The Cosmological Argument

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "The Cosmological Argument"

Transcription

1 The Cosmological Argument Reading Questions The Cosmological Argument: Elementary Version The Cosmological Argument: Intermediate Version The Cosmological Argument: Advanced Version Summary of the Cosmological Argument Reading Questions For question, consider the following argument: Everything was caused by something else that happened before it and so either there s an infinite causal chain extending backwards or there s a first cause, something that wasn t caused by anything else but which started everything else. There can t be an infinite causal chain extending backwards, though, which means that there must be first cause, something that wasn t caused by anything else but which started everything else. Therefore, God exists.. God exists. 2. Everything was caused by something else that happened before it. 3. Either there s an infinite causal chain extending backwards or there s a first cause, something that wasn t caused by anything else but which started everything else. 4. There can t be an infinite causal chain extending backwards. 5. There s a first cause, something that wasn t caused by anything else but which started everything else. 2 A B 5 C ) What is an objection to this argument? For question 2-4, consider the following argument: Every contingent being was caused by something else that happened before it and so either there s an infinite causal chain of contingent beings extending backwards or there s a first cause, some necessary being that wasn t caused by anything else but that started everything else. There can t be an infinite causal chain of contingent beings extending backwards, though, which means that there must be first cause, some necessary being that wasn t caused by anything else but that started everything else. Therefore, God exists.

2 2. God exists. 2. Every contingent being was caused by something else that happened before it. 3. Either there s an infinite causal chain of contingent beings extending backwards or there s a first cause, some necessary being that wasn t caused by anything else but that started everything else. 4. There can t be an infinite causal chain of contingent beings extending backwards. 5. There s a first cause, some necessary being that wasn t caused by anything else but that started everything else. 2 A B 5 C 2) What are contingent beings? 3) What are necessary beings? 4) What is an objection to premise 4 in this argument? For questions 5 and 6, consider the following argument: Now in efficient causes it is not possible to go on to infinity, because in all efficient causes following in order, the first is the cause of the intermediate cause, and the intermediate is the cause of the ultimate cause, whether the intermediate cause be several, or only one. Now to take away the cause is to take away the effect. Therefore, if there be no first cause among efficient causes, there will be no ultimate, nor any intermediate cause. But if in efficient causes it is possible to go on to infinity, there will be no first efficient cause, neither will there be an ultimate effect, nor any intermediate efficient causes; all of which is plainly false.. The causal chain behind everything we experience can t go back to infinity. 2. In a causal chain, the first cause causes the second, and so on, until you get the final effect in this case everything in existence now. 3. To take away the cause is to prevent the effect. 4. If there were no first cause, then the first cause would be taken away, the second cause wouldn t exist, and so on, and there wouldn t be anything in existence now. 5. If the causal chain were infinite, there would be no first cause. 6. If the causal chain were infinite, there would be nothing in existence now. 7. But there are things in existence now!

3 A B C 5) What does it mean for an argument to equivocate, or to trade upon an ambiguity? 6) What is wrong with this argument? For questions 7 and 8, consider the following argument: Clearly contingent things have causes, so we re faced with a causal chain going backwards in time. Either this causal chain doesn t go backwards forever, or it does. What are the consequences of each possibility? On the one hand, if the causal chain doesn t go backwards forever then there s a first cause, and this cause, not requiring a cause itself, must be a necessary being. Consequently, if the causal chain doesn t go backwards forever then there must be a necessary being. On the other hand, if the causal chain does go backwards forever, we can consider the entirety of the causal chain itself and ask ourselves why it exists. What is responsible for the existence of this infinite causal chain? Surely something is responsible for its existence, and whatever is responsible for the existence of the chain can t be a contingent being because all contingent beings are in the chain and nothing that s in the chain can be responsible for the existence of the chain. It follows that whatever is responsible for the existence of the chain must be a necessary being and so if the causal chain does go backwards forever then a necessary being must exist. Whether or not the chain of contingent being extends infinitely back, then, a necessary being must exist. It s reasonable to suppose that this necessary being is God, so God exists.. God exits. 2. Contingent things have causes. 3. We re faced with a causal chain going backwards in time. 4. Either this causal chain doesn t go backwards forever or it does go backwards forever. 5. If the causal chain doesn t go backwards forever then there s a first cause. 6. This first cause, not requiring a cause itself, must be a necessary being. 7. If the causal chain doesn t go backwards forever then there must be a necessary being. 8. If the causal chain does go backwards forever then something is responsible for its existence. 9. Whatever is responsible for the existence of the chain can t be a contingent being. 0. All contingent beings are in the chain.. Nothing that s in the chain can be responsible for the existence of the chain. 2. Whatever is responsible for the existence of the chain must be a necessary being.

4 4 3. If the causal chain does go backwards forever then a necessary being must exist. 4. Whether or not the chain of contingent being extends infinitely back, then, a necessary being must exist. 5. It s reasonable to suppose that this necessary being is God. 0 + C D A B E F G 7) What is the Principle of Sufficient Reason? 8) How might someone object to this argument? The Cosmological Argument: Elementary Version The cosmological argument often occurs to people naturally. Have you ever looked out into the universe (the cosmos) and pondered how everything got here? Have you ever thought something like this? A long time ago, there were dinosaurs that evolved from even more ancient animals. And those more ancient animals evolved from elementary cells that came from chemicals. And those chemicals resulted from atoms that came from the Big Bang. But what started that? What caused the Big Bang? Was there something before that? Did the universe just come out of nothing? Does it go back forever? Or did God start it all? If you ve ever thought along these lines, you ve already grasped the fundamentals of the cosmological argument. Here s a pretty standard statement of it, followed by its diagram. Everything was caused by something else that happened before it and so either there s an infinite causal chain extending backwards or there s a first cause, something that wasn t caused by anything else but that started everything else. There can t be an infinite causal chain extending backwards, though, which means that there must be first cause, something that wasn t caused by anything else but which started everything else. Therefore, God exists.. God exists. 2. Everything was caused by something else that happened before it.

5 5 3. Either there s an infinite causal chain extending backwards or there s a first cause, something that wasn t caused by anything else but that started everything else. 4. There can t be an infinite causal chain extending backwards. 5. There s a first cause, something that wasn t caused by anything else but that started everything else. 2 A B 5 C Stop and Think: What s your first reaction to this argument? Of course, this version of the cosmological argument is not without its problems. One problem is that it s not clear why the first cause is God and not, for instance, the Big Bang or some other natural event. This shows us that inference C is far from perfect. In practice, however, people who use the cosmological argument to establish the existence of God typically argue in two stages: first they argue for the claim that is a first cause of some sort or another, and then they argue that this first cause is God. We won t, therefore, be worrying too much about inference C here. Another problem with this argument is illustrated by the question What caused God? and if you find yourself asking this question then you see a rather deep problem with the argument as it stands. Repairing this problem will take us to a new, more advanced, version of the cosmological argument. The Cosmological Argument: Intermediate Version Thinking About Premise 2: Contingent and Necessary Beings So, assuming that the cosmological argument that we ve seen successfully establishes the existence of God, then what did cause God? Everything was caused by something else that happened before it and so either there s an infinite causal chain extending backwards or there s a first cause, something that wasn t caused by anything else but that started everything else. There can t be an infinite causal chain extending backwards, though, which means that there must be first cause, something that wasn t caused by anything else but which started everything else. Therefore, God exists.

