B) explains x(orx OBx). If transitivity is a plausible structural principle of explanation and N(R,B) does not explain x(orx OBx) (as I tried to argue above), then N(R,B) does not explain x(rx Bx) or x(rx Bx) does not explain x(orx OBx). On Armstrong s top-down step, N(R,B) entails and explains x(rx Bx). Then, the blame is on the alleged relation of explanation between x(rx Bx) and x(orx OBx). That is, x(rx Bx) does not explain x(orx OBx). Moreover, according to Smart, R and B, and OR and OB are four distinct universals; thus, x(rx Bx) can hardly explain why x(orx OBx). As Smart (2013: 323) puts it, once again, this is to claim that all massive objects curve spacetime are explained by [all] electrons have charge 1. Finally, from the point of view of necessitarianism, if N(R,B) explained 9

10 x(orx OBx), that relation of explanation would not be justified by the claim that N(R,B) does necessitate (in Armstrong s contingent necessitation sense) x(rx Bx). 6 When we are trying to justify our explanations, we are not trying to prove that our explanation is true. Granting that our explanation is true, we try to justify that the explanation provides understanding of the observed phenomena (Lipton 2004: 21). The best guide for inference is total science. Based on observation, for example, science would say that it is rational to infer that there is a law of nature that all Rs are Bs. Laws of nature provide understanding for our observations. In this scenario, it would not make sense to invoke a missing link, x(rx Bx), between our observations, x(orx OBx), and our inference, N(R,B). N(R,B) would directly explain x(orx OBx). Science is enough to justify our explanatory inferences. 4.2 (R,B) x(orx OBx) Recall that Smart s starting problem was how to infer x(orx OBx) from N(R,B). However, even if Smart s chain of explanation is correct, for reasons beyond my knowledge, actually, this chain per se does not help the absurd necessitarian to infer x(orx OBx) from N(R,B). Smart s chain of explanation only rewrites Armstrong s bottom-up step, and it is silent about what happens in Armstrong s top-down step. As I see it, Smart s starting problem is a red herring. Nothing in Smart s dilemma depends on Smart s starting problem. It may be suggested that there is indeed one more missing link in Armstrong s top-down step. It is missing x(rx Bx) between N(R,B) and x(orx OBx): N(R,B) entails x(rx Bx); x(rx Bx) entails x(orx OBx); thus, by transitivity, N(R,B) 6 This relation of contingent necessitation between N(R,B) and x(rx Bx) implies an infinite regress. See Bird (2005). 10

11 entails x(orx OBx). However, arguably, x(rx Bx) does not entail x(orx OBx) because it is not evident how a universally quantified conditional between two universals (R and B) can entail a universally quantified conditional between two completely distinct universals (OR and OB). If x(rx Bx) does not entail x(orx OBx), in light of Smart s proposal, it continues to be a mystery how x(orx OBx) may follow from N(R,B). x(orx OBx) follows from N(R,B) if some modifications in Smart s universals ontology are made. The predicate O_:_is observed must correspond to a universal. 7 Let s say observeness is the property that all observational things have in common. If the predicate O_: _is observed is a universal, then the universals OR, observed-raven, and OB, observed-black, can be defined as conjunctive properties. Observed-raven is the conjunction of the universals observedness (O) and ravenhood (R); that is, OR=O&R. Observed-black is the conjunction of the universals observedness (O) and blackness (B); that is, OB=O&B. For example, if the particular a has the property O and a has the distinct property R, then a has the property O&R. However, on the contrary to Smart, this is not to say that O, R and OR are three wholly distinct properties. Nor is OR a property above the property O and the property R. The same goes for the properties O, B and OB. If the previous conjunctive properties are accepted, then x(orx OBx) follows from N(R,B). (1) N(R,B) x(rx Bx) Premise (2) x(rx Bx) x((ox Rx) (Ox Bx)) Premise 7 It might be argued that observeness is not a monadic universal but rather a dyadic universal a relational universal, i.e., something as such _observes_. It seems to me that this is not an issue for my proposal. 11

12 (3) OR=O&R Premise (4) OB=O&B Premise (5) x(rx Bx) x(orx OBx) From (2)-(4) N(R,B) x(orx OBx) From (1) and (5) The previous solution is not satisfactory. It seems to me that being observed is not a universal. We are not forced to admit in our ontology the property being observed. To be or not to be observed depends on some other properties that particulars must have. Armstrong (1978: 11) notes that a necessary condition for something s being a property ( ) that property must endow the particular with some specific causal power. Visual stimuli are caused by electromagnetic radiation emitted by bodies. Different bodies have different electromagnetic spectrums. Some bodies are directly observed by humans; others are indirectly observed, via appropriately technology. It seems that the causal power of electromagnetic radiation is a property endowed to objects of perception such as ravens. Furthermore, it would be bizarre that a particular raven would not instantiate the universal being observed before first-time observation; afterwards, it would instantiate the universal being observed. That is, a particular raven would begin to instantiate a universal without any modification in its own physical structure. A genuine universal must result in some causal difference to the particular that instantiates it. To sum up, in light of Smart s proposal, it is a mystery how to infer x(orx OBx) from N(R,B). Smart s starting problem is a red herring. The next section shows that Armstrong does not need to infer x(orx OBx) from N(R,B). 4.3 OR and OB 12

13 Let us return to Smart s universals ontology. If Smart s chain of explanation is incorrect, as I demonstrated above, given Smart s dilemma, then the absurd necessitarian must bite the bullet and accept OR and OB as natural properties to explain our observations. That is, N(OR,OB) explains x(orx OBx). This outcome is not a surprise. After all, if the absurd necessitarian and Armstrong depart from two different explanandum, then two different explanans should be inferred. On the one hand, the absurd necessitarian wants to explain why all observed-ravens are observed-black, x(orx OBx). 8 Then, the absurd necessitarian must infer that it is a law of nature that all observed-ravens are observed-black, N(OR,OB). On the other hand, Armstrong wants to explain why all observed ravens are black, x((ox Rx) Bx). Then, Armstrong must infer that it is a law of nature that all ravens are black, N(R,B). Needless to say, N(OR,OB) does not seem to be a law of nature at all. The lawstatement all ravens are black, x(rx Bx), simply does not follow from N(OR,OB). Something is going wrong here. The root of the problem concerns the nature of OR and OB. Smart s discussion begins from an incorrect explanandum. We are not trying to explain why all observed-ravens are observed-black, x(orx OBx). What we are really trying to explain is why all observed ravens are black, x((ox Rx) Bx). Our observed data concern ravenhood (R) and blackness (B). Our observed data do not concern ORhood and OBness. Predicates do not stand in a one-one relation to universals. OR and OB are manmade things. OR and OB are cooked-up predicates that do not correspond to universals. Being observed-raven and being observed-black are not genuine properties. They are artificial properties. Actually, it seems to me that observed-raven and observed- 8 Actually, Smart also notes that we want to explain why all ravens in our sample have been observed to be black (Smart 2013: 323), but this formulisation of explanandum does not reappear in the remainder of section 2 of the paper, where this point is discussed. 13

