WHAT RAWLS CALLS JUSTICE

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "WHAT RAWLS CALLS JUSTICE"

Transcription

1 WHAT RAWLS CALLS JUSTICE Wallace Matson Carnap, seeking to clear up a difficulty in semantics, once suggested that we might translate expressions like 'This book treats of Africa' into ''This book contains the word Africa. ' 1 The proposal was shot down by a critic who noted that there could be "a book describing Australia but miscalling it Africa. " 2 John Rawls has provided a real-life instance of this type. Although the word justice occurs in the title and well over a thousand times in the text, his celebrated booka Theory of Justice 3 is not aboutjustice. I defend this allegation in the first part of this paper. In the second I speculate about the reasons behind Rawls' curious exercise. I Early in his book (5) Rawls, following Hart, draws a distinction between "the concept of justice," on which men agree, and "the various conceptions of justice," which are in dispute. 4 His aim is to recommend a certain conception of justice - not the only conception, for there are many; but the most adequate one. Now since I shall be arguing that in fact Rawls fails to put forward any conception of justice at all, whether adequate or inadequate, and since the main premise of my argument will be that his alleged conception of justice does not fall under the concept of justice, it is desirable to fix this distinction as clearly as possible.

2 46 THE OCCASIONAL REVIEW It will be helpful to begin by considering another notion, that of chastity. What is chastity? Different moralists will give different answers to this question. Some may say that it consists in abstention from illicit sexual activity (and those who agree on this definition may yet disagree on what particular activities are illicit); others that only complete abstinence from sex qualifies as chastity; still others that overt manifestations are not the crux, chastity requires also the avoidance of impure thoughts; and so on. These are different conceptions of chastity. But what makes them different conceptions of chastity is that they all agree in presupposing a certain minimal definition. Chastity has to do with sexual conduct (in the broadest sense), and it signifies purity in this respect. Chastity is sexual purity. That is the concept of chastity. We can tell that is the concept by noting that 'Whoever is chaste is sexually pure, and whoever is sexually pure is chaste' expresses a conceptual truth, that is to say, the sentence is true simply in virtue of the way these words are used in English. On the other hand, 'Whoever refrains from incest is chaste and whoever is chaste refrains from incest' would be taken as true not by every competent speaker of English but only by those whose conception of chastity, i.e. of sexual purity, was that it consisted in avoiding incest, and in nothing else. It might happen that some society from time immemorial had accepted a conception of chastity as avoidance of illicit sexual activity. And then a reformer might preach that lusting in the heart, even without doing anything overtly, was a violation of chastity. This prophet might be said to be 'redefining chastity.' It is important to note, however, that this 'redefinition' consists in the supplanting of one conception by another conception. Both before and after the redefinition, people using the word are talking about sexual purity. Replacement of one conception by another does not mean any change in concept. On the contrary, there could not be any such replacement unless the concept stood still. Concepts (in the Hart-Rawls sense) are non-controversial. Suppose that someone, at the present time, were to write a work called A Theory of Chastity, advocating a conception such that a person would be considered chaste just to the extent of his conformity to two Principles of Chastity: first, that he should own no more goods than absolutely necessary to support life; second, that he should obey his superiors in all things. Should we say that this book was about chastity? Obviously not; the author's claim, however sincere, must be rejected. For poverty and obedience are not conceptually linked to chastity. The concept of poverty has to do with the relation between persons and property, not with sexual behavior. This is so even if it should turn out that as a matter of fact all and only poor people are chaste. Similarly for obedience. We should have to say that the author had not produced a conception of chastity, either a right one or a wrong one; he was conceptually confused, like a man writing about

3 What Rawls Calls Justice 47 Australia but calling it Africa. For it is not possible even to begin to disagree with current conceptions of chastity and urge their modification or replacement, without accepting the concept. This acceptance of the concept is what makes the disagreement a disagreement about chastity. And, it is important to note, we should have to say this even if we had no objection, in principle, to 'redefining of terms.' The kind of redefining about which we may be permissive is that in which we alter conceptions. With these points in mind let us look at Rawls' formulation of the concept of justice, or rather of just institutions: "institutions are just when no arbitrary distinctions are made between persons in the assigning of basic rights and duties and when the rules determine a proper balance between competing claims to the advantages of social life.'' (5) Does this capture the concept of justice? (Concepts are non-controversial. It does not follow that every attempt to express a concept is correct.) Rawls' claim that this is a formulation on which "those who hold different conceptions of justice can... still agree" is questionable. For one thing, the presupposition that "basic rights and duties" are "assigned" 5 by "institutions" would be queried by those, such as Locke, Jefferson, and Nozick, who hold that rights are prior to institutions. Leaving that aside, the formulation is still unsatisfactory since it fails to cover the typical activities of the paradigmatic institutions of justice, namely, the courts. A court of justice is not ordinarily concerned with determining a proper balance between competing claims. That is the work of politicians and arbitrators. Judges, when confronted with competing claims, are concerned with deciding which one is right, has merit, is justified. Nor do judges assign basic rights and duties. Arbitrary distinctions between persons in the assigning of basic rights and duties (or anything else) are unjust, to be sure; but the reason they are is that, by definition, they fail to award persons their due. Well then, what is the concept of justice? Let us consider the traditional formula that it is the rendering to each person his due. This is, to be sure, personal justice, which Rawls explicitly disclaims any intention of discussing. However, the traditional concept of institutional justice is built upon that of personal justice: institutions (laws, customs, ''the basic structure of society'' if you will) are just to the extent that they facilitate rendering to each man his due, unjust when they frustrate it. In accord with this traditional concept, conceptions of justice may differ concerning what is someone's due, e.g. according to one conception a man's due is the market value of his product; according to another, it is commensurate to the social benefit of his

4 48 THE OCCASIONAL REVIEW work; etc. To paraphrase Austin, the concept is never the last word, but it is the.first. Now the traditional concept of justice is, in fact, the right one. To say this is not to advance a philosophical thesis but merely to make an observation about the English language, parallel to the observation that the concept of chastity is that of sexual purity. Anyone who wishes to deny that justice is giving every man his due must be prepared to allow the possibility of circumstances in which it would be correct to say 'This is not his due - this is not ''what is coming to him" -yet it is just for him to have it,' or 'This is his due, but it is just to deprive him of it.' And expressions of these forms are manifestly self-contradictory, as it is self-contradictory to say 'He is chaste but sexually impure' etc. 6 Now let us turn to the Rawlsian conception of justice and ask whether it is subsumable under the concept. The conception is summarized in two principles, stated first on page 60 and then with some modifications on page 302. The first principle is that "each person is to have an equal right to the most extensive basic liberty compatible with a similar liberty for others." (60) But this is not, and cannot be, a principle ofjustice any more than poverty can be a principle of chastity. If it were, then "with liberty and justice for all" would be a pleonasm. We must not let our approval of both liberty and justice blind us to the fact that they are two different things. There may be little or no liberty in a prison, monastery, or despotism, yet it makes perfect sense to speak of the warden, abbot, or despot as ruling justly or unjustly, and of the justice or injustice of the rules and regulations. Conversely, one might conceivably enjoy the fullest liberty under a regime which nevertheless capriciously imposed penalties and confiscations, thus acting unjustly. But if A and B can exist each without the other, neither A nor B is part of the concept of the other. So Rawls' justice, or R-justice as I shall henceforth call it, cannot be a conception, that is to say a specification or making-more-precise, of the concept justice. It contains an extraneous notion, namely liberty. While there may be some factual connection between liberty and justice such that, at least in extensive and heterogeneous societies, the one cannot exist without the other, there is no conceptual connection. Perhaps chastity is hard to preserve without the aid of poverty; all the same, poverty is not part of the concept of chastity. 1 This is enough, in logic, to show that R-justice is not a conception of justice. But the possibility is still open that R-justice is justice plus something more, viz. liberty. In that case, the second principle of R-justice would fall under the concept of justice. Let us consider this possibility.

