ON THE THING IN ITSELF IN DEFENCE OF KANT AGAINST NIETZSCHE

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "ON THE THING IN ITSELF IN DEFENCE OF KANT AGAINST NIETZSCHE"

Transcription

1 Asgeir Theodor Johannesson! 1! On The Thing In Itself Asgeir Theodor Johannesson Course: Ethics (Kant) Taught by Alice Pinheiro Walla January 2014 ON THE THING IN ITSELF IN DEFENCE OF KANT AGAINST NIETZSCHE 1. Introduction As an introduction to the topic I am going to begin with a short biographical note that illuminates the subject. The magnum opus of Arthur Schopenhauer, The World as Will and Representation, brought me to philosophy. In that regard I am not unique in the history of the field because the same is true of at least two giants in modern philosophy: Friedrich Nietzsche and Ludwig Wittgenstein. Both Nietzsche and Wittgenstein came to philosophy through Schopenhauer and were heavily influenced by his views. Both of them also overcame their early Schopenhauerian views, although one can spot that they were once under his spell, even in their later works where their rejection of his outlook reaches its peak. I also overcame the philosophy of Schopenhauer and developed intellectually in a very similar way as both Nietzsche and Wittgenstein (who are philosophically nearer to each other than many scholars seem to realise). Schopenhauer is a transcendental idealist, who considered Immanuel Kant as his predecessor. Schopenhauer s whole philosophy was to a large extent based on an interpretation of Kant s philosophy and what he considered to be corrections of it. In order to accept Schopenhauer s framework one has to accept Kant s basic premises, so Kant becomes a central figure for anyone who is interested in Schopenhauer.

2 Asgeir Theodor Johannesson! 2! On The Thing In Itself It is out of the scope of this essay to account for the agreements and disagreements of Kant and Schopenhauer, but the purpose of pointing this out is to explain why an acceptance and a rejection of Schopenhauer s scheme of things creates an acceptance and rejection of Kant s scheme of things. Such change of outlook is of no minor importance for the individual in question because it affects how she views the world and the life within it. For this reason the acceptance and the rejection are deeply emotional in the same or similar manner as changes in religious views are emotional. A central focus of the rejection in question has to do with Kant s idea of the thing-in-itself and its distinction from the thing as it appears to us. Kant was not the originator of the idea, but he developed the idea in a certain way and was its most esteemed and influential spokesman. Nietzsche s intellectual battle with Kant s philosophy was not just through Schopenhauer, but more direct as well. Nietzsche developed his own philosophical views in an era marked by Kantian revival. It is not known how thoroughly he read Kant s writings, but it is for example known that one of the books he read more than once was History of Materialism by Friedrich Albert Lange, where the problem of teleology after Kant was discussed. A direct or indirect reference to the Kantian distinction between thing-in-itself and appearance is frequent in Nietzsche s writings. The importance of this aspect of Nietzsche s philosophy is well expressed by Dr. Mattia Riccardi in his paper, Nietzsche s Critique of Kant s Thing In Itself, where he says the following: In particular, Nietzsche has often been presented as the philosopher who, after having endorsed this Kantian distinction in his previous work, eventually ends by rejecting the very notion of thing in itself and thus overcomes the metaphysical dualism which dominates most of the previous philosophical tradition. However, the question of whether he succeeds in substantiating his refusal of Kant s position is anything but clear. 1 Riccardi defends Nietzsche s position in his paper, but in this essay I am going to do the opposite: Defend Kant s position against Nietzsche s criticism. First I will account for the idea of thing-in-itself. Then I will explain its relevance for Kant s practical philosophy. Next, I am going to discuss both Nietzsche s early endorsement of Kant s framework and his later rejection of it. Finally, before I reach my conclusion, I will 1! Mattia Riccardi (2010), Nietzscheʼs Critique of Kantʼs Thing In Itself (Nietzsche Studien 39, pp ), p. 333.

3 Asgeir Theodor Johannesson! 3! On The Thing In Itself criticise Nietzsche s arguments and put forward my defence of Kant. The beforementioned Wittgenstein will reappear near the end of the essay. 2. Kant s idea of the thing in itself How human beings experience the world is dependent of our five senses: Touch, sight, hearing, smell and taste. We have no reason to think that our senses are perfect and that they perceive the world in a perfect way. On the contrary, our senses have developed through messy evolutionary process and we have every reason to think that they provide us with an imperfect perception of the world. When one has realised this fact about our condition the question is raised: How is the world on its own, independent of how we experience it, i.e. how are things in themselves? Kant is responding to such ruminations when he makes the distinction between a thing-in-itself and a thing as it appears to us. A thing-in-itself, according to Kant, is a thing as it is independent of how it is perceived by the perceiver or conceptualised by a rational being. Things-in-themselves are postulated by practical reason, but their attributes are in principle not subject to experience and therefore unknowable. The identification of things-in-themselves and the subsequent distinction between them and appearances, emerges from rational beings faculty of understanding, which is dependent on a linguistic form of life. Morals: Kant explains the idea in the third section of Groundwork of the Metaphysics of [A]ll representation that come to us without our choosing (like those of the senses) enable us to cognise objects only as they affect us, while what they may be in themselves remains unknown to us; and hence that, as far as representation of this kind is concerned, even with the most strenuous attentiveness and distinctness that the understanding may ever add, we can achieve only cognition of appearances, never of things in themselves. Once this difference has been noticed [ ], it follows of itself that one must concede and assume behind the appearances something else that is not appearance, namely the things in themselves; even if since they can never become known to us, but only ever how they affect us we of ourselves rest content with being unable to get any closer to them or ever to know what they are in themselves. 2 2! Immanuel Kant (Gr), Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), p. 60 (4:452).

4 Asgeir Theodor Johannesson! 4! On The Thing In Itself In the same paragraph he says that this view must yield a distinction, however rough, of a world of sense from the world of understanding. 3 The former world can be very dissimilar according to the dissimilar sensibility of many kinds of observers of the world, whereas the latter, which is the foundation of the world of sense, always remains the same. 4 Kant s distinction is roughly equivalent to his distinction between noumena and phenomena, where noumena correspond to things-in-themselves but phenomena to appearances. Still, although we can assume them to equivalent for our purposes, both Kant and Kantian scholars draw important distinctions between them in some contexts. 5 The noumena and the things-in-themselves are beyond the world of the senses in the meaning that they transcend that world. The transcendental realm is unknown to us but the understanding of its existence plays a key role for our view of the world, as I will later discuss. There has for a long time been much debate whether the thing-in-itself and the thing as it appears are two objects or two aspects of the same object. In my view, the second interpretation is more convincing and sensible. Although it is possible to find textual evidence for both interpretations in Critique of Pure Reason and other books by Kant, the ambiguity seems to be reduced by Kant s private correspondence, as Roger Scruton points out: Kant often describes transcendental idealism as the doctrine that we have a priori knowledge only of appearances and not of things as they are in themselves (or things-in-themselves ). His followers and critics disputed heatedly over the thing-in-itself. Moses Mendelssohn thought of it as a distinct entity, so that an appearance is one thing, the thing-in-itself another. Other, under the influence of Kant s pupil J. S. Beck, took the phrase thingin-itself to refer to a way of describing the very same object which we also know as an appearance. Kant lends support to this second interpretation in his correspondence with Beck, in many passages of the Critique of Practical Reason, and in a letter to one of its principal advocates: All objects that can be given to us can be conceptualised in two ways: on the one hand, as appearances; on the other hand, as things in themselves (C 103n.). 3! Ibid. 4! Ibid. 5! James R. OʼShea (2012), Kantʼs Critique of Pure Reason (Durham: Acumen), p. 26.

5 Asgeir Theodor Johannesson! 5! On The Thing In Itself But there is no doubt that his mind was not made up about the matter, and this led to a crucial ambiguity in the critical philosophy. 6 So the thing-in-itself is the aspect of the object which is independent from our experience while the phenomenal aspect refers to the very same object as it is experienced by us. Some commentators prefer to describe the difference in another way, for example Rae Langton who focuses on relational properties. In her account the phenomenal aspect is considered strictly relational, as it is defined through its relations to other things, while the noumenal aspect is considered strictly nonrelational or purely intrinsic. 7 But whether or not two objects or two aspects are distinguished, the distinction has arguably consequences, which some find disturbing but others pleasing, namely that although the phenomenal part of the world is the arena of our meaningful existence whether it is our sense of beauty, our knowledge of the universe, our constructive work, or something else there is another aspect which is in some deep sense truer or more real, the transcendental realm. The transcendental aspect of the world applies of course also to the thing that a human being is. This means that human beings are themselves both things-inthemselves and beings that belong to the world of sense. So, the view of many mystical traditions that people have truer self receives certain philosophical credibility through Kantʼs account of the world. Still the epistemological problem remains, according to him, as is stated in the following revealing passage: A human being cannot even according to the acquaintance he has with himself by inner sensation presume to cognise how he himself is in himself. For since he does not as it were create himself, and gets his concept not a priori but empirically, it is natural that about himself too he can gather intelligence only through the inner sense, and consequently only through the appearance of his nature, and the way in which his consciousness is affected; whereas beyond these characteristics of his own subject that are composed of nothing but sundry appearances he must necessarily assume something else lying at its foundation, namely his I, such as it may be in itself; and with respect to mere perception and receptivity to sensations he must thus count himself as belonging to the world of sense, but with regard to what there may be of pure activity in him (what reaches consciousness 6! Roger Scruton (1982), Kant (Oxford & New York: Oxford University Press), p ! Riccardi (2010), p. 342; cf. Rae Langton (1998), Kantian Humility: Our Ignorance of Things in Themselves (Oxford & New York: Oxford University Press).