14 black are a camouflage for three distinct predicates: O_:_is observed, R_:_is raven and B_:_is black. According to our best total science, prima facie, the predicates R_:_is raven and B_:_is black refer to the universals ravenhood and blackness, respectively. There is no corresponding universal to the predicate O_:_is observed, as stated above. Thus, the statement all observed ravens are black can be formulised as x((ox Rx) Bx). This is the correct explanandum that needs to be explained. The absurd necessitarian must now be discarded. It is absurd to try to explain an incorrect explanandum. Here is how things run. The scientific enterprise begins by discovering universals and relations between those universals. We observe that a is R and a is B, b is R and b is B, c is R and c is B, etc. Science assumes that R and B are universals. Science hypothesizes that there is a relation between Rs and Bs that explains why all observed Rs are Bs. That is, it is a law of nature that all Rs are Bs explains why all observed Rs are Bs. This step is a step of inference to the best explanation. Then, predictions are entailed by the law. The law entails and explains that all Rs are Bs. All Rs are Bs is logically equivalent to all observed Rs are Bs and all unobserved Rs are Bs. If we try to express the sentence all unobserved ravens are black in Smart s grammar of universals, once again, it is evident that observed-raven and observedblack are a camouflage for three distinct predicates. The sentence all unobserved ravens are black is required for our inductive inferences. Crucially, we need to infer something about the unobservable to amplify our reasoning, and prediction enters onto the stage. Following Smart s grammar, we may paraphrase all unobserved ravens are black by all unobserved ravens are unobserved black. This paraphrase is not good. Here, logical formulisation may help to see things more clearly. All unobserved ravens 14

15 are unobserved black may be formulised as x( ORx OBx). Clearly, this is incorrect. This formula means for all x, if x is not observed-raven, then x is not observed-black. A white shoe is neither observed-raven nor observed-black. However, a white shoe is not a raven. Let us try an alternative interpretation. Let UR and UB be universals. UR means unobserved-raven and UB means unobserved-black. Then, all unobserved ravens are unobserved black may be formulised as x(urx UBx). This new grammar continues to be problematic. Again: a white shoe is neither unobserved-raven nor unobserved-black; however, a white shoe is not a raven. Finally, let us try other formulisation for our paraphrase: x(( Ox ORx) OBx). This formula means for all x, if x is unobserved and x is observed-raven, then x is observed-black. Clearly, this sentence is not equivalent to all unobserved ravens are unobserved black. I conclude that the predicates OR_:_is observed-raven and OB_:_is observed-black are spurious in this discussion. The predicates O_:_is observed, R_:_is raven and B_:_is black are enough for our job. All unobserved ravens are black is simply formulised as x(( Ox Rx) Bx). 5 Second objection Smart s second objection is an analogy: if Humean s pattern of inference is irrational, then Armstrong s pattern of inference is also irrational. This is the passage: Armstrong s initial objection that the Humean s pattern of inference was reducible to the irrational e h [observed instances entails claims about unobserved instances] but if we look at Armstrong s own pattern of inference we can clearly see that he himself is committed to this pattern, as ultimately Armstrong s inference is an inductive inference, and all inductive inferences 15

16 take this form. ( ) In this case, the inference is not to the observed instances plus the unobserved instances (e + h), but from the observed instances to the unobservable (!) natural necessitation relation between the respective universals. If the Humean s observed to unobserved pattern of inference is irrational, then so is Armstrong s. (Smart 2013: 325). 6 Reply to the second objection In the above passage, there is a misunderstanding of Armstrong s proposal. The Humean jump from the observed to the unobserved per se is not irrational. The Humean justification of induction is irrational because his conception of laws of nature is flawed. The rationality of an inductive inference does not depend on the observational nature of the inference. We make rational inferences from the observed to the observable. For example, I may say that my car does not work because it is cold this morning. We make rational inferences from the observed to the unobservable. Scientific realists posit unobservable concrete theoretical entities to explain observed phenomena. Cloud chamber tracks are explained by the existence of unobservable particles. Mathematical realists posit unobservable abstract entities (e.g., prime numbers) to explain physical observed phenomena. The cicada life-cycle period is explained by the properties of prime numbers of mathematical number theory (Baker 2005). We make rational inferences from the unobserved to the observable. Maxwell inferred a distribution law for molecular velocities from the unobserved molecular nature of a gas that was posited by kinetic theory (Achinstein 1971: 118). We make rational inferences from the unobservable to the unobservable. Within mathematical applications, mathematical explanations are used to explain mathematical facts. The mathematical 16

17 fact that S(n) = (n+1)/n is proved by mathematical induction, but other proofs are considered to be more explanatory (Steiner 1978). Humeans and necessitarians have different conceptions of laws of nature. For the Humean, laws are taken to be universally quantified truths. That is, it is a law that all Rs are Bs means that all Rs are Bs, x(rx Bx). x(rx Bx) is logically equivalent to x((ox Rx) Bx) x(( Ox Rx) Bx). Therefore, for the Humean, the explanans it is a law that all Rs are Bs is the conjunction x((ox Rx) Bx) x(( Ox Rx) Bx). However, neither conjunct of the explanans explains the explanandum, x(ox Rx) Bx). On the one hand, the first conjunct x((ox Rx) Bx) does not explain why x((ox Rx) Bx) because it is circular. On the other hand, the second conjunct x(( Ox Rx) Bx) can hardly explain why x((ox Rx) Bx), as unobserved phenomena strictly concerning ravens, does not have explanatory power. Thus, the Humean does not explain why x((ox Rx) Bx). His conception of laws of nature is flawed. This, and only this, justification is irrational (Armstrong 1983: 52-59). Smart objects that a regularity can explain observations. He gives an example of political polls: the proportions in the total population do seem to explain the results of the polls (Smart 2013: 324). The total proportions do not explain why people choose to vote in the candidates but the total proportions explain why polls provide good predictions of election results. This example is flawed. It simply seems to me that there is no regularity here. Clearly, the proportions in the total population are not a regularity. The proportions in the total population are not fixed in time. Yesterday, I was Liberal; today, I am Socialist. This ideological fluctuation in time is valid for many. From the side of the necessitarian s proposal, there is also a jump from the observed to the unobserved (more precisely, a jump from the observed instances to the 17