6 6. God exists. 2. Everything was caused by something else that happened before it. 3. Either there s an infinite causal chain extending backwards or there s a first cause, something that wasn t caused by anything else but that started everything else. 4. There can t be an infinite causal chain extending backwards. 5. There s a first cause, something that wasn t caused by anything else but that started everything else. 2 A B 5 C (But what caused God?) There are only two possible answers to this What caused God? question: ) Something caused God, or 2) Nothing caused God. The first answer, Something caused God, is unavailable to an advocate of the cosmological argument that we ve been examining. Can you see why? If we say that something caused God then we re off on an infinite regress of causes going backwards, with something causing God (maybe a Super-God) something else causing the thing that caused God (maybe a Super-Duper-God) something else causing the thing that caused the thing that caused God (maybe a Super-Duper-Mega-God), and so on. But if we re okay with this, then we re rejecting premise 4 in the cosmological argument, which says that there can t be an infinite series of causes going backwards. This means that an advocate of the cosmological argument needs to adopt the second answer and say that nothing caused God. But if nothing caused God then God is uncaused, and if God is uncaused then premise 2, the claim that everything was caused by something that happened before it, is false. In order to address this difficulty, advocates of the cosmological argument maintain that God is importantly different from other things in a way that explains why God can be uncaused while everything else needs to have been caused by something else. They do this by claiming that only beings of a certain kind, called contingent beings, need a cause. Contingent beings, which include all of the objects in our experience, in some sense wouldn t have to have existed. It s these objects that need a cause, or an explanation for their existence. Suppose, for example, that you re holding a pen. Not only could we destroy the pen now, but the pen didn t have to have ever existed at all. If things had been different than they are, the pen wouldn t have existed. That s what we mean when we say that the pen is a contingent being. The existence of the pen is

7 7 contingent upon things in the universe having been a particular way upon there having been that particular pen company, for example and this contingency allows us to ask why the pen exists. It allows us to inquire into the conditions that brought the pen about. God, however, is presumably not like that pen. Many thinkers believe that God, if he exists, would be a necessary being, or a being that couldn t possibly fail to exist. Because necessary beings can t possibly fail to exist, we can t inquire into the particular conditions that are responsible for their existence. Necessary beings, in other words, don t require a prior cause. Advocates of the cosmological argument are usually much more precise about Premise 2, claiming only that all contingent beings have causes, and this allows them to say that God, as a necessary being doesn t require a prior cause. The revised, intermediate, version of the Cosmological Argument runs as follows: Every contingent being was caused by something else that happened before it and so either there s an infinite causal chain of contingent beings extending backwards or there s a first cause, some necessary being that wasn t caused by anything else but that started everything else. There can t be an infinite causal chain of contingent beings extending backwards, though, which means that there must be first cause, something that wasn t caused by anything else but which started everything else. Therefore, God exists.. God exists. 2. Every contingent being was caused by something else that happened before it. 3. Either there s an infinite causal chain of contingent beings extending backwards or there s a first cause, some necessary being that wasn t caused by anything else but that started everything else. 4. There can t be an infinite causal chain of contingent beings extending backwards. 5. There s a first cause, some necessary being that wasn t caused by anything else but that started everything else. 2 A B 5 C Of course, the argument still has some problems because employing the distinction between contingent and necessary beings raises difficulties of its own. For one thing, it isn t at all clear what a necessary being is, if any beings really are necessary, or if a

8 8 necessary being would be able to have the qualities that we typically ascribe to God. For another thing, some thinkers have asserted that the universe itself might be a necessary being, and if the universe itself is a necessary being then it wouldn t require a cause beyond itself. Why can t the universe as a whole to be uncaused, thereby avoiding the need for a creator God altogether? I m not sure what the answer to this question is. I don t know whether or not the universe is, itself, a contingent being, but I do know that one argument for the position that universe is a contingent being is bad. Essentially, this argument says that since all of the parts of the universe are contingent beings (which presumably they are), then the universe as a whole must be a contingent being. This way of thinking embodies the fallacy of composition. Just because the parts of something have a certain property, it doesn t follow that the whole thing has that property. Just because every member of the philosophy department drinks water, for example, it doesn t follow that the philosophy department as a whole drinks water. Just because every piece of a mosaic is two inches square, it doesn t follow that the mosaic as a whole is two inches square. Similarly, just because the parts of the universe are contingent beings, it needn t follow that the universe as a whole is a contingent being. Of course, as you know, a bad argument can have a true conclusion and so the universe might nonetheless be a contingent being. In fact, I m personally inclined to think that the universe as a whole is contingent because I think that the universe as a whole need not have existed. I think it makes some sense to suppose that there might not have been this universe, or any other, and to marvel at the fact that anything exists at all. Naturally, I might be wrong. This isn t a knock-down argument in favor of the contingency of the universe and so for now let s just assume that the universe as a whole is a contingent thing and note that this assumption although not definitively established is not unreasonable. We shall take the universe to be a contingent thing, the existence of which does require some explanation or cause. Thinking About Premise 4: St. Thomas Aquinas s Defense Now let s turn our attention to premise 4 of the argument, the claim that there can t be an infinite causal chain extending backwards. Some people attempt to argue against premise 4 by noting that we re quite willing to accept other kinds of backwards infinite series, including an infinite series of negative numbers. If we can have a backwards infinite series of numbers, like this: why can t we have a backwards infinite series of causes, like this?. your great-great-grandmother your great-grandmother your grandmother your mother you

9 9 But can you see an important difference between these two series? An advocate of the cosmological argument could counter that an infinite series of numbers is importantly different than an infinite series of causes. 2 isn t caused by 3, after all, and so it seems like the existence of 2 is independent of the existence of 3 (although it s hard to get a handle on what we mean when we say the existence of 2 ). Your grandmother, on the other hand, was caused by your great-grandmother so your grandmother s existence is dependent upon the existence of your great-grandmother. No great-grandmother ever, no grandmother either. St. Thomas Aquinas ( ) takes advantage of this feature of causal chains to argue that premise 4 is true and that we can t have an infinite causal sequence going backwards. Here s how he does it. In the world of sense we find there is an order of causes. There is no case known (neither is it, indeed, possible) in which a thing is found to be the cause of itself; for so it would be prior to itself, which is impossible. Now in causes it is not possible to go on to infinity, because in all causes following in order, the first is the cause of the intermediate cause, and the intermediate is the cause of the ultimate cause, whether the intermediate cause be several, or only one. Now to take away the cause is to take away the effect. Therefore, if there be no first cause among causes, there will be no ultimate, nor any intermediate cause. But if in causes it is possible to go on to infinity, there will be no first cause, neither will there be an ultimate effect, nor any intermediate causes; all of which is plainly false. Therefore it is necessary to admit a first cause, to which everyone gives the name of God. (The Second Way from The Summa Theologica) The argument that Aquinas has in mind goes something like this:. The causal chain behind everything we experience can t go back to infinity. 2. In a causal chain, the first cause causes the second, and so on, until you get the final effect in this case everything in existence now. 3. To take away the cause is to prevent the effect. 4. If there were no first cause, then the first cause would be taken away, the second cause wouldn t exist, and so on, and there wouldn t be anything in existence now. 5. If the causal chain were infinite, there would be no first cause. 6. If the causal chain were infinite, there would be nothing in existence now. 7. But there are things in existence now!

