Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy Volume 3, Number 2

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy Volume 3, Number 2"

Transcription

1 Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy Volume 3, Number 2 Editor in Chief Sandra Lapointe, McMaster University Jolen Galaugher. Russell s Philosophy of Logical Analysis: Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, xii $110 Hardcover. ISBN Reviewed by Kevin C. Klement Editorial Board Gary Ebbs, Indiana University Bloomington Greg Frost-Arnold, Hobart and William Smith Colleges Henry Jackman, York University Kevin C. Klement, University of Massachusetts Lydia Patton, Virginia Tech Marcus Rossberg, University of Connecticut Mark Textor, King s College London Richard Zach, University of Calgary Audrey Yap, University of Victoria Review Editors Juliet Floyd, Boston University Chris Pincock, Ohio State University Assistant Review Editor Sean Morris, Metropolitan State University of Denver Editorial Assistant Daniel Harris, Hunter College 2015 Kevin C. Klement

2 Review: Russell s Philosophy of Logical Analysis , by Jolen Galaugher Kevin C. Klement Palgrave s History of Analytic Philosophy series has lately been releasing important books in Bertrand Russell studies at a pace that makes it seem as though it were making up for lost time. The series editor, Michael Beaney, has recently in another context identified the early 1990s as the period when serious historical scholarship on analytic philosophy finally began in earnest (Beaney, 2013, p. 54). Two groundbreaking works from that period, by Hylton (1990) and Griffin (1991), reminded us of Russell s academic beginnings in the British Idealist tradition. Since then, important studies on the development of Russell s technical philosophical and mathematical logic during the first decade of the 20th century have also emerged, such as Landini (1998) and Makin (2000). One of the newest contributions from Palgrave s series, Galaugher s fascinating Russell s Philosophy of Logical Analysis: , serves as a bridge connecting these different areas of Russellian scholarship. She traces themes in Russell s work that have their origins during his idealist period but which remained prominent through his early logicist period. These include identity and difference (and thus plurality), the analysis of complexity, the nature of relations, judgments and meaning. Her study makes it clear that while Russell s views were in a state of constant flux, many interests and concerns remained constant. His transition from idealism to realism was not a simple matter of turning his back on what had come before, but can perhaps be better understood as involving a series of steps of fine tuning and improving upon a single overarching approach to logical analysis. Galaugher sets the stage in the first chapter with a discussion of Russell s abandonment of British Idealism. Russell himself later claimed that Moore led the way in this regard (Russell, 1958, p. 54), and Galaugher presents a nice summary of Moore s (1899) influential criticisms of Bradley s theory of judgment. As important as Moore s influence was on early Russell, Galaugher makes it clear that we must not consider that influence in isolation. Noting differences between Russell s eventual realist position and Moore s, Galaugher also considers Russell s transition in the light of tensions within his early philosophical views on the foundations of mathematics. In works such as his 1897 An Essay on the Foundation of Geometry, Russell had hoped to support the axioms of geometry using Kantian-style transcendental deductions. However, he wished to give an account of the synthetic a priori that made it a logical notion rather than a psychological one. This led Russell away from thinking in terms of the preconditions of our knowledge of geometric truths, and toward thinking instead of the logical features a system of relations must have in order for a geometry characterized by certain axioms to be relevant to it. The views on relations Russell held during this period, and in particular the version of the doctrine of internal relations according to which all relations depend on qualities of the relata or the relation itself, generated certain paradoxes of relativity when applied in mathematical contexts. Different geometrical points, for example, seem indistinguishable in their intrinsic qualities but nonetheless are distinguishable through their relations to one another. Galaugher also discusses the influence of Whitehead s Universal Algebra in bringing Russell to adopt a broader conception of the scope of mathematics. Finally, there are the relatively well-known difficulties Russell discussed in The Principles of Mathematics (chap. XXVI) with accommodating asymmetrical relations within a framework accepting the doctrine of internal relations. These various developments came to a head for Russell when he was working on his 1899 lectures on Leibniz (the basis for Russell, 1900). Russell attributed (perhaps wrongly) a similar view of relations to Leibniz and diagnoses problems as he sees them with Leibniz s views as stemming from this position. It was through a confluence Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy, vol. 3 no. 2 [1]

3 of these forces, according to Galaugher, that Russell came to abandon his neo-hegelian idealism in favor of the precise form of analytic realism that marked his early logicist period. The importance of Russell s work on Leibniz for his evolving views on relations is given an even more detailed examination in Galaugher s second chapter. There she examines the complex relationships between the view attributed by Russell to Leibniz that all predication involves analyzing a substance or, perhaps, the concept thereof into constituent predicates, the identity of indiscernibles, and the contention that all relations are intelligible things brought about by the mind in some way. Those familiar with Russell s work on Leibniz are no doubt well aware of Russell s dissatisfaction with Leibniz s strict adherence to subject/predicate analyses of propositions, and his contention that it prevented Leibniz from giving adequate philosophical accounts of such notions and space and time. Galaugher argues that these complaints with Leibniz brought Russell to reject broadly similar commitments within his own form of idealism. In particular, Russell came to abandon the principle of identity of indiscernibles as interpreted to mean that all difference between things is grounded in difference of concepts applicable to them. Instead, Russell came to regard mere numerical diversity as logically prior to difference in predicates, and presupposed by all relational judgments. This took Russell a step further away from the idealist monists of his day, and indeed, a step further than Moore had taken by this point. Early on in his realist phase, Moore continued to regard a thing, or even a concept, as a whole of its properties (concepts), and maintained that the relation between a whole and its parts was internal. Russell, however, took the radical step of holding all propositions to be relational, and all relations to be external, differentiating a thing from the sum of its qualities. Along with this, Russell began to see the basic logical relationships also as relational and synthetic, and thus distinct from part/whole relationships. This development culminated and was reinforced when he adopted Peano s symbolic logic as a replacement for the more limited Boolean logic of containment relationships between classes. Galaugher also stresses the importance of Russell s adopting an intensional view of relations, and one on which an asymmetrical relation is differentiated from its converse. It wasn t entirely clear to me how Galaugher understood the relationship between these two features of Russell s evolving views. Galaugher suggests, in both Chapters II and III, that early Russell believed that differentiating an asymmetrical relation from its converse, or equivalently, capturing the sense of an asymmetrical relation, requires an intensional view of relations. It was not clear to me why this should be. At least in contemporary parlance, the relations less than and greater than are not co-extensive, and thus they may be differentiated even on a fully extensional view of relations. A philosophical argument might be given to the effect that the extensions of these relations, considered, say, as sets of ordered pairs, can only be held different if we can account for the difference between such pairs as 3, 5 and 5, 3, and that doing so somehow requires intensional relations. However, there s nothing I know in Galaugher s exposition, or even in Russell s writings of the period, to suggest an argument along these lines. In Chapter III, Galaugher discusses Russell s emerging logicist views in the period, the importance of Russell s adoption of Peano s symbolic logic, and his discovery of the logical paradoxes such as the antinomy now known as Russell s paradox. She enters into the debates regarding whether or not Russell s logicism in the Principles of Mathematics should be regarded as having an if-then -ist or conditional form, differentiating her interpretation from those of Putnam (1975), Coffa (1981), Griffin (1982), Proops (2006), and Gandon (2011). Coffa interprets Russell s logicist treatment of geometry as taking the form of logically true conditionals from the axioms of a given geometry to the theorems. This sort of interpretation threatens to trivialize the logicist project, as the relationship between the axioms and theorems of any theory can always be understood as purely logical. Galaugher Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy, vol. 3 no. 2 [2]