18 observed instances plus the unobserved instances). However, contrary to the Humean s proposal, that jump is mediated by an extra thing a law of nature, N(R,B). 9 According to the necessitarian, laws of nature are not simply the universal quantification all Rs are Bs ; laws are first-order universals; they are dyadic relations of necessitation between first-order universals. Laws of nature are the tertium quid that mediates the observed and the unobserved. The inference from all observed Rs are Bs to it is a law that all Rs are Bs, N(R,B), is an instance of inference to the best explanation. That is, induction is a case of inference to the best explanation. N(R,B) is what best explains our observations. Thus, Armstrong s own pattern of inference is rational because it is a case of inference to the best explanation. Rhetorically, à la Strawson (1952), if inference to the best explanation is not rational, what is then rational? 10 7 Third objection In this objection, Smart puts aside the artificial universals OR and OB. Instead of these universals, he considers the traditional universals F and G. Smart insists that logical equivalence does not entail explanatory equivalence. That is, x(fx Gx) is logically equivalent to x((ox Fx) Gx) x(( Ox Fx) Gx) but it does not follow that x(fx Gx) has the same explanatory force of x((ox Fx) Gx) x(( Ox Fx) Gx). Let R(F,G) be the universal regularity between the universals Fness and G-ness. R(F,G) means all Fs are Gs. He thinks that he has shown that, 9 Contrary to Smart, the natural necessitation relation between universals, N(R,B), is not an unobservable entity. The natural necessitation relation is an object of perception. The notion of contingent necessity is postulated by our experience of singular causation relations that are an object of direct perception. This point is beyond the scope of this paper. 10 Smart takes his explanation, R(F,G), an instance of inference to the best explanation, too. 18

19 frequently, R(F,G) is the best explanation of our observations of Fs being Gs. To sum up, Smart s patterns of inference is the following: all observed Fs are Gs (via IBE) R(F,G); R(F,G) all observed Fs are Gs and all unobserved Fs are Gs. 8 Reply to the third objection Given my replies above, I do not have much to say about the third objection. As far I can see, Smart s claim (i.e., frequently, R(F,G) is the best explanation of our observations of Fs being Gs) is supported in two points: (1) all ravens are black explains all observed-ravens are observed-black ; (2) regarding political polls, the proportions in the total population explain the results of the polls. I replied against these two points. At my reply to the first objection, I argued that all ravens are black does not explain all observed-ravens are observed-black. At my reply to the second objection, I argued that the proportions in the total population are not a regularity. Thus, it is not often the case that R(F,G) is the best explanation of our observations of Fs being Gs. Moreover, at my reply to the second objection, I argued that N(F,G) is the best explanation of our observations of Fs being Gs, as the law of nature, N(F,G), is not simply an universal regularity, R(F,G) Conclusion This paper replied to Smart s objections against Armstrong s solution of the problem of induction. I have shown that the cooked-up predicates observed-raven and observedblack do not support Smart s desiderata. Armstrong s solution to the problem of induction does not require universally quantified conditionals to have explanatory value. 11 Armstrong (1983) makes a long discussion that demonstrates why the regularity theory fails to succeed in this point. It is redundant to follow this point. 19

20 Humean s pattern of inference is irrational, because his conception of laws of nature is flawed. Instead of universal regularities, the natural necessitation between universals is the best explanation for our observed regularities. References Achinstein, Peter Law and Explanation. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Armstrong, David A Theory of Universals: Volume 2: Universals and Scientific Realism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press What is a Law of ature? Cambridge: Cambridge University Press Reply to van Fraassen. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 66 (2): doi: / What Makes Induction Rational? Dialogue 30 (04): doi: /s The Identification Problem and the Inference Problem. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 53 (2): doi: / Baker, Alan Are There Genuine Mathematical Explanations of Physical Phenomena? Mind 114 (454): doi: /mind/fzi223. Beebee, Helen Necessary Connections and the Problem of Induction. oûs 45 (3): doi: /j x. Bird, Alexander The Ultimate Argument against Armstrong s Contingent Necessitation View of Laws. Analysis 65 (286): doi: /j x. Castro, Eduardo On Induction: Time-limited Necessity vs. Timeless Necessity. Teorema 33 (3):

21 Harman, Gilbert The Inference to the Best Explanation. The Philosophical Review 74 (1): doi: / Lipton, Peter Inference to the Best Explanation. London: Routledge. Mumford, Stephen Laws in ature. London: Routledge. Smart, Benjamin Is the Humean Defeated by Induction? Philosophical Studies 162 (2): doi: /s Steiner, M Mathematical Explanation. Philosophical Studies 34 (2): Strawson, Peter Introduction to Logical Theory. London: Methuen & Co Ltd. 21

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 4: Skepticism. Part 1: The Scope of Skepticism and Two Main Types of Skeptical Argument

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 4: Skepticism. Part 1: The Scope of Skepticism and Two Main Types of Skeptical Argument 1. The Scope of Skepticism Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 4: Skepticism Part 1: The Scope of Skepticism and Two Main Types of Skeptical Argument The scope of skeptical challenges can vary in a number

More information

The Problem of Induction and Popper s Deductivism

The Problem of Induction and Popper s Deductivism The Problem of Induction and Popper s Deductivism Issues: I. Problem of Induction II. Popper s rejection of induction III. Salmon s critique of deductivism 2 I. The problem of induction 1. Inductive vs.