5 What Rawls Calls Justice 49 The second principle of R-justice is: "social and economic inequalities are to be arranged so that they are both (a) reasonably expected to be to everyone's advantage, and (b) attached to positions and offices open to all." (60) The (a) part is the famous Difference Principle, to the elaboration and defense of which much of the book is devoted. The final and official statement (302) of this principle is: "Social and economic inequalities are to be arranged so that they are... (a) to the greatest benefit of the least advantaged, consistent with the just savings principle." In our discussion we can ignore the "just savings principle," which is a constraint introduced to prevent exhaustion of resources in a single generation. Our question then is whether our concept of distributive justice (which is what we are here concerned with) is satisfied by the difference principle; that is to say, whether to the question, 'How are things to be distributed in order to insure that the distribution is just?' a possible answer is: 'So that they are to the greatest benefit of the least advantaged.' We do not need to determine here whether this is the 'right' answer; merely whether it is a conceptually coherent answer. I shall argue that it is not. The easiest way to perceive the irrelevance to justice of the difference principle is to observe that it contains no reference, either explicit or implicit, to desert-which is the essence of the concept of justice. It is not the case, nor does Rawls claim, that the least advantaged (whoever they are) deserve, have as their due, the extraordinary solicitude to be lavished upon them. On the contrary, Rawls holds that no one deserves anything, really. Those who are better endowed, or ''more fortunate'' in their social position, cannot be said to deserve their advantages (15); these are determined (as things now stand) by "the natural lottery" (74). "Even the willingness to make an effort, to try, and so to be deserving in the ordinary sense is itself dependent upon happy family and social circumstances" (74). Now one might suppose Rawls to be saying what is undoubtedly trne, that natural endowments are non-deserved - neither deserved nor undeserved, the notion of desert does not apply to them. But no. Rawls says (I 00) that "since inequalities of birth and natural endowment are undeserved, these inc;qualities are to be somehow compensated for.'' (My emphasis.) We see then that the difference principle represents, in effect, an agreement to regard the distribution of natural talents as a common asset and to share in the benefits of this distribution whatever it turns out to be. Those who have been favored by nature, whoever they are, may gain from their good fortune only on terms that improve the situation of those who have lost out. The naturally advantaged are not to gain merely because they are more gifted, but only to cover the

6 50 THE OCCASIONAL REVIEW costs of training and education and for using their endowments in ways tha; help the less fortunate as well. No one deserves his greater natural capacity nor merits a more favorable starting place in society. (IOI f.) The Rawlsian argument seems to be: No one deserves his natural endowments. Therefore, no one deserves the fruits of their exercise. This is of course a non-sequitur, like: No lovable person deserves his innate lovable qu:1lities, therefore no lovable person deserves to be loved - and inequalities in lovableness are to be somehow compensated for, perhaps by requiring the lovable to love only the unlovable. To be sure, Rawls does allow a certain positive content to the notion of desert: If the government announces that a certain behavior will be rewarded, then those who behave in the prescribed manner deserve the reward. "But this sense of desert presupposes the existence of the cooperative scheme,'' (I 03) that is to say, desert is created by the government, so cannot afford a criterion of what the function of the government should be. This contention thus reinforces my claim that the difference principle is independent of desert (which for Rawls has no existence apart from reasons of state) and is therefore not a principle of justice, not even a wrong one. We come finally to the (b) part of the second principle ofr-justice, the final form of which is: "Social and economic inequalities are to be arranged so that they are... (b) attached to offices and positions open to all under conditions of fair equality of opportunity." I think this is a principle of fairness rather than justice (for the difference see Part II), but I do not wish to press this perhaps over-subtle point. Ifwe concede that in this principle R-justice does express one requirement of a just society, to that extent the claim that Rawls has nothing to say about justice must be softened to 'Well, hardly anything.'

7 What Rawls Calls Justice 51 II A melon-cup that no longer resembles a melon-cup and people still say, 'A melon-cup! A melon-cup!' - Confucius ldo not suppose that if perchance a Rawlsian were to read the first part of this paper he would fall to trembling and stuttering. He might observe that there must be something wrong with these objections, since even so astute and severe a critic of Rawls as Nozick has not gone so far as to accuse him of conceptual confusion. He would then point out as the obvious source of my confusion, my culpable overlooking of Rawls' repeated statements (first at page 7) that he was discussing social justice, with which my strictures concerning ''the attitudes and dispositions of persons" (7) have nothing to do. My rejoinder would be that there are not two kinds of justice, social and personal, but only one. Justice exists only in transactions between persons. Of some (by no means all) of the things one person does to another, some may be said to be done justly, some unjustly. Institutions and even ''the basic structure of society'' can only be just or unjust in the derivative sense that people behaving in accordance with them act justly or unjustly. But I think I have shown that any person acting according to the first principle of R-justice would be furthering liberty, not justice, thus could be acting justly only per accidens if at all; and that a person following the precept of the difference principle would be doing something equally devoid of conceptual linkage to justice. These complaints are certainly not irrelevant to a book entitled A Theory of Justice. However, this exchange does not go to the heart of the matter. The considerations on which I have relied to support the contention of conceptual confusion in Rawls are not complicated or subtle. Why then, if they are sound, have they been overlooked? How has Rawls managed to get away with it? And how can we explain why Rawls himself was taken in? I shall now try to answer these questions. In many ways Rawls deserves the sobriquet of Locke in our time. Both men tried to provide ideological underpinning for political practices that had come to be accepted as right despite their deviation from what were hitherto the received canons of propriety. Locke justified limited monarchy; Rawls justifies welfarism. Beginning with the New Deal, the thrust of government policy in this country, with analogues throughout the world, has been toward economic, social, and educational equality, brought about through use of the taxing power. Since government produces nothing, the only means at its disposal is to take from those who have more and give to

8 52 THE OCCASIONAL REVIEW those with less. Government can do this because it is the ultimate repository of force. But despite the fundamental change in policy, the official ideology has largely continued to be that of "free enterprise' - let people compete, openly and aboveboard, and let the most hard-working, efficient, and intelligent keep what they can get. Government was seen as umpire, and, in anti-trust legislation, as counteracting the alleged tendency of competition to end in monopoly. When departures in practice from this ideology were too flagrant to escape notice, they tended to be justified ad hoc: as emergency measures, as during the Great Depression; or as facilitating fairness in the initial conditions for competition, as in free education; or metaphysically as "compensation" for the wrongs suffered by the long-dead ancestors of groups singled out for special favors; and so on. The free-enterprise ideology has continued thus to be honored in the breach as well as the observance because at its core is the very strong moral intuition that people ought to get what they deserve - justice, in fact. Progressive income taxes and confiscatory death duties perhaps can be reconciled with this intuition, for the feeling is that while some people deserve more than others, nevertheless they are not so different as to justify very large discrepancies, especially when the wealth enjoyed has not been worked for. But when all has been done along these lines that can be done, and it is found necessary to take large amounts not just from the idle rich but from the industrious middle class, the ideology begins to falter. It might be thought that Marxism is the ideology appropriate to welfarism. However, Marxism does not reject the notion that people ought to get what they deserve: on the contrary, this is the basis of its moral condemnation of capitalism. It is held that the worker creates surplus value (and therefore deserves to enjoy it} but the capitalist expropriates it (and therefore enjoys what he does not deserve to enjoy). But much psychological and sociological thought in recent times takes a view of man according to which his deeds are the resultants of the forces operating on him, and nothing else: a genetico-social determinism. From this, many draw as a consequence 9 the untenability of any notion of differential desert. Rawls' lamentation on "the natural lottery," and the dependence on social circumstance of' 'even the willingness to make an effort" is only one presentation of this familiar theme, which has been impressively advocated by Rawls' colleague in psychology, B. F. Skinner. Man is a machine - a computer, in fact. And it makes no sense to speak of a machine's deserving anything. Rawls has accepted this view of man and has constructed an ethics