4 makes note of a response by Griffin stressing that the conditionals in Russell s logicism are better understood not as representing relationships between axioms and theorems, but rather as universally quantified statements making use of unrestricted variables where the antecedents and consequents state categorical conditions for the values of the variables to satisfy. Galaugher argues for a more nuanced position according to which Russell held a position aligning with Coffa s interpretation early on (in, e.g., the 1900 drafts of Principles), but one more in tune with Griffin s interpretation from mid-1901 onwards after fully integrating Peano s logic. Along with this change came a new attitude about the analysis of mathematical notions and definitions of mathematical terms. Russell no longer held that an analysis of a mathematical notion must preserve the intensional aspects of our pre-analytic understanding of the notion. Instead, he held that one may make use of any nominal definition preserving the formal features of the original notion. Russell became increasingly prone to giving nominal definitions making use of classes defined using purely logical propositional functions, making a fully logicist analysis of mathematical notions possible. The chapter concludes with a discussion of Russell s changing views on logic. Russell did not take over Peano s logic uncritically. Russell was dissatisfied with Peano s extensional treatment of relations and sought to supplement it with his own intensional theory. He also criticized Peano s logic for failing clearly to distinguish between a proposition and a propositional function. The latter notion emerged from Russell s consideration of the Peanist notions of formal implication (implication for all values of a variable) and class abstraction. Galaugher goes on to discuss Russell s discovery of the various versions of Russell s paradox, noting that the earliest manuscript in which it can be found gives a version stated in terms of predicates or class concepts not predicable of themselves. Galaugher stresses, quite rightly, that one of the most important lessons Russell drew from the paradox early on was that not every propositional function corresponds to a classconcept. Unfortunately, I think there are at least two ways in which Galaugher s discussion of these issues is not as clear as it might have been. Galaugher does not distinguish, as I think Russell does, between the claim that the functional part of a propositional function is not an independent entity (Principles, p. 88) from the simpler claim that the function itself is not an independent entity. As a result, it is a bit difficult to understand what Galaugher believes Russell s position in Principles was regarding the independent reality of propositional functions. Secondly, in contrasting Russell s reaction to the paradoxes to Frege s, Galaugher claims that Frege was not bothered by an intensional version of the paradox (p. 110). By this, she seems to mean that Frege s theory of levels of functions and concepts blocked the version involving a function not satisfied by itself, or a concept not falling under itself. But it is misleading to describe this as an intensional version, however, as Frege held an extensional view of both functions and concepts. For example, Frege claims that concepts coincide when the same objects fall under them. 1 Recall that concepts are the references of predicates for Frege. Intensional versions for Frege would be ones involving his notion of sense. Apart from some inconclusive discussion of a paradox of thoughts in his correspondence with Russell (Frege, 1980, pp ), Frege did not consider intensional versions. Moreover, it is even misleading to suggest that Frege s theory of levels avoids a function or concept version of the paradox. Given that Frege identifies the extension of a concept with the value-range of the concept considered as a function, and holds that the extension of a concept has its being in the concept (Frege, 1906, p. 183), arguably Frege considers the extension of a concept simply to be the concept considered as a logical subject. 2 If this is right, then it is not possible to differentiate the classes (or extensions) version of the paradox in Frege s logic from one involving a concept taking itself-qua-logical-subject as argument. Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy, vol. 3 no. 2 [3]

5 The fourth chapter compares Russell s logicist views with those of Frege, particularly with regard to their nominal definitions of numbers as classes (or extensions) of classes of likecardinality, and the relative priority of propositional and nonpropositional (or mathematical ) functions. Galaugher believes that the widespread claim that Russell independently rediscovered Frege s definition of number is too simplistic, and cites what she sees as non-negligible differences between their accounts of number. Ultimately, the differences stem from wider disagreements over the nature of propositions, intensional relations, functions and classes. Galaugher notes that Russell complained that Frege had failed to give a full account of how classes are to be understood as entities, having only equated them with extensions or value-ranges of functions obeying his problematic Basic Law V. Galaugher goes on to discuss Russell s own rapidly changing views on classes and their relationships to functions in the period. In so doing, she draws heavily upon Russell s very interesting correspondence with Couturat, which has not yet been published in English. There we find both praise of and frustration over Frege s more mathematical notion of a function. Galaugher nicely traces Russell s 1903 adoption of a view which eschewed classes altogether in favor of functions, various views of 1904 in which Russell sought to discover conditions under which some but not all functions determine classes, and Russell s eventual adoption after the theory of descriptions of 1905 of a substitutional theory according to which classes, relations in extension, and even propositional functions are all treated as mere façons de parler. In the final full chapter, Galaugher takes up the relationship between, on one hand, Russell s attempts to understand propositions involving functions and variables, and on the other, his views on meaning and denotation, culminating in his landmark On Denoting of Galaugher notes a similarity between the difficulty Russell pointed to in On Denoting concerning disambiguating between propositions about denoting concepts and propositions about their denotations, and an earlier puzzle about differentiating between what Russell had called a propositional concept in Principles, e.g., the death of Caesar, and the proposition it represents in our example, Caesar died. In his 1904 work on Meinong, Russell was led to the view that the difference could not be maintained. Galaugher also explores in some detail Russell s dissatisfaction with how his earlier theory of denoting handled non-propositional denoting functions, such as the father of x. The issue was important for Russell s treatment of mathematics, as most mathematical functions, e.g., the sine of x, the sum of x and y are of this type. Russell vacillated during the period between the view he held both earlier and later that propositional functions are more fundamental than others, and the more Fregean view that all functions can be treated uniformly. The issues involved are quite complicated. It is impossible here to provide more than a crude summary even of Galaugher s exploration, much less Russell s. However, there are at least two sources of worry. One involves whether or not Russell can provide a coherent account of aboutness when denoting functions are involved. The father of Russell was a political activist appears to be about Russell. Notice here Russell only occurs as argument to a denoting function, and thus as a part of the denoting complex the father of Russell. Yet, according to the theory of denoting concepts, the proposition is not at all about this complex or its parts, but only about what it denotes. Another worry involves Russell s attempts to do away with functions, both propositional and denoting, as distinct entities separable from their values. While at some points Russell was willing to consider the view that functions were separable from their values, at others he took denying this to be a promising route for solving functional versions of Russell s paradox. The hope was to replace the notion of the values of a function with the notion of different results of substitution within a complex. However, if p is a proposition containing a denoting complex such as the father of Russell, does p! represent the! Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy, vol. 3 no. 2 [4]

