Can Rationality Be Naturalistically Explained? Jeffrey Dunn. Abstract: Dan Chiappe and John Vervaeke (1997) conclude their article, Fodor,

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Can Rationality Be Naturalistically Explained? Jeffrey Dunn. Abstract: Dan Chiappe and John Vervaeke (1997) conclude their article, Fodor,"

Transcription

1 Can Rationality Be Naturalistically Explained? Jeffrey Dunn Abstract: Dan Chiappe and John Vervaeke (1997) conclude their article, Fodor, Cherniak and the Naturalization of Rationality, with an argument for the claim that we could never naturalistically explain rationality. I first clarify this argument and the conclusion that it is meant to establish. I then argue that once clarified, the argument fails. Introduction Dan Chiappe and John Vervaeke conclude their article, Fodor, Cherniak and the Naturalization of Rationality, with an argument for the claim that we are epistemically bounded from naturalistically explaining rationality. There are different things that one might be attempting to do when explaining human rationality. One might be trying to explain what a rational set of beliefs or a rational action is like. Such explanations will take the form of substantive theories of rational belief and action, and are usually formulated by decision theorists and logicians. Alternatively, one might be trying to give an explanatory story about how the human brain evolved to its present state. Such explanations are scientific and will be provided (if they are provided) by evolutionary biology. Either kind of explanation seems amenable to the naturalist: a naturalist could, perhaps, offer an instrumental account of what it is that makes these beliefs or actions rational,(1) and could simply adopt the scientific explanation of how the brain evolved. When trying to explain human rationality, however, one might be after something slightly different than either of these: one might want to explain how it is that humans

2 manage to be rational. Thus, one is after not just a scientific theory of how the brain evolved---an explanation of how the brain got to be like it is, is distinct from an explanation of how humans manage to be rational, even if we humans are rational in virtue of our brains being how they are.(2) Nor would one be after a substantive theory of rational beliefs and actions---such a theory purports to tell us what a rational belief set is, but now how we manage to realize this. Instead, one might be after an explanation of how it is that we manage to be rational, when we are. It seems to be this kind of explanation that Chiappe & Vervaeke think the naturalist could not possibly give. They write: we will give reasons for believing that we cannot provide an explanation of how rationality can come to exist from purely natural processes (p. 811). In this paper I will evaluate their argument for this claim. Before doing so, however, let me briefly note why such an argument is important. Above I said that we may get a substantive account of rationality from logic and decision theory. But one may be unhappy with this. One may think that a large part of rationality consists not only in the resulting beliefs and actions, but in the processes and procedures that bring about rational behavior and beliefs. If so, then explaining this is important if we are to understand human rationality. Thus, if it is impossible to give a certain kind of naturalistic explanation of rationality, then a naturalistic theory of this aspect of rationality is impossible. The Argument Chiappe & Vervaeke tell us that they are specifically concerned with methodological naturalism. They state the view as follows: Methodological naturalism claims that we 2

3 should explain the mind using processes that do not presuppose rationality (p. 812). As stated, this only commits the methodological naturalist to a claim about our obligations. But the methodological naturalist is plausibly committed to the claim that we should and can explain the mind using processes that do not presuppose rationality. Since Chiappe & Vervaeke are only concerned with the possibility of so-doing, we can initially state methodological naturalism as the following: (MN) It is possible that we scientifically explain the mind using processes that do not presuppose rationality.(3) Since we are specifically concerned with giving a naturalistic explanation of rationality, it will be helpful to have a more specific instance of MN: (MN-Rat) It is possible that we scientifically explain rationality using processes that do not presuppose rationality. The conclusion of Chiappe & Vervaeke s argument is that there can be no naturalistic explanation of rationality. This corresponds to a denial of MN-Rat. This denial is to follow from considerations about methodological naturalism, together with claims about scientific explanation made by both Carl Hempel (1988) and Hilary Putnam (1985). Hempel and Putnam both argue that scientific theories, when they explain, presuppose rationality. Given this, the basic argument given by Chiappe & Vervaeke is: 1. If MN-Rat is true, then it is possible to scientifically explain rationality using processes that do not presuppose rationality. 2. When scientific theories explain, they presuppose rationality. 3. Thus, MN-Rat is not true. 3

4 The conclusion establishes what Chiappe & Vervaeke want: that there can be no naturalistically acceptable explanation of rationality. Premise 1 is true because of their definition of methodological naturalism. Premise 2 requires a bit more defense. The idea is that scientific theories do not explain on their own, only theories which presuppose relevance in some way. They write: theories by themselves do not explain anything. It is only theories plus their implicit assumptions of relevance that explain events (p. 815).(4) They then note that one aspect of human rationality is the ability to judge relevance, from which we get premise 2.(5) Premise 1 Before evaluating this argument we must clarify a few things. Consider, again, the statement of methodological naturalism: (MN-Rat) It is possible that we scientifically explain rationality using processes that do not presuppose rationality. Although this statement of the view allows us to easily formulate the argument, it is doubly ambiguous. First: does it claim that when giving explanations we must not use processes that presuppose rationality, or that explanations must not appeal to processes that presuppose rationality? Second: what does it mean to say that a process presupposes rationality? The answer to these two questions are critical to understanding the argument. In giving their account of methodological naturalism, Chiappe & Vervaeke appeal to Gary Hatfield s (1990) account. Hatfield tells us: naturalistic explanation requires more than simply speaking of laws of thought as any theorist of the soul might; the naturalist must reduce the activities 4

5 of the mind to processes that do not include irreducibly rational or judgmental operations. Reason and judgment must themselves be explained by appeal to laws that do not include bare cognitive powers (p. 25)(6) It appears, then, that we have an answer to our second question. A process presupposes rationality when no matter how we reduce it to other processes, at least one unreduced rational or judgmental process remains. This is further supported by looking at one of Chiappe & Vervaeke s own examples. Christopher Cherniak, according to Chiappe & Vervaeke, attempts to (partially) naturalistically explain how humans are able to realize rational thought. Part of his explanation appeals to the fact that humans store different information in different mental compartments, which are sorted by relevance. Chiappe & Vervaeke object: Cherniak has not explained how the compartments are created the process of organizing information into compartments itself requires the skill [rationality] to be explained (p. 810). The problem with Cherniak s explanation is that it appeals to a process that itself includes an irreducibly judgmental operation: the ability sort information by relevance. In Chiappe & Vervaeke s terminology, his explanation appeals to a process that presupposes rationality. With our new understanding of the phrase presupposes rationality, our first question is: does methodological naturalism claim that when we give explanations we must not use processes that include irreducibly rational or judgmental operations, or that explanations must not appeal to such processes? Methodological naturalism, of course, is a methodological thesis. It tells us what explanations should look like. But it hardly matters to such a thesis what procedures we use when we give such explanations. The 5