10 A B C To see what Aquinas is saying, think about a long chain of dominos. If a pendulum strikes the first domino, that domino will fall to strike the second domino, which will fall to strike the third domino, and so on through the chain. If someone were to remove the 20 th domino before the pendulum swung then the 202 nd domino wouldn t fall and neither would any domino after it. If someone were to remove the 0 st domino before the pendulum swung then the 02 nd wouldn t fall and neither would any domino after it. And if someone were to remove the st domino before the pendulum swung then the 2 nd domino wouldn t fall and neither would any dominos after it. If the first domino were removed, in other words, then no dominos would fall; there would be no domino effects at all. Similarly, when we turn our attention from the dominos and think about the totality of existence, we can see that if the first cause were removed then there would be no subsequent effects at all. There would, in other words, be nothing. But clearly there s something, so there must have been a first cause. Get it? Although this argument might look good, it doesn t work. To see what s wrong, let s consider a joke that was making the rounds when I was in 3 rd grade. Sue: I love pizza! Ann: So when are you gonna marry it? Everyone: Ha ha ha ha ha ha ha ha! This joke is funny to some 3 rd graders because it relies about a fact about language that some 3 rd graders are probably just starting to fully appreciate: one word, like love, can have multiple meanings. We can say that this joke trades upon an ambiguity or equivocates. A word is ambiguous if it has more than one distinct meaning. We re said to trade upon an ambiguity, or equivocate, if we switch between these meanings. This joke trades upon an ambiguity, or equivocates, because it confuses one kind of love with another kind of love. When you re relatively little, and just figuring out that one word can have different meanings, this is hilarious. Arguments can go wrong when they trade upon an ambiguity, or equivocate. For example, consider this little argument. (The odd numbering will make it easier to compare to Aquinas s argument later on.)

11 4. If the bank is under water then our money will get wet. 5. If the river rises then the banks will be under water. 6. If the river rises then our money will get wet B 6 Can you see why the inference in this argument doesn t work? There are two different kinds of bank. Premise 4 is talking about the kind of bank with tellers and safety deposit boxes. Premise 5 is talking about the side of a river. Because premises 4 and 5 aren t talking about the same thing at all, they can t go together to prove anything. In just this way, premises 4 and 5 in Aquinas s argument aren t talking about the same thing, either. Let s take a look: 4. If there were no first cause, then the first cause would be taken away, the second cause wouldn t exist, and so on, and there wouldn t be anything in existence now. 5. If the causal chain were infinite, there would be no first cause. 6. If the causal chain were infinite, there would be nothing in existence now B 6 Can you see how there are different ways in which there can be no first cause, just like there are different kinds banks? Premise 4 is talking about there being no first cause because the cause has been removed. Premise 5 is talking about there being no first cause because there is an infinite series of causes. Those are completely different ways to have no first cause, and so premises 4 and 5 can t work together. If there s no first cause because the chain is infinite (idea 5) then there never was a first cause; it s not as though the first cause has been taken away (idea 4). This means that we can t conclude that if the causal chain were infinite there would be nothing now, any more than we could conclude that our money will get wet if the river rises. Inference B is bad because it equivocates upon no first cause. It trades upon an ambiguity, and this makes the entire argument bad.. The causal chain behind everything we experience can t go back to infinity. 2. In a causal chain, the first cause causes the second, and so on, until you get the final effect in this case everything in existence now. 3. To take away the cause is to prevent the effect. 4. If there were no first cause, then the first cause would be taken away, the second cause wouldn t exist, and so on, and there wouldn t be anything in existence now.

12 2 5. If the causal chain were infinite, there would be no first cause. 6. If the causal chain were infinite, there would be nothing in existence now. 7. But there are things in existence now! A B C The Cosmological Argument: Advanced Version So far, then, the cosmological argument is in trouble because we can t establish that there has to be a first cause. For all we know, the chain of causes could go back forever. But never fear: a more advanced version of the cosmological argument incorporate this fact. Here s how it goes: Clearly contingent things have causes, so we re faced with a causal chain going backwards in time. Either this causal chain doesn t go backwards forever, or it does. What are the consequences of each possibility? On the one hand, if the causal chain doesn t go backwards forever then there s a first cause, and this cause, not requiring a cause itself, must be a necessary being. Consequently, if the causal chain doesn t go backwards forever then there must be a necessary being. On the other hand, if the causal chain does go backwards forever, we can consider the entirety of the causal chain itself and ask ourselves why it exists. What is responsible for the existence of this infinite causal chain? Surely something is responsible for its existence, and whatever is responsible for the existence of the chain can t be a contingent being because all contingent beings are in the chain and nothing that s in the chain can be responsible for the existence of the chain. It follows that whatever is responsible for the existence of the chain must be a necessary being and so if the causal chain does go backwards forever then a necessary being must exist. Whether or not the chain of contingent being extends infinitely back, then, a necessary being must exist. It s reasonable to suppose that this necessary being is God, so God exists.. God exits. 2. Contingent things have causes. 3. We re faced with a causal chain going backwards in time. 4. Either this causal chain doesn t go backwards forever or it does go backwards forever. 5. If the causal chain doesn t go backwards forever then there s a first cause. 6. This first cause, not requiring a cause itself, must be a necessary being. 7. If the causal chain doesn t go backwards forever then there must be a necessary being.

13 3 8. If the causal chain does go backwards forever then something is responsible for its existence. 9. Whatever is responsible for the existence of the chain can t be a contingent being. 0. All contingent beings are in the chain.. Nothing that s in the chain can be responsible for the existence of the chain. 2. Whatever is responsible for the existence of the chain must be a necessary being. 3. If the causal chain does go backwards forever then a necessary being must exist. 4. Whether or not the chain of contingent being extends infinitely back, then, a necessary being must exist. 5. It s reasonable to suppose that this necessary being is God. 0 + C D A B E F G It s probably pretty obvious why this is a much more advanced version of the cosmological argument than the other versions we ve seen. Not only is it more structurally complex, but it recognizes the distinction between necessary and contingent beings and avoids the assumption that there can t be an infinite causal chain. It does, however, make another assumption to which some thinkers object. The Principle of Sufficient Reason states that there must be a reason, or an explanation, for every contingent fact. As you can see, this drives the cosmological argument, appearing in Premise 5 and again more problematically - in Premise 8. But is this principle true? In particular, must something be responsible for the totality of existence, if that totality, as hypothesized in Premise 8, extends infinitely into the past? Couldn t this infinite causal chain just happen to be, without explanation or reason? I suspect that your attitude toward the cosmological argument will be a function of your attitude toward the Principle of Sufficient Reason. If you accept the Principle of Sufficient Reason then you ll be inclined to conclude that there must be some ultimate cause of existence and you ll be driven to postulate some necessary being (although claim that this necessary being is God will need some fleshing out). If you don t accept the Principle of Sufficient Reason, on the other hand, then you won t feel compelled to postulate a necessary being or an ultimate cause of existence.

14 4 So, what s more the more rational stance? Should we accept the Principle of Sufficient Reason or should we reject it? It seems to me as though rational people can fall on both sides of this issue. Some rational people will accept the Principle of Sufficient Reason and so endorse the cosmological argument. Other rational people will reject the Principle of Sufficient Reason and the cosmological argument along with it. And this might go a long way toward explaining why rational individuals can be found in both the theist and atheist camps. Of course, the debate continues. Philosophers question whether or not all versions of the cosmological argument need to invoke the Principle of Sufficient Reason. They distinguish between different versions of that principle, and argue for and against the acceptance of any particular version. We re leaving our discussion of the cosmological argument here, but the discussion goes on without us as people advance arguments and criticize them, respond to the criticisms and object to the responses, on and on, indefinitely. No word in philosophy is ever the final word. The key is to find a place that makes sense to you and to be content to rest there for the moment.