6 result of replacing y with x y even where y occurs only in the meanings in p, or just within the denotations of those meanings? It proved difficult to answer this and related questions coherently, while at the same time providing a uniform means for differentiating between complex meanings and their possibly complex denotations. Such complications were sidestepped by Russell s mature theory of descriptions which replaced denoting functions with descriptions to be interpreted within the scope of a greater propositional context. The book ends with a short concluding postscript in which Galaugher summarizes the development of Russell s views on logical analysis in the years covered. There are some puzzling claims made here that seemed out of sorts with claims made in the body of the book. It is unclear whether these were mere infelicities of expression, or indicative of a deeper misunderstanding. For example, Galaugher writes (p. 176): While Russell initially subscribed to a naïve comprehension principle on which every predicate or class-concept determines some class, the contradiction of predicates not predicable of themselves and class concepts not members of their own extensions led him to reject this principle... However, what the body of the book had argued (p. 107), and what in fact Russell concluded from these versions of the paradox, was that not every class has a defining predicate or class-concept. This is not the same as the claim that not every predicate or classconcept defines a class. To my knowledge, Russell continued to maintain that every class-concept or (simple) predicate defines a class, even when denying that every class is so defined. He also, separately from this (I think), abandoned the (naïve abstractionist) view that every propositional function defines a class, but as Russell did not equate predicates or class concepts with propositional functions, this would not require him to give up the view quoted above. Similarly, Galaugher writes (p. 175): While Russell initially held that relations in intension are to identified with class concepts (PoM, p. 514), he came to hold that class concepts are marked by intensional propositional functions. If Galaugher had argued that Russell at one time held that relations in intension were class concepts in the body of the book, I missed it. As far as I know, Russell never held such a view. Class concepts are monadic qualities of individuals; to equate relations with class concepts would seem to amount to the adoption of an extreme form of the doctrine of internal relations. She cites p. 514 of Principles, but I cannot find anything relevant on that page. Moreover, I do not know what it is for class concepts to be marked by propositional functions, nor how that view would be contrary to the view previously held. I suspect, however, that these remarks and similar remarks in the summary section of the book are simply sloppily worded, and that Galaugher meant something different by them than what I have understood. Indeed, it is possible that some of my concerns over passages in earlier chapters are the result of misunderstandings brought on by otherwise minor infelicities of expression. Overall, Galaugher s prose is dense, and I think it is fair to say that it is quite demanding on the reader. The topics are many and varied. In the space of a few pages, Galaugher moves between such difficult topics as Leibniz s theory of monads, Bradley s views on relations, the differences between projective and metric geometries and logicist theories of cardinal number. Her writing assumes that the reader has at least a basic understanding of all these topics. Unfortunately, not everyone is the sort of polyglot Russell himself was. While this may limit the book s audience, it is not meant as a criticism. Only by delving into so many issues is Galaugher able to draw connections usually unnoticed between diverse areas of Russell s thought, which is one of the chief merits of Galaugher s work. Two such contributions stand out as particularly valuable. Firstly, there is Galaugher s excellent discussion in the first two chapters about the importance of Russell s confronta- Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy, vol. 3 no. 2 [5]

7 tion with Leibniz for understanding both his abandonment of idealism and his newly emerging views on relations and propositional analysis. Secondly, Galaugher s discussion, especially in the fifth chapter, makes it abundantly clear that the secondary literature so far has underestimated the connection between Russell s work on the theory of descriptions and his greater logicist project. These two contributions will, I predict, make a lasting impact on Russell studies and Galaugher s book would be worth a read for them alone. However, for the reader up to the challenge, the book offers many additional insights into the development of Russell s philosophy as well. Kevin C. Klement University of Massachusetts Amherst klement@philos.umass.edu Notes 1 See Frege (1979a, p. 122). There are other places as well in which Galaugher seems to attribute to Frege an intensional view of functions. For example, she claims that Frege is committed to taking the identity relation to be a relation in intension in order to solve the belief puzzles (p. 120). It is unclear to me what she means by this, or how she reaches this conclusion. The received (and probably correct) interpretation of Frege is that the cognitive difference between a = b and a = a stems from the differing senses of a and b which contribute to the sense of (i.e., thought expressed by) the whole equations. This view does not require him to take the references of a and b to be different when flanking =, nor to insist that = refer to some kind of intensional relation, or relation between intensions. 2 For discussion, see Cocchiarella (1987, chap. 2) and Klement (2012, sec. 4). Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy, vol. 3 no. 2 [6]

8 References Beaney, Michael, ed., The Oxford Handbook of the History of Analytic Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Cocchiarella, Nino, Logical Studies in Early Analytic Philosophy. Columbus: Ohio State University Press. Coffa, J. Alberto, Russell and Kant. Synthese 46: Frege, Gottlob, On Schoenflies: Die logischen Paradoxien der Mengenlehre. In Frege (1979b), pp ,. 1979a. Comments on Sense and Meaning. In Frege (1979b), pp b. Posthumous Writings. Chicago: University of Chicago Press Philosophical and Mathematical Correspondence. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Gandon, Sébastien, Logicism and Mathematical Practices Russell s Theory of Metrical Geometry in The Principles of Mathematics (1903). In Analytic Philosophy and the Foundations of Mathematics. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan. Griffin, Nicholas, New Work on Russell s Early Philosophy. Russell 2: Klement, Kevin C., Frege s Changing Conception of Number. Theoria 78: Landini, Gregory, Russell s Hidden Substitutional Theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Makin, Gideon, The Metaphysicians of Meaning: Russell and Frege on Sense and Denotation. London: Routledge. Moore, G. E., The Nature of Judgment. Mind 8: Proops, Ian, Russell s Reasons for Logicism. Journal of the History of Philosophy 44: Putnam, Hilary, The Thesis that Mathematics Is Logic. In Philosophical Papers, vol. 1, Mathematics, Matter and Method- Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Russell, Bertrand, An Essay on the Foundations of Geometry. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press A Critical Exposition of the Philosophy of Leibniz. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press The Principles of Mathematics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2nd ed My Philosophical Development. London: Allen and Unwin Russell s Idealist Apprenticeship. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Hylton, Peter, Russell, Idealism and the Emergence of Analytic Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy, vol. 3 no. 2 [7]

Mathematics in and behind Russell s logicism, and its

Mathematics in and behind Russell s logicism, and its The Cambridge companion to Bertrand Russell, edited by Nicholas Griffin, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, UK and New York, US, xvii + 550 pp. therein: Ivor Grattan-Guinness. reception. Pp. 51 83.