9 What Rawls Calls Justice 53 appropriate to it: an ethics without desert. 10 Now, if nobody is more deserving than anybody else, there is no reason, of a moral kind, to treat one man differently from another. Thus we arrive at the Rawlsian egalitarian "benchmark" (62): "a hypothetical initial arrangement in which all the social primary goods are equally distributed: everyone has similar rights and duties and income and wealth are evenly shared." As Nozick has noted, 11 Rawls provides no argument for equality. But why should he -indeed how could he, conceiving of man in this way? In Rawls' system equality has the status of a Collingwoodian absolute presupposition. There have been social thinkers who have envisioned a return to the egalitarian Eden as the goal of social progress, supposing that once inequality was abolished, everybody would live in brotherly harmony, cooperatively producing and enjoying abundance of all goods that could be rationally desired. But Rawls is more worldly wise. He knows that this is not a practical proposition. People are no damn good. Where they cannot hope to gain anything for themselves, they will not put out any more than they are compelled to. Accommodation, alas, must be made to these dismal facts. When everyone shares exactly alike, there will be a meager pot to share. So those erdowed by the "natural lottery" with more intelligence, industry, and willingness to try-rawls' worldly wisdom again keeps him from denying that there are and always wili be these natural differences - must be provided with incentives to exercise their endowments.

10 54 THE OCCASIONAL REVIEW But that is immoral! No one deserves more; and particularly, these sports don't. But wait: while there can be no moral reason to give A more than B, there is another reason, of a prudential sort. One computer does not deserve a higher voltage input than another, nevertheless it may not compute unless it gets it. And we can, after all, avoid violating morality if we arrange things so that the greater production of the naturally more favored is distributed to everybody's benefit. Let the 'favored' keep just enough extra to be an incentive to make them produce; give the rest of their output to the less favored. So we have arrived at the Difference Principle, which is the Rawlsian analogue to St. Paul's "It is better to marry than to bum." As sex was to Paul, so profit is to Rawls. The elect will shun it, but it must be conceded to the unregenerate, though under strict safeguards that will take as much of the joy out of it as possible. In an ethics without desert,justice - giving each man his due, more to whom more is due - becomes a vacuous concept. So the book in which this ethics is expounded will have nothing to say about justice. Thus Rawls' book differs profoundly from the absent-minded geographer's book about Australia: Rawls did not forget to write about justice, he necessarily could not. But he used the word often enough. What then was he really writing about? It is significant that Rawls' own label for his ethical theory is "justice as fairness." Now 'justice' and 'fairness' are near synonyms. 'Fair' indeed exhibits a tendency to replace 'just' in much ordinary speech. But they are not exactly the same thing. Criticism, for example, can be at one and the same time both fair (it doesn't misrepresent, it doesn't appeal to prejudice and irrelevance) and unjust (it fails to assign the mark due to the piece criticized). And a contract might be awarded fairly though mistakenly, but not justly though mistakenly. However, the main difference between fairness and justice is that the former but not the latter applies to distributions where desert plays no part. If none of the children at the party has done anything in particular to deserve any cake at all, it would be strained to complain of injustice if one gets a larger piece than another; but it would certainly be unfair. 12 The pirate booty is not the due of any pirate, so it is (absolutely) unjust for any pirate to have any of it; nevertheless the pirate king is unfair if he doesn't divvy it up equally (or in proportion to services rendered). Fairness can thus be regarded as a sort of degenerate case of justice, or the moral principle that takes over in distributions when considerations of desert do not arise. And fairness, unlike justice, does (in general) demand equality.

11 What Rawls Calls Justice 55 So now we can understand how Rawls is able to make such an astonishing assertion as "Injustice, then, is simply inequalities that are not to the benefit of all." (62) This begins to make sense if for "injustice" we substitute 'unfairness' and suppose consideration of desert not to enter the picture. The close connection between fairness and justice, especially in colloquial speech, is one reason why Rawls, apparently without knowing what he was doing, was able to write a book containing the word justice but not about justice. But only one. Another and probably more influential reason is to be found in a proclivity to suppose that 'social justice' is a special kind of justice, to which the same sentiments are appropriate as to plain justice. Almost the first words of Rawls' book are these: Justice is the first virtue of social institutions, as truth is of systems of thought. A theory however elegant and economical must be rejected or revised if it is untrue; likewise laws and institutions no matter how efficient and well-arranged must be reformed or abolished if they are unjust. Each person possesses an inviolability founded on justice that even the welfare of society as a whole cannot override. For this reason justice denies that the loss of freedom for some is made right by a greater good shared by others. (3f.) The justice to which this hymn is appropriate is the real thing. It is not R-justice: just see what happens if you substitute 'difference principle' wherever "justice" occurs in it! This justice is what we do demand of those set in authority over us: they should render us our due. But the justice that Society affords is, by definition 'social justice' (so Rawls would say), which is a kind of justice, coordinate with personal justice, and deserving the same reverence or rather more. And if in certain situations social justice seems to conflict with the dictates of personal justice, e.g. if social justice allows or even requires a man to be robbed of what he has earned ( et passim), that need occasion no embarrassement, for Society is bigger than any of us. This slope, down which Rawls invites us to slide, has been smoothed by many an eminent bottom, beginning with Plato's. But we would do well to stay off it. There is in fact no concept (in the Hart-Rawls sense) of social justice - nothing in which 'those who hold different conceptions of social justice can still agree.' 'Social justice' is neither an expression of ordinary language, nor a term of art in a branch of learning. It is mere cant, an empty bottle ready to be filled with any brew that envy and sentimentality can concoct. And that is only what we should have expected when we saw that ominous adjective 'social,' which functions as a spoiler, making nonsense of otherwise useful words to which it is conjoined: social democracy; social welfare; social work; social credit; social security; social science; social philosophy;...