6 Asgeir Theodor Johannesson! 6! On The Thing In Itself not by affection of the senses, but immediately) as belonging to the intellectual world, with which he is yet no further acquainted. 8 So, what Kant calls pure activity (the terminology should be understood in the way Baruch Spinoza used it) belongs to the intellectual world. Now the focus has turned to freedom of rational beings and one can glimpse how Kantʼs idea of thing-in-itself affects his practical philosophy, a subject we will now turn to. 3. The practical relevance of the thing-in-itself According to Kant every change which occurs in the world has a cause, without exception. So, every natural event is a link in a chain of necessity, one thing leads to another. Such mechanical view of the natural world had become a common view among intellectuals at the time of Kant in the 18th century and it is still a common view, although pure necessity has been replaced by certain degree of randomness and probability. But if every event in nature is necessary (or even sometimes random), does this not also apply to human beings and their actions? If the mechanism in question applies fully to human beings there is no room left for genuine agency of a person and therefore no freedom. People, although rational beings, would so to speak be slaves to the natural order of things. Without freedom to choose between options one can neither blame rational beings for wrongdoings nor praise them for rightful actions; the blame and the praise could only be directed towards the whole fabric of the world and its possible source or creator (if the creator is not free either, even she cannot be blamed or praised). If this would be a commonly accepted description of the human condition, morality would loose its meaning; it would become senseless. Still, people would consider some behaviour socially constructive and other behaviour socially destructive, etc. So people would continue to judge the necessary actions of others but the vocabulary for such expression would change to reflect the condition of rational beings without genuine agency. The new vocabulary would purely refer to 8! Kant (Gr), pp (4:451). Arthur Schopenhauer takes another route than Kant in this regard. For Schopenhauer, the fact that we ourselves are part of the noumena gives us an epistemological access to the noumena, although not through reason but feelings. This was the basis for his sentimentalist moral views.

7 Asgeir Theodor Johannesson! 7! On The Thing In Itself fate; a morally wrong action would become an unfortunate action and a morally right action would be a fortunate one. This is the reason why there is, according to Kant, no morality without freedom. Morality requires freedom. Consequently, the starting point of Kant s ethics is the concept of freedom. Rational beings conceive of themselves as free, as the spontaneous originators of their actions without any fundamental constraints woven into their own nature and the causal connection of the world. If rational beings are free they are not determined by causes outside of themselves but are able to be the first cause of a new chain of events. Without them able to be a first cause there is a contradiction between the natural order and human freedom. In order to solve the puzzle it is tempting to say that the phenomenon of reason, which developed in human beings, is a faculty which establishes freedom, in other words that the use of reason creates the possibility of a first cause. The problem with such account, however, is that there is now answer to the question why reason itself is not one other link in the natural chain and that rational precesses are determined in the same way as everything else. One could say there is a problem of infinite regress in the solution of invoking reason alone. It is not sufficient to establish genuine moral agency. So, is our sense of freedom only self-deception and our morality a fiction? Kant did not want to go down that route, rather he sought to establish human freedom and morality by solving the paradox without circular reasoning. Kant s solution was to invoke the ontological argument for the distinction between a thing-in-itself and the same thing as belonging to the world of the senses. The noumenal realm of things-inthemselves is the transcendent intelligence which grounds the rules of the phenomenal order, the world as we experience it. This feature of our nature, along with our rational faculty, is the source of our agency, what enables us to be a first cause on our own. One s rational faculty and consequent consciousness thus unleashes a corresponding intelligent source in one s own being; this source is an aspect of a person, a person as a thing-in-itself. This is Kant s key to people s autonomy and activity, as opposed to being passive to the causal chain of nature, or

8 Asgeir Theodor Johannesson! 8! On The Thing In Itself the determining causes of the world of sense, as he calls it. 9 Frederick Rauscher explains the situation as follows in a Critical Guide to the Groundwork edited by Jens Timmermann: As members of the intelligible world, human beings are active and rational, able to initiate action independent of causal determination in the sensible world, that is, as things in themselves they possess a free will understood as an ability to choose. As free in themselves humans then recognise that they are both obligated and able to conform to rational constraints on their actions. 10 Sometimes Kant seems content with the psychological belief that we consider ourselves free rather than an ontological demonstration of it. Thus, he concludes the sub-chapter in the Groundwork in following manner: For now we see that when we think of ourselves as free we transfer ourselves into the world of understanding as members of it and cognise autonomy of the will along with its consequence, morality; but if we think of ourselves as put under obligation we regard ourselves as belonging to the world of sense and yet at the same time to the world of understanding. 11 It is also noteworthy to consider Kantʼs view regarding the mark human freedom leaves on the phenomenal world. Jens Timmermann puts it well when he says the following in his Commentary on the Groundwork: There is no trace of the supernatural provenance of human action in the phenomenal world. Rather, actions appear to be determined by other appearances desires and inclinations in accordance with the causal laws of nature. The causality of freedom lies beyond the realm of knowledge. Even so, the assumption of our dual membership remains. 12 Thus, the prerequisite of morality, freedom, has not an empirical grounding, according to Kant, but a transcendental one. The ontology and the psychology of freedom, along with Kant s whole practical philosophy, is established on the bases of 9! Kant (Gr.), p. 62 (4:453). 10!Frederick Rauscher (2009), Freedom and Reason in Groundwork III (pp ) in Timmermann, Jens (ed.) Kantʼs Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), p Rauscher adds: The argument is said to fail, and Kant is said to have realised this failure before writing the Critique of Practical Reason, in which he abandoned any hope of deduction of morality in favour of a very different approach, an assertion of the validity of the moral law as a ʻfact of reasonʼ which requires, and is susceptible to, no deduction. (ibid.) 11! Kant (Gr.), p. 62 (4:453). 12! Jens Timmermann (2007), Kantʼs Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals: A Commentary (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), p. 140.

9 Asgeir Theodor Johannesson! 9! On The Thing In Itself a simple idea, the idea of a thing-in-itself. That idea has been controversial and I will now turn my attention to one of its antagonists. 4. Nietzsche s Early Endorsement Kant s distinction between noumenon and the phenomenon, the thing-in-itself and thing thing as it appeares, was of major importance for Nietzsche since he was in his early twenties. He endorsed the distinction; for him it was the fundamental premise of philosophical enquiry. Following Schopenhauer, Nietzsche s theory of perception was representationalist, which committed him to the Kantian framework of metaphysics and its cognitive limitation. The Kantian-Schopenhauerian metaphysical picture of the world played a crucial role in Nietzsche s first books, not least the well known The Birth of Tragedy. It is not until Human, All Too Human, which was first published in 1878, when Nietzsche was 34 years old, that one can notice scepticism about the idea of things-inthemselves. This scepticism goes hand in hand with a major shift in Nietzsche s philosophy: He abandons his early Dionysian-Apollonian metaphysics, although he continues to use the terms with different meanings, and adopts a non-metaphysical standpoint where the ultimate reality of the world of our senses is not questioned. He develops his philosophy of free-spirits on the rejection of metaphysics. But even in Human, All Too Human his rejection of Kantian metaphysics of things-in-themselves is not an ontological rejection, as is evident from the following passage: It is true, there could be a metaphysical world; the absolute possibility of it is hardly to be disputed. We behold all things through the human head and cannot cut off this head; while the question nonetheless remains what of the world would still be there if one had cut it off. 13 Rather it is an epistemological and psychological rejection, as Mattia Riccardi points out: [Nietzsche s] criticism does not directly challenge the ontological distinction between the thing in itself and its appearance, but rather dismisses it as a mere theoretical question which is ultimately meaningless in terms of our actions in life ! Friedrich Nietzsche (HH1), Human All Too Human. Translated by R. J. Hollingdale (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), 9. 14! Riccardi (2010), p. 338.

10 Asgeir Theodor Johannesson! 10! On The Thing In Itself So the metaphysical world might exist, but it has, according to Nietzsche at that stage, no relevance to life. One could claim that even Kant is agnostic about thingsin-themselves, in a way that for example Schopenhauer was not, but for Kant the metaphysical distinction had a deep meaning and consequences, not only for theoretical philosophy but also for practical philosophy, for our life. The distinguished Nietzsche scholar Maudemarie Clark uses the word agnosticism to describe Nietzscheʼs position regarding the thing-in-itself in Human, All Too Human, but as I have explained it is a type of agnosticism which is psychologically equivalent to a rejection of the metaphysical framework in question. 15 It is valuable to understand how Nietzscheʼs views regarding the thing-in-itself develop, but now I will turn to the destination of the development, a fully-fledged ontological rejection of the idea. 5. Nietzsche s ontological rejection The Daybreak, published in 1881, marks a new period in Nietzscheʼs thought. In the subsequent books he puts forward a more radical criticism of the idea of thing-initself than he had done before. The passages in Nietzscheʼs writings which have been the subject of most discussion among scholars with regard to criticism of thingin-itself appear in Beyond Good and Evil and The Gay Science. In the former book, Nietzsche dismisses the argument for a thing-in-itself because he claims it contains contradictio in adjecto, that is to say, a contradiction between parts of the argument: There are still harmless self-observers who believe in the existence of immediate certainties, such as I think, or the I will that was Schopenhauer s superstition: just as if knowledge had been given an object here to seize, stark naked, as a thing in itself, and no falsification took place from either the side of the subject or the side of the object. But I will say this a hundred times: immediate certainty, like absolute knowledge and the thing in itself contains a contradictio in adjecto ! Maudemarie Clark (1990), Nietzsche on Truth and Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), p ! Friedrich Nietzsche (BGE), Beyond Good and Evil. Translated by Judith Norman (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2002), 16.