More information

[3.] Bertrand Russell. 1

[3.] Bertrand Russell. 1 [3.] Bertrand Russell. 1 [3.1.] Biographical Background. 1872: born in the city of Trellech, in the county of Monmouthshire, now part of Wales 2 One of his grandfathers was Lord John Russell, who twice

More information

Articles THE ORIGINS OF THE PROPOSITIONAL FUNCTIONS VERSION OF RUSSELL S PARADOX. Philosophy / U. of Massachusetts

Articles THE ORIGINS OF THE PROPOSITIONAL FUNCTIONS VERSION OF RUSSELL S PARADOX. Philosophy / U. of Massachusetts Articles THE ORIGINS OF THE PROPOSITIONAL FUNCTIONS VERSION OF RUSSELL S PARADOX KEVIN C. KLEMENT Philosophy / U. of Massachusetts Amherst, MA 01003, USA KLEMENT@PHILOS.UMASS.EDU Russell discovered the

More information

^rticles SUBSTITUTION S UNSOLVED INSOLUBILIA. J. B Galaugher Philosophy / U. of Iowa Iowa City, ia , usa.

^rticles SUBSTITUTION S UNSOLVED INSOLUBILIA. J. B Galaugher Philosophy / U. of Iowa Iowa City, ia , usa. ^rticles SUBSTITUTION S UNSOLVED INSOLUBILIA J. B Galaugher Philosophy / U. of Iowa Iowa City, ia 52242 1408, usa jolenb1@gmail.com Russell s substitutional theory conferred philosophical advantages over

More information

Bertrand Russell Proper Names, Adjectives and Verbs 1

Bertrand Russell Proper Names, Adjectives and Verbs 1 Bertrand Russell Proper Names, Adjectives and Verbs 1 Analysis 46 Philosophical grammar can shed light on philosophical questions. Grammatical differences can be used as a source of discovery and a guide

More information

Foundations of Analytic Philosophy

Foundations of Analytic Philosophy Foundations of Analytic Philosophy Foundations of Analytic Philosophy (2016-7) Mark Textor Lecture Plan: We will look at the ideas of Frege, Russell and Wittgenstein and the relations between them. Frege

More information

PHILOSOPHY OF LOGIC AND LANGUAGE OVERVIEW FREGE JONNY MCINTOSH 1. FREGE'S CONCEPTION OF LOGIC

PHILOSOPHY OF LOGIC AND LANGUAGE OVERVIEW FREGE JONNY MCINTOSH 1. FREGE'S CONCEPTION OF LOGIC PHILOSOPHY OF LOGIC AND LANGUAGE JONNY MCINTOSH 1. FREGE'S CONCEPTION OF LOGIC OVERVIEW These lectures cover material for paper 108, Philosophy of Logic and Language. They will focus on issues in philosophy

More information

Philosophy of Mathematics Kant

Philosophy of Mathematics Kant Philosophy of Mathematics Kant Owen Griffiths oeg21@cam.ac.uk St John s College, Cambridge 20/10/15 Immanuel Kant Born in 1724 in Königsberg, Prussia. Enrolled at the University of Königsberg in 1740 and

More information

Kevin C. Klement Curriculum Vitæ

Kevin C. Klement Curriculum Vitæ Kevin C. Klement Curriculum Vitæ Research and teaching interests University of Massachusetts Amherst Philosophy Dept., E305 South College 150 Hicks Way, Amherst, MA 01003 USA klement@philos.umass.edu http://people.umass.edu/klement/

More information

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras Module - 28 Lecture - 28 Linguistic turn in British philosophy

More information

Reviews WITTGENSTEIN, CRITIC OF RUSSELL. Russell Wahl. English and Philosophy / Idaho State U Pocatello, id 83209, usa

Reviews WITTGENSTEIN, CRITIC OF RUSSELL. Russell Wahl. English and Philosophy / Idaho State U Pocatello, id 83209, usa Reviews WITTGENSTEIN, CRITIC OF RUSSELL Russell Wahl English and Philosophy / Idaho State U Pocatello, id 83209, usa wahlruss@isu.edu Jérôme Sackur. Formes et faits: Analyse et théorie de la connaissance

More information

Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy

Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy Volume7,Number1 Editor in Chief Marcus Rossberg, University of Connecticut Editorial Board Annalisa Coliva, UC Irvine Henry Jackman, York University Kevin

More information

Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy Volume 3, Number 1

Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy Volume 3, Number 1 Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy Volume 3, Number 1 Editor in Chief Sandra Lapointe, McMaster University Kevin Mulligan, Katarzyna Kijania-Placek and Tomasz Placek, The History and Philosophy

More information

Twentieth-Century Analytic Philosophy by Avrum Stroll

Twentieth-Century Analytic Philosophy by Avrum Stroll Twentieth-Century Analytic Philosophy by Avrum Stroll Columbia University Press: New York, 2000. 302pp, Hardcover, $32.50. Brad Majors University of Kansas The history of analytic philosophy is a troubled

More information

^rticles THREE UNPUBLISHED MANUSCRIPTS FROM 1903

^rticles THREE UNPUBLISHED MANUSCRIPTS FROM 1903 ^rticles THREE UNPUBLISHED MANUSCRIPTS FROM 1903 Kevin C. Klement Philosophy / U. Massachusetts Amherst Amherst, ma 01003, usa klement@philos.umass.edu I present and discuss three previously unpublished

More information

Russell on Denoting. G. J. Mattey. Fall, 2005 / Philosophy 156. The concept any finite number is not odd, nor is it even.

Russell on Denoting. G. J. Mattey. Fall, 2005 / Philosophy 156. The concept any finite number is not odd, nor is it even. Russell on Denoting G. J. Mattey Fall, 2005 / Philosophy 156 Denoting in The Principles of Mathematics This notion [denoting] lies at the bottom (I think) of all theories of substance, of the subject-predicate

More information

Remarks on the philosophy of mathematics (1969) Paul Bernays

Remarks on the philosophy of mathematics (1969) Paul Bernays Bernays Project: Text No. 26 Remarks on the philosophy of mathematics (1969) Paul Bernays (Bemerkungen zur Philosophie der Mathematik) Translation by: Dirk Schlimm Comments: With corrections by Charles

More information

356 THE MONIST all Cretans were liars. It can be put more simply in the form: if a man makes the statement I am lying, is he lying or not? If he is, t

356 THE MONIST all Cretans were liars. It can be put more simply in the form: if a man makes the statement I am lying, is he lying or not? If he is, t 356 THE MONIST all Cretans were liars. It can be put more simply in the form: if a man makes the statement I am lying, is he lying or not? If he is, that is what he said he was doing, so he is speaking

More information

Russell: On Denoting

Russell: On Denoting Russell: On Denoting DENOTING PHRASES Russell includes all kinds of quantified subject phrases ( a man, every man, some man etc.) but his main interest is in definite descriptions: the present King of

More information

Theories of propositions

Theories of propositions Theories of propositions phil 93515 Jeff Speaks January 16, 2007 1 Commitment to propositions.......................... 1 2 A Fregean theory of reference.......................... 2 3 Three theories of