12 56 THE OCCASIONAL REVIEW NOTES 'Philosophy and Logical Syntax (1935), pp. 61, 65; quoted in C. J. Ducasse, Philosophy as a Science (New York: Oskar Piest, 1941), p Ducasse, op. cit.. p. 97. 'Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press, All numbers in parentheses in the text are page references to this book. 4 This terminology is certainly awkward. The distinction itself needs further testing before being licensed for use without a prescription. However, it is part of Rawls' apparatus. and I am confident that its employment is unproblematic in the present paper at least. 'This tendentious word 'assign,' or its synonym 'arrange,' occurs again and again at crucial points in Rawls' argumentation, e.g. in the very statement of the difference principle which (it will be recalled) begins "social and economic inequalities are to be arranged..." These words signal a fundamental Rawlsian presupposition to the effect that in any society whatsoever there is an "assignment" or "arrangement" of rights, duties and advantages, made by human decisions, consciously or unconsciously, in accordance with rules. This may sound obvious and innocent; but it is a presupposition with content. A major difference between a free and an authoritarian society is that in the latter a person's rank etc. are assigned by bureaucrats, whereas in the former nobody makes such assignments - the individual decides what sort oflife he wants to lead and then pursues it, with more or less success ("the pursuit of happiness"). But on the Rawlsian view, there is no difference of kind between the two cases. So the task of the social philosopher is greatly simplified: if he wants to innovate, he need not begin by showing that it is a good idea to have a system of assignments at all; he can skip this step and go on to recommend the superior merits of his particular proposal for assigning things. Rawls takes full advantage of this gift to himself. This is analogous to the advantage gained by Marx in his invention of capitausm, which makes the choice appear to be between two isms rather than between that condition in which the economic decisions of individuals have their natural effects, on the one hand, and an artificially structured economy on the other. since the traditional concept of justice is correct, it follows that if Rawls' formulation were acceptable then it would either be equivalent to it or an amplification ofit. With some straining, it could perhaps be read that way: viz., if "arbitrary distinction" were taken to mean a distinction not based on desert, and if' 'a proper balance between competing claims'' were intended to refer only to those cases, if any, in which some non-sharable thing is equally deserved by more than one person. It is clear, however, that Rawls was far from intending his definition to be read in this way. In any case, we are justified henceforth in taking 'rendering each man his due' as the concept of justice.

13 What Rawls Calls Justice 57 'If the claim were to be made that liberty was part of the conception of justice in that liberty is everybody's due, therefore institutions cannot be just that do not provide it, the claim would have to be rejected as simply false. Liberty is not the due of dangerous criminals, for example, who are, nevertheless, just as entitled to justice as everybody else. "The Wisdom of Confucius, ed. and trans. Lin Yutang (New York: Modern Library, 1938), p Wrongly, as I have tried to show in my book Sentience (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1976). '"Though, with stunning inconsistency, he proclaims "self-respect" to be "the most important primary good." (440) "What Rawls Calls Self Respect" is a topic for another paper. "Robert Nozick, Anarchy, State, and Utopia (New York: Basic Books, 1974), p "Though Rawls (85) calls the equal division of the cake a paradigm of "pure procedural justice." )I!{a 1)0t:BI,EFACE, A "\ \ :-.-or TO HE TKl"''1'F.P.

Lecture Notes Wallace Matson, What Rawls Calls Justice (1978) Keith Burgess-Jackson 6 December 2016

Lecture Notes Wallace Matson, What Rawls Calls Justice (1978) Keith Burgess-Jackson 6 December 2016 Lecture Notes Wallace Matson, What Rawls Calls Justice (1978) Keith Burgess-Jackson 6 December 2016 Biography. Wallace I. Matson (born 1921 in Portland, Oregon; died 3 March 2012) was, at the time of his

More information

FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. by Immanuel Kant

FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. by Immanuel Kant FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS SECOND SECTION by Immanuel Kant TRANSITION FROM POPULAR MORAL PHILOSOPHY TO THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS... This principle, that humanity and generally every

More information

McCLOSKEY ON RATIONAL ENDS: The Dilemma of Intuitionism

McCLOSKEY ON RATIONAL ENDS: The Dilemma of Intuitionism 48 McCLOSKEY ON RATIONAL ENDS: The Dilemma of Intuitionism T om R egan In his book, Meta-Ethics and Normative Ethics,* Professor H. J. McCloskey sets forth an argument which he thinks shows that we know,

More information

10 CERTAINTY G.E. MOORE: SELECTED WRITINGS

10 CERTAINTY G.E. MOORE: SELECTED WRITINGS 10 170 I am at present, as you can all see, in a room and not in the open air; I am standing up, and not either sitting or lying down; I have clothes on, and am not absolutely naked; I am speaking in a

More information

THE CONCEPT OF OWNERSHIP by Lars Bergström

THE CONCEPT OF OWNERSHIP by Lars Bergström From: Who Owns Our Genes?, Proceedings of an international conference, October 1999, Tallin, Estonia, The Nordic Committee on Bioethics, 2000. THE CONCEPT OF OWNERSHIP by Lars Bergström I shall be mainly

More information

The Quality of Mercy is Not Strained: Justice and Mercy in Proslogion 9-11

The Quality of Mercy is Not Strained: Justice and Mercy in Proslogion 9-11 The Quality of Mercy is Not Strained: Justice and Mercy in Proslogion 9-11 Michael Vendsel Tarrant County College Abstract: In Proslogion 9-11 Anselm discusses the relationship between mercy and justice.

More information

factors in Bentham's hedonic calculus.

factors in Bentham's hedonic calculus. Answers to quiz 1. An autonomous person: a) is socially isolated from other people. b) directs his or her actions on the basis his or own basic values, beliefs, etc. c) is able to get by without the help

More information

Rawls s veil of ignorance excludes all knowledge of likelihoods regarding the social

Rawls s veil of ignorance excludes all knowledge of likelihoods regarding the social Rawls s veil of ignorance excludes all knowledge of likelihoods regarding the social position one ends up occupying, while John Harsanyi s version of the veil tells contractors that they are equally likely

More information

-- The search text of this PDF is generated from uncorrected OCR text.

-- The search text of this PDF is generated from uncorrected OCR text. Citation: 21 Isr. L. Rev. 113 1986 Content downloaded/printed from HeinOnline (http://heinonline.org) Sun Jan 11 12:34:09 2015 -- Your use of this HeinOnline PDF indicates your acceptance of HeinOnline's

More information

KANTIAN ETHICS (Dan Gaskill)

KANTIAN ETHICS (Dan Gaskill) KANTIAN ETHICS (Dan Gaskill) German philosopher Immanuel Kant (1724-1804) was an opponent of utilitarianism. Basic Summary: Kant, unlike Mill, believed that certain types of actions (including murder,

More information

Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly *

Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly * Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly * Ralph Wedgwood 1 Two views of practical reason Suppose that you are faced with several different options (that is, several ways in which you might act in a

More information

Rawls, rationality, and responsibility: Why we should not treat our endowments as morally arbitrary

Rawls, rationality, and responsibility: Why we should not treat our endowments as morally arbitrary Rawls, rationality, and responsibility: Why we should not treat our endowments as morally arbitrary OLIVER DUROSE Abstract John Rawls is primarily known for providing his own argument for how political

More information

Zdenko Kodelja HOW TO UNDERSTAND EQUITY IN HIGHER EDUCATION? (Draft)

Zdenko Kodelja HOW TO UNDERSTAND EQUITY IN HIGHER EDUCATION? (Draft) Zdenko Kodelja HOW TO UNDERSTAND EQUITY IN HIGHER EDUCATION? (Draft) The question How to understand equity in higher education? presupposes that it is not clear enough what exactly equity means. If this

More information

Making Decisions on Behalf of Others: Who or What Do I Select as a Guide? A Dilemma: - My boss. - The shareholders. - Other stakeholders

Making Decisions on Behalf of Others: Who or What Do I Select as a Guide? A Dilemma: - My boss. - The shareholders. - Other stakeholders Making Decisions on Behalf of Others: Who or What Do I Select as a Guide? - My boss - The shareholders - Other stakeholders - Basic principles about conduct and its impacts - What is good for me - What

More information

Understanding Truth Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002

Understanding Truth Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002 1 Symposium on Understanding Truth By Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002 2 Precis of Understanding Truth Scott Soames Understanding Truth aims to illuminate

More information

Two Approaches to Natural Law;Note

Two Approaches to Natural Law;Note Notre Dame Law School NDLScholarship Natural Law Forum 1-1-1956 Two Approaches to Natural Law;Note Vernon J. Bourke Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarship.law.nd.edu/nd_naturallaw_forum

More information

(i) Morality is a system; and (ii) It is a system comprised of moral rules and principles.