6 real claim of the methodological naturalist is that the explanans shouldn t appeal to processes that include irreducibly rational or judgmental operations in explaining the explanandum. It would be no objection to MN-Rat to show that we must use some process which is irreducibly rational when giving explanations, so long as we never need to appeal to this process to explain rationality. Given this, we are in a position to state a more precise version of MN-Rat: (MN-Rat) It is possible, when giving a scientific explanation of rationality, that the explanans appeal only to processes that do not include irreducibly rational or judgmental operations. The original argument, then, will need to be reworked. Premise 2 says that scientific theories presuppose rationality, while premise 1 says that we can explain rationality only by appealing to certain kinds of processes. Thus, we must either add further premises or rework premise 2. On the face of it, there isn t much that can be done to shore up the argument. To see why, first consider premise 2. For this premise to be true, the phrase presuppose rationality must have something to do with the way in which theories get applied during the act of explanation. This is made clear, when Chiappe & Vervaeke argue for the truth of premise 2. They tell us: theoretical statements are expected to hold only under relevant conditions, which conditions are not determined by the explicit content of theories Theories are not algorithms that determine there own conditions of application. Instead, they presuppose a rational homunculus whose judgements of relevance can 6

7 complete theories by determining the relevant conditions for their application. (p. 814) Premise 2 is concerned with the act of explanation. However, we ve just seen that premise 1 is concerned with what is appealed to in the content of the explanation. From the fact that it is possible to explain something without appealing to irreducibly rational processes, it doesn t follow that we can explain that thing without using rational processes, and applying theories in a generally intelligent way. Thus, as it stands, their argument does not support the desired conclusion. Rethinking the Argument Chiappe & Vervaeke are committed to the claim that there is something especially pernicious about purportedly explanatory naturalistic theories of rationality in contrast to other theories in the natural sciences (see, for instance, p. 817). They make a point of emphasizing that any explanation of rationality will be objectionably circular, in a way that other explanations will not be. They write: explanations of how a phenomenon comes to be must not postulate an ontology that is itself constituted by the phenomenon to be explained (p. 812). For example, you can t explain solidity by postulating solidity. So, the worry is that there is no explanation that we could give of our own rationality which would be non-circular. If we are careful in spelling out how scientific explanations are to presuppose rationality (that is, premise 2), I think we will be able to get a better picture of the objectionable circularity that Chiappe & Vervaeke are worried about and thus a better representation of their argument. 7

8 First, according to Chiappe & Vervaeke, a circular explanation of x is one that postulates an ontology of x-ness. To see how a naturalistic explanation of rationality might postulate an ontology of rationality, we need to say something more specific about how scientific explanations are to presuppose rationality. Chiappe & Vervaeke focus not on rationality, in general, but rather one aspect of it: the ability to judge relevance. Since the ability to judge relevance is part of rationality, it is acceptable to focus on this. Their specific claim is that scientific explanations presuppose relevance. But how is it that scientific explanations do this? In a typical deductive-nomological (D-N) explanation,(7) we cite the relevant law, then cite the fact that the case under consideration falls under the law. If this entails the event in question, then we have explained the event.(8) Consider, then, what a simple D-N explanation for some event, E, might look like: 1. It is a law that if A, then E. 2. It was the case that A. 3. Thus, it was the case that E. The claim made by both Hempel and Putnam (and endorsed by Chiappe & Vervaeke), that scientific explanations presuppose relevance, can be seen as modifying the D-N explanation. They propose that explanations in science really look like this: 1. (In relevant circumstances) it is a law that if A, then E. 2. It was the case that A. 3. The circumstances were relevant. 4. Thus, it was the case that E. 8

9 Given this, any scientific explanation will somewhere appeal to a law that has the form of the law in 1 and a fact like the one mentioned in 3.(9) We are now in a position to see how an explanation of our ability to judge relevance might be unacceptably circular. In virtue of the law in 1 and the fact in line 3, scientific explanations postulate an ontology of relevance. More perspicuously: the law holds only in certain circumstances, circumstances that have the property of relevancy. But this means that any explanation appealing to laws like this postulates that there are these things: circumstances that have the property of relevancy. If, then, we re scientifically explaining our ability to judge relevance, the explanation itself appeals to the property of relevancy. This, one could claim, makes the explanation circular. However persuasive this line of thought is, it can t be right. Remember that according to Chiappe & Vervaeke, a circular explanation of x is one that postulates an ontology of x-ness. Thus, a circular explanation of our ability to judge relevance would be one that appeals to an ontology which includes the property ability-to-judge-relevance. But this is not what happens in scientific explanations of our ability to judge relevance. Instead, the explanation of our ability to judge relevance appeals to an ontology of relevancy. In general, however, this does not make for circular explanations. For example, an explanation of our ability to judge spiciness (of food) is not circular because it appeals to an ontology that includes the property of spiciness. So, is there anything objectionably circular about explaining our ability to judge relevance? An explanation of our ability to judge xness obviously postulates the existence of xness (otherwise, there is no such ability to explain). But, as we ve seen, this is not yet circular. One thought is that such an explanation is objectionable because the property of 9

10 relevancy is understood solely in terms of our ability to judge relevance. Thus, an explanation that appeals to relevancy tacitly appeals to our ability to judge relevance. But this is implausible: we don t make things relevant to each other by judging them to be so. An alternative way of pushing the idea that this kind of circularity is objectionable is by noting that, according to Hempel and Putnam, whether or not some law, L, is relevant to some situation, S, is not a feature of L and S themselves. Rather, as Chiappe & Vervaeke tell us, it requires a rational homunculus whose judgements of relevance can complete theories by determining the relevant conditions for their application (p. 814). On this view, relevance is a relation that holds between rationally interpreted laws and situations. Thus, what explains our ability to judge relevance is a rationallyinterpreted law, L, and the appropriate conditions holding. This, however, is not a problem. If we grant the Hempel/Putnam point, then for L to explain it must be rationally-interpreted. But from this it does not follow that such an explanation is objectionably circular. The rationally interpreted laws explain our ability to judge relevance. Again, we must be mindful of the distinction between using our ability to judge relevance and appealing to our ability to judge relevance. We use our rational ability to interpret laws in the kind of way that allows us to explain rationality. There is nothing circular here. An alternative thought about what is objectionable is that an explanation of our ability to judge xness requires us to explain xness.(10) That is, if you re going to explain our ability to judge spiciness, then you must be able to explain what spiciness is. And, the thought goes, you can t do this non-circularly when it comes to our ability to judge relevance. For example, perhaps we explain spiciness as: the property that things have, 10