More information

Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy Volume 3, Number 9

Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy Volume 3, Number 9 Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy Volume 3, Number 9 Editor in Chief Kevin C. Klement, University of Massachusetts Editorial Board Gary Ebbs, Indiana University Bloomington Greg Frost-Arnold,

More information

How Do We Know Anything about Mathematics? - A Defence of Platonism

How Do We Know Anything about Mathematics? - A Defence of Platonism How Do We Know Anything about Mathematics? - A Defence of Platonism Majda Trobok University of Rijeka original scientific paper UDK: 141.131 1:51 510.21 ABSTRACT In this paper I will try to say something

More information

PHILOSOPHICAL PROBLEMS & THE ANALYSIS OF LANGUAGE

PHILOSOPHICAL PROBLEMS & THE ANALYSIS OF LANGUAGE PHILOSOPHICAL PROBLEMS & THE ANALYSIS OF LANGUAGE Now, it is a defect of [natural] languages that expressions are possible within them, which, in their grammatical form, seemingly determined to designate

More information

The Collected Papers of Bertrand Russell, Vol. 4, Foundations of Logic: , ed. by Alsdair Urquhard (London: Routledge, 1994).

The Collected Papers of Bertrand Russell, Vol. 4, Foundations of Logic: , ed. by Alsdair Urquhard (London: Routledge, 1994). A. Works by Russell The Collected Papers of Bertrand Russell, Vol. 4, Foundations of Logic: 1903-1905, ed. by Alsdair Urquhard (London: Routledge, 1994). The Collected Papers of Bertrand Russell, Vol.

More information

Department of Philosophy

Department of Philosophy Department of Philosophy Module descriptions 2018/19 Level I (i.e. normally 2 nd Yr.) Modules Please be aware that all modules are subject to availability. If you have any questions about the modules,

More information

15. Russell on definite descriptions

15. Russell on definite descriptions 15. Russell on definite descriptions Martín Abreu Zavaleta July 30, 2015 Russell was another top logician and philosopher of his time. Like Frege, Russell got interested in denotational expressions as

More information

This is a longer version of the review that appeared in Philosophical Quarterly Vol. 47 (1997)

This is a longer version of the review that appeared in Philosophical Quarterly Vol. 47 (1997) This is a longer version of the review that appeared in Philosophical Quarterly Vol. 47 (1997) Frege by Anthony Kenny (Penguin, 1995. Pp. xi + 223) Frege s Theory of Sense and Reference by Wolfgang Carl

More information

The Theory of Reality: A Critical & Philosophical Elaboration

The Theory of Reality: A Critical & Philosophical Elaboration 55 The Theory of Reality: A Critical & Philosophical Elaboration Anup Kumar Department of Philosophy Jagannath University Email: anupkumarjnup@gmail.com Abstract Reality is a concept of things which really

More information

What is the Frege/Russell Analysis of Quantification? Scott Soames

What is the Frege/Russell Analysis of Quantification? Scott Soames What is the Frege/Russell Analysis of Quantification? Scott Soames The Frege-Russell analysis of quantification was a fundamental advance in semantics and philosophical logic. Abstracting away from details

More information

Russell s Problems of Philosophy

Russell s Problems of Philosophy Russell s Problems of Philosophy UNIVERSALS & OUR KNOWLEDGE OF THEM F e b r u a r y 2 Today : 1. Review A Priori Knowledge 2. The Case for Universals 3. Universals to the Rescue! 4. On Philosophy Essays

More information

The Metaphysics of Logical Atomism

The Metaphysics of Logical Atomism The Metaphysics of Logical Atomism Bernard Linsky May 12, 2000 Bertrand Russell made use of logic as an analytical tool from the start of his philosophical career and early on adopted a metaphysics that

More information

The Paradox of the stone and two concepts of omnipotence

The Paradox of the stone and two concepts of omnipotence Filo Sofija Nr 30 (2015/3), s. 239-246 ISSN 1642-3267 Jacek Wojtysiak John Paul II Catholic University of Lublin The Paradox of the stone and two concepts of omnipotence Introduction The history of science

More information

Philosophical Issues, vol. 8 (1997), pp

Philosophical Issues, vol. 8 (1997), pp Philosophical Issues, vol. 8 (1997), pp. 313-323. Different Kinds of Kind Terms: A Reply to Sosa and Kim 1 by Geoffrey Sayre-McCord University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill In "'Good' on Twin Earth"

More information

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction Kent State University BIBLID [0873-626X (2014) 39; pp. 139-145] Abstract The causal theory of reference (CTR) provides a well-articulated and widely-accepted account

More information

Resemblance Nominalism and counterparts

Resemblance Nominalism and counterparts ANAL63-3 4/15/2003 2:40 PM Page 221 Resemblance Nominalism and counterparts Alexander Bird 1. Introduction In his (2002) Gonzalo Rodriguez-Pereyra provides a powerful articulation of the claim that Resemblance

More information

Philosophical Logic. LECTURE SEVEN MICHAELMAS 2017 Dr Maarten Steenhagen

Philosophical Logic. LECTURE SEVEN MICHAELMAS 2017 Dr Maarten Steenhagen Philosophical Logic LECTURE SEVEN MICHAELMAS 2017 Dr Maarten Steenhagen ms2416@cam.ac.uk Last week Lecture 1: Necessity, Analyticity, and the A Priori Lecture 2: Reference, Description, and Rigid Designation

More information

Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy

Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy Volume 1, Number 2 Editor in Chief Mark Textor, King s College London Editorial Board Juliet Floyd, Boston University Greg Frost-Arnold, Hobart and William

More information

Soames on the Metaphysics and Epistemology of Moore and Russell

Soames on the Metaphysics and Epistemology of Moore and Russell Soames on the Metaphysics and Epistemology of Moore and Russell A contribution to a forthcoming Philosophical Studies book symposium on Scott Soames s Philosophical Analysis in the Twentieth Century: Volume

More information

Tools for Logical Analysis. Roger Bishop Jones

Tools for Logical Analysis. Roger Bishop Jones Tools for Logical Analysis Roger Bishop Jones Started 2011-02-10 Last Change Date: 2011/02/12 09:14:19 http://www.rbjones.com/rbjpub/www/papers/p015.pdf Draft Id: p015.tex,v 1.2 2011/02/12 09:14:19 rbj

More information

On the Rationality of Metaphysical Commitments in Immature Science

On the Rationality of Metaphysical Commitments in Immature Science On the Rationality of Metaphysical Commitments in Immature Science ALEXANDER KLEIN, CORNELL UNIVERSITY Kuhn famously claimed that like jigsaw puzzles, paradigms include rules that limit both the nature

More information

Reply to Florio and Shapiro

Reply to Florio and Shapiro Reply to Florio and Shapiro Abstract Florio and Shapiro take issue with an argument in Hierarchies for the conclusion that the set theoretic hierarchy is open-ended. Here we clarify and reinforce the argument