More information

5 A Modal Version of the

5 A Modal Version of the 5 A Modal Version of the Ontological Argument E. J. L O W E Moreland, J. P.; Sweis, Khaldoun A.; Meister, Chad V., Jul 01, 2013, Debating Christian Theism The original version of the ontological argument

More information

Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000)

Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000) Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000) One of the advantages traditionally claimed for direct realist theories of perception over indirect realist theories is that the

More information

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW DISCUSSION NOTE BY CAMPBELL BROWN JOURNAL OF ETHICS & SOCIAL PHILOSOPHY DISCUSSION NOTE MAY 2015 URL: WWW.JESP.ORG COPYRIGHT CAMPBELL BROWN 2015 Two Versions of Hume s Law MORAL CONCLUSIONS CANNOT VALIDLY

More information

II RESEMBLANCE NOMINALISM, CONJUNCTIONS

II RESEMBLANCE NOMINALISM, CONJUNCTIONS Meeting of the Aristotelian Society held at Senate House, University of London, on 22 October 2012 at 5:30 p.m. II RESEMBLANCE NOMINALISM, CONJUNCTIONS AND TRUTHMAKERS The resemblance nominalist says that

More information

PHILOSOPHY 4360/5360 METAPHYSICS. Methods that Metaphysicians Use

PHILOSOPHY 4360/5360 METAPHYSICS. Methods that Metaphysicians Use PHILOSOPHY 4360/5360 METAPHYSICS Methods that Metaphysicians Use Method 1: The appeal to what one can imagine where imagining some state of affairs involves forming a vivid image of that state of affairs.

More information

Resemblance Nominalism and counterparts

Resemblance Nominalism and counterparts ANAL63-3 4/15/2003 2:40 PM Page 221 Resemblance Nominalism and counterparts Alexander Bird 1. Introduction In his (2002) Gonzalo Rodriguez-Pereyra provides a powerful articulation of the claim that Resemblance

More information

Van Fraassen: Arguments Concerning Scientific Realism

Van Fraassen: Arguments Concerning Scientific Realism Aaron Leung Philosophy 290-5 Week 11 Handout Van Fraassen: Arguments Concerning Scientific Realism 1. Scientific Realism and Constructive Empiricism What is scientific realism? According to van Fraassen,

More information

Explanatory Indispensability and Deliberative Indispensability: Against Enoch s Analogy Alex Worsnip University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill

Explanatory Indispensability and Deliberative Indispensability: Against Enoch s Analogy Alex Worsnip University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill Explanatory Indispensability and Deliberative Indispensability: Against Enoch s Analogy Alex Worsnip University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill Forthcoming in Thought please cite published version In

More information

Philosophy Epistemology Topic 5 The Justification of Induction 1. Hume s Skeptical Challenge to Induction

Philosophy Epistemology Topic 5 The Justification of Induction 1. Hume s Skeptical Challenge to Induction Philosophy 5340 - Epistemology Topic 5 The Justification of Induction 1. Hume s Skeptical Challenge to Induction In the section entitled Sceptical Doubts Concerning the Operations of the Understanding

More information

A Solution to the Gettier Problem Keota Fields. the three traditional conditions for knowledge, have been discussed extensively in the

A Solution to the Gettier Problem Keota Fields. the three traditional conditions for knowledge, have been discussed extensively in the A Solution to the Gettier Problem Keota Fields Problem cases by Edmund Gettier 1 and others 2, intended to undermine the sufficiency of the three traditional conditions for knowledge, have been discussed

More information

Does Deduction really rest on a more secure epistemological footing than Induction?

Does Deduction really rest on a more secure epistemological footing than Induction? Does Deduction really rest on a more secure epistemological footing than Induction? We argue that, if deduction is taken to at least include classical logic (CL, henceforth), justifying CL - and thus deduction

More information

Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods

Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods delineating the scope of deductive reason Roger Bishop Jones Abstract. The scope of deductive reason is considered. First a connection is discussed between the

More information

Merricks on the existence of human organisms

Merricks on the existence of human organisms Merricks on the existence of human organisms Cian Dorr August 24, 2002 Merricks s Overdetermination Argument against the existence of baseballs depends essentially on the following premise: BB Whenever

More information

Van Fraassen: Arguments concerning scientific realism

Van Fraassen: Arguments concerning scientific realism Van Fraassen: Arguments concerning scientific realism 1. Scientific realism and constructive empiricism a) Minimal scientific realism 1) The aim of scientific theories is to provide literally true stories

More information

Kripke on the distinctness of the mind from the body

Kripke on the distinctness of the mind from the body Kripke on the distinctness of the mind from the body Jeff Speaks April 13, 2005 At pp. 144 ff., Kripke turns his attention to the mind-body problem. The discussion here brings to bear many of the results

More information

Philosophy Epistemology. Topic 3 - Skepticism

Philosophy Epistemology. Topic 3 - Skepticism Michael Huemer on Skepticism Philosophy 3340 - Epistemology Topic 3 - Skepticism Chapter II. The Lure of Radical Skepticism 1. Mike Huemer defines radical skepticism as follows: Philosophical skeptics

More information

Some Good and Some Not so Good Arguments for Necessary Laws. William Russell Payne Ph.D.

Some Good and Some Not so Good Arguments for Necessary Laws. William Russell Payne Ph.D. Some Good and Some Not so Good Arguments for Necessary Laws William Russell Payne Ph.D. The view that properties have their causal powers essentially, which I will here call property essentialism, has

More information

Against the No-Miracle Response to Indispensability Arguments

Against the No-Miracle Response to Indispensability Arguments Against the No-Miracle Response to Indispensability Arguments I. Overview One of the most influential of the contemporary arguments for the existence of abstract entities is the so-called Quine-Putnam

More information

Introduction. I. Proof of the Minor Premise ( All reality is completely intelligible )

Introduction. I. Proof of the Minor Premise ( All reality is completely intelligible ) Philosophical Proof of God: Derived from Principles in Bernard Lonergan s Insight May 2014 Robert J. Spitzer, S.J., Ph.D. Magis Center of Reason and Faith Lonergan s proof may be stated as follows: Introduction

More information

From Necessary Truth to Necessary Existence

From Necessary Truth to Necessary Existence Prequel for Section 4.2 of Defending the Correspondence Theory Published by PJP VII, 1 From Necessary Truth to Necessary Existence Abstract I introduce new details in an argument for necessarily existing

More information

Necessity and Truth Makers

Necessity and Truth Makers JAN WOLEŃSKI Instytut Filozofii Uniwersytetu Jagiellońskiego ul. Gołębia 24 31-007 Kraków Poland Email: jan.wolenski@uj.edu.pl Web: http://www.filozofia.uj.edu.pl/jan-wolenski Keywords: Barry Smith, logic,

More information

Realism and the success of science argument. Leplin:

Realism and the success of science argument. Leplin: Realism and the success of science argument Leplin: 1) Realism is the default position. 2) The arguments for anti-realism are indecisive. In particular, antirealism offers no serious rival to realism in