11 Asgeir Theodor Johannesson! 11! On The Thing In Itself There is not a scholarly consensus why Nietzsche considers the argument to be selfcontradictory, but the following passage from Gay Science could provide a hint: What is appearance to me now! Certainly not the opposite of some essence what could I say about any essence except name the predicates of its appearance! Certainly not a dead mask that one could put on an unknown x and probably also take off x! 17 Nietzsche is arguing that our world is the world as it appears to us, the world of our senses, and that it makes no sense to make a distinction between that world and something we have no way of cognising or even no way of properly conceiving. 18 Nietzscheʼs ontological rejection of thing-in-itself does not take the form there is no x, rather it takes the form that to claim there is such an x is not sensical. During his agnostic period, mentioned earlier, he maintained that it is impossible to know the answer of the question posed, but his ontological rejection consists in saying that the question itself makes no sense. In this regard, section 354 in Gay Science is of interest and could cast further light on the matter: [I]t is not the opposition between subject and object which concerns me here; I leave that distinction to those epistemologists who have got tangled up in the snares of grammar (of folk metaphysics). Even less am I concerned with the opposition between thing in itself and appearance: for we know far too little to even be entitled to make that distinction. We simply have no organ for knowing, for truth : we know (or believe or imagine) exactly as much as is useful to the human herd, to the species: and even what is here called usefulness is finally also just a belief, a fiction, and perhaps just that supremely fatal stupidity of which we some day will perish. 19 So, Nietzsche advocates more epistemological modesty and he does not allow his ontology to exceed his epistemology. He also talks about the snares of grammar regarding the opposition between subject and object, a phrase that is very much in the spirit of later Wittgenstein. 17! Friedrich Nietzsche (GS), The Gay Science. Translated by Walter Kaufmann (New York: Vintage Books 1974), ! Maudemarie Clark argues that the thing-in-itself is inconceivable, according to Nietzsche, while Mattia Riccardi interpretation text as making a weaker claim, that the thing-in-itself cannot be cognised. 19! Nietzsche (GS), 354. Here I use the translation of Josefine Nauckhoff (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001).

12 Asgeir Theodor Johannesson! 12! On The Thing In Itself Nietzsche does neither want to postulate that things have aspects which belong to an unknown realm nor to postulate that they have an unknown source or true essence. On the contrary, we can only speculate on the deep nature of things by analysing and investigating things as objects of our senses. In another passage in Gay Science Nietzsche says that what starts as appearance in the end nearly always becomes essence and effectively acts as its essence. 20 Here, he could be interpreted as saying that the only essence of a thing that we can understand is what springs from the thingʼs representative nature. But what has all this to do with Nietzscheʼs claim that Kantʼs argument for thingin-itself contains a contradiction? The answer is between the lines in Nietzscheʼs writings and his argument is a common argument against Kantʼs idea, an argument which is eloquently summarised by Roger Scruton: [A]ppearances possess all the characteristics of physical objects. To say that an appearance is also an appearance of something is surely incoherent. For, by Kant s own theory, the something which supposedly underlies appearance could only be a noumenon, and about noumena nothing significant can be said. 21 If things-in-themselves cannot be known we cannot make any claims about them. Lanier Anderson, who is both a scholar of Kant and Nietzsche, reaches the following conclusion on the subject after a thorough reflection: The unknowability of things in themselves is part of their very conception: it arises not from some contingent deficiency or incompleteness in our experience or theorising to date, but from general and inevitable limitations on our cognitive resources, most importantly the lack of intellectual intuitions capable of representing such objects. This means that in attempting to conceive of things in themselves, we outstrip the legitimate realm of our concepts, and therefore stop making sense altogether. 22 Although it is controversial how reliable Nietzscheʼs unpublished writings are as evidence for his views (he deliberately decided not to publish them), they should at least up to some extent be useful as a tool of interpretation of his published books. 20! Nietzsche (GS), ! Scruton (1982), p ! R. Lanier Anderson (1999), Nietzscheʼs Views on Truth and the Kantian Background of His Epistemology, in Babette Babich and Robert S. Cohen (eds.), Nietzsche, Epistemology, and Philosophy of Science: Nietzsche and the Sciences II (Boston: Springer), pp

13 Asgeir Theodor Johannesson! 13! On The Thing In Itself He mentions the thing-in-itself frequently in his notebooks, for example in the following note from 1886: Kant was no longer entitled to his distinction between appearance and thing in itself he had denied himself the right to continue to distinguish in this old, traditional way having rejected as invalid the inference from the appearance to a cause of the appearance in accordance with his understanding of the concept of causality and of its purely intra-phenomenal validity[.] 23 In 1987 he also calls the thing-in-itself absurd for the following reason: If I remove all relations, all properties [,] all activities of a thing, then no thing remains left. 24 In a similar vein, Paul Guyer argues in Kant and the Claims of Knowledge that Kantʼs idea of things-in-themselves seems to follow from his prejudice against the ultimate reality of relations. 25 However, what Nietzsche holds against the idea of a thing-in-itself is not merely that he considers it contradictory and nonsensical. He maintains the distinction is also unfruitful for human life, because a mystical realm is established which draws the attention from our actual world as we experience it, here and now, the only stage where we live our lives, the material for our creativity and the object of our aesthetic sentiments. Kantʼs idea is therefore unethical, according to Nietzsche, in the sense that it may distract people from the ideal earthly life and may direct their attention to the unknown or the mystical, which would not be likely to contribute to human advancement. This can be called a consequentalist argument against the idea. In a chapter called How the 'Real World' at last Became a Myth History of an Error in one of his last books, Twilight of the Idols, Nietzsche expresses how he views the idea of the thing-in-itself in the context of intellectual history. In the chapter, the consequentalist argument against the thing-in-itself is poetically interwoven with his ontological argument: 23! Friedrich Nietzsche (WP) The Will to Power. (A posthumous publication of Nietzscheʼs notebooks). 2nd edn. Translated by Walter Kaufmann and R. J. Hollingdale (New York: Vintage Books, 1968), Nachlass 1886, 5[4], KSA 12, pp ! Nietzsche (WP), Nachlass 1887, 10 [202], KSA 12, p ! Paul Guyer (1987), Kant and the Claims of Knowledge (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), p. 350).

14 Asgeir Theodor Johannesson! 14! On The Thing In Itself 1. The real world, attainable to the wise, the pious, the virtuous man he dwells in it, he is it. (Oldest form of the idea, relatively sensible, simple, convincing. Transcription of the proposition 'I, Plato, am the truth.') The real world, unattainable for the moment, but promised to the wise, the pious, the virtuous man ('to the sinner who repents'). (Progress of the idea: it grows more refined, more inticing, more incomprehensible [ ]) 3. The real world, unattainable, undemonstrable, cannot be promised, but even when merely thought of a consolation, a duty, an imperative. (Fundamentally the same old sun, but shining through mist and scepticism; the idea grown sublime, pale, northerly, Königsbergian.) The real world unattainable? Unattained, at any rate. And if unattained also unknown. Consequently also no consolation, no redemption, no duty: how could we have a duty towards something unknown? (The grey of dawn. First yawnings of reason. Cock-crow of positivism.) The 'real world' and idea no longer of any use, not even a duty any longer an idea grown useless, superfluous, consequently a refuted idea: let us abolish it! (Broad daylight; return of cheerfulness and bons sens; Plato blushes for shame; all free spirits run riot.) 6. We have abolished the real world: what world is left? The apparent world perhaps? But no! With the real world we have also abolished the apparent world! (Mid-day; moment of the shortest shadow; end of the longest error; zenith of mankind; INCIPIT ZARATHUSTRA). 29 The last words, Incipit Zarathustra, mean Zarathustra begins and refer to the main character in Thus Spoke Zarathustra, Nietzsche s aesthetic and ethical ideal, whose time is ripe when the idea of thing-in-itself has been abandoned. Nietzsche s criticism is seductive, but I think it is misguided, as I will now account for. 26! Translatorʼs footnote: The truth = Wahrheit, corresponding to wahre Welt = real world. 27! Translatorʼs footnote: i.e. Kantian, from the northerly German city in which Kant was born and in which he lived and died. 28!Translatorʼs footnote: Here meaning empiricism, philosophy founded on observation and experiment. 29! Friedrich Nietzsche (TI), Twilight of the Idols. In Twilight of the Idols and The Anti-Christ. 2nd edn. Translated by R. J. Hollingdale (London: Penguin Books, 1990), pp