More information

PHI2391: Logical Empiricism I 8.0

PHI2391: Logical Empiricism I 8.0 1 2 3 4 5 PHI2391: Logical Empiricism I 8.0 Hume and Kant! Remember Hume s question:! Are we rationally justified in inferring causes from experimental observations?! Kant s answer: we can give a transcendental

More information

From Transcendental Logic to Transcendental Deduction

From Transcendental Logic to Transcendental Deduction From Transcendental Logic to Transcendental Deduction Let me see if I can say a few things to re-cap our first discussion of the Transcendental Logic, and help you get a foothold for what follows. Kant

More information

The real problem behind Russell s paradox

The real problem behind Russell s paradox The real problem behind Russell s paradox Student: L.M. Geerdink Student Number: 3250318 Email: leon.geerdink@phil.uu.nl Thesis supervisors: prof. dr. Albert Visser prof. dr. Paul Ziche 1 Küçük Ayıma Adanmış

More information

Truth At a World for Modal Propositions

Truth At a World for Modal Propositions Truth At a World for Modal Propositions 1 Introduction Existentialism is a thesis that concerns the ontological status of individual essences and singular propositions. Let us define an individual essence

More information

Analytic Philosophy IUC Dubrovnik,

Analytic Philosophy IUC Dubrovnik, Analytic Philosophy IUC Dubrovnik, 10.5.-14.5.2010. Debating neo-logicism Majda Trobok University of Rijeka trobok@ffri.hr In this talk I will not address our official topic. Instead I will discuss some

More information

Some Good and Some Not so Good Arguments for Necessary Laws. William Russell Payne Ph.D.

Some Good and Some Not so Good Arguments for Necessary Laws. William Russell Payne Ph.D. Some Good and Some Not so Good Arguments for Necessary Laws William Russell Payne Ph.D. The view that properties have their causal powers essentially, which I will here call property essentialism, has

More information

Structuralism in the Philosophy of Mathematics

Structuralism in the Philosophy of Mathematics 1 Synthesis philosophica, vol. 15, fasc.1-2, str. 65-75 ORIGINAL PAPER udc 130.2:16:51 Structuralism in the Philosophy of Mathematics Majda Trobok University of Rijeka Abstract Structuralism in the philosophy

More information

Putnam: Meaning and Reference

Putnam: Meaning and Reference Putnam: Meaning and Reference The Traditional Conception of Meaning combines two assumptions: Meaning and psychology Knowing the meaning (of a word, sentence) is being in a psychological state. Even Frege,

More information

TRUTH-MAKERS AND CONVENTION T

TRUTH-MAKERS AND CONVENTION T TRUTH-MAKERS AND CONVENTION T Jan Woleński Abstract. This papers discuss the place, if any, of Convention T (the condition of material adequacy of the proper definition of truth formulated by Tarski) in

More information

The Development of Laws of Formal Logic of Aristotle

The Development of Laws of Formal Logic of Aristotle This paper is dedicated to my unforgettable friend Boris Isaevich Lamdon. The Development of Laws of Formal Logic of Aristotle The essence of formal logic The aim of every science is to discover the laws

More information

Structural realism and metametaphysics

Structural realism and metametaphysics Structural realism and metametaphysics Ted Sider For Rutgers conference on Structural Realism and Metaphysics of Science, May 2017 Many structural realists have developed that theory in a relatively conservative

More information

Class #14: October 13 Gödel s Platonism

Class #14: October 13 Gödel s Platonism Philosophy 405: Knowledge, Truth and Mathematics Fall 2010 Hamilton College Russell Marcus Class #14: October 13 Gödel s Platonism I. The Continuum Hypothesis and Its Independence The continuum problem

More information

Evaluating Classical Identity and Its Alternatives by Tamoghna Sarkar

Evaluating Classical Identity and Its Alternatives by Tamoghna Sarkar Evaluating Classical Identity and Its Alternatives by Tamoghna Sarkar Western Classical theory of identity encompasses either the concept of identity as introduced in the first-order logic or language

More information

Russell and the Universalist Conception of Logic. Russell is often said to have shared with Frege a distinctively universalist conception

Russell and the Universalist Conception of Logic. Russell is often said to have shared with Frege a distinctively universalist conception Russell and the Universalist Conception of Logic Russell is often said to have shared with Frege a distinctively universalist conception of logic. 1 This supposed feature of his view is commonly taken

More information

Definite Descriptions and the Argument from Inference

Definite Descriptions and the Argument from Inference Philosophia (2014) 42:1099 1109 DOI 10.1007/s11406-014-9519-9 Definite Descriptions and the Argument from Inference Wojciech Rostworowski Received: 20 November 2013 / Revised: 29 January 2014 / Accepted:

More information

Great Philosophers Bertrand Russell Evening lecture series, Department of Philosophy. Dr. Keith Begley 28/11/2017

Great Philosophers Bertrand Russell Evening lecture series, Department of Philosophy. Dr. Keith Begley 28/11/2017 Great Philosophers Bertrand Russell Evening lecture series, Department of Philosophy. Dr. Keith Begley kbegley@tcd.ie 28/11/2017 Overview Early Life Education Logicism Russell s Paradox Theory of Descriptions

More information

Contents EMPIRICISM. Logical Atomism and the beginnings of pluralist empiricism. Recap: Russell s reductionism: from maths to physics

Contents EMPIRICISM. Logical Atomism and the beginnings of pluralist empiricism. Recap: Russell s reductionism: from maths to physics Contents EMPIRICISM PHIL3072, ANU, 2015 Jason Grossman http://empiricism.xeny.net lecture 9: 22 September Recap Bertrand Russell: reductionism in physics Common sense is self-refuting Acquaintance versus

More information

Alan W. Richardson s Carnap s Construction of the World

Alan W. Richardson s Carnap s Construction of the World Alan W. Richardson s Carnap s Construction of the World Gabriella Crocco To cite this version: Gabriella Crocco. Alan W. Richardson s Carnap s Construction of the World. Erkenntnis, Springer Verlag, 2000,

More information

The Ontological Argument for the existence of God. Pedro M. Guimarães Ferreira S.J. PUC-Rio Boston College, July 13th. 2011

The Ontological Argument for the existence of God. Pedro M. Guimarães Ferreira S.J. PUC-Rio Boston College, July 13th. 2011 The Ontological Argument for the existence of God Pedro M. Guimarães Ferreira S.J. PUC-Rio Boston College, July 13th. 2011 The ontological argument (henceforth, O.A.) for the existence of God has a long

More information

1 What is conceptual analysis and what is the problem?

1 What is conceptual analysis and what is the problem? 1 What is conceptual analysis and what is the problem? 1.1 What is conceptual analysis? In this book, I am going to defend the viability of conceptual analysis as a philosophical method. It therefore seems