More information

Armstrongian Particulars with Necessary Properties

Armstrongian Particulars with Necessary Properties Armstrongian Particulars with Necessary Properties Daniel von Wachter [This is a preprint version, available at http://sammelpunkt.philo.at, of: Wachter, Daniel von, 2013, Amstrongian Particulars with

More information

Broad on Theological Arguments. I. The Ontological Argument

Broad on Theological Arguments. I. The Ontological Argument Broad on God Broad on Theological Arguments I. The Ontological Argument Sample Ontological Argument: Suppose that God is the most perfect or most excellent being. Consider two things: (1)An entity that

More information

Philosophy of Mathematics Nominalism

Philosophy of Mathematics Nominalism Philosophy of Mathematics Nominalism Owen Griffiths oeg21@cam.ac.uk Churchill and Newnham, Cambridge 8/11/18 Last week Ante rem structuralism accepts mathematical structures as Platonic universals. We

More information

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory Western University Scholarship@Western 2015 Undergraduate Awards The Undergraduate Awards 2015 Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory David Hakim Western University, davidhakim266@gmail.com

More information

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori PHIL 83104 November 2, 2011 Both Boghossian and Harman address themselves to the question of whether our a priori knowledge can be explained in

More information

Can Rationality Be Naturalistically Explained? Jeffrey Dunn. Abstract: Dan Chiappe and John Vervaeke (1997) conclude their article, Fodor,

Can Rationality Be Naturalistically Explained? Jeffrey Dunn. Abstract: Dan Chiappe and John Vervaeke (1997) conclude their article, Fodor, Can Rationality Be Naturalistically Explained? Jeffrey Dunn Abstract: Dan Chiappe and John Vervaeke (1997) conclude their article, Fodor, Cherniak and the Naturalization of Rationality, with an argument

More information

How Do We Know Anything about Mathematics? - A Defence of Platonism

How Do We Know Anything about Mathematics? - A Defence of Platonism How Do We Know Anything about Mathematics? - A Defence of Platonism Majda Trobok University of Rijeka original scientific paper UDK: 141.131 1:51 510.21 ABSTRACT In this paper I will try to say something

More information

SIMON BOSTOCK Internal Properties and Property Realism

SIMON BOSTOCK Internal Properties and Property Realism SIMON BOSTOCK Internal Properties and Property Realism R ealism about properties, standardly, is contrasted with nominalism. According to nominalism, only particulars exist. According to realism, both

More information

The cosmological argument (continued)

The cosmological argument (continued) The cosmological argument (continued) Remember that last time we arrived at the following interpretation of Aquinas second way: Aquinas 2nd way 1. At least one thing has been caused to come into existence.

More information

Lecture 3: Properties II Nominalism & Reductive Realism. Lecture 3: Properties II Nominalism & Reductive Realism

Lecture 3: Properties II Nominalism & Reductive Realism. Lecture 3: Properties II Nominalism & Reductive Realism 1. Recap of previous lecture 2. Anti-Realism 2.1. Motivations 2.2. Austere Nominalism: Overview, Pros and Cons 3. Reductive Realisms: the Appeal to Sets 3.1. Sets of Objects 3.2. Sets of Tropes 4. Overview

More information

ARMSTRONGIAN PARTICULARS WITH NECESSARY PROPERTIES *

ARMSTRONGIAN PARTICULARS WITH NECESSARY PROPERTIES * ARMSTRONGIAN PARTICULARS WITH NECESSARY PROPERTIES * Daniel von Wachter Internationale Akademie für Philosophie, Santiago de Chile Email: epost@abc.de (replace ABC by von-wachter ) http://von-wachter.de

More information

Ayer and Quine on the a priori

Ayer and Quine on the a priori Ayer and Quine on the a priori November 23, 2004 1 The problem of a priori knowledge Ayer s book is a defense of a thoroughgoing empiricism, not only about what is required for a belief to be justified

More information

Philosophy 125 Day 4: Overview

Philosophy 125 Day 4: Overview Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 1 Philosophy 125 Day 4: Overview Administrative Stuff Final rosters for sections have been determined. Please check the sections page asap. Important: you must get

More information

Anti-Metaphysicalism, Necessity, and Temporal Ontology 1

Anti-Metaphysicalism, Necessity, and Temporal Ontology 1 Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Philosophy and Phenomenological Research doi: 10.1111/phpr.12129 2014 Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, LLC Anti-Metaphysicalism, Necessity, and Temporal

More information

Reply to Kit Fine. Theodore Sider July 19, 2013

Reply to Kit Fine. Theodore Sider July 19, 2013 Reply to Kit Fine Theodore Sider July 19, 2013 Kit Fine s paper raises important and difficult issues about my approach to the metaphysics of fundamentality. In chapters 7 and 8 I examined certain subtle

More information

Is there a good epistemological argument against platonism? DAVID LIGGINS

Is there a good epistemological argument against platonism? DAVID LIGGINS [This is the penultimate draft of an article that appeared in Analysis 66.2 (April 2006), 135-41, available here by permission of Analysis, the Analysis Trust, and Blackwell Publishing. The definitive

More information

Deflationary Nominalism s Commitment to Meinongianism

Deflationary Nominalism s Commitment to Meinongianism Res Cogitans Volume 7 Issue 1 Article 8 6-24-2016 Deflationary Nominalism s Commitment to Meinongianism Anthony Nguyen Reed College Follow this and additional works at: http://commons.pacificu.edu/rescogitans

More information

Lecture One: The Aspiration for a Natural Science of the Social

Lecture One: The Aspiration for a Natural Science of the Social Lecture One: The Aspiration for a Natural Science of the Social Explanation These lectures presuppose that the primary task of science is to explain. This does not mean that the only task of science is

More information

2 Why Truthmakers GONZALO RODRIGUEZ-PEREYRA 1. INTRODUCTION

2 Why Truthmakers GONZALO RODRIGUEZ-PEREYRA 1. INTRODUCTION 2 Why Truthmakers GONZALO RODRIGUEZ-PEREYRA 1. INTRODUCTION Consider a certain red rose. The proposition that the rose is red is true because the rose is red. One might say as well that the proposition

More information

SKEPTICISM, ABDUCTIVISM, AND THE EXPLANATORY GAP. Ram Neta University of North Carolina, Chapel Hill

SKEPTICISM, ABDUCTIVISM, AND THE EXPLANATORY GAP. Ram Neta University of North Carolina, Chapel Hill Philosophical Issues, 14, Epistemology, 2004 SKEPTICISM, ABDUCTIVISM, AND THE EXPLANATORY GAP Ram Neta University of North Carolina, Chapel Hill I. Introduction:The Skeptical Problem and its Proposed Abductivist

More information

MAKING A METAPHYSICS FOR NATURE. Alexander Bird, Nature s Metaphysics: Laws and Properties. Oxford: Clarendon, Pp. xiv PB.