15 Asgeir Theodor Johannesson! 15! On The Thing In Itself 6. A defence of Kant against Nietzsche Nietzsche s criticism of Kant s idea of the thing-in-itself has been very influential in the 20th century. Nietzsche has frequently been celebrated for overcoming so-called Kantian dualism. Here, however, I will defend Kant against Nietzsche s criticism and I will argue against both his ontological argument and his consequentalist argument. I will first react to the latter argument and I will begin by discussing how the rejection of the thing-in-itself affected Nietzsche s own ideas and psychology. In my view, the most revealing evidence is a letter he wrote to his friend Franz Overbeck in 1881, the same year as The Daybreak was published. In it he expresses his intellectual affinity with Baruch Spinoza, the 17th century philosopher: Not only is his whole tendency like my own to make knowledge the most powerful passion but also in five main points of his doctrine I find myself; this most abnormal and lonely thinker is closest to me in these points precisely: he denies free will, purposes, the moral world order, the nonegoistical, evil; of course the differences are enormous, but they are differences more of period, culture, field of knowledge. 30 Spinoza was an inspiring thinker. Kant read him also and was influenced by him. Still, Kant found many of his views problematic. Spinoza was a philosopher of radical immanence; he rejected the transcendent. Kant was partly responding to Spinozaʼs views with his own transcendentalism. So, it is not surprising that Nietzsche was drawn to Spinozaʼs immanent account of the world at the time when he was distancing himself from Kantian-Schopenhauerian metaphysics. The rejection of the transcendent realm causes both Spinoza and Nietzsche to deny free will, the nonegoistical and the moral world order, as is stated in the letter. These are exactly the things Kant established by his transcendental account, the idea of thingin-itself. Spinozaʼs denial of the moral world order on the one hand and the nonegoistical on the other, was closely related: his ethics was deeply egoistical. The same can be said about Nietzscheʼs ethics. Spinoza was a determinist, if not a pure necessitarian, and Nietzsche followed in his footsteps and adopted fatalistic views regarding both nature and human behaviour. The rejection of transcendent views turned Spinoza 30! Friedrich Nietzsche (SL), Selected Letters of Friedrich Nietzsche. Edited and translated by Christopher Middleton (Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing, 1969), Letter 89 (to Franz Overbeck; Sils Maria, July 30, 1881), p. 177.

16 Asgeir Theodor Johannesson! 16! On The Thing In Itself into a pantheist while Nietzsche became an atheist, but the difference between those two standpoint was not great. Some scholars have identified Spinoza as an atheist, while others have noticed the religious urge in Nietzscheʼs thought. Spinozaʼs slogan Amor Dei, love of God, has a very similar meaning as Nietzscheʼs slogan Amor Fati, love of fate. They both had an intense psychological need for love in their worldview, but had a hard time finding it in their immanent account of our existence. Fatalism goes against the natural instinct of rational beings, who consider themselves to be free, at least to some extent. Fatalism is a difficult position psychologically and most likely not a fruitful mentality for many people. One can also question the fruitfulness of denying the nonegoistical and a moral world order. One could argue that the attitude in question did not have a good effect on neither Spinoza nor Nietzsche, that it isolated them, made them depressed and even made their life shorter than it otherwise would have been. At least it would not be far-fetched to make such a claim in the case of Nietzsche. One could also argue that the philosophy of fatalistic, egoistic, non-moralistic immanence did not have positive affect of many of Nietzscheʼs followers in the 20th century. In short, there is a reason to suspect that the rejection of thing-in-itself and the transcendent realm does not advance human life, but quite the opposite. Now we shall turn to the ontological argument. To begin with, one can question how ontological Kantʼs metaphysical framework in fact is. Jens Timmermann argues for example that Kantʼs invocation of the intelligible world is not intended to be merely theoretical, and certainly not an ontological, claim : Rather, he is identifying a practical self-conception of human beings as rational agents. Our experience of the ideas and principles of reason, in particular of the categorical imperative, cannot be readily explained using the sensible world alone. We invoke a distinct order of reason, yet cannot explain how this order of reason can be the cause of any effects in the world. 31 Kantʼs idea of thing-in-itself is ontological in the sense that he is in some way describing state of affairs in the world, but his metaphysical account serves to establish the world as we experience it, but it does not lead to conclusions which are foreign to our conception. People conceive themselves as being free, at least to a certain degree, and they have a moral sense. People are also conscious about the 31! Timmermann (2009), p. 223.

17 Asgeir Theodor Johannesson! 17! On The Thing In Itself imperfection of their sensual apparatus and that things may not necessarily be as they seem to us. In a deep sense, Kantʼs ontology leaves everything as it is, and then he goes on to explore the rules of reason and to ground a rationalistic morality. Kantʼs metaphysical account, including his idea of thing-in-itself, is in line with Wittgensteinʼs advice that a philosopher should leave everything as it is. Behind the advice is the view that philosophy does not contribute to human knowledge, but only to human understanding. This is a modest view of philosophy but still does not trivialise the discipline, because the understanding in question is not trivial but illuminating and important. Nietzsche, however, has de facto an ontological picture of the world that deeply affects his psychology. His philosophical views made him an anti-moral fatalist. It is ironic that Nietzsche let philosophical pseudo-knowledge affect his life, while Kant devised philosophical views which helped people to escape such pseudo-knowledge. At the end of the day, it was Nietzsche who got tangled up in the snares of grammar, while Kant snared grammar to tangle what he sought in the world. It is Nietzsche who fails the test of epistemological modesty, but Kant who passes it. This observation is in line with Henry Allisonʼs remark in Kantʼs Transcendental Idealism: The thing in itself should be understood non-metaphysically: In Wittgensteinian terms, Kant was not trying to say what is unsayable, but merely to define the boundaries of what can be said or asked. In order to do so, however, he had to introduce the metalanguage of transcendental philosophy. Thus such expressions as things as they are in themselves, noumena, the transcendental object, and their correlates are to be understood as technical terms within this metalanguage rather than as terms referring to transcendentally real entities. 32 In the criticism of Kant, Nietzsche lacks interpretative sophistication; he understands Kant too literally and attacks a straw-man. Roger Scruton reaches a similar conclusion as Allison with regard to interpretation of Kantʼs views, as is evident from the following insightful and beautiful passage: [Kant] dismissed as insubstantial any pretence to an absolute form of knowledge, which seeks to soar above the resistant medium of experience. The notion of a transcendental object is misunderstood when considered as referring to a real thing. The idea is posited only as a point of view (A 681, B 710), in order to make clear that the principles of pure understanding can 32! Henry E. Allison (2004), Kantʼs Transcendental Idealism (New Haven & London: Yale University Press), p. 73.

18 Asgeir Theodor Johannesson! 18! On The Thing In Itself apply only to objects of the senses never to things in general without regard to the mode in which we are able to apprehend them (A 246, B 303). There is no description of the world that can free itself from the reference to experience. Although the world that we know is not our creation, nor merely a synopsis of our perspective, it cannot be known except from the point of view which is ours. All attempts to break through the limits imposed by experience end in self-contradiction, and although we may have intimations of a transcendental knowledge, that knowledge can never be ours. These intimations are confined to moral life and aesthetic experience, and while they tell us, in a sense, what we really are, they can be translated into words only to speak unintelligibly. Philosophy, which describes the limits of knowledge, is always tempted to transcend them. But Kant s final advice to it is that given in the last sentence of Wittgenstein s Tractatus Logico- Philosohpicus: That whereof we cannot speak, we must consign to silence. 33 If Kantʼs metaphysical framework, along with the idea of thing-in-itself, is understood in the way Allison and Scruton interpret it, the framework withstands Nietzscheʼs criticism. The ideal of perspectiveless knowledge is unrealisable, but a philosophical outlook is incomplete without concepts for such an ideal. The thing-in-itself is such a concept. We cannot cognise the ideal it refers to but we can conceive it, although vaguely and obscurely. Surely, there seems to be a paradox in Kantʼs account of human freedom and morality, how one is subject of freedom as a thing-in-itself, but at the same time bound within a causal chain from a phenomenal point of view. But Kant accepts the apparent paradox and responds to it in the wisest manner, that although we may not comprehend these things, we do comprehend its incomprehensibility, and this is all that can reasonably be required of a philosophy that in its principles strives up to the boundary of human reason. 34 Human action, choice and morality are all pervading features of human life and they certainly do not strike us as mysterious while we are acting, choosing and behaving morally, but these things become mysterious when we begin to reflect on them. Then it becomes evident that a man sees well enough what he has, but not what he is, as Wittgenstein famously put it ! Scruton (1982), p ! Kant (Gr), p. 72 (4:463). 35! Ludwig Wittgenstein, Culture and Value. (revised second edition), G. H. Wright. (ed.) (Oxford: Blackwell Publishing, 1998), p. 56.

19 Asgeir Theodor Johannesson! 19! On The Thing In Itself 7. Conclusion I began this essay by accounting for Kant s idea of the thing-in-itself. Then I explained its relevance for Kant s practical philosophy. Next, I discussed Nietzsche s early endorsement of it and the arguments for his eventual rejection, which were both of an ontological and a consequentalist kind. Finally, I defended Kant against Nietzsche s criticism. Firstly, I refuted the fruitfulness of rejecting the transcendent; secondly I gave a meta-philosophical reason for preferring Kant s framework rather than Nietzsche s; thirdly, I maintained that Nietzsche interpreted Kant s idea too literally and therefore he attacked a straw-man. Asgeir Theodor Johannesson

20 Asgeir Theodor Johannesson! 20! On The Thing In Itself Works Cited Allison, Henry E. (2004) Kantʼs Transcendental Idealism. New Haven & London: Yale University Press. Clark, Maudemarie. (1990) Nietzsche on Truth and Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press). Guyer, Paul. (1987) Kant and the Claims of Knowledge. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Kant, Immanuel. (Gr) Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals. Revised Edition. Edited by Mary Gregor and Jens Timmermann. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2012). Kant, Immanuel. (PP) Practical Philosophy. Translated and edited by Mary J. Gregor. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, Kant, Immanuel. (A/B) Critique of Pure Reason. Translated and edited by Paul Guyer and Allen W. Wood. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2009 (first published 1998). Kant, Immanuel. (BR) Basic Writings of Kant. Edited by Allen W. Wood. New York: The Modern Library, Langton, Rae. (1998) Kantian Humility: Our Ignorance of Things in Themselves. Oxford & New York: Oxford University Press. Nietzsche, Friedrich. (BGE) Beyond Good and Evil. Translated by Judith Norman. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, Nietzsche, Friedrich. (BT) The Birth of Tragedy in Kaufmann, Walter (ed.) Basic Writings of Nietzsche. Translated by Walter Kaufmann. New York: The Modern Library, Nietzsche, Friedrich. (D) Daybreak. Translated by R. J. Hollingdale. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, Nietzsche, Friedrich. (GM) On the Genealogy of Morality. Translated by Maudemarie Clark and Alan J. Swensen. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing, Nietzsche, Friedrich. (GS) The Gay Science. Translated by Walter Kaufmann. New York: Vintage Books, Nietzsche, Friedrich. (GS) The Gay Science. Translated by Josefine Nauckhoff. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, Nietzsche, Friedrich. (HH1; HH2a; HH2b) Human All Too Human. Translated by R. J. Hollingdale. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996.