11 such that in relevant situations, when things have that property they cause a certain response. If the property of relevancy is explained in an analogous way, then we explain relevancy as: the property that things have, such that in relevant circumstances, things with that property meet some condition. Of course, this kind of explanation of the property of relevancy is circular. Nevertheless, there is nothing to worry about here for the naturalist. First of all, we have shifted senses of explanation. No longer are we giving causal explanations, but rather trying to explain properties, in some different sense of explanation. Second, and more importantly, we should reject the claim that to scientifically explain our ability to judge xness, we must be able to explain in this new sense of explanation the property of xness. For example, it seems possible that we explain our ability to judge distance, without being able to explain what it is for two things to be separated by some distance. So long as we generally understand the notion of distance, this will suffice. We can simply take distance as a primitive, unexplained notion. Perhaps it would be disappointing that we couldn t wholly elucidate the notion of distance, but it would not impugn our explanation of our ability to judge distance. After all, explanations must come to an end somewhere. To make these points clearer, let us consider an example. We can construct cases where an explanation appeals to a law with certain assumptions about relevance that yield bad explanations of our ability to judge relevance. For example, perhaps we want to explain how humans judge whether or not a bit of information is relevant to restaurant situations. Imagine that the proffered explanation appeals to different mental compartments, one of which is the restaurant compartment, where information relevant 11

12 to restaurant situations is stored. The explanation for how information gets sorted between these different compartments, appeals to the following law: L: In relevant conditions, the agent stores received information in the restaurant compartment. Let us suppose that relevant conditions here just means: situations where the agent receives restaurant-relevant information. If this is the case, then of course, any explanation appealing to L of how the agent manages to judge which information is relevant to restaurant situations is unsatisfying. By understanding relevant conditions in this way we do not seem to gain much insight into how this sorting is to proceed. Nevertheless, it is important to note that such an explanation is not circular. We use our rational ability to judge situations where the agent receives restaurant-relevant information to fill in the content of the law. This is then put to use in explaining how the agent manages to make a certain judgment about relevance. Of course, there is something unsatisfying about this explanation. We d prefer to know something more about how this sorting proceeds. That is, since we don t think that there is a little rational homunculus inside each person s head, we d like to know what features of these relevant situations are being tracked so that they are sorted into the proper mental compartment. But there seems to be no reason that a (slightly) more realistic kind of law couldn t be both put to use in a more satisfying explanation and be naturalistically unobjectionable. Consider a law of the following form: L : [In relevant situations], if conditions C are met, the agent s sorting mechanism stores received information in the agent s restaurant compartment. 12

13 In L the prefix in relevant situations is merely implicit in the statement of the law, as Hempel and Putnam urge. Specification of conditions C is what will really give such a law explanatory power, and there is no reason that these conditions must be expressed by appealing to restaurant-relevant situations. For instance, conditions C could be completely qualitatively expressed. The relevancy prefix may only serve to rule out really off-the-wall situations, for example, situations when the agent suddenly undergoes massive brain trauma, or is under alien mind-control, or where the agent has a strong desire to act erratically, etc. But such an appeal to relevancy does not seem to render unsatisfying the explanation of our ability to judge whether or not a bit of information is relevant to restaurant situations. Thus, although we certainly can construct circularsounding explanations by appealing to dubious laws, it isn t required by naturalism that we do so. Conclusion We began by looking at Chiappe & Vervaeke s interesting argument to the claim that we can never naturalistically explain rationality. The first gloss of this argument was seen to be flawed for a very fundamental reason: part of the argument concerned itself with the act of explanation, while the other part concerned itself with the content of an explanation. The second gloss of the argument remedied this problem, focusing entirely on the content of purported naturalistic explanations of rationality. The alleged problem with such explanations was that they are circular: such explanations try to explain our ability to judge relevancy while appealing to our ability to judge relevancy. However, we saw that this was mistaken, too. Explanations of our ability to judge relevancy may 13

14 appeal to relevancy, but need not appeal to our ability to judge relevancy. Thus, there is no circularity in such explanations. Accordingly, Chiappe & Vervaeke s argument does not establish the desired conclusion. One might think, however, that though the methodological naturalist need not be upset about this situation, this argument gives the metaphysical naturalist a reason for concern. On one way of understanding the view, metaphysical naturalism does not want to admit an ontology that includes the (irreducible) property of relevancy. But if that is the problem, it is hard to see how the problem really has anything to do with explanations of rationality. Indeed, if we grant the Hempel/Putnam point that all scientific explanations have assumptions of relevance, any scientific explanation is enough to show that naturalism is a hopeless project. Whatever the merits of such an argument, it is not the argument that Chiappe & Vervaeke give. They are clear that there is a special problem for the naturalist when it comes to scientific explanations of rationality. We ve seen that such an argument fails. Notes 1 That is, an account of the following form: A belief/action is rational if and only if it is instrumentally useful for attaining the agents desires. One could then spell out instrumentally useful in any number of ways. Whether or not such an account is plausible is another story. But the project does not seem to be self-defeating in any kind of obvious way. 14

15 2 Compare: an explanation of how my leg moved as it did is different than an explanation of how I managed to kick the ball, even if my leg moving as it did was my kicking of the ball. Explanations are intensional, not extensional. 3 Since the methodological naturalist takes scientific explanation as his guide, the kinds of explanations that the methodological naturalist is concerned with are scientific explanations. 4 In addition: theoretical statements are expected to hold only under relevant conditions, which conditions are not determined by the explicit content of theories they presuppose a rational homunculus whose judgements of relevance can complete theories by determining the relevant conditions for their application (p. 814). 5 It is important to note that the aspect of rationality that will concern us here is the human ability to judge relevance (p. 812). 6 This account of methodological naturalism is Hatfield s account of what methodological naturalism meant to early modern theorists such as Descartes and Hume. It is an open question whether or not this is the best way to formulate methodological naturalism today. Nevertheless, I will continue to presuppose this account of methodological naturalism since it is the one appealed to by Chiappe & Vervaeke. 7 See Hempel & Oppenheim (1948). 15

16 8 There are well-known problems with D-N explanations, which shouldn t matter for this illustrative purpose. 9 Note that the same will be true if we adopt a causal account of explanation. The relevant causal statements will, as Chiappe & Vervaeke note, appeal to relevant circumstances in a similar kind of way. Thus, moving to, say, a causal account of explanation merely makes the problem harder to state, it doesn t make it go away. One could, at this point, claim that causal explanations don t admit this kind of assumption of relevance. But I will continue to assume that they do, since I believe that even granting this assumption, there is a flaw in the argument. 10 If one takes this suggestion, the argument might look like the following: 1. If MN-Rat is true, then it is possible to scientifically explain our ability to judge relevance. 2. If it is possible to scientifically explain our ability to judge relevance, then you can scientifically explain what it is to be relevant independent of our ability to judge relevance. 3. It is not the case that you can explain what it is to be relevant, independent of our ability to judge relevance (because all explanations presuppose our ability to judge relevance). 4. Thus, MN-Rat is false. As I explain shortly, premise 2 should be rejected. 16