More information

VI. CEITICAL NOTICES.

VI. CEITICAL NOTICES. VI. CEITICAL NOTICES. Our Knowledge of the External World. By BBBTBAND RUSSELL. Open Court Co. Pp. ix, 245. THIS book Mr. Russell's Lowell Lectures though intentionally somewhat popular in tone, contains

More information

Self-Evidence and A Priori Moral Knowledge

Self-Evidence and A Priori Moral Knowledge Self-Evidence and A Priori Moral Knowledge Colorado State University BIBLID [0873-626X (2012) 33; pp. 459-467] Abstract According to rationalists about moral knowledge, some moral truths are knowable a

More information

Copyright 2015 by KAD International All rights reserved. Published in the Ghana

Copyright 2015 by KAD International All rights reserved. Published in the Ghana Copyright 2015 by KAD International All rights reserved. Published in the Ghana http://kadint.net/our-journal.html The Problem of the Truth of the Counterfactual Conditionals in the Context of Modal Realism

More information

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy Res Cogitans Volume 5 Issue 1 Article 20 6-4-2014 Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy Kevin Harriman Lewis & Clark College Follow this and additional works at: http://commons.pacificu.edu/rescogitans

More information

Kant on the Notion of Being İlhan İnan

Kant on the Notion of Being İlhan İnan Kant on the Notion of Being İlhan İnan Bogazici University, Department of Philosophy In his Critique of Pure Reason Kant attempts to refute Descartes' Ontological Argument for the existence of God by claiming

More information

How Not to Defend Metaphysical Realism (Southwestern Philosophical Review, Vol , 19-27)

How Not to Defend Metaphysical Realism (Southwestern Philosophical Review, Vol , 19-27) How Not to Defend Metaphysical Realism (Southwestern Philosophical Review, Vol 3 1986, 19-27) John Collier Department of Philosophy Rice University November 21, 1986 Putnam's writings on realism(1) have

More information

the aim is to specify the structure of the world in the form of certain basic truths from which all truths can be derived. (xviii)

the aim is to specify the structure of the world in the form of certain basic truths from which all truths can be derived. (xviii) PHIL 5983: Naturalness and Fundamentality Seminar Prof. Funkhouser Spring 2017 Week 8: Chalmers, Constructing the World Notes (Introduction, Chapters 1-2) Introduction * We are introduced to the ideas

More information

Putnam on Methods of Inquiry

Putnam on Methods of Inquiry Putnam on Methods of Inquiry Indiana University, Bloomington Abstract Hilary Putnam s paradigm-changing clarifications of our methods of inquiry in science and everyday life are central to his philosophy.

More information

Comments on Carl Ginet s

Comments on Carl Ginet s 3 Comments on Carl Ginet s Self-Evidence Juan Comesaña* There is much in Ginet s paper to admire. In particular, it is the clearest exposition that I know of a view of the a priori based on the idea that

More information

Soames on the metaphysics and epistemology of Moore and Russell

Soames on the metaphysics and epistemology of Moore and Russell Philos Stud (2006) 129:627 635 DOI 10.1007/s11098-006-0014-4 DISCUSSION Soames on the metaphysics and epistemology of Moore and Russell Ian Proops Accepted: 27 March 2006 Ó Springer Science+Business Media

More information

Conventionalism and the linguistic doctrine of logical truth

Conventionalism and the linguistic doctrine of logical truth 1 Conventionalism and the linguistic doctrine of logical truth 1.1 Introduction Quine s work on analyticity, translation, and reference has sweeping philosophical implications. In his first important philosophical

More information

Department of Philosophy. Module descriptions 20118/19. Level C (i.e. normally 1 st Yr.) Modules

Department of Philosophy. Module descriptions 20118/19. Level C (i.e. normally 1 st Yr.) Modules Department of Philosophy Module descriptions 20118/19 Level C (i.e. normally 1 st Yr.) Modules Please be aware that all modules are subject to availability. If you have any questions about the modules,

More information

Does the Skeptic Win? A Defense of Moore. I. Moorean Methodology. In A Proof of the External World, Moore argues as follows:

Does the Skeptic Win? A Defense of Moore. I. Moorean Methodology. In A Proof of the External World, Moore argues as follows: Does the Skeptic Win? A Defense of Moore I argue that Moore s famous response to the skeptic should be accepted even by the skeptic. My paper has three main stages. First, I will briefly outline G. E.

More information

Logical Foundations of Metaphysics

Logical Foundations of Metaphysics 1 Logical Foundations of Metaphysics IUC - Dubrovnik, Croatia 21-26 May 2007 Hume s Principle and Sortal Concepts Majda Trobok, trobok@ffri.hr 1. Introduction. In this talk I try to evaluate the neo-fregeans

More information

Introduction. I. Proof of the Minor Premise ( All reality is completely intelligible )

Introduction. I. Proof of the Minor Premise ( All reality is completely intelligible ) Philosophical Proof of God: Derived from Principles in Bernard Lonergan s Insight May 2014 Robert J. Spitzer, S.J., Ph.D. Magis Center of Reason and Faith Lonergan s proof may be stated as follows: Introduction

More information

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras Module - 21 Lecture - 21 Kant Forms of sensibility Categories

More information

Russell s Paradox in Appendix B of the Principles of Mathematics: Was Frege s response adequate?

Russell s Paradox in Appendix B of the Principles of Mathematics: Was Frege s response adequate? HISTORY AND PHILOSOPHY OF LOGIC, 22 (2001), 13± 28 Russell s Paradox in Appendix B of the Principles of Mathematics: Was Frege s response adequate? Ke v i n C. Kl e m e n t Department of Philosophy, University

More information

Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods

Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods delineating the scope of deductive reason Roger Bishop Jones Abstract. The scope of deductive reason is considered. First a connection is discussed between the

More information

Russell, Propositional Unity, and the Correspondence Intuition By Anssi Korhonen

Russell, Propositional Unity, and the Correspondence Intuition By Anssi Korhonen Russell, Propositional Unity, and the Correspondence Intuition By Anssi Korhonen ANSSI.KORHONEN@HELSINKI.FI K atarina Perovic, in her contribution to the Fall 2015 issue of the Bulletin, raises intriguing

More information

Kant s Transcendental Exposition of Space and Time in the Transcendental Aesthetic : A Critique

Kant s Transcendental Exposition of Space and Time in the Transcendental Aesthetic : A Critique 34 An International Multidisciplinary Journal, Ethiopia Vol. 10(1), Serial No.40, January, 2016: 34-45 ISSN 1994-9057 (Print) ISSN 2070--0083 (Online) Doi: http://dx.doi.org/10.4314/afrrev.v10i1.4 Kant

More information

Propositional Ontology and Logical Atomism. Francisco Rodríguez-Consuegra

Propositional Ontology and Logical Atomism. Francisco Rodríguez-Consuegra Propositional Ontology and Logical Atomism Francisco Rodríguez-Consuegra Abstract. In the following I will briefly indicate the role of propositional functions in Principia, then point out the way in which