15 5 Summary of the Cosmological Argument An Elementary Version of the Cosmological Argument Everything was caused by something else that happened before it and so either there s an infinite causal chain extending backwards or there s a first cause, something that wasn t caused by anything else but that started everything else. There can t be an infinite causal chain extending backwards, though, which means that there must be first cause, something that wasn t caused by anything else but which started everything else. Therefore, God exists.. God exists. 2. Everything was caused by something else that happened before it. 3. Either there s an infinite causal chain extending backwards or there s a first cause, something that wasn t caused by anything else but that started everything else. 4. There can t be an infinite causal chain extending backwards. 5. There s a first cause, something that wasn t caused by anything else but that started everything else. 2 A B 5 C A Problem with the Elementary Version of the Cosmological Argument: If we think that something caused God then we re off on an infinite regress, rejecting premise 4. If we think that nothing caused God then we re denying premise 2. An Intermediate Version of the Cosmological Argument Every contingent being was caused by something else that happened before it and so either there s an infinite causal chain of contingent beings extending backwards or there s a first cause, some necessary being that wasn t caused by anything else but that started everything else. There can t be an infinite causal chain of contingent beings extending backwards, though, which means that there must be first cause, something that wasn t caused by anything else but which started everything else. Therefore, God exists.

16 6. God exists. 2. Every contingent being was caused by something else that happened before it. (Note: Contingent beings are beings that wouldn t have to have existed.) 3. Either there s an infinite causal chain of contingent beings extending backwards or there s a first cause, some necessary being that wasn t caused by anything else but that started everything else. (Note: A necessary being is a being that couldn t possibly fail to exist.) 4. There can t be an infinite causal chain of contingent beings extending backwards. 5. There s a first cause, some necessary being that wasn t caused by anything else but that started everything else. 2 A B 5 C Aquinas s argument in defense of Premise 4:. The causal chain behind everything we experience can t go back to infinity. 2. In a causal chain, the first cause causes the second, and so on, until you get the final effect in this case everything in existence now. 3. To take away the cause is to prevent the effect. 4. If there were no first cause, then the first cause would be taken away, the second cause wouldn t exist, and so on, and there wouldn t be anything in existence now. 5. If the causal chain were infinite, there would be no first cause. 6. If the causal chain were infinite, there would be nothing in existence now. 7. But there are things in existence now! A B C A Problem with Aquinas s Argument: It equivocates on no first cause. Premise 4 talks about there being no first cause because the cause has been removed. Premise 5 talks about there being no first cause because there is an infinite series of causes. Those are different

17 7 ways to have no first cause so premises 4 and 5 can t work together. This undermines inference B. A Problem with the Intermediate Version of the Cosmological Argument: We lack a reason to think that can t be an infinite causal chain of contingent beings extending backwards. An Advanced Version of the Cosmological Argument Clearly contingent things have causes, so we re faced with a causal chain going backwards in time. Either this causal chain doesn t go backwards forever, or it does. What are the consequences of each possibility? On the one hand, if the causal chain doesn t go backwards forever then there s a first cause, and this cause, not requiring a cause itself, must be a necessary being. Consequently, if the causal chain doesn t go backwards forever then there must be a necessary being. On the other hand, if the causal chain does go backwards forever, we can consider the entirety of the causal chain itself and ask ourselves why it exists. What is responsible for the existence of this infinite causal chain? Surely something is responsible for its existence, and whatever is responsible for the existence of the chain can t be a contingent being because all contingent beings are in the chain and nothing that s in the chain can be responsible for the existence of the chain. It follows that whatever is responsible for the existence of the chain must be a necessary being and so if the causal chain does go backwards forever then a necessary being must exist. Whether or not the chain of contingent being extends infinitely back, then, a necessary being must exist. It s reasonable to suppose that this necessary being is God, so God exists.. God exits. 2. Contingent things have causes. 3. We re faced with a causal chain going backwards in time. 4. Either this causal chain doesn t go backwards forever or it does go backwards forever. 5. If the causal chain doesn t go backwards forever then there s a first cause. 6. This first cause, not requiring a cause itself, must be a necessary being. 7. If the causal chain doesn t go backwards forever then there must be a necessary being. 8. If the causal chain does go backwards forever then something is responsible for its existence. 9. Whatever is responsible for the existence of the chain can t be a contingent being. 0. All contingent beings are in the chain.. Nothing that s in the chain can be responsible for the existence of the chain. 2. Whatever is responsible for the existence of the chain must be a necessary being.

18 8 3. If the causal chain does go backwards forever then a necessary being must exist. 4. Whether or not the chain of contingent being extends infinitely back, then, a necessary being must exist. 5. It s reasonable to suppose that this necessary being is God. 0 + C D A B E F G A Problem with the Advanced Version of the Cosmological Argument: A rational person could deny the Principle of Sufficient Reason, which says that there must be a reason, or explanation, for every contingent fact. This would allow that person to reject premise 8.

Cosmological Arguments

Cosmological Arguments Cosmological Arguments Cosmology: u Study of the origins of the Universe u Why is there something rather than nothing? u Where did everything come from? u Where did the stars come from? u Aquinas: u If

More information

Summer Preparation Work

Summer Preparation Work 2017 Summer Preparation Work Philosophy of Religion Theme 1 Arguments for the existence of God Instructions: Philosophy of Religion - Arguments for the existence of God The Cosmological Argument 1. Watch

More information

Cosmological arguments for the Existence of God Gerald Jones Dialogue Issue 26 April 2006

Cosmological arguments for the Existence of God Gerald Jones Dialogue Issue 26 April 2006 Cosmological arguments for the Existence of God Gerald Jones Dialogue Issue 26 April 2006 In its most basic form, a cosmological argument attempts to understand and answer the question 'Why is there a

More information

Cosmological Arguments

Cosmological Arguments Cosmological Arguments Arguments that God exists: Review Ontological: the existence of God follows from the very concept of God. exp: Anselm s Ontological Argument This is the only a priori argument for

More information

Aquinas Cosmological argument in everyday language

Aquinas Cosmological argument in everyday language Aquinas Cosmological argument in everyday language P1. If there is no first cause, there cannot be any effects. P2. But we have observed that there are effects, like observing change in the world. C: So

More information

The cosmological argument (continued)

The cosmological argument (continued) The cosmological argument (continued) Remember that last time we arrived at the following interpretation of Aquinas second way: Aquinas 2nd way 1. At least one thing has been caused to come into existence.

More information

Today we begin our discussion of the existence of God.

Today we begin our discussion of the existence of God. Aquinas Five Ways Today we begin our discussion of the existence of God. The main philosophical problem about the existence of God can be put like this: is it possible to provide good arguments either

More information

Lecture 4.2 Aquinas Phil Religion TOPIC: Aquinas Cosmological Arguments for the existence of God. Critiques of Aquinas arguments.

Lecture 4.2 Aquinas Phil Religion TOPIC: Aquinas Cosmological Arguments for the existence of God. Critiques of Aquinas arguments. TOPIC: Lecture 4.2 Aquinas Phil Religion Aquinas Cosmological Arguments for the existence of God. Critiques of Aquinas arguments. KEY TERMS/ GOALS: Cosmological argument. The problem of Infinite Regress.