17 References Chiappe, Dan & Vervaeke, John. (1997). Fodor, Cherniak and the Naturalization of Rationality. Theory & Psychology, 7, Hatfield, Gary. (1990). The Natural and the Normative: Theories of spatial perception from Kant to Helmholtz. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Hempel, C. G. & Oppenheim, Paul. (1948). Studies in the logic of explanation. Philosophy of Science, 15, Hempel, C. G. (1988). Provisos: A problem concerning the inferential function of scientific theories. In A. Grunbaum & W. C. Salmon (Eds.), The Limitations of Deductivism (pp ). Berkeley: University of California Press. Putnam, Hilary. (1985). Why reason can t be naturalized. in Hilary Putnam, Realism and Reason: Philosophical papers volume 3 (pp ). New York: Cambridge University Press. Putnam, Hilary. (1993). Renewing Philosophy. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. 17

Vol. II, No. 5, Reason, Truth and History, 127. LARS BERGSTRÖM

Vol. II, No. 5, Reason, Truth and History, 127. LARS BERGSTRÖM Croatian Journal of Philosophy Vol. II, No. 5, 2002 L. Bergström, Putnam on the Fact-Value Dichotomy 1 Putnam on the Fact-Value Dichotomy LARS BERGSTRÖM Stockholm University In Reason, Truth and History

More information

Reply to Robert Koons

Reply to Robert Koons 632 Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic Volume 35, Number 4, Fall 1994 Reply to Robert Koons ANIL GUPTA and NUEL BELNAP We are grateful to Professor Robert Koons for his excellent, and generous, review

More information

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006 In Defense of Radical Empiricism Joseph Benjamin Riegel A thesis submitted to the faculty of the University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of

More information

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction Kent State University BIBLID [0873-626X (2014) 39; pp. 139-145] Abstract The causal theory of reference (CTR) provides a well-articulated and widely-accepted account

More information

Stout s teleological theory of action

Stout s teleological theory of action Stout s teleological theory of action Jeff Speaks November 26, 2004 1 The possibility of externalist explanations of action................ 2 1.1 The distinction between externalist and internalist explanations

More information

Introduction to Cognitivism; Motivational Externalism; Naturalist Cognitivism

Introduction to Cognitivism; Motivational Externalism; Naturalist Cognitivism Introduction to Cognitivism; Motivational Externalism; Naturalist Cognitivism Felix Pinkert 103 Ethics: Metaethics, University of Oxford, Hilary Term 2015 Cognitivism, Non-cognitivism, and the Humean Argument

More information

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 4: Skepticism. Part 1: The Scope of Skepticism and Two Main Types of Skeptical Argument

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 4: Skepticism. Part 1: The Scope of Skepticism and Two Main Types of Skeptical Argument 1. The Scope of Skepticism Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 4: Skepticism Part 1: The Scope of Skepticism and Two Main Types of Skeptical Argument The scope of skeptical challenges can vary in a number

More information

Psillos s Defense of Scientific Realism

Psillos s Defense of Scientific Realism Luke Rinne 4/27/04 Psillos and Laudan Psillos s Defense of Scientific Realism In this paper, Psillos defends the IBE based no miracle argument (NMA) for scientific realism against two main objections,

More information

Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000)

Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000) Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000) One of the advantages traditionally claimed for direct realist theories of perception over indirect realist theories is that the

More information

To appear in The Journal of Philosophy.

To appear in The Journal of Philosophy. To appear in The Journal of Philosophy. Lucy Allais: Manifest Reality: Kant s Idealism and his Realism. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2015, pp. xi + 329. 40.00 (hb). ISBN: 9780198747130. Kant s doctrine

More information

Chapter Six. Putnam's Anti-Realism

Chapter Six. Putnam's Anti-Realism 119 Chapter Six Putnam's Anti-Realism So far, our discussion has been guided by the assumption that there is a world and that sentences are true or false by virtue of the way it is. But this assumption

More information

Why I Am Not a Property Dualist By John R. Searle

Why I Am Not a Property Dualist By John R. Searle 1 Why I Am Not a Property Dualist By John R. Searle I have argued in a number of writings 1 that the philosophical part (though not the neurobiological part) of the traditional mind-body problem has a

More information

Explanatory Indispensability and Deliberative Indispensability: Against Enoch s Analogy Alex Worsnip University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill

Explanatory Indispensability and Deliberative Indispensability: Against Enoch s Analogy Alex Worsnip University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill Explanatory Indispensability and Deliberative Indispensability: Against Enoch s Analogy Alex Worsnip University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill Forthcoming in Thought please cite published version In

More information

Kantian Humility and Ontological Categories Sam Cowling University of Massachusetts, Amherst

Kantian Humility and Ontological Categories Sam Cowling University of Massachusetts, Amherst Kantian Humility and Ontological Categories Sam Cowling University of Massachusetts, Amherst [Forthcoming in Analysis. Penultimate Draft. Cite published version.] Kantian Humility holds that agents like

More information

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View Chapter 98 Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View Lars Leeten Universität Hildesheim Practical thinking is a tricky business. Its aim will never be fulfilled unless influence on practical

More information

Philosophy Epistemology. Topic 3 - Skepticism

Philosophy Epistemology. Topic 3 - Skepticism Michael Huemer on Skepticism Philosophy 3340 - Epistemology Topic 3 - Skepticism Chapter II. The Lure of Radical Skepticism 1. Mike Huemer defines radical skepticism as follows: Philosophical skeptics

More information

FOREWORD: ADDRESSING THE HARD PROBLEM OF CONSCIOUSNESS

FOREWORD: ADDRESSING THE HARD PROBLEM OF CONSCIOUSNESS Biophysics of Consciousness: A Foundational Approach R. R. Poznanski, J. A. Tuszynski and T. E. Feinberg Copyright 2017 World Scientific, Singapore. FOREWORD: ADDRESSING THE HARD PROBLEM OF CONSCIOUSNESS

More information

Skepticism and Internalism

Skepticism and Internalism Skepticism and Internalism John Greco Abstract: This paper explores a familiar skeptical problematic and considers some strategies for responding to it. Section 1 reconstructs and disambiguates the skeptical

More information

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea. Book reviews World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Naturalism, by Michael C. Rea. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2004, viii + 245 pp., $24.95. This is a splendid book. Its ideas are bold and

More information

PHL340 Handout 8: Evaluating Dogmatism

PHL340 Handout 8: Evaluating Dogmatism PHL340 Handout 8: Evaluating Dogmatism 1 Dogmatism Last class we looked at Jim Pryor s paper on dogmatism about perceptual justification (for background on the notion of justification, see the handout

More information

NATURALISED JURISPRUDENCE

NATURALISED JURISPRUDENCE NATURALISED JURISPRUDENCE NATURALISM a philosophical view according to which philosophy is not a distinct mode of inquiry with its own problems and its own special body of (possible) knowledge philosophy

More information

Unit VI: Davidson and the interpretational approach to thought and language

Unit VI: Davidson and the interpretational approach to thought and language Unit VI: Davidson and the interpretational approach to thought and language October 29, 2003 1 Davidson s interdependence thesis..................... 1 2 Davidson s arguments for interdependence................