21 Asgeir Theodor Johannesson! 21! On The Thing In Itself Nietzsche, Friedrich. (SL) Selected Letters of Friedrich Nietzsche. Edited and translated by Christopher Middleton. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing, Nietzsche, Friedrich. (TI) Twilight of the Idols. In Twilight of the Idols and The Anti- Christ. 2nd edn. Translated by R. J. Hollingdale. London: Penguin Books, Nietzsche, Friedrich. (UM) Untimely Meditations. Translated by R. J. Hollingdale. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, Nietzsche, Friedrich. (WLN) Writings from the Late Notebooks. Translated by Kate Sturge. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, Nietzsche, Friedrich. (WP) The Will to Power. (A posthumous publication of Nietzscheʼs notebooks). 2nd edn. Translated by Walter Kaufmann and R. J. Hollingdale. New York: Vintage Books, OʼShea, James R. (2012) Kantʼs Critique of Pure Reason. Durham: Acumen. Riccardi, Mattia. (2010) Nietzscheʼs Critique of Kantʼs Thing In Itself in Nietzsche- Studien 39, pp Scruton, Roger. (1982) Kant. Oxford & New York: Oxford University Press. Timmermann, Jens. (2007) Kantʼs Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals: A Commentary. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Timmermann, Jens (ed.) (2009) Kantʼs Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals: A Critical Guide. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Wittgenstein, Ludwig. Ed. G. H. Wright. Culture and Value. Oxford: Blackwell Publishing, 1998 (revised second edition). Wittgenstein, Ludwig. Philosophical Investigations. Oxford: Blackwell Publishing Ltd., 2001 (third edition).

THE STUDY OF UNKNOWN AND UNKNOWABILITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY

THE STUDY OF UNKNOWN AND UNKNOWABILITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY THE STUDY OF UNKNOWN AND UNKNOWABILITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY Subhankari Pati Research Scholar Pondicherry University, Pondicherry The present aim of this paper is to highlights the shortcomings in Kant

More information

Freedom as Morality. UWM Digital Commons. University of Wisconsin Milwaukee. Hao Liang University of Wisconsin-Milwaukee. Theses and Dissertations

Freedom as Morality. UWM Digital Commons. University of Wisconsin Milwaukee. Hao Liang University of Wisconsin-Milwaukee. Theses and Dissertations University of Wisconsin Milwaukee UWM Digital Commons Theses and Dissertations May 2014 Freedom as Morality Hao Liang University of Wisconsin-Milwaukee Follow this and additional works at: http://dc.uwm.edu/etd

More information

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory Western University Scholarship@Western 2015 Undergraduate Awards The Undergraduate Awards 2015 Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory David Hakim Western University, davidhakim266@gmail.com

More information

Kant and his Successors

Kant and his Successors Kant and his Successors G. J. Mattey Winter, 2011 / Philosophy 151 The Sorry State of Metaphysics Kant s Critique of Pure Reason (1781) was an attempt to put metaphysics on a scientific basis. Metaphysics

More information

This paper serves as an enquiry into whether or not a theory of metaphysics can grow

This paper serves as an enquiry into whether or not a theory of metaphysics can grow Mark B. Rasmuson For Harrison Kleiner s Kant and His Successors and Utah State s Fourth Annual Languages, Philosophy, and Speech Communication Student Research Symposium Spring 2008 This paper serves as

More information

From the Categorical Imperative to the Moral Law

From the Categorical Imperative to the Moral Law From the Categorical Imperative to the Moral Law Marianne Vahl Master Thesis in Philosophy Supervisor Olav Gjelsvik Department of Philosophy, Classics, History of Arts and Ideas UNIVERSITY OF OSLO May

More information

Resolutio of Idealism into Atheism in Fichte

Resolutio of Idealism into Atheism in Fichte Maria Pia Mater Thomistic Week 2018 Resolutio of Idealism into Atheism in Fichte Introduction Cornelio Fabro s God in Exile, traces the progression of modern atheism from its roots in the cogito of Rene

More information

1/5. The Critique of Theology

1/5. The Critique of Theology 1/5 The Critique of Theology The argument of the Transcendental Dialectic has demonstrated that there is no science of rational psychology and that the province of any rational cosmology is strictly limited.

More information

III Knowledge is true belief based on argument. Plato, Theaetetus, 201 c-d Is Justified True Belief Knowledge? Edmund Gettier

III Knowledge is true belief based on argument. Plato, Theaetetus, 201 c-d Is Justified True Belief Knowledge? Edmund Gettier III Knowledge is true belief based on argument. Plato, Theaetetus, 201 c-d Is Justified True Belief Knowledge? Edmund Gettier In Theaetetus Plato introduced the definition of knowledge which is often translated

More information

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras Module - 22 Lecture - 22 Kant The idea of Reason Soul, God

More information

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg 1 In Search of the Ontological Argument Richard Oxenberg Abstract We can attend to the logic of Anselm's ontological argument, and amuse ourselves for a few hours unraveling its convoluted word-play, or

More information

1/12. The A Paralogisms

1/12. The A Paralogisms 1/12 The A Paralogisms The character of the Paralogisms is described early in the chapter. Kant describes them as being syllogisms which contain no empirical premises and states that in them we conclude

More information

The Groundwork, the Second Critique, Pure Practical Reason and Motivation

The Groundwork, the Second Critique, Pure Practical Reason and Motivation 金沢星稜大学論集第 48 巻第 1 号平成 26 年 8 月 35 The Groundwork, the Second Critique, Pure Practical Reason and Motivation Shohei Edamura Introduction In this paper, I will critically examine Christine Korsgaard s claim

More information

Wittgenstein on The Realm of Ineffable

Wittgenstein on The Realm of Ineffable Wittgenstein on The Realm of Ineffable by Manoranjan Mallick and Vikram S. Sirola Abstract The paper attempts to delve into the distinction Wittgenstein makes between factual discourse and moral thoughts.

More information

7/31/2017. Kant and Our Ineradicable Desire to be God

7/31/2017. Kant and Our Ineradicable Desire to be God Radical Evil Kant and Our Ineradicable Desire to be God 1 Immanuel Kant (1724-1804) Kant indeed marks the end of the Enlightenment: he brought its most fundamental assumptions concerning the powers of

More information

1/10. The Fourth Paralogism and the Refutation of Idealism

1/10. The Fourth Paralogism and the Refutation of Idealism 1/10 The Fourth Paralogism and the Refutation of Idealism The Fourth Paralogism is quite different from the three that preceded it because, although it is treated as a part of rational psychology, it main

More information

Descartes and Schopenhauer on Voluntary Movement:

Descartes and Schopenhauer on Voluntary Movement: Descartes and Schopenhauer on Voluntary Movement: Why My Arm Is Lifted When I Will Lift It? Katsunori MATSUDA (Received on October 2, 2014) The purpose of this paper In the ordinary literature on modern

More information

1/8. Introduction to Kant: The Project of Critique

1/8. Introduction to Kant: The Project of Critique 1/8 Introduction to Kant: The Project of Critique This course is focused on the interpretation of one book: The Critique of Pure Reason and we will, during the course, read the majority of the key sections

More information

Accessing the Moral Law through Feeling

Accessing the Moral Law through Feeling Kantian Review, 20, 2,301 311 KantianReview, 2015 doi:10.1017/s1369415415000060 Accessing the Moral Law through Feeling owen ware Simon Fraser University Email: owenjware@gmail.com Abstract In this article

More information

FREEDOM AND THE SOURCE OF VALUE: KORSGAARD AND WOOD ON KANT S FORMULA OF HUMANITY CHRISTOPHER ARROYO

FREEDOM AND THE SOURCE OF VALUE: KORSGAARD AND WOOD ON KANT S FORMULA OF HUMANITY CHRISTOPHER ARROYO Published by Blackwell Publishing Ltd, 9600 Garsington Road, Oxford OX4 2DQ, UK, and 350 Main Street, Malden, MA 02148, USA METAPHILOSOPHY Vol. 42, No. 4, July 2011 0026-1068 FREEDOM AND THE SOURCE OF

More information

Excerpt from J. Garvey, The Twenty Greatest Philosophy Books (Continuum, 2007): Immanuel Kant s Critique of Pure Reason

Excerpt from J. Garvey, The Twenty Greatest Philosophy Books (Continuum, 2007): Immanuel Kant s Critique of Pure Reason Excerpt from J. Garvey, The Twenty Greatest Philosophy Books (Continuum, 2007): Immanuel Kant s Critique of Pure Reason In a letter to Moses Mendelssohn, Kant says this about the Critique of Pure Reason:

More information

Fr. Copleston vs. Bertrand Russell: The Famous 1948 BBC Radio Debate on the Existence of God

Fr. Copleston vs. Bertrand Russell: The Famous 1948 BBC Radio Debate on the Existence of God Fr. Copleston vs. Bertrand Russell: The Famous 1948 BBC Radio Debate on the Existence of God Father Frederick C. Copleston (Jesuit Catholic priest) versus Bertrand Russell (agnostic philosopher) Copleston:

More information

Moral Obligation. by Charles G. Finney

Moral Obligation. by Charles G. Finney Moral Obligation by Charles G. Finney The idea of obligation, or of oughtness, is an idea of the pure reason. It is a simple, rational conception, and, strictly speaking, does not admit of a definition,

More information

Ludwig Feuerbach The Essence of Christianity (excerpts) 1 PHIL101 Prof. Oakes updated: 10/23/13 9:10 AM. Section III: How do I know? Reading III.