More information

Critical Thinking. The Four Big Steps. First example. I. Recognizing Arguments. The Nature of Basics

Critical Thinking. The Four Big Steps. First example. I. Recognizing Arguments. The Nature of Basics Critical Thinking The Very Basics (at least as I see them) Dona Warren Department of Philosophy The University of Wisconsin Stevens Point What You ll Learn Here I. How to recognize arguments II. How to

More information

Scholasticism In the 1100s, scholars and monks rediscovered the ancient Greek texts that had been lost for so long. Scholasticism was a revival of

Scholasticism In the 1100s, scholars and monks rediscovered the ancient Greek texts that had been lost for so long. Scholasticism was a revival of Scholasticism In the 1100s, scholars and monks rediscovered the ancient Greek texts that had been lost for so long. Scholasticism was a revival of the ancient methods of logic and reasoning applied to

More information

CHAPTER 9 DIAGRAMMING DEBATES. What You ll Learn in this Chapter

CHAPTER 9 DIAGRAMMING DEBATES. What You ll Learn in this Chapter 1 CHAPTER 9 DIAGRAMMING DEBATES What You ll Learn in this Chapter So far, we ve learned how to analyze and evaluate arguments as they stand alone. Frequently, however, arguments are interrelated, with

More information

Simplicity and Why the Universe Exists

Simplicity and Why the Universe Exists Simplicity and Why the Universe Exists QUENTIN SMITH I If big bang cosmology is true, then the universe began to exist about 15 billion years ago with a 'big bang', an explosion of matter, energy and space

More information

The Five Ways THOMAS AQUINAS ( ) Thomas Aquinas: The five Ways

The Five Ways THOMAS AQUINAS ( ) Thomas Aquinas: The five Ways The Five Ways THOMAS AQUINAS (1225-1274) Aquinas was an Italian theologian and philosopher who spent his life in the Dominican Order, teaching and writing. His writings set forth in a systematic form a

More information

ARTICLE PRESENTATION, EXAMPLE 2: AQUINAS PHI 101: INTRODUCTION TO PHILOSOPHY DR. DAVE YOUNT

ARTICLE PRESENTATION, EXAMPLE 2: AQUINAS PHI 101: INTRODUCTION TO PHILOSOPHY DR. DAVE YOUNT ARTICLE PRESENTATION, EXAMPLE 2: AQUINAS PHI 101: INTRODUCTION TO PHILOSOPHY DR. DAVE YOUNT 1. BEARINGS/BIO: Briefly describe the assigned philosopher/author and state the name of the assigned material

More information

The Existence of God

The Existence of God The Existence of God The meaning of the words theist, atheist and agnostic Atheist- person who does not believe in God. Theist- Person who does believe in God Agnostic- Person who does not know if God

More information

A Short Course in Logic Example 3

A Short Course in Logic Example 3 A Short Course in Logic Example 3 I) Recognizing Arguments III) Evaluating Arguments II) Analyzing Arguments Bad Argument: Bad Inference Identifying the Parts of the Argument Premises Inferences Diagramming

More information

HANDBOOK (New or substantially modified material appears in boxes.)

HANDBOOK (New or substantially modified material appears in boxes.) 1 HANDBOOK (New or substantially modified material appears in boxes.) I. ARGUMENT RECOGNITION Important Concepts An argument is a unit of reasoning that attempts to prove that a certain idea is true by

More information

A Compatibilist Account of Free Will and Moral Responsibility

A Compatibilist Account of Free Will and Moral Responsibility A Compatibilist Account of Free Will and Moral Responsibility If Frankfurt is right, he has shown that moral responsibility is compatible with the denial of PAP, but he hasn t yet given us a detailed account

More information

Aquinas' Third Way Modalized

Aquinas' Third Way Modalized Philosophy of Religion Aquinas' Third Way Modalized Robert E. Maydole Davidson College bomaydole@davidson.edu ABSTRACT: The Third Way is the most interesting and insightful of Aquinas' five arguments for

More information

A R G U M E N T S I N A C T I O N

A R G U M E N T S I N A C T I O N ARGUMENTS IN ACTION Descriptions: creates a textual/verbal account of what something is, was, or could be (shape, size, colour, etc.) Used to give you or your audience a mental picture of the world around

More information

Baha i Proofs for the Existence of God

Baha i Proofs for the Existence of God Page 1 Baha i Proofs for the Existence of God Ian Kluge to show that belief in God can be rational and logically coherent and is not necessarily a product of uncritical religious dogmatism or ignorance.

More information

Review of Constructive Empiricism: Epistemology and the Philosophy of Science

Review of Constructive Empiricism: Epistemology and the Philosophy of Science Review of Constructive Empiricism: Epistemology and the Philosophy of Science Constructive Empiricism (CE) quickly became famous for its immunity from the most devastating criticisms that brought down

More information

HANDBOOK (New or substantially modified material appears in boxes.)

HANDBOOK (New or substantially modified material appears in boxes.) 1 HANDBOOK (New or substantially modified material appears in boxes.) I. ARGUMENT RECOGNITION Important Concepts An argument is a unit of reasoning that attempts to prove that a certain idea is true by

More information

Aquinas s Third Way Keith Burgess-Jackson 24 September 2017

Aquinas s Third Way Keith Burgess-Jackson 24 September 2017 Aquinas s Third Way Keith Burgess-Jackson 24 September 2017 Cosmology, a branch of astronomy (or astrophysics), is The study of the origin and structure of the universe. 1 Thus, a thing is cosmological

More information

Five Ways to Prove the Existence of God. From Summa Theologica. St. Thomas Aquinas

Five Ways to Prove the Existence of God. From Summa Theologica. St. Thomas Aquinas Five Ways to Prove the Existence of God From Summa Theologica St. Thomas Aquinas Thomas Aquinas (1225 1274), born near Naples, was the most influential philosopher of the medieval period. He joined the

More information

THEISM AND BELIEF. Etymological note: deus = God in Latin; theos = God in Greek.

THEISM AND BELIEF. Etymological note: deus = God in Latin; theos = God in Greek. THEISM AND BELIEF Etymological note: deus = God in Latin; theos = God in Greek. A taxonomy of doxastic attitudes Belief: a mental state the content of which is taken as true or an assertion put forward

More information

HANDBOOK. IV. Argument Construction Determine the Ultimate Conclusion Construct the Chain of Reasoning Communicate the Argument 13

HANDBOOK. IV. Argument Construction Determine the Ultimate Conclusion Construct the Chain of Reasoning Communicate the Argument 13 1 HANDBOOK TABLE OF CONTENTS I. Argument Recognition 2 II. Argument Analysis 3 1. Identify Important Ideas 3 2. Identify Argumentative Role of These Ideas 4 3. Identify Inferences 5 4. Reconstruct the

More information

By J. Alexander Rutherford. Part one sets the roles, relationships, and begins the discussion with a consideration

By J. Alexander Rutherford. Part one sets the roles, relationships, and begins the discussion with a consideration An Outline of David Hume s Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion An outline of David Hume s Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion By J. Alexander Rutherford I. Introduction Part one sets the roles, relationships,

More information

Cosmological Arguments: A Cause for the Cosmos. 1. arguments offer reasons to believe that the cosmos depends on something itself. (p.207 k.

Cosmological Arguments: A Cause for the Cosmos. 1. arguments offer reasons to believe that the cosmos depends on something itself. (p.207 k. 1. arguments offer reasons to believe that the cosmos depends on something itself. (p.207 k.2234) 2. What has been referred to as the fundamental philosophical question? (p.207 k.2238) 3. What is one common

More information

Avicenna, Proof of the Necessary of Existence

Avicenna, Proof of the Necessary of Existence Why is there something rather than nothing? Leibniz Avicenna, Proof of the Necessary of Existence Avicenna offers a proof for the existence of God based on the nature of possibility and necessity. First,

More information

New Chapter: Philosophy of Religion

New Chapter: Philosophy of Religion Intro to Philosophy Phil 110 Lecture 3: 1-16 Daniel Kelly I. Mechanics A. Upcoming Readings 1. Today we ll discuss a. Aquinas s The Summa Theologica (The Cosmological Argument) b. Anselm, Proslogium (The

More information

Explaining causal loops

Explaining causal loops EXPLAINING CAUSAL LOOPS 259 Schaffer, J. 2010. Monism: the priority of the whole. Philosophical Review 119: 31 76. Sider, T. 2007. Parthood. Philosophical Review 116: 51 91. Tillman, C. 2011. Musical Materialism.