More information

How Successful Is Naturalism?

How Successful Is Naturalism? How Successful Is Naturalism? University of Notre Dame T he question raised by this volume is How successful is naturalism? The question presupposes that we already know what naturalism is and what counts

More information

Realism and instrumentalism

Realism and instrumentalism Published in H. Pashler (Ed.) The Encyclopedia of the Mind (2013), Thousand Oaks, CA: SAGE Publications, pp. 633 636 doi:10.4135/9781452257044 mark.sprevak@ed.ac.uk Realism and instrumentalism Mark Sprevak

More information

The Philosophy of Physics. Physics versus Metaphysics

The Philosophy of Physics. Physics versus Metaphysics The Philosophy of Physics Lecture One Physics versus Metaphysics Rob Trueman rob.trueman@york.ac.uk University of York Preliminaries Physics versus Metaphysics Preliminaries What is Meta -physics? Metaphysics

More information

Is there a good epistemological argument against platonism? DAVID LIGGINS

Is there a good epistemological argument against platonism? DAVID LIGGINS [This is the penultimate draft of an article that appeared in Analysis 66.2 (April 2006), 135-41, available here by permission of Analysis, the Analysis Trust, and Blackwell Publishing. The definitive

More information

Tuukka Kaidesoja Précis of Naturalizing Critical Realist Social Ontology

Tuukka Kaidesoja Précis of Naturalizing Critical Realist Social Ontology Journal of Social Ontology 2015; 1(2): 321 326 Book Symposium Open Access Tuukka Kaidesoja Précis of Naturalizing Critical Realist Social Ontology DOI 10.1515/jso-2015-0016 Abstract: This paper introduces

More information

CLASS #17: CHALLENGES TO POSITIVISM/BEHAVIORAL APPROACH

CLASS #17: CHALLENGES TO POSITIVISM/BEHAVIORAL APPROACH CLASS #17: CHALLENGES TO POSITIVISM/BEHAVIORAL APPROACH I. Challenges to Confirmation A. The Inductivist Turkey B. Discovery vs. Justification 1. Discovery 2. Justification C. Hume's Problem 1. Inductive

More information

Naturalism and is Opponents

Naturalism and is Opponents Undergraduate Review Volume 6 Article 30 2010 Naturalism and is Opponents Joseph Spencer Follow this and additional works at: http://vc.bridgew.edu/undergrad_rev Part of the Epistemology Commons Recommended

More information

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism? Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism? Author: Terence Rajivan Edward, University of Manchester. Abstract. In the sixth chapter of The View from Nowhere, Thomas Nagel attempts to identify a form of idealism.

More information

Saul Kripke, Naming and Necessity

Saul Kripke, Naming and Necessity 24.09x Minds and Machines Saul Kripke, Naming and Necessity Excerpt from Saul Kripke, Naming and Necessity (Harvard, 1980). Identity theorists have been concerned with several distinct types of identifications:

More information

REVIEW. Hilary Putnam, Representation and Reality. Cambridge, Nass.: NIT Press, 1988.

REVIEW. Hilary Putnam, Representation and Reality. Cambridge, Nass.: NIT Press, 1988. REVIEW Hilary Putnam, Representation and Reality. Cambridge, Nass.: NIT Press, 1988. In his new book, 'Representation and Reality', Hilary Putnam argues against the view that intentional idioms (with as

More information

Attraction, Description, and the Desire-Satisfaction Theory of Welfare

Attraction, Description, and the Desire-Satisfaction Theory of Welfare Attraction, Description, and the Desire-Satisfaction Theory of Welfare The desire-satisfaction theory of welfare says that what is basically good for a subject what benefits him in the most fundamental,

More information

DO SENSE EXPERIENTIAL STATES HAVE CONCEPTUAL CONTENT?

DO SENSE EXPERIENTIAL STATES HAVE CONCEPTUAL CONTENT? DO SENSE EXPERIENTIAL STATES HAVE CONCEPTUAL CONTENT? BILL BREWER My thesis in this paper is: (CC) Sense experiential states have conceptual content. I take it for granted that sense experiential states

More information

Against the No-Miracle Response to Indispensability Arguments

Against the No-Miracle Response to Indispensability Arguments Against the No-Miracle Response to Indispensability Arguments I. Overview One of the most influential of the contemporary arguments for the existence of abstract entities is the so-called Quine-Putnam

More information

Lecture One: The Aspiration for a Natural Science of the Social

Lecture One: The Aspiration for a Natural Science of the Social Lecture One: The Aspiration for a Natural Science of the Social Explanation These lectures presuppose that the primary task of science is to explain. This does not mean that the only task of science is

More information

Rationality in Action. By John Searle. Cambridge: MIT Press, pages, ISBN Hardback $35.00.

Rationality in Action. By John Searle. Cambridge: MIT Press, pages, ISBN Hardback $35.00. 106 AUSLEGUNG Rationality in Action. By John Searle. Cambridge: MIT Press, 2001. 303 pages, ISBN 0-262-19463-5. Hardback $35.00. Curran F. Douglass University of Kansas John Searle's Rationality in Action

More information

Ethics is subjective.

Ethics is subjective. Introduction Scientific Method and Research Ethics Ethical Theory Greg Bognar Stockholm University September 22, 2017 Ethics is subjective. If ethics is subjective, then moral claims are subjective in

More information

Russellianism and Explanation. David Braun. University of Rochester

Russellianism and Explanation. David Braun. University of Rochester Forthcoming in Philosophical Perspectives 15 (2001) Russellianism and Explanation David Braun University of Rochester Russellianism is a semantic theory that entails that sentences (1) and (2) express

More information

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy Res Cogitans Volume 5 Issue 1 Article 20 6-4-2014 Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy Kevin Harriman Lewis & Clark College Follow this and additional works at: http://commons.pacificu.edu/rescogitans

More information

Does the Skeptic Win? A Defense of Moore. I. Moorean Methodology. In A Proof of the External World, Moore argues as follows:

Does the Skeptic Win? A Defense of Moore. I. Moorean Methodology. In A Proof of the External World, Moore argues as follows: Does the Skeptic Win? A Defense of Moore I argue that Moore s famous response to the skeptic should be accepted even by the skeptic. My paper has three main stages. First, I will briefly outline G. E.