Ludwig Feuerbach The Essence of Christianity (excerpts) 1 PHIL101 Prof. Oakes updated: 10/23/13 9:10 AM. Section III: How do I know? Reading III. Ludwig Feuerbach The Essence of Christianity (excerpts) 1 PHIL101 Prof. Oakes updated: 10/23/13 9:10 AM Section III: How do I know? Reading III.6 The German philosopher, Ludwig Feuerbach, develops a humanist

More information

The CopernicanRevolution

The CopernicanRevolution Immanuel Kant: The Copernican Revolution The CopernicanRevolution Immanuel Kant (1724-1804) The Critique of Pure Reason (1781) is Kant s best known work. In this monumental work, he begins a Copernican-like

More information

A HOLISTIC VIEW ON KNOWLEDGE AND VALUES

A HOLISTIC VIEW ON KNOWLEDGE AND VALUES A HOLISTIC VIEW ON KNOWLEDGE AND VALUES CHANHYU LEE Emory University It seems somewhat obscure that there is a concrete connection between epistemology and ethics; a study of knowledge and a study of moral

More information

The Middle Path: A Case for the Philosophical Theologian. Leo Strauss roots the vitality of Western civilization in the ongoing conflict between

The Middle Path: A Case for the Philosophical Theologian. Leo Strauss roots the vitality of Western civilization in the ongoing conflict between Lee Anne Detzel PHI 8338 Revised: November 1, 2004 The Middle Path: A Case for the Philosophical Theologian Leo Strauss roots the vitality of Western civilization in the ongoing conflict between philosophy

More information

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras Module - 21 Lecture - 21 Kant Forms of sensibility Categories

More information

Consciousness might be defined as the perceiver of mental phenomena. We might say that there are no differences between one perceiver and another, as

Consciousness might be defined as the perceiver of mental phenomena. We might say that there are no differences between one perceiver and another, as 2. DO THE VALUES THAT ARE CALLED HUMAN RIGHTS HAVE INDEPENDENT AND UNIVERSAL VALIDITY, OR ARE THEY HISTORICALLY AND CULTURALLY RELATIVE HUMAN INVENTIONS? Human rights significantly influence the fundamental

More information

24.01 Classics of Western Philosophy

24.01 Classics of Western Philosophy 1 Plan: Kant Lecture #2: How are pure mathematics and pure natural science possible? 1. Review: Problem of Metaphysics 2. Kantian Commitments 3. Pure Mathematics 4. Transcendental Idealism 5. Pure Natural

More information

Rationalism. A. He, like others at the time, was obsessed with questions of truth and doubt

Rationalism. A. He, like others at the time, was obsessed with questions of truth and doubt Rationalism I. Descartes (1596-1650) A. He, like others at the time, was obsessed with questions of truth and doubt 1. How could one be certain in the absence of religious guidance and trustworthy senses

More information

Tuesday, November 11, Hegel s Idealism

Tuesday, November 11, Hegel s Idealism Hegel s Idealism G. W. F. Hegel Hegel Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel (1770-1831) was perhaps the last great philosophical system builder. His distinctively dynamic form of idealism set the stage for other

More information

Projection in Hume. P J E Kail. St. Peter s College, Oxford.

Projection in Hume. P J E Kail. St. Peter s College, Oxford. Projection in Hume P J E Kail St. Peter s College, Oxford Peter.kail@spc.ox.ac.uk A while ago now (2007) I published my Projection and Realism in Hume s Philosophy (Oxford University Press henceforth abbreviated

More information

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras Module - 20 Lecture - 20 Critical Philosophy: Kant s objectives

More information

THE NATURE OF NORMATIVITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY OF LOGIC REBECCA V. MILLSOP S

THE NATURE OF NORMATIVITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY OF LOGIC REBECCA V. MILLSOP S THE NATURE OF NORMATIVITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY OF LOGIC REBECCA V. MILLSOP S I. INTRODUCTION Immanuel Kant claims that logic is constitutive of thought: without [the laws of logic] we would not think at

More information

The Copernican Shift and Theory of Knowledge in Immanuel Kant and Edmund Husserl.

The Copernican Shift and Theory of Knowledge in Immanuel Kant and Edmund Husserl. The Copernican Shift and Theory of Knowledge in Immanuel Kant and Edmund Husserl. Matthew O Neill. BA in Politics & International Studies and Philosophy, Murdoch University, 2012. This thesis is presented

More information

LOCKE STUDIES Vol ISSN: X

LOCKE STUDIES Vol ISSN: X LOCKE STUDIES Vol. 18 https://doi.org/10.5206/ls.2018.3525 ISSN: 2561-925X Submitted: 28 JUNE 2018 Published online: 30 JULY 2018 For more information, see this article s homepage. 2018. Nathan Rockwood

More information

Thought is Being or Thought and Being? Feuerbach and his Criticism of Hegel's Absolute Idealism by Martin Jenkins

Thought is Being or Thought and Being? Feuerbach and his Criticism of Hegel's Absolute Idealism by Martin Jenkins Thought is Being or Thought and Being? Feuerbach and his Criticism of Hegel's Absolute Idealism by Martin Jenkins Although he was once an ardent follower of the Philosophy of GWF Hegel, Ludwig Feuerbach

More information

Modern Philosophy II

Modern Philosophy II Modern Philosophy II 2016-17 Michaelmas: Kant Reading List and Essay Titles Lectures & tutorials: Dr. Andrew Cooper Module aims To introduce students to Kant s Critique of Pure Reason and to the philosophies

More information

Has Logical Positivism Eliminated Metaphysics?

Has Logical Positivism Eliminated Metaphysics? International Journal of Humanities and Social Science Invention ISSN (Online): 2319 7722, ISSN (Print): 2319 7714 Volume 3 Issue 11 ǁ November. 2014 ǁ PP.38-42 Has Logical Positivism Eliminated Metaphysics?

More information

A Studying of Limitation of Epistemology as Basis of Toleration with Special Reference to John Locke

A Studying of Limitation of Epistemology as Basis of Toleration with Special Reference to John Locke A Studying of Limitation of Epistemology as Basis of Toleration with Special Reference to John Locke Roghieh Tamimi and R. P. Singh Center for philosophy, Social Science School, Jawaharlal Nehru University,

More information

Tuesday, September 2, Idealism

Tuesday, September 2, Idealism Idealism Enlightenment Puzzle How do these fit into a scientific picture of the world? Norms Necessity Universality Mind Idealism The dominant 19th-century response: often today called anti-realism Everything

More information

Introductory Kant Seminar Lecture

Introductory Kant Seminar Lecture Introductory Kant Seminar Lecture Intentionality It is not unusual to begin a discussion of Kant with a brief review of some history of philosophy. What is perhaps less usual is to start with a review

More information

The Boundaries of Hegel s Criticism of Kant s Concept of the Noumenal

The Boundaries of Hegel s Criticism of Kant s Concept of the Noumenal Arthur Kok, Tilburg The Boundaries of Hegel s Criticism of Kant s Concept of the Noumenal Kant conceives of experience as the synthesis of understanding and intuition. Hegel argues that because Kant is

More information

Unifying the Categorical Imperative* Marcus Arvan University of Tampa

Unifying the Categorical Imperative* Marcus Arvan University of Tampa Unifying the Categorical Imperative* Marcus Arvan University of Tampa [T]he concept of freedom constitutes the keystone of the whole structure of a system of pure reason [and] this idea reveals itself

More information

The Unbearable Lightness of Theory of Knowledge:

The Unbearable Lightness of Theory of Knowledge: The Unbearable Lightness of Theory of Knowledge: Desert Mountain High School s Summer Reading in five easy steps! STEP ONE: Read these five pages important background about basic TOK concepts: Knowing

More information

Verificationism. PHIL September 27, 2011

Verificationism. PHIL September 27, 2011 Verificationism PHIL 83104 September 27, 2011 1. The critique of metaphysics... 1 2. Observation statements... 2 3. In principle verifiability... 3 4. Strong verifiability... 3 4.1. Conclusive verifiability

More information

Wittgenstein on forms of life: a short introduction

Wittgenstein on forms of life: a short introduction E-LOGOS Electronic Journal for Philosophy 2017, Vol. 24(1) 13 18 ISSN 1211-0442 (DOI 10.18267/j.e-logos.440),Peer-reviewed article Journal homepage: e-logos.vse.cz Wittgenstein on forms of life: a short

More information

Today we turn to the work of one of the most important, and also most difficult, philosophers: Immanuel Kant.