MAKING A METAPHYSICS FOR NATURE. Alexander Bird, Nature s Metaphysics: Laws and Properties. Oxford: Clarendon, Pp. xiv PB. Metascience (2009) 18:75 79 Ó Springer 2009 DOI 10.1007/s11016-009-9239-0 REVIEW MAKING A METAPHYSICS FOR NATURE Alexander Bird, Nature s Metaphysics: Laws and Properties. Oxford: Clarendon, 2007. Pp.

More information

Fatalism and Truth at a Time Chad Marxen

Fatalism and Truth at a Time Chad Marxen Stance Volume 6 2013 29 Fatalism and Truth at a Time Chad Marxen Abstract: In this paper, I will examine an argument for fatalism. I will offer a formalized version of the argument and analyze one of the

More information

Ayer on the criterion of verifiability

Ayer on the criterion of verifiability Ayer on the criterion of verifiability November 19, 2004 1 The critique of metaphysics............................. 1 2 Observation statements............................... 2 3 In principle verifiability...............................

More information

Scientific Realism and Empiricism

Scientific Realism and Empiricism Philosophy 164/264 December 3, 2001 1 Scientific Realism and Empiricism Administrative: All papers due December 18th (at the latest). I will be available all this week and all next week... Scientific Realism

More information

THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE

THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE Diametros nr 29 (wrzesień 2011): 80-92 THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE Karol Polcyn 1. PRELIMINARIES Chalmers articulates his argument in terms of two-dimensional

More information

All philosophical debates not due to ignorance of base truths or our imperfect rationality are indeterminate.

All philosophical debates not due to ignorance of base truths or our imperfect rationality are indeterminate. PHIL 5983: Naturalness and Fundamentality Seminar Prof. Funkhouser Spring 2017 Week 11: Chalmers, Constructing the World Notes (Chapters 6-7, Twelfth Excursus) Chapter 6 6.1 * This chapter is about the

More information

What is the Frege/Russell Analysis of Quantification? Scott Soames

What is the Frege/Russell Analysis of Quantification? Scott Soames What is the Frege/Russell Analysis of Quantification? Scott Soames The Frege-Russell analysis of quantification was a fundamental advance in semantics and philosophical logic. Abstracting away from details

More information

This is a repository copy of Does = 5? : In Defense of a Near Absurdity.

This is a repository copy of Does = 5? : In Defense of a Near Absurdity. This is a repository copy of Does 2 + 3 = 5? : In Defense of a Near Absurdity. White Rose Research Online URL for this paper: http://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/127022/ Version: Accepted Version Article: Leng,

More information

THE SEMANTIC REALISM OF STROUD S RESPONSE TO AUSTIN S ARGUMENT AGAINST SCEPTICISM

THE SEMANTIC REALISM OF STROUD S RESPONSE TO AUSTIN S ARGUMENT AGAINST SCEPTICISM SKÉPSIS, ISSN 1981-4194, ANO VII, Nº 14, 2016, p. 33-39. THE SEMANTIC REALISM OF STROUD S RESPONSE TO AUSTIN S ARGUMENT AGAINST SCEPTICISM ALEXANDRE N. MACHADO Universidade Federal do Paraná (UFPR) Email:

More information

Psillos s Defense of Scientific Realism

Psillos s Defense of Scientific Realism Luke Rinne 4/27/04 Psillos and Laudan Psillos s Defense of Scientific Realism In this paper, Psillos defends the IBE based no miracle argument (NMA) for scientific realism against two main objections,

More information

Is Klein an infinitist about doxastic justification?

Is Klein an infinitist about doxastic justification? Philos Stud (2007) 134:19 24 DOI 10.1007/s11098-006-9016-5 ORIGINAL PAPER Is Klein an infinitist about doxastic justification? Michael Bergmann Published online: 7 March 2007 Ó Springer Science+Business

More information

Generic truth and mixed conjunctions: some alternatives

Generic truth and mixed conjunctions: some alternatives Analysis Advance Access published June 15, 2009 Generic truth and mixed conjunctions: some alternatives AARON J. COTNOIR Christine Tappolet (2000) posed a problem for alethic pluralism: either deny the

More information

Qualitative and quantitative inference to the best theory. reply to iikka Niiniluoto Kuipers, Theodorus

Qualitative and quantitative inference to the best theory. reply to iikka Niiniluoto Kuipers, Theodorus University of Groningen Qualitative and quantitative inference to the best theory. reply to iikka Niiniluoto Kuipers, Theodorus Published in: EPRINTS-BOOK-TITLE IMPORTANT NOTE: You are advised to consult

More information

Aboutness and Justification

Aboutness and Justification For a symposium on Imogen Dickie s book Fixing Reference to be published in Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. Aboutness and Justification Dilip Ninan dilip.ninan@tufts.edu September 2016 Al believes

More information

1. Introduction. Against GMR: The Incredulous Stare (Lewis 1986: 133 5).

1. Introduction. Against GMR: The Incredulous Stare (Lewis 1986: 133 5). Lecture 3 Modal Realism II James Openshaw 1. Introduction Against GMR: The Incredulous Stare (Lewis 1986: 133 5). Whatever else is true of them, today s views aim not to provoke the incredulous stare.