More information

The Principle of Sufficient Reason and Free Will

The Principle of Sufficient Reason and Free Will Stance Volume 3 April 2010 The Principle of Sufficient Reason and Free Will ABSTRACT: I examine Leibniz s version of the Principle of Sufficient Reason with respect to free will, paying particular attention

More information

Critique of Cosmological Argument

Critique of Cosmological Argument David Hume: Critique of Cosmological Argument Critique of Cosmological Argument DAVID HUME (1711-1776) David Hume is one of the most important philosophers in the history of philosophy. Born in Edinburgh,

More information

How Not to Defend Metaphysical Realism (Southwestern Philosophical Review, Vol , 19-27)

How Not to Defend Metaphysical Realism (Southwestern Philosophical Review, Vol , 19-27) How Not to Defend Metaphysical Realism (Southwestern Philosophical Review, Vol 3 1986, 19-27) John Collier Department of Philosophy Rice University November 21, 1986 Putnam's writings on realism(1) have

More information

5 A Modal Version of the

5 A Modal Version of the 5 A Modal Version of the Ontological Argument E. J. L O W E Moreland, J. P.; Sweis, Khaldoun A.; Meister, Chad V., Jul 01, 2013, Debating Christian Theism The original version of the ontological argument

More information

BOOK REVIEW: Gideon Yaffee, Manifest Activity: Thomas Reid s Theory of Action

BOOK REVIEW: Gideon Yaffee, Manifest Activity: Thomas Reid s Theory of Action University of Nebraska - Lincoln DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln Faculty Publications - Department of Philosophy Philosophy, Department of 2005 BOOK REVIEW: Gideon Yaffee, Manifest Activity:

More information

The Grand Design and the Kalam Cosmological Argument. The Book

The Grand Design and the Kalam Cosmological Argument. The Book The Grand Design and the Kalam Cosmological Argument Edwin Chong CFN, October 13, 2010 The Book Stephen Hawking and Leonard Mlodinow, The Grand Design, Bantam, 2010. Interest to Christians: Widely discussed

More information

The Five Ways of St. Thomas in proving the existence of

The Five Ways of St. Thomas in proving the existence of The Language of Analogy in the Five Ways of St. Thomas Aquinas Moses Aaron T. Angeles, Ph.D. San Beda College The Five Ways of St. Thomas in proving the existence of God is, needless to say, a most important

More information

PHI 1700: Global Ethics

PHI 1700: Global Ethics PHI 1700: Global Ethics Session 3 February 11th, 2016 Harman, Ethics and Observation 1 (finishing up our All About Arguments discussion) A common theme linking many of the fallacies we covered is that

More information

St. Thomas Aquinas Excerpt from Summa Theologica

St. Thomas Aquinas Excerpt from Summa Theologica St. Thomas Aquinas Excerpt from Summa Theologica Part 1, Question 2, Articles 1-3 The Existence of God Because the chief aim of sacred doctrine is to teach the knowledge of God, not only as He is in Himself,

More information

The Rationality of Religious Beliefs

The Rationality of Religious Beliefs The Rationality of Religious Beliefs Bryan Frances Think, 14 (2015), 109-117 Abstract: Many highly educated people think religious belief is irrational and unscientific. If you ask a philosopher, however,

More information

Monday, September 26, The Cosmological Argument

Monday, September 26, The Cosmological Argument The Cosmological Argument God? Classical Theism Classical conception of God: God is Eternal: everlasting Omnipotent: all-powerful Transcendent: beyond the world Omnipresent: everywhere Compassionate:

More information

On Some Alleged Consequences Of The Hartle-Hawking Cosmology. In [3], Quentin Smith claims that the Hartle-Hawking cosmology is inconsistent with

On Some Alleged Consequences Of The Hartle-Hawking Cosmology. In [3], Quentin Smith claims that the Hartle-Hawking cosmology is inconsistent with On Some Alleged Consequences Of The Hartle-Hawking Cosmology In [3], Quentin Smith claims that the Hartle-Hawking cosmology is inconsistent with classical theism in a way which redounds to the discredit

More information

What God Could Have Made

What God Could Have Made 1 What God Could Have Made By Heimir Geirsson and Michael Losonsky I. Introduction Atheists have argued that if there is a God who is omnipotent, omniscient and omnibenevolent, then God would have made

More information

Helpful Hints for doing Philosophy Papers (Spring 2000)

Helpful Hints for doing Philosophy Papers (Spring 2000) Helpful Hints for doing Philosophy Papers (Spring 2000) (1) The standard sort of philosophy paper is what is called an explicative/critical paper. It consists of four parts: (i) an introduction (usually

More information

Does God Exist? Understanding arguments for the existence of God. HZT4U1 February

Does God Exist? Understanding arguments for the existence of God. HZT4U1 February Does God Exist? Understanding arguments for the existence of God HZT4U1 February 19 2016 The Ontological Argument for the existence Ontological : of God The Ontological Argument for the existence of God

More information

A level Religious Studies at Titus Salt

A level Religious Studies at Titus Salt Component 2 Philosophy of Religion Theme 1: Arguments for the existence of God inductive This theme considers how the philosophy of religion has, over time, influenced and been influenced by developments

More information

Ethics Demonstrated in Geometrical Order

Ethics Demonstrated in Geometrical Order Ethics Demonstrated in Geometrical Order Benedict Spinoza Copyright Jonathan Bennett 2017. All rights reserved [Brackets] enclose editorial explanations. Small dots enclose material that has been added,

More information

-1 Peter 3:15-16 (NSRV)

-1 Peter 3:15-16 (NSRV) Defending Your Faith with Reason and Precision 3. Why does anything at all exist? 4. Why did the universe begin? 5. Why is the universe fine-tuned for life? Sunday, February 24, 2013, 10 to 10:50 am, in

More information

spring 05 topics in philosophy of mind session 7

spring 05 topics in philosophy of mind session 7 24.500 spring 05 topics in philosophy of mind session 7 teatime self-knowledge 24.500 S05 1 plan self-blindness, one more time Peacocke & Co. immunity to error through misidentification: Shoemaker s self-reference

More information

Ultimate Naturalistic Causal Explanations

Ultimate Naturalistic Causal Explanations Ultimate Naturalistic Causal Explanations There are various kinds of questions that might be asked by those in search of ultimate explanations. Why is there anything at all? Why is there something rather

More information

Why Christians should not use the Kalaam argument. David Snoke University of Pittsburgh

Why Christians should not use the Kalaam argument. David Snoke University of Pittsburgh Why Christians should not use the Kalaam argument David Snoke University of Pittsburgh I ve heard all kinds of well-meaning and well-educated Christian apologists use variations of the Kalaam argument

More information

The Cosmological Argument

The Cosmological Argument The Cosmological Argument Stage I 1. Causal Premise: Everything of type T has a cause. [note: cause purpose]. 2. Something of type T exists. 3. There is a reason X for thinking that there is a First Cause

More information

Objections to Descartes s Meditations, and his Replies

Objections to Descartes s Meditations, and his Replies 1 Copyright Jonathan Bennett [Brackets] enclose editorial explanations. Small dots enclose material that has been added, but can be read as though it were part of the original text. Occasional bullets,