More information

PHILOSOPHIES OF SCIENTIFIC TESTING

PHILOSOPHIES OF SCIENTIFIC TESTING PHILOSOPHIES OF SCIENTIFIC TESTING By John Bloore Internet Encyclopdia of Philosophy, written by John Wttersten, http://www.iep.utm.edu/cr-ratio/#h7 Carl Gustav Hempel (1905 1997) Known for Deductive-Nomological

More information

Aboutness and Justification

Aboutness and Justification For a symposium on Imogen Dickie s book Fixing Reference to be published in Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. Aboutness and Justification Dilip Ninan dilip.ninan@tufts.edu September 2016 Al believes

More information

TWO ACCOUNTS OF THE NORMATIVITY OF RATIONALITY

TWO ACCOUNTS OF THE NORMATIVITY OF RATIONALITY DISCUSSION NOTE BY JONATHAN WAY JOURNAL OF ETHICS & SOCIAL PHILOSOPHY DISCUSSION NOTE DECEMBER 2009 URL: WWW.JESP.ORG COPYRIGHT JONATHAN WAY 2009 Two Accounts of the Normativity of Rationality RATIONALITY

More information

BELIEF POLICIES, by Paul Helm. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, Pp. xiii and 226. $54.95 (Cloth).

BELIEF POLICIES, by Paul Helm. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, Pp. xiii and 226. $54.95 (Cloth). BELIEF POLICIES, by Paul Helm. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1994. Pp. xiii and 226. $54.95 (Cloth). TRENTON MERRICKS, Virginia Commonwealth University Faith and Philosophy 13 (1996): 449-454

More information

PHILOSOPHY EPISTEMOLOGY ESSAY TOPICS AND INSTRUCTIONS

PHILOSOPHY EPISTEMOLOGY ESSAY TOPICS AND INSTRUCTIONS PHILOSOPHY 5340 - EPISTEMOLOGY ESSAY TOPICS AND INSTRUCTIONS INSTRUCTIONS 1. As is indicated in the syllabus, the required work for the course can take the form either of two shorter essay-writing exercises,

More information

THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE

THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE Diametros nr 29 (wrzesień 2011): 80-92 THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE Karol Polcyn 1. PRELIMINARIES Chalmers articulates his argument in terms of two-dimensional

More information

PARFIT'S MISTAKEN METAETHICS Michael Smith

PARFIT'S MISTAKEN METAETHICS Michael Smith PARFIT'S MISTAKEN METAETHICS Michael Smith In the first volume of On What Matters, Derek Parfit defends a distinctive metaethical view, a view that specifies the relationships he sees between reasons,

More information

DISCUSSION THE GUISE OF A REASON

DISCUSSION THE GUISE OF A REASON NADEEM J.Z. HUSSAIN DISCUSSION THE GUISE OF A REASON The articles collected in David Velleman s The Possibility of Practical Reason are a snapshot or rather a film-strip of part of a philosophical endeavour

More information

is knowledge normative?

is knowledge normative? Mark Schroeder University of Southern California March 20, 2015 is knowledge normative? Epistemology is, at least in part, a normative discipline. Epistemologists are concerned not simply with what people

More information

The Problem of Induction and Popper s Deductivism

The Problem of Induction and Popper s Deductivism The Problem of Induction and Popper s Deductivism Issues: I. Problem of Induction II. Popper s rejection of induction III. Salmon s critique of deductivism 2 I. The problem of induction 1. Inductive vs.

More information

Are There Reasons to Be Rational?

Are There Reasons to Be Rational? Are There Reasons to Be Rational? Olav Gjelsvik, University of Oslo The thesis. Among people writing about rationality, few people are more rational than Wlodek Rabinowicz. But are there reasons for being

More information

R. Keith Sawyer: Social Emergence. Societies as Complex Systems. Cambridge University Press

R. Keith Sawyer: Social Emergence. Societies as Complex Systems. Cambridge University Press R. Keith Sawyer: Social Emergence. Societies as Complex Systems. Cambridge University Press. 2005. This is an ambitious book. Keith Sawyer attempts to show that his new emergence paradigm provides a means

More information

Etchemendy, Tarski, and Logical Consequence 1 Jared Bates, University of Missouri Southwest Philosophy Review 15 (1999):

Etchemendy, Tarski, and Logical Consequence 1 Jared Bates, University of Missouri Southwest Philosophy Review 15 (1999): Etchemendy, Tarski, and Logical Consequence 1 Jared Bates, University of Missouri Southwest Philosophy Review 15 (1999): 47 54. Abstract: John Etchemendy (1990) has argued that Tarski's definition of logical

More information

Can A Priori Justified Belief Be Extended Through Deduction? It is often assumed that if one deduces some proposition p from some premises

Can A Priori Justified Belief Be Extended Through Deduction? It is often assumed that if one deduces some proposition p from some premises Can A Priori Justified Belief Be Extended Through Deduction? Introduction It is often assumed that if one deduces some proposition p from some premises which one knows a priori, in a series of individually

More information

Luck, Rationality, and Explanation: A Reply to Elga s Lucky to Be Rational. Joshua Schechter. Brown University

Luck, Rationality, and Explanation: A Reply to Elga s Lucky to Be Rational. Joshua Schechter. Brown University Luck, Rationality, and Explanation: A Reply to Elga s Lucky to Be Rational Joshua Schechter Brown University I Introduction What is the epistemic significance of discovering that one of your beliefs depends

More information

Two Kinds of Naturalism in Ethics

Two Kinds of Naturalism in Ethics Two Kinds of Naturalism in Ethics NEIL SINCLAIR neil.sinclair@nottingham.ac.uk Penultimate draft. Final paper published in Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 2006, 9(4): 417-439 ABSTRACT: What are the conditions

More information

Jerry A. Fodor. Hume Variations John Biro Volume 31, Number 1, (2005) 173-176. Your use of the HUME STUDIES archive indicates your acceptance of HUME STUDIES Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.humesociety.org/hs/about/terms.html.

More information

Buck-Passers Negative Thesis

Buck-Passers Negative Thesis Mark Schroeder November 27, 2006 University of Southern California Buck-Passers Negative Thesis [B]eing valuable is not a property that provides us with reasons. Rather, to call something valuable is to

More information

Social mechanisms and explaining how: A reply to Kimberly Chuang Johannes Persson, Lund University

Social mechanisms and explaining how: A reply to Kimberly Chuang Johannes Persson, Lund University Social mechanisms and explaining how: A reply to Kimberly Chuang Johannes Persson, Lund University Kimberly Chuang s detailed and helpful reply to my article (2012a) concerns Jon Elster s struggle to develop

More information

appearance is often different from reality, and it s reality that counts.

appearance is often different from reality, and it s reality that counts. Relativism Appearance vs. Reality Philosophy begins with the realisation that appearance is often different from reality, and it s reality that counts. Parmenides and others were maybe hyper Parmenides

More information

Received: 30 August 2007 / Accepted: 16 November 2007 / Published online: 28 December 2007 # Springer Science + Business Media B.V.