More information

Introduction to Cognitivism; Motivational Externalism; Naturalist Cognitivism

Introduction to Cognitivism; Motivational Externalism; Naturalist Cognitivism Introduction to Cognitivism; Motivational Externalism; Naturalist Cognitivism Felix Pinkert 103 Ethics: Metaethics, University of Oxford, Hilary Term 2015 Cognitivism, Non-cognitivism, and the Humean Argument

More information

Higher-Order Approaches to Consciousness and the Regress Problem

Higher-Order Approaches to Consciousness and the Regress Problem Higher-Order Approaches to Consciousness and the Regress Problem Paul Bernier Département de philosophie Université de Moncton Moncton, NB E1A 3E9 CANADA Keywords: Consciousness, higher-order theories

More information

INDUCTIVE KNOWLEDGE. (For Routledge Companion to Epistemology) Alexander Bird

INDUCTIVE KNOWLEDGE. (For Routledge Companion to Epistemology) Alexander Bird INDUCTIVE KNOWLEDGE (For Routledge Companion to Epistemology) Alexander Bird 1 Introduction In this article I take a loose, functional approach to defining induction: Inductive forms of reasoning include

More information

CONCEPT FORMATION IN ETHICAL THEORIES: DEALING WITH POLAR PREDICATES

CONCEPT FORMATION IN ETHICAL THEORIES: DEALING WITH POLAR PREDICATES DISCUSSION NOTE CONCEPT FORMATION IN ETHICAL THEORIES: DEALING WITH POLAR PREDICATES BY SEBASTIAN LUTZ JOURNAL OF ETHICS & SOCIAL PHILOSOPHY DISCUSSION NOTE AUGUST 2010 URL: WWW.JESP.ORG COPYRIGHT SEBASTIAN

More information

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction Kent State University BIBLID [0873-626X (2014) 39; pp. 139-145] Abstract The causal theory of reference (CTR) provides a well-articulated and widely-accepted account

More information

Divine omniscience, timelessness, and the power to do otherwise

Divine omniscience, timelessness, and the power to do otherwise Religious Studies 42, 123 139 f 2006 Cambridge University Press doi:10.1017/s0034412506008250 Printed in the United Kingdom Divine omniscience, timelessness, and the power to do otherwise HUGH RICE Christ

More information

Minds and Machines spring The explanatory gap and Kripke s argument revisited spring 03

Minds and Machines spring The explanatory gap and Kripke s argument revisited spring 03 Minds and Machines spring 2003 The explanatory gap and Kripke s argument revisited 1 preliminaries handouts on the knowledge argument and qualia on the website 2 Materialism and qualia: the explanatory

More information

Empiricism, Natural Regularity, and Necessity

Empiricism, Natural Regularity, and Necessity University of Colorado, Boulder CU Scholar Philosophy Graduate Theses & Dissertations Philosophy Spring 1-1-2011 Empiricism, Natural Regularity, and Necessity Tyler William Hildebrand University of Colorado

More information

Ontological Justification: From Appearance to Reality Anna-Sofia Maurin (PhD 2002)

Ontological Justification: From Appearance to Reality Anna-Sofia Maurin (PhD 2002) Ontological Justification: From Appearance to Reality Anna-Sofia Maurin (PhD 2002) PROJECT SUMMARY The project aims to investigate the notion of justification in ontology. More specifically, one particular

More information

Anti-Metaphysicalism, Necessity, and Temporal Ontology 1

Anti-Metaphysicalism, Necessity, and Temporal Ontology 1 Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Vol. XCII No. 1, January 2016 doi: 10.1111/phpr.12129 2014 Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, LLC Anti-Metaphysicalism,

More information

Williams on Supervaluationism and Logical Revisionism

Williams on Supervaluationism and Logical Revisionism Williams on Supervaluationism and Logical Revisionism Nicholas K. Jones Non-citable draft: 26 02 2010. Final version appeared in: The Journal of Philosophy (2011) 108: 11: 633-641 Central to discussion

More information

SWINBURNE ON THE SIMPLICITY OF THEISM

SWINBURNE ON THE SIMPLICITY OF THEISM SWINBURNE ON THE SIMPLICITY OF THEISM University of Melbourne Abstract. This paper argues that (1) Richard Swinburne s general account of the simplicity of empirical hypotheses fails because it involves

More information

Saul Kripke, Naming and Necessity

Saul Kripke, Naming and Necessity 24.09x Minds and Machines Saul Kripke, Naming and Necessity Excerpt from Saul Kripke, Naming and Necessity (Harvard, 1980). Identity theorists have been concerned with several distinct types of identifications:

More information

Verificationism. PHIL September 27, 2011

Verificationism. PHIL September 27, 2011 Verificationism PHIL 83104 September 27, 2011 1. The critique of metaphysics... 1 2. Observation statements... 2 3. In principle verifiability... 3 4. Strong verifiability... 3 4.1. Conclusive verifiability

More information

Understanding Truth Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002

Understanding Truth Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002 1 Symposium on Understanding Truth By Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002 2 Precis of Understanding Truth Scott Soames Understanding Truth aims to illuminate

More information

Phil 1103 Review. Also: Scientific realism vs. anti-realism Can philosophers criticise science?

Phil 1103 Review. Also: Scientific realism vs. anti-realism Can philosophers criticise science? Phil 1103 Review Also: Scientific realism vs. anti-realism Can philosophers criticise science? 1. Copernican Revolution Students should be familiar with the basic historical facts of the Copernican revolution.

More information

Review: The Objects of Thought, by Tim Crane. Guy Longworth University of Warwick

Review: The Objects of Thought, by Tim Crane. Guy Longworth University of Warwick Review: The Objects of Thought, by Tim Crane. Guy Longworth University of Warwick 24.4.14 We can think about things that don t exist. For example, we can think about Pegasus, and Pegasus doesn t exist.

More information

HPS 1653 / PHIL 1610 Revision Guide (all topics)

HPS 1653 / PHIL 1610 Revision Guide (all topics) HPS 1653 / PHIL 1610 Revision Guide (all topics) General Questions What is the distinction between a descriptive and a normative project in the philosophy of science? What are the virtues of this or that

More information

Russell: On Denoting

Russell: On Denoting Russell: On Denoting DENOTING PHRASES Russell includes all kinds of quantified subject phrases ( a man, every man, some man etc.) but his main interest is in definite descriptions: the present King of

More information

- We might, now, wonder whether the resulting concept of justification is sufficiently strong. According to BonJour, apparent rational insight is

- We might, now, wonder whether the resulting concept of justification is sufficiently strong. According to BonJour, apparent rational insight is BonJour I PHIL410 BonJour s Moderate Rationalism - BonJour develops and defends a moderate form of Rationalism. - Rationalism, generally (as used here), is the view according to which the primary tool

More information

Is Epistemic Probability Pascalian?