More information

CRITICAL THINKING: THE VERY BASICS - HANDBOOK

CRITICAL THINKING: THE VERY BASICS - HANDBOOK 1 CRITICAL THINKING: THE VERY BASICS - HANDBOOK Dona Warren, Philosophy Department, The University of Wisconsin Stevens Point I. RECOGNIZING ARGUMENTS An argument is a unit of reasoning that attempts to

More information

The Kalam Cosmological Argument

The Kalam Cosmological Argument The Kalam Cosmological Argument Abstract We show that the Kalam Cosmological Argument as proposed by William Lane Craig is not capable of being analysed without further re-interpretation because his terms

More information

Van Fraassen: Arguments Concerning Scientific Realism

Van Fraassen: Arguments Concerning Scientific Realism Aaron Leung Philosophy 290-5 Week 11 Handout Van Fraassen: Arguments Concerning Scientific Realism 1. Scientific Realism and Constructive Empiricism What is scientific realism? According to van Fraassen,

More information

Wk 10Y5 Existence of God 2 - October 26, 2018

Wk 10Y5 Existence of God 2 - October 26, 2018 1 2 3 4 5 The Existence of God (2) Module: Philosophy Lesson 10 Some Recommended Resources Reasonable Faith, by William Lane Craig. pp. 91-204 To Everyone an Answer, by Beckwith, Craig, and Moreland. pp.

More information

Christian Apologetics The Classical Arguments

Christian Apologetics The Classical Arguments I. Introduction to the Classical Arguments A. Classical Apologetics Christian Apologetics The Classical Arguments Lecture II September 24, 2015 1. An approach to apologetics based upon attempted deductive

More information

5 Cosmological Arguments

5 Cosmological Arguments 5 Cosmological Arguments THE rejection of Berkeley's form of theism entails that if a god is to be introduced at all, it must be as a supplement to the material world, not as a substitute for it. The rejection

More information

The Existence of God. G. Brady Lenardos

The Existence of God. G. Brady Lenardos Page 1 of 16 The Existence of God By G. Brady Lenardos (c) 1995, 2000 G. Brady Lenardos In August of 1993, my friend, Jeff McCain, and I participated in a debate at the Orange County Regional Gathering

More information

1/6. The Resolution of the Antinomies

1/6. The Resolution of the Antinomies 1/6 The Resolution of the Antinomies Kant provides us with the resolutions of the antinomies in order, starting with the first and ending with the fourth. The first antinomy, as we recall, concerned the

More information

Proof of the Necessary of Existence

Proof of the Necessary of Existence Proof of the Necessary of Existence by Avicenna (Ibn Sīnā), various excerpts (~1020-1037 AD) *** The Long Version from Kitab al-najat (The Book of Salvation), second treatise (~1020 AD) translated by Jon

More information

Noncognitivism in Ethics, by Mark Schroeder. London: Routledge, 251 pp.

Noncognitivism in Ethics, by Mark Schroeder. London: Routledge, 251 pp. Noncognitivism in Ethics, by Mark Schroeder. London: Routledge, 251 pp. Noncognitivism in Ethics is Mark Schroeder s third book in four years. That is very impressive. What is even more impressive is that

More information

the negative reason existential fallacy

the negative reason existential fallacy Mark Schroeder University of Southern California May 21, 2007 the negative reason existential fallacy 1 There is a very common form of argument in moral philosophy nowadays, and it goes like this: P1 It

More information

MPS 17 The Structure of Persuasion Logos: reasoning, reasons, good reasons not necessarily about formal logic

MPS 17 The Structure of Persuasion Logos: reasoning, reasons, good reasons not necessarily about formal logic MPS 17 The Structure of Persuasion Logos: reasoning, reasons, good reasons not necessarily about formal logic Making and Refuting Arguments Steps of an Argument You make a claim The conclusion of your

More information

Chapter 5: Freedom and Determinism

Chapter 5: Freedom and Determinism Chapter 5: Freedom and Determinism Let me state at the outset a basic point that will reappear again below with its justification. The title of this chapter (and many other discussions too) make it appear

More information

Note: This is the penultimate draft of an article the final and definitive version of which is

Note: This is the penultimate draft of an article the final and definitive version of which is The Flicker of Freedom: A Reply to Stump Note: This is the penultimate draft of an article the final and definitive version of which is scheduled to appear in an upcoming issue The Journal of Ethics. That

More information

Philosophy is dead. Thus speaks Stephen Hawking, the bestknown

Philosophy is dead. Thus speaks Stephen Hawking, the bestknown 26 Dominicana Summer 2012 THE SCIENCE BEYOND SCIENCE Humbert Kilanowski, O.P. Philosophy is dead. Thus speaks Stephen Hawking, the bestknown physicist of the contemporary age and author of A Brief History

More information

What Must There be to Account for Being?

What Must There be to Account for Being? The University of Akron IdeaExchange@UAkron Honors Research Projects The Dr. Gary B. and Pamela S. Williams Honors College Spring 2016 What Must There be to Account for Being? Dillon T. McCrea University

More information

On The Existence of God Thomas Aquinas

On The Existence of God Thomas Aquinas On The Existence of God Thomas Aquinas Art 1: Whether the Existence of God is Self-Evident? Objection 1. It seems that the existence of God is self-evident. Now those things are said to be self-evident

More information

Chapter 5: Freedom and Determinism

Chapter 5: Freedom and Determinism Chapter 5: Freedom and Determinism At each time t the world is perfectly determinate in all detail. - Let us grant this for the sake of argument. We might want to re-visit this perfectly reasonable assumption

More information

The St. Petersburg paradox & the two envelope paradox

The St. Petersburg paradox & the two envelope paradox The St. Petersburg paradox & the two envelope paradox Consider the following bet: The St. Petersburg I am going to flip a fair coin until it comes up heads. If the first time it comes up heads is on the

More information

Critical Thinking 5.7 Validity in inductive, conductive, and abductive arguments

Critical Thinking 5.7 Validity in inductive, conductive, and abductive arguments 5.7 Validity in inductive, conductive, and abductive arguments REMEMBER as explained in an earlier section formal language is used for expressing relations in abstract form, based on clear and unambiguous

More information

2017 Philosophy. Higher. Finalised Marking Instructions

2017 Philosophy. Higher. Finalised Marking Instructions National Qualifications 07 07 Philosophy Higher Finalised Marking Instructions Scottish Qualifications Authority 07 The information in this publication may be reproduced to support SQA qualifications only

More information

The Divine Nature. from Summa Theologiae (Part I, Questions 3-11) by Thomas Aquinas (~1265 AD) translated by Brian J.