Today we turn to the work of one of the most important, and also most difficult, philosophers: Immanuel Kant. Kant s antinomies Today we turn to the work of one of the most important, and also most difficult, philosophers: Immanuel Kant. Kant was born in 1724 in Prussia, and his philosophical work has exerted

More information

To appear in The Journal of Philosophy.

To appear in The Journal of Philosophy. To appear in The Journal of Philosophy. Lucy Allais: Manifest Reality: Kant s Idealism and his Realism. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2015, pp. xi + 329. 40.00 (hb). ISBN: 9780198747130. Kant s doctrine

More information

1/6. The Resolution of the Antinomies

1/6. The Resolution of the Antinomies 1/6 The Resolution of the Antinomies Kant provides us with the resolutions of the antinomies in order, starting with the first and ending with the fourth. The first antinomy, as we recall, concerned the

More information

Categorical Imperative by. Kant

Categorical Imperative by. Kant Categorical Imperative by Dr. Desh Raj Sirswal Assistant Professor (Philosophy), P.G.Govt. College for Girls, Sector-11, Chandigarh http://drsirswal.webs.com Kant Immanuel Kant Immanuel Kant (1724 1804)

More information

Duns Scotus on Divine Illumination

Duns Scotus on Divine Illumination MP_C13.qxd 11/23/06 2:29 AM Page 110 13 Duns Scotus on Divine Illumination [Article IV. Concerning Henry s Conclusion] In the fourth article I argue against the conclusion of [Henry s] view as follows:

More information

Examining the nature of mind. Michael Daniels. A review of Understanding Consciousness by Max Velmans (Routledge, 2000).

Examining the nature of mind. Michael Daniels. A review of Understanding Consciousness by Max Velmans (Routledge, 2000). Examining the nature of mind Michael Daniels A review of Understanding Consciousness by Max Velmans (Routledge, 2000). Max Velmans is Reader in Psychology at Goldsmiths College, University of London. Over

More information

Leibniz, Principles, and Truth 1

Leibniz, Principles, and Truth 1 Leibniz, Principles, and Truth 1 Leibniz was a man of principles. 2 Throughout his writings, one finds repeated assertions that his view is developed according to certain fundamental principles. Attempting

More information

KANT'S PROLEGOMENA TO ANY FUTURE METAPHYSICS CHICAGO DR. PAUL CARUS THE OPEN COURT PUBLISHING COMPANY

KANT'S PROLEGOMENA TO ANY FUTURE METAPHYSICS CHICAGO DR. PAUL CARUS THE OPEN COURT PUBLISHING COMPANY KANT'S PROLEGOMENA TO ANY FUTURE METAPHYSICS EDITED IN ENGLISH DR. PAUL CARUS WITH AN ESSAY ON KANT'S PHILOSOPHY, AND OTHER SUPPLEMENTARY MATERIAL FOR THE STUDY OF KANT CHICAGO THE OPEN COURT PUBLISHING

More information

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy Res Cogitans Volume 5 Issue 1 Article 20 6-4-2014 Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy Kevin Harriman Lewis & Clark College Follow this and additional works at: http://commons.pacificu.edu/rescogitans

More information

The Paradox of the stone and two concepts of omnipotence

The Paradox of the stone and two concepts of omnipotence Filo Sofija Nr 30 (2015/3), s. 239-246 ISSN 1642-3267 Jacek Wojtysiak John Paul II Catholic University of Lublin The Paradox of the stone and two concepts of omnipotence Introduction The history of science

More information

Introduction. I. Proof of the Minor Premise ( All reality is completely intelligible )

Introduction. I. Proof of the Minor Premise ( All reality is completely intelligible ) Philosophical Proof of God: Derived from Principles in Bernard Lonergan s Insight May 2014 Robert J. Spitzer, S.J., Ph.D. Magis Center of Reason and Faith Lonergan s proof may be stated as follows: Introduction

More information

PH 329: Seminar in Kant Fall 2010 L.M. Jorgensen

PH 329: Seminar in Kant Fall 2010 L.M. Jorgensen PH 329: Seminar in Kant Fall 2010 L.M. Jorgensen Immanuel Kant (1724 1804) was one of the most influential philosophers of the modern period. This seminar will begin with a close study Kant s Critique

More information

7AAN2039 Kant I: Critique of Pure Reason Syllabus Academic year 2015/16

7AAN2039 Kant I: Critique of Pure Reason Syllabus Academic year 2015/16 7AAN2039 Kant I: Critique of Pure Reason Syllabus Academic year 2015/16 Basic information Credits: 20 Module Tutor: Dr Sacha Golob Office: 705, Philosophy Building Consultation time: 11:00 12:00 Wed Semester:

More information

Kant and Demystification of Ethics and Religion *

Kant and Demystification of Ethics and Religion * University of Tabriz-Iran Philosophical Investigations Vol. 11/ No. 21/ Fall & Winter 2017 Kant and Demystification of Ethics and Religion * Qodratullah Qorbani ** Associate Professor of Philosophy, Kharazmi

More information

This handout follows the handout on The nature of the sceptic s challenge. You should read that handout first.

This handout follows the handout on The nature of the sceptic s challenge. You should read that handout first. Michael Lacewing Three responses to scepticism This handout follows the handout on The nature of the sceptic s challenge. You should read that handout first. MITIGATED SCEPTICISM The term mitigated scepticism

More information

Today we turn to the work of one of the most important, and also most difficult, philosophers: Immanuel Kant.

Today we turn to the work of one of the most important, and also most difficult, philosophers: Immanuel Kant. Kant s antinomies Today we turn to the work of one of the most important, and also most difficult, philosophers: Immanuel Kant. Kant was born in 1724 in Prussia, and his philosophical work has exerted

More information

Summary of Kant s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals

Summary of Kant s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals Summary of Kant s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals Version 1.1 Richard Baron 2 October 2016 1 Contents 1 Introduction 3 1.1 Availability and licence............ 3 2 Definitions of key terms 4 3

More information

CHAPTER III KANT S APPROACH TO A PRIORI AND A POSTERIORI

CHAPTER III KANT S APPROACH TO A PRIORI AND A POSTERIORI CHAPTER III KANT S APPROACH TO A PRIORI AND A POSTERIORI Introduction One could easily find out two most influential epistemological doctrines, namely, rationalism and empiricism that have inadequate solutions

More information

KANT S EXPLANATION OF THE NECESSITY OF GEOMETRICAL TRUTHS. John Watling

KANT S EXPLANATION OF THE NECESSITY OF GEOMETRICAL TRUTHS. John Watling KANT S EXPLANATION OF THE NECESSITY OF GEOMETRICAL TRUTHS John Watling Kant was an idealist. His idealism was in some ways, it is true, less extreme than that of Berkeley. He distinguished his own by calling

More information

Today we turn to the work of one of the most important, and also most difficult, of philosophers: Immanuel Kant.

Today we turn to the work of one of the most important, and also most difficult, of philosophers: Immanuel Kant. Kant s antinomies Today we turn to the work of one of the most important, and also most difficult, of philosophers: Immanuel Kant. Kant was born in 1724 in Prussia, and his philosophical work has exerted

More information

Thursday, November 30, 17. Hegel s Idealism

Thursday, November 30, 17. Hegel s Idealism Hegel s Idealism G. W. F. Hegel Hegel Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel (1770-1831) was perhaps the last great philosophical system builder. His distinctively dynamic form of idealism set the stage for other

More information

Ayer on the criterion of verifiability

Ayer on the criterion of verifiability Ayer on the criterion of verifiability November 19, 2004 1 The critique of metaphysics............................. 1 2 Observation statements............................... 2 3 In principle verifiability...............................

More information

Important dates. PSY 3360 / CGS 3325 Historical Perspectives on Psychology Minds and Machines since David Hume ( )

Important dates. PSY 3360 / CGS 3325 Historical Perspectives on Psychology Minds and Machines since David Hume ( ) PSY 3360 / CGS 3325 Historical Perspectives on Psychology Minds and Machines since 1600 Dr. Peter Assmann Spring 2018 Important dates Feb 14 Term paper draft due Upload paper to E-Learning https://elearning.utdallas.edu

More information

In Kant s Conception of Humanity, Joshua Glasgow defends a traditional reading of

In Kant s Conception of Humanity, Joshua Glasgow defends a traditional reading of Glasgow s Conception of Kantian Humanity Richard Dean ABSTRACT: In Kant s Conception of Humanity, Joshua Glasgow defends a traditional reading of the humanity formulation of the Categorical Imperative.