(i) Morality is a system; and (ii) It is a system comprised of moral rules and principles. Ethics and Morality Ethos (Greek) and Mores (Latin) are terms having to do with custom, habit, and behavior. Ethics is the study of morality. This definition raises two questions: (a) What is morality?

More information

MORAL RELATIVISM. By: George Bassilios St Antonius Coptic Orthodox Church, San Francisco Bay Area

MORAL RELATIVISM. By: George Bassilios St Antonius Coptic Orthodox Church, San Francisco Bay Area MORAL RELATIVISM By: George Bassilios St Antonius Coptic Orthodox Church, San Francisco Bay Area Introduction In this age, we have lost the confidence that statements of fact can ever be anything more

More information

Chapter 3 PHILOSOPHICAL ETHICS AND BUSINESS CHAPTER OBJECTIVES. After exploring this chapter, you will be able to:

Chapter 3 PHILOSOPHICAL ETHICS AND BUSINESS CHAPTER OBJECTIVES. After exploring this chapter, you will be able to: Chapter 3 PHILOSOPHICAL ETHICS AND BUSINESS MGT604 CHAPTER OBJECTIVES After exploring this chapter, you will be able to: 1. Explain the ethical framework of utilitarianism. 2. Describe how utilitarian

More information

Phil 108, August 10, 2010 Punishment

Phil 108, August 10, 2010 Punishment Phil 108, August 10, 2010 Punishment Retributivism and Utilitarianism The retributive theory: (1) It is good in itself that those who have acted wrongly should suffer. When this happens, people get what

More information

Can Christianity be Reduced to Morality? Ted Di Maria, Philosophy, Gonzaga University Gonzaga Socratic Club, April 18, 2008

Can Christianity be Reduced to Morality? Ted Di Maria, Philosophy, Gonzaga University Gonzaga Socratic Club, April 18, 2008 Can Christianity be Reduced to Morality? Ted Di Maria, Philosophy, Gonzaga University Gonzaga Socratic Club, April 18, 2008 As one of the world s great religions, Christianity has been one of the supreme

More information

PHL271 Handout 2: Hobbes on Law and Political Authority. Many philosophers of law treat Hobbes as the grandfather of legal positivism.

PHL271 Handout 2: Hobbes on Law and Political Authority. Many philosophers of law treat Hobbes as the grandfather of legal positivism. PHL271 Handout 2: Hobbes on Law and Political Authority 1 Background: Legal Positivism Many philosophers of law treat Hobbes as the grandfather of legal positivism. Legal Positivism (Rough Version): whether

More information

R. M. Hare (1919 ) SINNOTT- ARMSTRONG. Definition of moral judgments. Prescriptivism

R. M. Hare (1919 ) SINNOTT- ARMSTRONG. Definition of moral judgments. Prescriptivism 25 R. M. Hare (1919 ) WALTER SINNOTT- ARMSTRONG Richard Mervyn Hare has written on a wide variety of topics, from Plato to the philosophy of language, religion, and education, as well as on applied ethics,

More information

CONVENTIONALISM AND NORMATIVITY

CONVENTIONALISM AND NORMATIVITY 1 CONVENTIONALISM AND NORMATIVITY TORBEN SPAAK We have seen (in Section 3) that Hart objects to Austin s command theory of law, that it cannot account for the normativity of law, and that what is missing

More information

Socratic and Platonic Ethics

Socratic and Platonic Ethics Socratic and Platonic Ethics G. J. Mattey Winter, 2017 / Philosophy 1 Ethics and Political Philosophy The first part of the course is a brief survey of important texts in the history of ethics and political

More information

Course Syllabus Political Philosophy PHIL 462, Spring, 2017

Course Syllabus Political Philosophy PHIL 462, Spring, 2017 Instructor: Dr. Matt Zwolinski Office Hours: 1:00-3:30, Mondays and Wednesdays Office: F167A Course Website: http://ole.sandiego.edu/ Phone: 619-260-4094 Email: mzwolinski@sandiego.edu Course Syllabus

More information

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View Chapter 98 Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View Lars Leeten Universität Hildesheim Practical thinking is a tricky business. Its aim will never be fulfilled unless influence on practical

More information

Rawls versus utilitarianism: the subset objection

Rawls versus utilitarianism: the subset objection E-LOGOS Electronic Journal for Philosophy 2016, Vol. 23(2) 37 41 ISSN 1211-0442 (DOI: 10.18267/j.e-logos.435),Peer-reviewed article Journal homepage: e-logos.vse.cz Rawls versus utilitarianism: the subset

More information

Kant The Grounding of the Metaphysics of Morals (excerpts) 1 PHIL101 Prof. Oakes. Section IV: What is it worth? Reading IV.2.

Kant The Grounding of the Metaphysics of Morals (excerpts) 1 PHIL101 Prof. Oakes. Section IV: What is it worth? Reading IV.2. Kant The Grounding of the Metaphysics of Morals (excerpts) 1 PHIL101 Prof. Oakes Section IV: What is it worth? Reading IV.2 Kant s analysis of the good differs in scope from Aristotle s in two ways. In

More information

Self-Evidence and A Priori Moral Knowledge

Self-Evidence and A Priori Moral Knowledge Self-Evidence and A Priori Moral Knowledge Colorado State University BIBLID [0873-626X (2012) 33; pp. 459-467] Abstract According to rationalists about moral knowledge, some moral truths are knowable a

More information

ECON 4270 Distributive Justice 2011 Lecture 9 Deserts, merit, responsibility

ECON 4270 Distributive Justice 2011 Lecture 9 Deserts, merit, responsibility ECON 4270 Distributive Justice 2011 Lecture 9 Deserts, merit, responsibility Hilde Bojer www.folk.uio.no/hbojer hbojer@econ.uio.no April 14, 2011 Responsibility The fruit of our labours Deserts Children

More information

Writing Essays at Oxford

Writing Essays at Oxford Writing Essays at Oxford Introduction One of the best things you can take from an Oxford degree in philosophy/politics is the ability to write an essay in analytical philosophy, Oxford style. Not, obviously,

More information

Informalizing Formal Logic

Informalizing Formal Logic Informalizing Formal Logic Antonis Kakas Department of Computer Science, University of Cyprus, Cyprus antonis@ucy.ac.cy Abstract. This paper discusses how the basic notions of formal logic can be expressed

More information

Hume's Representation Argument Against Rationalism 1 by Geoffrey Sayre-McCord University of North Carolina/Chapel Hill

Hume's Representation Argument Against Rationalism 1 by Geoffrey Sayre-McCord University of North Carolina/Chapel Hill Hume's Representation Argument Against Rationalism 1 by Geoffrey Sayre-McCord University of North Carolina/Chapel Hill Manuscrito (1997) vol. 20, pp. 77-94 Hume offers a barrage of arguments for thinking

More information

Comment on Martha Nussbaum s Purified Patriotism

Comment on Martha Nussbaum s Purified Patriotism Comment on Martha Nussbaum s Purified Patriotism Patriotism is generally thought to require a special attachment to the particular: to one s own country and to one s fellow citizens. It is therefore thought

More information

Phil 114, February 29, 2012 Sir Robert Filmer, Observations Concerning the Originall of Government