The Divine Nature. from Summa Theologiae (Part I, Questions 3-11) by Thomas Aquinas (~1265 AD) translated by Brian J. The Divine Nature from Summa Theologiae (Part I, Questions 3-11) by Thomas Aquinas (~1265 AD) translated by Brian J. Shanley (2006) Question 3. Divine Simplicity Once it is grasped that something exists,

More information

Philosophical Perspectives, 16, Language and Mind, 2002 THE AIM OF BELIEF 1. Ralph Wedgwood Merton College, Oxford

Philosophical Perspectives, 16, Language and Mind, 2002 THE AIM OF BELIEF 1. Ralph Wedgwood Merton College, Oxford Philosophical Perspectives, 16, Language and Mind, 2002 THE AIM OF BELIEF 1 Ralph Wedgwood Merton College, Oxford 0. Introduction It is often claimed that beliefs aim at the truth. Indeed, this claim has

More information

The Cosmological Argument

The Cosmological Argument The Cosmological Argument The Cosmological Argument is an argument that attempts to demonstrate the existence of God using only one starting assumption: Something exists. 1. Three sorts of being: Whatever

More information

Comments on Leibniz and Pantheism by Robert Adams for The Twelfth Annual NYU Conference on Issues in Modern Philosophy: God

Comments on Leibniz and Pantheism by Robert Adams for The Twelfth Annual NYU Conference on Issues in Modern Philosophy: God Comments on Leibniz and Pantheism by Robert Adams for The Twelfth Annual NYU Conference on Issues in Modern Philosophy: God Jeffrey McDonough jkmcdon@fas.harvard.edu Professor Adams s paper on Leibniz

More information

CONSCIOUSNESS, INTENTIONALITY AND CONCEPTS: REPLY TO NELKIN

CONSCIOUSNESS, INTENTIONALITY AND CONCEPTS: REPLY TO NELKIN ----------------------------------------------------------------- PSYCHE: AN INTERDISCIPLINARY JOURNAL OF RESEARCH ON CONSCIOUSNESS ----------------------------------------------------------------- CONSCIOUSNESS,

More information

Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000)

Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000) Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000) One of the advantages traditionally claimed for direct realist theories of perception over indirect realist theories is that the

More information

The Nature of Death. chapter 8. What Is Death?

The Nature of Death. chapter 8. What Is Death? chapter 8 The Nature of Death What Is Death? According to the physicalist, a person is just a body that is functioning in the right way, a body capable of thinking and feeling and communicating, loving

More information

BEGINNINGLESS PAST AND ENDLESS FUTURE: REPLY TO CRAIG. Wes Morriston. In a recent paper, I claimed that if a familiar line of argument against

BEGINNINGLESS PAST AND ENDLESS FUTURE: REPLY TO CRAIG. Wes Morriston. In a recent paper, I claimed that if a familiar line of argument against Forthcoming in Faith and Philosophy BEGINNINGLESS PAST AND ENDLESS FUTURE: REPLY TO CRAIG Wes Morriston In a recent paper, I claimed that if a familiar line of argument against the possibility of a beginningless

More information

Fr. Copleston vs. Bertrand Russell: The Famous 1948 BBC Radio Debate on the Existence of God

Fr. Copleston vs. Bertrand Russell: The Famous 1948 BBC Radio Debate on the Existence of God Fr. Copleston vs. Bertrand Russell: The Famous 1948 BBC Radio Debate on the Existence of God Father Frederick C. Copleston (Jesuit Catholic priest) versus Bertrand Russell (agnostic philosopher) Copleston:

More information

Epistemological Foundations for Koons Cosmological Argument?

Epistemological Foundations for Koons Cosmological Argument? Epistemological Foundations for Koons Cosmological Argument? Koons (2008) argues for the very surprising conclusion that any exception to the principle of general causation [i.e., the principle that everything

More information

Stout s teleological theory of action

Stout s teleological theory of action Stout s teleological theory of action Jeff Speaks November 26, 2004 1 The possibility of externalist explanations of action................ 2 1.1 The distinction between externalist and internalist explanations

More information

A Short Course in Logic Answers to Practice

A Short Course in Logic Answers to Practice A Short Course in Logic Answers to Practice Logic is a skill and, like any skill, it s improved with practice. I) Analyzing Arguments Sometimes it can be difficult to identify the ultimate conclusion of

More information

Ethics Demonstrated in Geometrical Order

Ethics Demonstrated in Geometrical Order 1 Copyright Jonathan Bennett [Brackets] enclose editorial explanations. Small dots enclose material that has been added, but can be read as though it were part of the original text. Occasional bullets,

More information

LTJ 27 2 [Start of recorded material] Interviewer: From the University of Leicester in the United Kingdom. This is Glenn Fulcher with the very first

LTJ 27 2 [Start of recorded material] Interviewer: From the University of Leicester in the United Kingdom. This is Glenn Fulcher with the very first LTJ 27 2 [Start of recorded material] Interviewer: From the University of Leicester in the United Kingdom. This is Glenn Fulcher with the very first issue of Language Testing Bytes. In this first Language

More information

RECONSIDERING THE NECESSARY BEINGS OF AQUINAS S THIRD WAY

RECONSIDERING THE NECESSARY BEINGS OF AQUINAS S THIRD WAY RECONSIDERING THE NECESSARY BEINGS OF AQUINAS S THIRD WAY GREGORY J. ROBSON Duke University Abstract. Surprisingly few articles have focused on Aquinas s particular conception of necessary beings in the

More information

Philosophy Epistemology. Topic 3 - Skepticism

Philosophy Epistemology. Topic 3 - Skepticism Michael Huemer on Skepticism Philosophy 3340 - Epistemology Topic 3 - Skepticism Chapter II. The Lure of Radical Skepticism 1. Mike Huemer defines radical skepticism as follows: Philosophical skeptics

More information

Ontological Argument page 2

Ontological Argument page 2 ONTOLOGICAL ARGUMENT (A harbour-side café somewhere in the Peloponnese; Anna Kalypsas is sitting at a table outside a café with Theo Sevvis, and they re joined by Anna s students, Mel Etitis and Kathy

More information

One of the many common questions that are asked is If God does exist what reasons

One of the many common questions that are asked is If God does exist what reasons 1 of 10 2010-09-01 11:16 How Do We Know God is One? A Theological & Philosophical Perspective Hamza Andreas Tzortzis 6/7/2010 124 views One of the many common questions that are asked is If God does exist

More information

Philosophy of Religion. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

Philosophy of Religion. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology Philosophy of Religion Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology Philosophical Theology 1 (TH5) Aug. 15 Intro to Philosophical Theology; Logic Aug. 22 Truth & Epistemology Aug. 29 Metaphysics

More information

WHAT ARISTOTLE TAUGHT

WHAT ARISTOTLE TAUGHT WHAT ARISTOTLE TAUGHT Aristotle was, perhaps, the greatest original thinker who ever lived. Historian H J A Sire has put the issue well: All other thinkers have begun with a theory and sought to fit reality

More information

What is the Frege/Russell Analysis of Quantification? Scott Soames

What is the Frege/Russell Analysis of Quantification? Scott Soames What is the Frege/Russell Analysis of Quantification? Scott Soames The Frege-Russell analysis of quantification was a fundamental advance in semantics and philosophical logic. Abstracting away from details

More information

Bradley on Chance, Admissibility & the Mind of God

Bradley on Chance, Admissibility & the Mind of God Bradley on Chance, Admissibility & the Mind of God Alastair Wilson University of Birmingham & Monash University a.j.wilson@bham.ac.uk 15 th October 2013 Abstract: Darren Bradley s recent reply (Bradley

More information

THE GOD OF QUARKS & CROSS. bridging the cultural divide between people of faith and people of science

THE GOD OF QUARKS & CROSS. bridging the cultural divide between people of faith and people of science THE GOD OF QUARKS & CROSS bridging the cultural divide between people of faith and people of science WHY A WORKSHOP ON FAITH AND SCIENCE? The cultural divide between people of faith and people of science*

More information

Non-evidential believing and permissivism about evidence: A reply to Dan-Johan Eklund

Non-evidential believing and permissivism about evidence: A reply to Dan-Johan Eklund Non-evidential believing and permissivism about evidence: A reply to Dan-Johan Eklund JOSHUA COCKAYNE Department of Philosophy, University of York, York, YO10 5DD, UK jlc513@york.ac.uk DAVID EFIRD Department

More information