Received: 30 August 2007 / Accepted: 16 November 2007 / Published online: 28 December 2007 # Springer Science + Business Media B.V. Acta anal. (2007) 22:267 279 DOI 10.1007/s12136-007-0012-y What Is Entitlement? Albert Casullo Received: 30 August 2007 / Accepted: 16 November 2007 / Published online: 28 December 2007 # Springer Science

More information

EXERCISES, QUESTIONS, AND ACTIVITIES My Answers

EXERCISES, QUESTIONS, AND ACTIVITIES My Answers EXERCISES, QUESTIONS, AND ACTIVITIES My Answers Diagram and evaluate each of the following arguments. Arguments with Definitional Premises Altruism. Altruism is the practice of doing something solely because

More information

It is advisable to refer to the publisher s version if you intend to cite from the work.

It is advisable to refer to the publisher s version if you intend to cite from the work. Article Capacity, Mental Mechanisms, and Unwise Decisions Thornton, Tim Available at http://clok.uclan.ac.uk/4356/ Thornton, Tim (2011) Capacity, Mental Mechanisms, and Unwise Decisions. Philosophy, Psychiatry,

More information

From the Categorical Imperative to the Moral Law

From the Categorical Imperative to the Moral Law From the Categorical Imperative to the Moral Law Marianne Vahl Master Thesis in Philosophy Supervisor Olav Gjelsvik Department of Philosophy, Classics, History of Arts and Ideas UNIVERSITY OF OSLO May

More information

How Do We Know Anything about Mathematics? - A Defence of Platonism

How Do We Know Anything about Mathematics? - A Defence of Platonism How Do We Know Anything about Mathematics? - A Defence of Platonism Majda Trobok University of Rijeka original scientific paper UDK: 141.131 1:51 510.21 ABSTRACT In this paper I will try to say something

More information

How Not to Defend Metaphysical Realism (Southwestern Philosophical Review, Vol , 19-27)

How Not to Defend Metaphysical Realism (Southwestern Philosophical Review, Vol , 19-27) How Not to Defend Metaphysical Realism (Southwestern Philosophical Review, Vol 3 1986, 19-27) John Collier Department of Philosophy Rice University November 21, 1986 Putnam's writings on realism(1) have

More information

Phil 1103 Review. Also: Scientific realism vs. anti-realism Can philosophers criticise science?

Phil 1103 Review. Also: Scientific realism vs. anti-realism Can philosophers criticise science? Phil 1103 Review Also: Scientific realism vs. anti-realism Can philosophers criticise science? 1. Copernican Revolution Students should be familiar with the basic historical facts of the Copernican revolution.

More information

SKEPTICISM, ABDUCTIVISM, AND THE EXPLANATORY GAP. Ram Neta University of North Carolina, Chapel Hill

SKEPTICISM, ABDUCTIVISM, AND THE EXPLANATORY GAP. Ram Neta University of North Carolina, Chapel Hill Philosophical Issues, 14, Epistemology, 2004 SKEPTICISM, ABDUCTIVISM, AND THE EXPLANATORY GAP Ram Neta University of North Carolina, Chapel Hill I. Introduction:The Skeptical Problem and its Proposed Abductivist

More information

ON CAUSAL AND CONSTRUCTIVE MODELLING OF BELIEF CHANGE

ON CAUSAL AND CONSTRUCTIVE MODELLING OF BELIEF CHANGE ON CAUSAL AND CONSTRUCTIVE MODELLING OF BELIEF CHANGE A. V. RAVISHANKAR SARMA Our life in various phases can be construed as involving continuous belief revision activity with a bundle of accepted beliefs,

More information

In Defense of Pure Reason: A Rationalist Account of A Priori Justification, by Laurence BonJour. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,

In Defense of Pure Reason: A Rationalist Account of A Priori Justification, by Laurence BonJour. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, Book Reviews 1 In Defense of Pure Reason: A Rationalist Account of A Priori Justification, by Laurence BonJour. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998. Pp. xiv + 232. H/b 37.50, $54.95, P/b 13.95,

More information

Shafer-Landau's defense against Blackburn's supervenience argument

Shafer-Landau's defense against Blackburn's supervenience argument University of Gothenburg Department of Philosophy, Linguistics and Theory of Science Shafer-Landau's defense against Blackburn's supervenience argument Author: Anna Folland Supervisor: Ragnar Francén Olinder

More information

Fundamentals of Metaphysics

Fundamentals of Metaphysics Fundamentals of Metaphysics Objective and Subjective One important component of the Common Western Metaphysic is the thesis that there is such a thing as objective truth. each of our beliefs and assertions

More information

Take Home Exam #1. PHI 1500: Major Issues in Philosophy Prof. Lauren R. Alpert

Take Home Exam #1. PHI 1500: Major Issues in Philosophy Prof. Lauren R. Alpert PHI 1500: Major Issues in Philosophy Prof. Lauren R. Alpert Name: Date: Take Home Exam #1 Instructions Answer as many questions as you are able to. Please write your answers clearly in the blanks provided.

More information

Epistemology for Naturalists and Non-Naturalists: What s the Difference?

Epistemology for Naturalists and Non-Naturalists: What s the Difference? Res Cogitans Volume 3 Issue 1 Article 3 6-7-2012 Epistemology for Naturalists and Non-Naturalists: What s the Difference? Jason Poettcker University of Victoria Follow this and additional works at: http://commons.pacificu.edu/rescogitans

More information

Huemer s Clarkeanism

Huemer s Clarkeanism Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Vol. LXXVIII No. 1, January 2009 Ó 2009 International Phenomenological Society Huemer s Clarkeanism mark schroeder University

More information

time poses challenging problems. This is certainly true, but hardly interesting enough

time poses challenging problems. This is certainly true, but hardly interesting enough Methodological Problems in the Phenomenology of Time Gianfranco Soldati Department of Philosophy, Fribourg University, Switzerland (Polish Journal of Philosophy, 2016) 1. Introduction It is generally acknowledged,

More information

Utilitarianism: For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), pp Reprinted in Moral Luck (CUP, 1981).

Utilitarianism: For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), pp Reprinted in Moral Luck (CUP, 1981). Draft of 3-21- 13 PHIL 202: Core Ethics; Winter 2013 Core Sequence in the History of Ethics, 2011-2013 IV: 19 th and 20 th Century Moral Philosophy David O. Brink Handout #14: Williams, Internalism, and

More information

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory Western University Scholarship@Western 2015 Undergraduate Awards The Undergraduate Awards 2015 Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory David Hakim Western University, davidhakim266@gmail.com

More information

The Simple Desire-Fulfillment Theory

The Simple Desire-Fulfillment Theory NOÛS 33:2 ~1999! 247 272 The Simple Desire-Fulfillment Theory Mark C. Murphy Georgetown University An account of well-being that Parfit labels the desire-fulfillment theory ~1984, 493! has gained a great

More information

Quine s Naturalized Epistemology, Epistemic Normativity and the. Gettier Problem

Quine s Naturalized Epistemology, Epistemic Normativity and the. Gettier Problem Quine s Naturalized Epistemology, Epistemic Normativity and the Gettier Problem Dr. Qilin Li (liqilin@gmail.com; liqilin@pku.edu.cn) The Department of Philosophy, Peking University Beiijing, P. R. China