Phil 114, February 29, 2012 Sir Robert Filmer, Observations Concerning the Originall of Government Phil 114, February 29, 2012 Sir Robert Filmer, Observations Concerning the Originall of Government, p. 234 (bspace) John Locke, First Treatise of Government, Ch. 4 41 43 (review), Ch. 9 84 103 (review)

More information

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory Western University Scholarship@Western 2015 Undergraduate Awards The Undergraduate Awards 2015 Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory David Hakim Western University, davidhakim266@gmail.com

More information

Modern Deontological Theory: Rawlsian Deontology

Modern Deontological Theory: Rawlsian Deontology Modern Deontological Theory: Rawlsian Deontology John Rawls A Theory of Justice Nathan Kellen University of Connecticut February 26th, 2015 Table of Contents Preliminary Notes Preliminaries Two Principles

More information

Moral Objectivism. RUSSELL CORNETT University of Calgary

Moral Objectivism. RUSSELL CORNETT University of Calgary Moral Objectivism RUSSELL CORNETT University of Calgary The possibility, let alone the actuality, of an objective morality has intrigued philosophers for well over two millennia. Though much discussed,

More information

DISCUSSION PRACTICAL POLITICS AND PHILOSOPHICAL INQUIRY: A NOTE

DISCUSSION PRACTICAL POLITICS AND PHILOSOPHICAL INQUIRY: A NOTE Practical Politics and Philosophical Inquiry: A Note Author(s): Dale Hall and Tariq Modood Reviewed work(s): Source: The Philosophical Quarterly, Vol. 29, No. 117 (Oct., 1979), pp. 340-344 Published by:

More information

J.f. Stephen s On Fraternity And Mill s Universal Love 1

J.f. Stephen s On Fraternity And Mill s Universal Love 1 Τέλος Revista Iberoamericana de Estudios Utilitaristas-2012, XIX/1: (77-82) ISSN 1132-0877 J.f. Stephen s On Fraternity And Mill s Universal Love 1 José Montoya University of Valencia In chapter 3 of Utilitarianism,

More information

Summary of Kant s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals

Summary of Kant s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals Summary of Kant s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals Version 1.1 Richard Baron 2 October 2016 1 Contents 1 Introduction 3 1.1 Availability and licence............ 3 2 Definitions of key terms 4 3

More information

Utilitarianism: For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), pp Reprinted in Moral Luck (CUP, 1981).

Utilitarianism: For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), pp Reprinted in Moral Luck (CUP, 1981). Draft of 3-21- 13 PHIL 202: Core Ethics; Winter 2013 Core Sequence in the History of Ethics, 2011-2013 IV: 19 th and 20 th Century Moral Philosophy David O. Brink Handout #14: Williams, Internalism, and

More information

Reply to Kit Fine. Theodore Sider July 19, 2013

Reply to Kit Fine. Theodore Sider July 19, 2013 Reply to Kit Fine Theodore Sider July 19, 2013 Kit Fine s paper raises important and difficult issues about my approach to the metaphysics of fundamentality. In chapters 7 and 8 I examined certain subtle

More information

J.KAU: Islamic Econ., Vol. 12, pp (1420 A.H / 2000 A.D)

J.KAU: Islamic Econ., Vol. 12, pp (1420 A.H / 2000 A.D) J.KAU: Islamic Econ., Vol. 12, pp. 69-73 (1420 A.H / 2000 A.D) Rodney Wilson Economics, Ethics and Religion: Jewish, Christian and Muslim Economic Thought New York: New York University Press, 1997 233

More information

Rawlsian Values. Jimmy Rising

Rawlsian Values. Jimmy Rising Rawlsian Values Jimmy Rising A number of questions can be asked about the validity of John Rawls s arguments in Theory of Justice. In general, they fall into two classes which should not be confused. One

More information

Equality of Capacity AMARTYA SEN

Equality of Capacity AMARTYA SEN Equality of Capacity AMARTYA SEN WHY EQUALITY? WHAT EQUALITY? Two central issues for ethical analysis of equality are: (1) Why equality? (2) Equality of what? The two questions are distinct but thoroughly

More information

Legal Positivism: the Separation and Identification theses are true.

Legal Positivism: the Separation and Identification theses are true. PHL271 Handout 3: Hart on Legal Positivism 1 Legal Positivism Revisited HLA Hart was a highly sophisticated philosopher. His defence of legal positivism marked a watershed in 20 th Century philosophy of

More information

Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods

Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods delineating the scope of deductive reason Roger Bishop Jones Abstract. The scope of deductive reason is considered. First a connection is discussed between the

More information

HAVE WE REASON TO DO AS RATIONALITY REQUIRES? A COMMENT ON RAZ

HAVE WE REASON TO DO AS RATIONALITY REQUIRES? A COMMENT ON RAZ HAVE WE REASON TO DO AS RATIONALITY REQUIRES? A COMMENT ON RAZ BY JOHN BROOME JOURNAL OF ETHICS & SOCIAL PHILOSOPHY SYMPOSIUM I DECEMBER 2005 URL: WWW.JESP.ORG COPYRIGHT JOHN BROOME 2005 HAVE WE REASON

More information

Vol. II, No. 5, Reason, Truth and History, 127. LARS BERGSTRÖM

Vol. II, No. 5, Reason, Truth and History, 127. LARS BERGSTRÖM Croatian Journal of Philosophy Vol. II, No. 5, 2002 L. Bergström, Putnam on the Fact-Value Dichotomy 1 Putnam on the Fact-Value Dichotomy LARS BERGSTRÖM Stockholm University In Reason, Truth and History

More information

Action in Special Contexts

Action in Special Contexts Part III Action in Special Contexts c36.indd 283 c36.indd 284 36 Rationality john broome Rationality as a Property and Rationality as a Source of Requirements The word rationality often refers to a property

More information

38 Groundwork for the Metaphysics of Morals. [Ak 4:422] [Ak4:421]

38 Groundwork for the Metaphysics of Morals. [Ak 4:422] [Ak4:421] 38 Groundwork for the Metaphysics of Morals [Ak 4:422] [Ak4:421] what one calls duty is an empty concept, we can at least indicate what we are thinking in the concept of duty and what this concept means.

More information

The Experience Machine and Mental State Theories of Wellbeing

The Experience Machine and Mental State Theories of Wellbeing The Journal of Value Inquiry 33: 381 387, 1999 EXPERIENCE MACHINE AND MENTAL STATE THEORIES OF WELL-BEING 1999 Kluwer Academic Publishers. Printed in the Netherlands. 381 The Experience Machine and Mental

More information

A Case against Subjectivism: A Reply to Sobel

A Case against Subjectivism: A Reply to Sobel A Case against Subjectivism: A Reply to Sobel Abstract Subjectivists are committed to the claim that desires provide us with reasons for action. Derek Parfit argues that subjectivists cannot account for

More information

SUMMARIES AND TEST QUESTIONS UNIT 6

SUMMARIES AND TEST QUESTIONS UNIT 6 SUMMARIES AND TEST QUESTIONS UNIT 6 Textbook: Louis P. Pojman, Editor. Philosophy: The quest for truth. New York: Oxford University Press, 2006. ISBN-10: 0199697310; ISBN-13: 9780199697311 (6th Edition)

More information

MILL ON JUSTICE: CHAPTER 5 of UTILITARIANISM Lecture Notes Dick Arneson Philosophy 13 Fall, 2005