More information

Lecture 3. I argued in the previous lecture for a relationist solution to Frege's puzzle, one which

Lecture 3. I argued in the previous lecture for a relationist solution to Frege's puzzle, one which 1 Lecture 3 I argued in the previous lecture for a relationist solution to Frege's puzzle, one which posits a semantic difference between the pairs of names 'Cicero', 'Cicero' and 'Cicero', 'Tully' even

More information

Timothy Williamson: Modal Logic as Metaphysics Oxford University Press 2013, 464 pages

Timothy Williamson: Modal Logic as Metaphysics Oxford University Press 2013, 464 pages 268 B OOK R EVIEWS R ECENZIE Acknowledgement (Grant ID #15637) This publication was made possible through the support of a grant from the John Templeton Foundation. The opinions expressed in this publication

More information

Kate Moran Brandeis University

Kate Moran Brandeis University On the whole, I am sympathetic to many of Surprenant s arguments that various institutions and practices are conducive to virtue. I tend to be more sceptical about claims about the institutional or empirical

More information

MATHEMATICS ITS FOUNDATIONS AND THEIR IMPLICAT

MATHEMATICS ITS FOUNDATIONS AND THEIR IMPLICAT Syllabus MATHEMATICS ITS FOUNDATIONS AND THEIR IMPLICAT - 15738 Last update 03-02-2014 HU Credits: 2 Degree/Cycle: 1st degree (Bachelor) and 2nd degree (Master) Responsible Department: Academic year: 0

More information

What kind of Intensional Logic do we really want/need?

What kind of Intensional Logic do we really want/need? What kind of Intensional Logic do we really want/need? Toward a Modal Metaphysics Dana S. Scott University Professor Emeritus Carnegie Mellon University Visiting Scholar University of California, Berkeley

More information

Chapter 18 David Hume: Theory of Knowledge

Chapter 18 David Hume: Theory of Knowledge Key Words Chapter 18 David Hume: Theory of Knowledge Empiricism, skepticism, personal identity, necessary connection, causal connection, induction, impressions, ideas. DAVID HUME (1711-76) is one of the

More information

Department of Philosophy. Module descriptions 2017/18. Level C (i.e. normally 1 st Yr.) Modules

Department of Philosophy. Module descriptions 2017/18. Level C (i.e. normally 1 st Yr.) Modules Department of Philosophy Module descriptions 2017/18 Level C (i.e. normally 1 st Yr.) Modules Please be aware that all modules are subject to availability. If you have any questions about the modules,

More information

- We might, now, wonder whether the resulting concept of justification is sufficiently strong. According to BonJour, apparent rational insight is

- We might, now, wonder whether the resulting concept of justification is sufficiently strong. According to BonJour, apparent rational insight is BonJour I PHIL410 BonJour s Moderate Rationalism - BonJour develops and defends a moderate form of Rationalism. - Rationalism, generally (as used here), is the view according to which the primary tool

More information

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW DISCUSSION NOTE BY CAMPBELL BROWN JOURNAL OF ETHICS & SOCIAL PHILOSOPHY DISCUSSION NOTE MAY 2015 URL: WWW.JESP.ORG COPYRIGHT CAMPBELL BROWN 2015 Two Versions of Hume s Law MORAL CONCLUSIONS CANNOT VALIDLY

More information

Semantic Externalism, by Jesper Kallestrup. London: Routledge, 2012, x+271 pages, ISBN (pbk).

Semantic Externalism, by Jesper Kallestrup. London: Routledge, 2012, x+271 pages, ISBN (pbk). 131 are those electrical stimulations, given that they are the ones causing these experiences. So when the experience presents that there is a red, round object causing this very experience, then that

More information

Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy Volume 2, Number 10

Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy Volume 2, Number 10 Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy Volume 2, Number 10 Editor in Chief Sandra Lapointe, McMaster University Mark Textor, Frege on Sense and Reference. London and New York. Routledge, 2011,

More information

Class 33 - November 13 Philosophy Friday #6: Quine and Ontological Commitment Fisher 59-69; Quine, On What There Is

Class 33 - November 13 Philosophy Friday #6: Quine and Ontological Commitment Fisher 59-69; Quine, On What There Is Philosophy 240: Symbolic Logic Fall 2009 Mondays, Wednesdays, Fridays: 9am - 9:50am Hamilton College Russell Marcus rmarcus1@hamilton.edu I. The riddle of non-being Two basic philosophical questions are:

More information

Early Russell on Philosophical Grammar

Early Russell on Philosophical Grammar Early Russell on Philosophical Grammar G. J. Mattey Fall, 2005 / Philosophy 156 Philosophical Grammar The study of grammar, in my opinion, is capable of throwing far more light on philosophical questions

More information

WHAT DOES KRIPKE MEAN BY A PRIORI?

WHAT DOES KRIPKE MEAN BY A PRIORI? Diametros nr 28 (czerwiec 2011): 1-7 WHAT DOES KRIPKE MEAN BY A PRIORI? Pierre Baumann In Naming and Necessity (1980), Kripke stressed the importance of distinguishing three different pairs of notions:

More information

Predict the Behavior. Leonardo Caffo. Propositional Attitudes and Philosophy of Action. University of Milan - Department of Philosophy

Predict the Behavior. Leonardo Caffo. Propositional Attitudes and Philosophy of Action. University of Milan - Department of Philosophy Predict the Behavior Propositional Attitudes and Philosophy of Action Leonardo Caffo University of Milan - Department of Philosophy Personal Adress: Via Conte Rosso, 19 Milan, Italy. Postal Code 20134.

More information

INTRODUCTION: ANALYTIC PHILOSOPHY AND THE FALL AND RISE OF THE KANT HEGEL TRADITION

INTRODUCTION: ANALYTIC PHILOSOPHY AND THE FALL AND RISE OF THE KANT HEGEL TRADITION INTRODUCTION: ANALYTIC PHILOSOPHY AND THE FALL AND RISE OF THE KANT HEGEL TRADITION Should it come as a surprise when a technical work in the philosophy of language by a prominent analytic philosopher

More information

Review of Philosophical Logic: An Introduction to Advanced Topics *

Review of Philosophical Logic: An Introduction to Advanced Topics * Teaching Philosophy 36 (4):420-423 (2013). Review of Philosophical Logic: An Introduction to Advanced Topics * CHAD CARMICHAEL Indiana University Purdue University Indianapolis This book serves as a concise

More information

Cory Juhl, Eric Loomis, Analyticity (New York: Routledge, 2010).

Cory Juhl, Eric Loomis, Analyticity (New York: Routledge, 2010). Cory Juhl, Eric Loomis, Analyticity (New York: Routledge, 2010). Reviewed by Viorel Ţuţui 1 Since it was introduced by Immanuel Kant in the Critique of Pure Reason, the analytic synthetic distinction had

More information