More information

A number of epistemologists have defended

A number of epistemologists have defended American Philosophical Quarterly Volume 50, Number 1, January 2013 Doxastic Voluntarism, Epistemic Deontology, and Belief- Contravening Commitments Michael J. Shaffer 1. Introduction A number of epistemologists

More information

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW DISCUSSION NOTE BY CAMPBELL BROWN JOURNAL OF ETHICS & SOCIAL PHILOSOPHY DISCUSSION NOTE MAY 2015 URL: WWW.JESP.ORG COPYRIGHT CAMPBELL BROWN 2015 Two Versions of Hume s Law MORAL CONCLUSIONS CANNOT VALIDLY

More information

PHILOSOPHICAL PERSPECTIVES

PHILOSOPHICAL PERSPECTIVES PHILOSOPHICAL PERSPECTIVES Philosophical Perspectives, 25, Metaphysics, 2011 EXPERIENCE AND THE PASSAGE OF TIME Bradford Skow 1. Introduction Some philosophers believe that the passage of time is a real

More information

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology. Topic 6: Theories of Justification: Foundationalism versus Coherentism. Part 2: Susan Haack s Foundherentist Approach

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology. Topic 6: Theories of Justification: Foundationalism versus Coherentism. Part 2: Susan Haack s Foundherentist Approach Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 6: Theories of Justification: Foundationalism versus Coherentism Part 2: Susan Haack s Foundherentist Approach Susan Haack, "A Foundherentist Theory of Empirical Justification"

More information

Citation for the original published paper (version of record):

Citation for the original published paper (version of record): http://www.diva-portal.org Postprint This is the accepted version of a paper published in Utilitas. This paper has been peerreviewed but does not include the final publisher proof-corrections or journal

More information

NORMATIVITY WITHOUT NORMATIVISM 1

NORMATIVITY WITHOUT NORMATIVISM 1 FORO DE DEBATE / DEBATE FORUM 195 NORMATIVITY WITHOUT NORMATIVISM 1 Jesús Zamora-Bonilla jpzb@fsof.uned.es UNED, Madrid. Spain. Stephen Turner s book Explaining the Normative (Polity, Oxford, 2010) constitutes

More information

Curriculum Vitae Contact Harvard University Department of Philosophy 25 Quincy Street Cambridge, MA

Curriculum Vitae Contact Harvard University Department of Philosophy 25 Quincy Street Cambridge, MA JEREMY DAVID FIX Curriculum Vitae 07.21.16 Contact Department of Philosophy jdfix@fas.harvard.edu 25 Quincy Street Cambridge, MA 02138 908.902.0804 Education 2008-2016 HARVARD UNIVERSITY PHD 10.2016 1

More information

Philosophy Epistemology Topic 5 The Justification of Induction 1. Hume s Skeptical Challenge to Induction

Philosophy Epistemology Topic 5 The Justification of Induction 1. Hume s Skeptical Challenge to Induction Philosophy 5340 - Epistemology Topic 5 The Justification of Induction 1. Hume s Skeptical Challenge to Induction In the section entitled Sceptical Doubts Concerning the Operations of the Understanding

More information

Realism and the success of science argument. Leplin:

Realism and the success of science argument. Leplin: Realism and the success of science argument Leplin: 1) Realism is the default position. 2) The arguments for anti-realism are indecisive. In particular, antirealism offers no serious rival to realism in

More information

The Illusion of Scientific Realism: An Argument for Scientific Soft Antirealism

The Illusion of Scientific Realism: An Argument for Scientific Soft Antirealism The Illusion of Scientific Realism: An Argument for Scientific Soft Antirealism Peter Carmack Introduction Throughout the history of science, arguments have emerged about science s ability or non-ability

More information

Purple Haze: The Puzzle of Consciousness

Purple Haze: The Puzzle of Consciousness Purple Haze: The Puzzle of Consciousness The MIT Faculty has made this article openly available. Please share how this access benefits you. Your story matters. Citation As Published Publisher Levine, Joseph.

More information

Sometimes doing what is Right has No Right Answer: On Hilary Putnam s Pragmatism with Existential Choices

Sometimes doing what is Right has No Right Answer: On Hilary Putnam s Pragmatism with Existential Choices Sometimes doing what is Right has No Right Answer: On Hilary Putnam s Pragmatism with Existential Choices Kai Nielsen The University of Calgary I This essay was inspired (or if inspired is a too pretentious

More information

Behavior and Other Minds: A Response to Functionalists

Behavior and Other Minds: A Response to Functionalists Behavior and Other Minds: A Response to Functionalists MIKE LOCKHART Functionalists argue that the "problem of other minds" has a simple solution, namely, that one can ath'ibute mentality to an object

More information

Experiences Don t Sum

Experiences Don t Sum Philip Goff Experiences Don t Sum According to Galen Strawson, there could be no such thing as brute emergence. If weallow thatcertain x s can emergefromcertain y s in a way that is unintelligible, even

More information

What God Could Have Made

What God Could Have Made 1 What God Could Have Made By Heimir Geirsson and Michael Losonsky I. Introduction Atheists have argued that if there is a God who is omnipotent, omniscient and omnibenevolent, then God would have made

More information

Freedom as Morality. UWM Digital Commons. University of Wisconsin Milwaukee. Hao Liang University of Wisconsin-Milwaukee. Theses and Dissertations

Freedom as Morality. UWM Digital Commons. University of Wisconsin Milwaukee. Hao Liang University of Wisconsin-Milwaukee. Theses and Dissertations University of Wisconsin Milwaukee UWM Digital Commons Theses and Dissertations May 2014 Freedom as Morality Hao Liang University of Wisconsin-Milwaukee Follow this and additional works at: http://dc.uwm.edu/etd

More information

THEISM, EVOLUTIONARY EPISTEMOLOGY, AND TWO THEORIES OF TRUTH

THEISM, EVOLUTIONARY EPISTEMOLOGY, AND TWO THEORIES OF TRUTH THEISM, EVOLUTIONARY EPISTEMOLOGY, AND TWO THEORIES OF TRUTH by John Lemos Abstract. In Michael Ruse s recent publications, such as Taking Darwin Seriously (1998) and Evolutionary Naturalism (1995), he

More information

Others may concern the reliability of methods for forming belief:

Others may concern the reliability of methods for forming belief: Forthcoming. The European Legacy, special issue devoted to Richard Rorty. DRAFT No citations without permission Truth and Freedom Michael Patrick Lynch University of Connecticut What does truth have to

More information

Final Paper. May 13, 2015

Final Paper. May 13, 2015 24.221 Final Paper May 13, 2015 Determinism states the following: given the state of the universe at time t 0, denoted S 0, and the conjunction of the laws of nature, L, the state of the universe S at

More information