MILL ON JUSTICE: CHAPTER 5 of UTILITARIANISM Lecture Notes Dick Arneson Philosophy 13 Fall, 2005 1 MILL ON JUSTICE: CHAPTER 5 of UTILITARIANISM Lecture Notes Dick Arneson Philosophy 13 Fall, 2005 Some people hold that utilitarianism is incompatible with justice and objectionable for that reason. Utilitarianism

More information

Take Home Exam #2. PHI 1700: Global Ethics Prof. Lauren R. Alpert

Take Home Exam #2. PHI 1700: Global Ethics Prof. Lauren R. Alpert PHI 1700: Global Ethics Prof. Lauren R. Alpert Name: Date: Take Home Exam #2 Instructions (Read Before Proceeding!) Material for this exam is from class sessions 8-15. Matching and fill-in-the-blank questions

More information

out in his Three Dialogues and Principles of Human Knowledge, gives an argument specifically

out in his Three Dialogues and Principles of Human Knowledge, gives an argument specifically That Thing-I-Know-Not-What by [Perm #7903685] The philosopher George Berkeley, in part of his general thesis against materialism as laid out in his Three Dialogues and Principles of Human Knowledge, gives

More information

What is the "Social" in "Social Coherence?" Commentary on Nelson Tebbe's Religious Freedom in an Egalitarian Age

What is the Social in Social Coherence? Commentary on Nelson Tebbe's Religious Freedom in an Egalitarian Age Journal of Civil Rights and Economic Development Volume 31 Issue 1 Volume 31, Summer 2018, Issue 1 Article 5 June 2018 What is the "Social" in "Social Coherence?" Commentary on Nelson Tebbe's Religious

More information

"Book Review: FRANKFURT, Harry G. On Inequality. Princeton and Oxford: Princeton University Press, 2015, 102 pp., $14.95 (hbk), ISBN

Book Review: FRANKFURT, Harry G. On Inequality. Princeton and Oxford: Princeton University Press, 2015, 102 pp., $14.95 (hbk), ISBN "Book Review: FRANKFURT, Harry G. On Inequality. Princeton and Oxford: Princeton University Press, 2015, 102 pp., $14.95 (hbk), ISBN 9780691167145." 1 Andrea Luisa Bucchile Faggion Universidade Estadual

More information

THE MEANING OF OUGHT. Ralph Wedgwood. What does the word ought mean? Strictly speaking, this is an empirical question, about the

THE MEANING OF OUGHT. Ralph Wedgwood. What does the word ought mean? Strictly speaking, this is an empirical question, about the THE MEANING OF OUGHT Ralph Wedgwood What does the word ought mean? Strictly speaking, this is an empirical question, about the meaning of a word in English. Such empirical semantic questions should ideally

More information

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. The Physical World Author(s): Barry Stroud Source: Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, New Series, Vol. 87 (1986-1987), pp. 263-277 Published by: Blackwell Publishing on behalf of The Aristotelian

More information

2 FREE CHOICE The heretical thesis of Hobbes is the orthodox position today. So much is this the case that most of the contemporary literature

2 FREE CHOICE The heretical thesis of Hobbes is the orthodox position today. So much is this the case that most of the contemporary literature Introduction The philosophical controversy about free will and determinism is perennial. Like many perennial controversies, this one involves a tangle of distinct but closely related issues. Thus, the

More information

Varieties of Apriority

Varieties of Apriority S E V E N T H E X C U R S U S Varieties of Apriority T he notions of a priori knowledge and justification play a central role in this work. There are many ways in which one can understand the a priori,

More information

Israel Kirzner is a name familiar to all readers of the Review of

Israel Kirzner is a name familiar to all readers of the Review of Discovery, Capitalism, and Distributive Justice. By Israel M. Kirzner. New York: Basil Blackwell, 1989. Israel Kirzner is a name familiar to all readers of the Review of Austrian Economics. Kirzner's association

More information

PLANTINGA ON THE FREE WILL DEFENSE. Hugh LAFoLLETTE East Tennessee State University

PLANTINGA ON THE FREE WILL DEFENSE. Hugh LAFoLLETTE East Tennessee State University PLANTINGA ON THE FREE WILL DEFENSE Hugh LAFoLLETTE East Tennessee State University I In his recent book God, Freedom, and Evil, Alvin Plantinga formulates an updated version of the Free Will Defense which,

More information

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW DISCUSSION NOTE BY CAMPBELL BROWN JOURNAL OF ETHICS & SOCIAL PHILOSOPHY DISCUSSION NOTE MAY 2015 URL: WWW.JESP.ORG COPYRIGHT CAMPBELL BROWN 2015 Two Versions of Hume s Law MORAL CONCLUSIONS CANNOT VALIDLY

More information

University of York, UK

University of York, UK Justice and the Public Sphere: A Critique of John Rawls Political Liberalism Wanpat Youngmevittaya University of York, UK Abstract This article criticizes John Rawls conception of political liberalism,

More information

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism Mathais Sarrazin J.L. Mackie s Error Theory postulates that all normative claims are false. It does this based upon his denial of moral

More information

WHY RELATIVISM IS NOT SELF-REFUTING IN ANY INTERESTING WAY

WHY RELATIVISM IS NOT SELF-REFUTING IN ANY INTERESTING WAY Preliminary draft, WHY RELATIVISM IS NOT SELF-REFUTING IN ANY INTERESTING WAY Is relativism really self-refuting? This paper takes a look at some frequently used arguments and its preliminary answer to

More information

Preliminary Remarks on Locke's The Second Treatise of Government (T2)

Preliminary Remarks on Locke's The Second Treatise of Government (T2) Preliminary Remarks on Locke's The Second Treatise of Government (T2) Locke's Fundamental Principles and Objectives D. A. Lloyd Thomas points out, in his introduction to Locke's political theory, that

More information

FREEDOM OF CHOICE. Freedom of Choice, p. 2

FREEDOM OF CHOICE. Freedom of Choice, p. 2 FREEDOM OF CHOICE Human beings are capable of the following behavior that has not been observed in animals. We ask ourselves What should my goal in life be - if anything? Is there anything I should live

More information

Contractarianism and Animal Rights

Contractarianism and Animal Rights Journal of Applied Philosophy, Vol.14, No. 3, 1997 Contractarianism and Animal Rights MARK ROWLANDS abstract It is widely accepted, by both friends and foes of animal rights, that contractarianism is the

More information

BELIEF POLICIES, by Paul Helm. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, Pp. xiii and 226. $54.95 (Cloth).

BELIEF POLICIES, by Paul Helm. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, Pp. xiii and 226. $54.95 (Cloth). BELIEF POLICIES, by Paul Helm. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1994. Pp. xiii and 226. $54.95 (Cloth). TRENTON MERRICKS, Virginia Commonwealth University Faith and Philosophy 13 (1996): 449-454

More information

Positivism A Model Of For System Of Rules

Positivism A Model Of For System Of Rules Positivism A Model Of For System Of Rules Positivism is a model of and for a system of rules, and its central notion of a single fundamental test for law forces us to miss the important standards that

More information

Introduction: the original position and The Original Position an overview

Introduction: the original position and The Original Position an overview Introduction: the original position and The Original Position an overview Timothy Hinton John Rawls s idea of the original position arguably the centerpiece of his theory of justice has proved to have

More information

PHILOSOPHY DEPARTMENT FALL SEMESTER 2009 COURSE OFFERINGS

PHILOSOPHY DEPARTMENT FALL SEMESTER 2009 COURSE OFFERINGS PHILOSOPHY DEPARTMENT FALL SEMESTER 2009 COURSE OFFERINGS INTRODUCTION TO PHILOSOPHY (PHIL 100W) MIND BODY PROBLEM (PHIL 101) LOGIC AND CRITICAL THINKING (PHIL 110) INTRODUCTION TO ETHICS (PHIL 120) CULTURE