More information

1/8. The Schematism. schema of empirical concepts, the schema of sensible concepts and the

1/8. The Schematism. schema of empirical concepts, the schema of sensible concepts and the 1/8 The Schematism I am going to distinguish between three types of schematism: the schema of empirical concepts, the schema of sensible concepts and the schema of pure concepts. Kant opens the discussion

More information

Kant and the 19 th Century ***Syllabus***

Kant and the 19 th Century ***Syllabus*** Prof. James Conant and Dr. Nicholas Koziolek Phil 27000 University of Chicago Spring Quarter, 2016 Course Description Kant and the 19 th Century ***Syllabus*** The philosophical ideas and methods of Immanuel

More information

Kant s Misrepresentations of Hume s Philosophy of Mathematics in the Prolegomena

Kant s Misrepresentations of Hume s Philosophy of Mathematics in the Prolegomena Kant s Misrepresentations of Hume s Philosophy of Mathematics in the Prolegomena Mark Steiner Hume Studies Volume XIII, Number 2 (November, 1987) 400-410. Your use of the HUME STUDIES archive indicates

More information

Contemporary Theology I: Hegel to Death of God Theologies

Contemporary Theology I: Hegel to Death of God Theologies Contemporary Theology I: Hegel to Death of God Theologies ST503 LESSON 19 of 24 John S. Feinberg, Ph.D. Experience: Professor of Biblical and Systematic Theology, Trinity Evangelical Divinity School. In

More information

Kantian Humility and Ontological Categories Sam Cowling University of Massachusetts, Amherst

Kantian Humility and Ontological Categories Sam Cowling University of Massachusetts, Amherst Kantian Humility and Ontological Categories Sam Cowling University of Massachusetts, Amherst [Forthcoming in Analysis. Penultimate Draft. Cite published version.] Kantian Humility holds that agents like

More information

FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. by Immanuel Kant

FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. by Immanuel Kant FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS SECOND SECTION by Immanuel Kant TRANSITION FROM POPULAR MORAL PHILOSOPHY TO THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS... This principle, that humanity and generally every

More information

Epistemology and sensation

Epistemology and sensation Cazeaux, C. (2016). Epistemology and sensation. In H. Miller (ed.), Sage Encyclopaedia of Theory in Psychology Volume 1, Thousand Oaks: Sage: 294 7. Epistemology and sensation Clive Cazeaux Sensation refers

More information

SUPPORT MATERIAL FOR 'DETERMINISM AND FREE WILL ' (UNIT 2 TOPIC 5)

SUPPORT MATERIAL FOR 'DETERMINISM AND FREE WILL ' (UNIT 2 TOPIC 5) SUPPORT MATERIAL FOR 'DETERMINISM AND FREE WILL ' (UNIT 2 TOPIC 5) Introduction We often say things like 'I couldn't resist buying those trainers'. In saying this, we presumably mean that the desire to

More information

Stabilizing Kant s First and Second Critiques: Causality and Freedom

Stabilizing Kant s First and Second Critiques: Causality and Freedom Stabilizing Kant s First and Second Critiques: Causality and Freedom Justin Yee * B.A. Candidate, Department of Philosophy, California State University Stanislaus, 1 University Circle, Turlock, CA 95382

More information

Understanding How we Come to Experience Purposive. Behavior. Jacob Roundtree. Colby College Mayflower Hill, Waterville, ME USA

Understanding How we Come to Experience Purposive. Behavior. Jacob Roundtree. Colby College Mayflower Hill, Waterville, ME USA Understanding How we Come to Experience Purposive Behavior Jacob Roundtree Colby College 6984 Mayflower Hill, Waterville, ME 04901 USA 1-347-241-4272 Ludwig von Mises, one of the Great 20 th Century economists,

More information

Happiness and Personal Growth: Dial.

Happiness and Personal Growth: Dial. TitleKant's Concept of Happiness: Within Author(s) Hirose, Yuzo Happiness and Personal Growth: Dial Citation Philosophy, Psychology, and Compara 43-49 Issue Date 2010-03-31 URL http://hdl.handle.net/2433/143022

More information

Sufficient Reason and Infinite Regress: Causal Consistency in Descartes and Spinoza. Ryan Steed

Sufficient Reason and Infinite Regress: Causal Consistency in Descartes and Spinoza. Ryan Steed Sufficient Reason and Infinite Regress: Causal Consistency in Descartes and Spinoza Ryan Steed PHIL 2112 Professor Rebecca Car October 15, 2018 Steed 2 While both Baruch Spinoza and René Descartes espouse

More information

The fact that some action, A, is part of a valuable and eligible pattern of action, P, is a reason to perform A. 1

The fact that some action, A, is part of a valuable and eligible pattern of action, P, is a reason to perform A. 1 The Common Structure of Kantianism and Act Consequentialism Christopher Woodard RoME 2009 1. My thesis is that Kantian ethics and Act Consequentialism share a common structure, since both can be well understood

More information

The Character of Space in Kant s First Critique By Justin Murphy October 16, 2006

The Character of Space in Kant s First Critique By Justin Murphy October 16, 2006 The Character of Space in Kant s First Critique By Justin Murphy October 16, 2006 The familiar problems of skepticism necessarily entangled in empiricist epistemology can only be avoided with recourse

More information

Charles Hartshorne argues that Kant s criticisms of Anselm s ontological

Charles Hartshorne argues that Kant s criticisms of Anselm s ontological Aporia vol. 18 no. 2 2008 The Ontological Parody: A Reply to Joshua Ernst s Charles Hartshorne and the Ontological Argument Charles Hartshorne argues that Kant s criticisms of Anselm s ontological argument

More information

In Defense of Pure Reason: A Rationalist Account of A Priori Justification, by Laurence BonJour. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,

In Defense of Pure Reason: A Rationalist Account of A Priori Justification, by Laurence BonJour. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, Book Reviews 1 In Defense of Pure Reason: A Rationalist Account of A Priori Justification, by Laurence BonJour. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998. Pp. xiv + 232. H/b 37.50, $54.95, P/b 13.95,

More information

Kant's philosophy of the self.

Kant's philosophy of the self. University of Massachusetts Amherst ScholarWorks@UMass Amherst Masters Theses 1911 - February 2014 Dissertations and Theses 1987 Kant's philosophy of the self. Michio Fushihara University of Massachusetts

More information

Spinoza and the Axiomatic Method. Ever since Euclid first laid out his geometry in the Elements, his axiomatic approach to

Spinoza and the Axiomatic Method. Ever since Euclid first laid out his geometry in the Elements, his axiomatic approach to Haruyama 1 Justin Haruyama Bryan Smith HON 213 17 April 2008 Spinoza and the Axiomatic Method Ever since Euclid first laid out his geometry in the Elements, his axiomatic approach to geometry has been

More information

Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus (abridged version) Ludwig Wittgenstein

Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus (abridged version) Ludwig Wittgenstein Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus (abridged version) Ludwig Wittgenstein PREFACE This book will perhaps only be understood by those who have themselves already thought the thoughts which are expressed in

More information

The Impossibility of Evil Qua Evil: Kantian Limitations on Human Immorality

The Impossibility of Evil Qua Evil: Kantian Limitations on Human Immorality Georgia State University ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University Philosophy Theses Department of Philosophy 7-31-2006 The Impossibility of Evil Qua Evil: Kantian Limitations on Human Immorality Timothy

More information

A Most Affecting View: Transcendental Affection as Causation De-Schematized. Chad Mohler

A Most Affecting View: Transcendental Affection as Causation De-Schematized. Chad Mohler A Most Affecting View: Transcendental Affection as Causation De-Schematized Abstract Kant claims that things-in-themselves produce in us sensible representations. Unfortunately, this transcendental affection

More information

THE FREEDOM OF THE WILL By Immanuel Kant From Critique of Pure Reason (1781)

THE FREEDOM OF THE WILL By Immanuel Kant From Critique of Pure Reason (1781) THE FREEDOM OF THE WILL By Immanuel Kant From Critique of Pure Reason (1781) From: A447/B475 A451/B479 Freedom independence of the laws of nature is certainly a deliverance from restraint, but it is also

More information

Every simple idea has a simple impression, which resembles it; and every simple impression a correspondent idea

Every simple idea has a simple impression, which resembles it; and every simple impression a correspondent idea 'Every simple idea has a simple impression, which resembles it; and every simple impression a correspondent idea' (Treatise, Book I, Part I, Section I). What defence does Hume give of this principle and

More information

Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics 1. By Tom Cumming

Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics 1. By Tom Cumming Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics 1 By Tom Cumming Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics represents Martin Heidegger's first attempt at an interpretation of Kant's Critique of Pure Reason (1781). This

More information

THE MORAL ARGUMENT. Peter van Inwagen. Introduction, James Petrik

THE MORAL ARGUMENT. Peter van Inwagen. Introduction, James Petrik THE MORAL ARGUMENT Peter van Inwagen Introduction, James Petrik THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHICAL DISCUSSIONS of human freedom is closely intertwined with the history of philosophical discussions of moral responsibility.

More information

Some Notes Toward a Genealogy of Existential Philosophy Robert Burch

Some Notes Toward a Genealogy of Existential Philosophy Robert Burch Some Notes Toward a Genealogy of Existential Philosophy Robert Burch Descartes - ostensive task: to secure by ungainsayable rational means the orthodox doctrines of faith regarding the existence of God

More information

FIL 4600/10/20: KANT S CRITIQUE AND CRITICAL METAPHYSICS

FIL 4600/10/20: KANT S CRITIQUE AND CRITICAL METAPHYSICS FIL 4600/10/20: KANT S CRITIQUE AND CRITICAL METAPHYSICS Autumn 2012, University of Oslo Thursdays, 14 16, Georg Morgenstiernes hus 219, Blindern Toni Kannisto t.t.kannisto@ifikk.uio.no SHORT PLAN 1 23/8:

More information

On Exceeding Determination and the Ideal of Reason

On Exceeding Determination and the Ideal of Reason On Exceeding Determination and the Ideal of Reason On Exceeding Determination and the Ideal of Reason: Immanuel Kant, William Desmond, and the Noumenological Principle By Christopher David Shaw On Exceeding

More information