Is Epistemic Probability Pascalian? Is Epistemic Probability Pascalian? James B. Freeman Hunter College of The City University of New York ABSTRACT: What does it mean to say that if the premises of an argument are true, the conclusion is

More information

SPINOZA S VERSION OF THE PSR: A Critique of Michael Della Rocca s Interpretation of Spinoza

SPINOZA S VERSION OF THE PSR: A Critique of Michael Della Rocca s Interpretation of Spinoza SPINOZA S VERSION OF THE PSR: A Critique of Michael Della Rocca s Interpretation of Spinoza by Erich Schaeffer A thesis submitted to the Department of Philosophy In conformity with the requirements for

More information

THE MEANING OF OUGHT. Ralph Wedgwood. What does the word ought mean? Strictly speaking, this is an empirical question, about the

THE MEANING OF OUGHT. Ralph Wedgwood. What does the word ought mean? Strictly speaking, this is an empirical question, about the THE MEANING OF OUGHT Ralph Wedgwood What does the word ought mean? Strictly speaking, this is an empirical question, about the meaning of a word in English. Such empirical semantic questions should ideally

More information

Fundamentals of Metaphysics

Fundamentals of Metaphysics Fundamentals of Metaphysics Objective and Subjective One important component of the Common Western Metaphysic is the thesis that there is such a thing as objective truth. each of our beliefs and assertions

More information

Ayer s linguistic theory of the a priori

Ayer s linguistic theory of the a priori Ayer s linguistic theory of the a priori phil 43904 Jeff Speaks December 4, 2007 1 The problem of a priori knowledge....................... 1 2 Necessity and the a priori............................ 2

More information

Review Tutorial (A Whirlwind Tour of Metaphysics, Epistemology and Philosophy of Religion)

Review Tutorial (A Whirlwind Tour of Metaphysics, Epistemology and Philosophy of Religion) Review Tutorial (A Whirlwind Tour of Metaphysics, Epistemology and Philosophy of Religion) Arguably, the main task of philosophy is to seek the truth. We seek genuine knowledge. This is why epistemology

More information

P. Weingartner, God s existence. Can it be proven? A logical commentary on the five ways of Thomas Aquinas, Ontos, Frankfurt Pp. 116.

P. Weingartner, God s existence. Can it be proven? A logical commentary on the five ways of Thomas Aquinas, Ontos, Frankfurt Pp. 116. P. Weingartner, God s existence. Can it be proven? A logical commentary on the five ways of Thomas Aquinas, Ontos, Frankfurt 2010. Pp. 116. Thinking of the problem of God s existence, most formal logicians

More information

A Priori Bootstrapping

A Priori Bootstrapping A Priori Bootstrapping Ralph Wedgwood In this essay, I shall explore the problems that are raised by a certain traditional sceptical paradox. My conclusion, at the end of this essay, will be that the most

More information

CLASS #17: CHALLENGES TO POSITIVISM/BEHAVIORAL APPROACH

CLASS #17: CHALLENGES TO POSITIVISM/BEHAVIORAL APPROACH CLASS #17: CHALLENGES TO POSITIVISM/BEHAVIORAL APPROACH I. Challenges to Confirmation A. The Inductivist Turkey B. Discovery vs. Justification 1. Discovery 2. Justification C. Hume's Problem 1. Inductive

More information

A Note on Straight-Thinking

A Note on Straight-Thinking A Note on Straight-Thinking A supplementary note for the 2nd Annual JTS/CGST Public Ethics Lecture March 5, 2002(b), adj. 2009:03:05 G.E.M. of TKI Arguments & Appeals In arguments, people try to persuade

More information

The Moving Spotlight Theory

The Moving Spotlight Theory The Moving Spotlight Theory Daniel Deasy, University College Dublin (Published in 2015 in Philosophical Studies 172: 2073-2089) Abstract The aim of this paper is to describe and defend the moving spotlight

More information

Degrees of Belief II

Degrees of Belief II Degrees of Belief II HT2017 / Dr Teruji Thomas Website: users.ox.ac.uk/ mert2060/2017/degrees-of-belief 1 Conditionalisation Where we have got to: One reason to focus on credences instead of beliefs: response

More information

Postmodal Metaphysics

Postmodal Metaphysics Postmodal Metaphysics Ted Sider Structuralism seminar 1. Conceptual tools in metaphysics Tools of metaphysics : concepts for framing metaphysical issues. They structure metaphysical discourse. Problem

More information

Can logical consequence be deflated?

Can logical consequence be deflated? Can logical consequence be deflated? Michael De University of Utrecht Department of Philosophy Utrecht, Netherlands mikejde@gmail.com in Insolubles and Consequences : essays in honour of Stephen Read,

More information

Varieties of Apriority

Varieties of Apriority S E V E N T H E X C U R S U S Varieties of Apriority T he notions of a priori knowledge and justification play a central role in this work. There are many ways in which one can understand the a priori,

More information

Scientific Progress, Verisimilitude, and Evidence

Scientific Progress, Verisimilitude, and Evidence L&PS Logic and Philosophy of Science Vol. IX, No. 1, 2011, pp. 561-567 Scientific Progress, Verisimilitude, and Evidence Luca Tambolo Department of Philosophy, University of Trieste e-mail: l_tambolo@hotmail.com

More information

In Part I of the ETHICS, Spinoza presents his central

In Part I of the ETHICS, Spinoza presents his central TWO PROBLEMS WITH SPINOZA S ARGUMENT FOR SUBSTANCE MONISM LAURA ANGELINA DELGADO * In Part I of the ETHICS, Spinoza presents his central metaphysical thesis that there is only one substance in the universe.

More information

ALTERNATIVE SELF-DEFEAT ARGUMENTS: A REPLY TO MIZRAHI

ALTERNATIVE SELF-DEFEAT ARGUMENTS: A REPLY TO MIZRAHI ALTERNATIVE SELF-DEFEAT ARGUMENTS: A REPLY TO MIZRAHI Michael HUEMER ABSTRACT: I address Moti Mizrahi s objections to my use of the Self-Defeat Argument for Phenomenal Conservatism (PC). Mizrahi contends

More information

The Question of Metaphysics

The Question of Metaphysics The Question of Metaphysics metaphysics seriously. Second, I want to argue that the currently popular hands-off conception of metaphysical theorising is unable to provide a satisfactory answer to the question

More information

Stout s teleological theory of action

Stout s teleological theory of action Stout s teleological theory of action Jeff Speaks November 26, 2004 1 The possibility of externalist explanations of action................ 2 1.1 The distinction between externalist and internalist explanations

More information

proceedings of the aristotelian society

proceedings of the aristotelian society proceedings of the aristotelian society issue i volume cxiii 2012-2013 Resemblance Nominalism, Conjunctions and Truthmakers gonzalo rodriguez-pereyra university of oxford D r a f t P a p e r 1 8 8 8 c

More information