More information

Ayer and Quine on the a priori

Ayer and Quine on the a priori Ayer and Quine on the a priori November 23, 2004 1 The problem of a priori knowledge Ayer s book is a defense of a thoroughgoing empiricism, not only about what is required for a belief to be justified

More information

Reply to Robert Koons

Reply to Robert Koons 632 Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic Volume 35, Number 4, Fall 1994 Reply to Robert Koons ANIL GUPTA and NUEL BELNAP We are grateful to Professor Robert Koons for his excellent, and generous, review

More information

PPL 399, Philosophical Perspectives on Liberty. Office Phone: Spring 2007 SYLLABUS

PPL 399, Philosophical Perspectives on Liberty. Office Phone: Spring 2007 SYLLABUS Loren E. Lomasky PPL 399, Philosophical Perspectives on Liberty Office: 527 Cabell M, W 6-7:15, Cabell Office Phone: 434-924-6925 Spring 2007 lel3f@virginia.edu SYLLABUS I. Required Texts Adam Smith, Wealth

More information

Conference on the Epistemology of Keith Lehrer, PUCRS, Porto Alegre (Brazil), June

Conference on the Epistemology of Keith Lehrer, PUCRS, Porto Alegre (Brazil), June 2 Reply to Comesaña* Réplica a Comesaña Carl Ginet** 1. In the Sentence-Relativity section of his comments, Comesaña discusses my attempt (in the Relativity to Sentences section of my paper) to convince

More information

The Subjectivity of Values By J.L. Mackie (1977)

The Subjectivity of Values By J.L. Mackie (1977) The Subjectivity of Values By J.L. Mackie (1977) Moral Skepticism There are no objective values. This is a bald statement of the thesis of this chapter The claim that values are not objective, are not

More information

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg 1 In Search of the Ontological Argument Richard Oxenberg Abstract We can attend to the logic of Anselm's ontological argument, and amuse ourselves for a few hours unraveling its convoluted word-play, or

More information

Phil 114, Wednesday, April 11, 2012 Hegel, The Philosophy of Right 1 7, 10 12, 14 16, 22 23, 27 33, 135, 141

Phil 114, Wednesday, April 11, 2012 Hegel, The Philosophy of Right 1 7, 10 12, 14 16, 22 23, 27 33, 135, 141 Phil 114, Wednesday, April 11, 2012 Hegel, The Philosophy of Right 1 7, 10 12, 14 16, 22 23, 27 33, 135, 141 Dialectic: For Hegel, dialectic is a process governed by a principle of development, i.e., Reason

More information

New Aristotelianism, Routledge, 2012), in which he expanded upon

New Aristotelianism, Routledge, 2012), in which he expanded upon Powers, Essentialism and Agency: A Reply to Alexander Bird Ruth Porter Groff, Saint Louis University AUB Conference, April 28-29, 2016 1. Here s the backstory. A couple of years ago my friend Alexander

More information

CHAPTER 5. CULTURAL RELATIVISM.

CHAPTER 5. CULTURAL RELATIVISM. CHAPTER 5. CULTURAL RELATIVISM. I have mentioned earlier that business is embedded in society and that for it and society to flourish, good interdependent relations are necessary. But societies are different,

More information

Remarks on a Foundationalist Theory of Truth. Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh

Remarks on a Foundationalist Theory of Truth. Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh For Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Remarks on a Foundationalist Theory of Truth Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh I Tim Maudlin s Truth and Paradox offers a theory of truth that arises from

More information

ON THE DEVOLVEMENT OF OBLIGATION. Robert J. FOGELIN

ON THE DEVOLVEMENT OF OBLIGATION. Robert J. FOGELIN ON THE DEVOLVEMENT OF OBLIGATION Robert J. FOGELIN In his critical study of Marcus Singer's Generalization in Ethics, George Nakhnildan offers a clear formulation of Singer's Generalization Principle GP),

More information

What Lurks Beneath the Integrity Objection. Bernard Williams s alienation and integrity arguments against consequentialism have

What Lurks Beneath the Integrity Objection. Bernard Williams s alienation and integrity arguments against consequentialism have What Lurks Beneath the Integrity Objection Bernard Williams s alienation and integrity arguments against consequentialism have served as the point of departure for much of the most interesting work that

More information

MULTI-PEER DISAGREEMENT AND THE PREFACE PARADOX. Kenneth Boyce and Allan Hazlett

MULTI-PEER DISAGREEMENT AND THE PREFACE PARADOX. Kenneth Boyce and Allan Hazlett MULTI-PEER DISAGREEMENT AND THE PREFACE PARADOX Kenneth Boyce and Allan Hazlett Abstract The problem of multi-peer disagreement concerns the reasonable response to a situation in which you believe P1 Pn

More information

A Modern Defense of Religious Authority

A Modern Defense of Religious Authority Linda Zagzebski A Modern Defense of Religious Authority 1. The Modern Rejection of Authority It has often been observed that one characteristic of the modern world is the utter rejection of authority,

More information

Bayesian Probability

Bayesian Probability Bayesian Probability Patrick Maher September 4, 2008 ABSTRACT. Bayesian decision theory is here construed as explicating a particular concept of rational choice and Bayesian probability is taken to be

More information

CHAPTER THREE Philosophical Argument

CHAPTER THREE Philosophical Argument CHAPTER THREE Philosophical Argument General Overview: As our students often attest, we all live in a complex world filled with demanding issues and bewildering challenges. In order to determine those

More information

In Defense of Culpable Ignorance

In Defense of Culpable Ignorance It is common in everyday situations and interactions to hold people responsible for things they didn t know but which they ought to have known. For example, if a friend were to jump off the roof of a house

More information

TILLICH ON IDOLATRY. beyond the God of theism... the ground of being and meaning" (RS, p. 114). AUL TILLICH'S concept of idolatry, WILLIAM P.

TILLICH ON IDOLATRY. beyond the God of theism... the ground of being and meaning (RS, p. 114). AUL TILLICH'S concept of idolatry, WILLIAM P. P TILLICH ON IDOLATRY WILLIAM P. ALSTON* AUL TILLICH'S concept of idolatry, although it seems clear enough at first sight, presents on closer analysis some puzzling problems. Since this concept is quite

More information

Aims of Rawls s theory

Aims of Rawls s theory RAWLS In a hypothetical choice situation modeling fairness, we d agree to principles of justice ensuring basic liberties and allowing inequalities only where they benefit the worst off. Aims of Rawls s

More information

Man and the Presence of Evil in Christian and Platonic Doctrine by Philip Sherrard

Man and the Presence of Evil in Christian and Platonic Doctrine by Philip Sherrard Man and the Presence of Evil in Christian and Platonic Doctrine by Philip Sherrard Source: Studies in Comparative Religion, Vol. 2, No.1. World Wisdom, Inc. www.studiesincomparativereligion.com OF the

More information

Ethical Consistency and the Logic of Ought

Ethical Consistency and the Logic of Ought Ethical Consistency and the Logic of Ought Mathieu Beirlaen Ghent University In Ethical Consistency, Bernard Williams vindicated the possibility of moral conflicts; he proposed to consistently allow for

More information

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy Res Cogitans Volume 5 Issue 1 Article 20 6-4-2014 Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy Kevin Harriman Lewis & Clark College Follow this and additional works at: http://commons.pacificu.edu/rescogitans

More information