Horwich's Minimalism and the Liar

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Horwich's Minimalism and the Liar"

Transcription

1 Horwich's Minimalism and the Liar Abstract Minimalism like all deationary theories of truth faces the problem of how to cope with paradoxes, e.g. with the Liar sentence. This essay provides a short overview of the current debate on that issue. In detail, I'll advance as follows. In section 1, I'll set the stage for the debate by locating the status of minimalism within deationism. In section 2, I'll describe objections against the thesis. At that I'll focus specically on the Liar paradox (section 2.2) and the proposed solutions to that issue (section 2.3), indicating that Horwich's most recent strategyincorporating an account of groundedness into one's theory of truthis indeed the most promising way out of paradoxes. Word count (including footnotes): approximately Final draft of 21/01/2011.

2 Contents 1 Deationism & Minimalism Deationism Minimalism Objections to Minimalism The Generalisation Problem The Liar Solutions to the Liar Paradox Non-paradoxical Instances Ungrounded Propositions Why Restrict the Equivalence Schema? The Status of the Liar References 13 ii

3 1 Deationism & Minimalism 1.1 Deationism Truth has always been one of the philosophically most interesting topics. In recent times, deationary theories of truth have been especially popular. These theories `deate' the notion of truth by saying, very roughly put, that truth is signicantly less interesting than most people (and most philosophers) would expect. Minimalism is one very popular variant of deationism and is the topic of this essay. All theories of truth, not only deationary ones, face the problem of how to cope with paradoxes. The most well-known paradox is probably the so-called Liar. The essay presents two strategies, suggested by Paul Horwich, with which the Liar paradox may be avoided. Horwich's minimalist theory of truth is one of the most inuential developments in the recent literature on deationary theories of truth. Deationary theories of truth, as dened by Horwich (2010), meet four closely related criteria. These criteria are the core elements of deationism and are shared by all deationists. Every claim about truth that goes beyond these three elements is controversial even among deationists themselves. But before we consider the controversial aspects, it is rst necessary to dene what is common among deationists. The four theses on which deationists of all types agree concern dierent aspects of the truth predicate, i.e. the function of the truth predicate, its meaning, the property it denotes and its conceptual role. All these dierent aspects regarding truth are very closely related, as will become clear when minimalism itself is described. As regards the function and meaning of the truth predicatate, deationists agree that the predicate is quite dierent from ordinary, empirical predicates. It fulls a particular functionand it is unclear what funcion that isthat is not fullled by any other predicate. Even more importantly, the meaning of the predicate is, due to its dissimilarities to empirical predicates, not empirical and irreducable. That leads to the third point on which deationists agree, namely the claim that the truth predicate does not denote an underlying property all truths might have in common. Lastly, deationism as characterised by Horwich implies the view that other concepts, especially meaning, cannot be based on our conception of truth. Interestingly, Horwich does not incorporate the equivalence schema into his cursory characterisation of deationism. It is often taken for granted that this schema in one form or other is at the core of deationary theories of truth. One reason why it is not taken to be a dening feature of deationism could be the fact that deationists disgree about what the primary truth bearers are. In Horwich's account the truth bearers are propositions. The equivalence schema, however, is normally stated in terms of sentence 1

4 types or utterances. Horwich himself sticks to this convention when he circumscribes the schema by saying that we apply [`true'] to a statement, s, when we take s to have the same content (i.e., meaning) as something we are already disposed to assert (2010, 17). In accordance with Horwich's view, the equivalence schema may be formulated in terms of propositions: (ES) <p> is true p. 1 If we were to add the schema to the characterisation of deationism, we would then also have to add the caveat that it must be formulated according to whatever the relevant deationist takes as the primary bearers of truth. 1.2 Minimalism With these very basic deationary insights at hand, minimalists argue, an adequate theory of truth is almost complete. Recall the afore-mentioned equivalence schema: <p> is true p. According to Horwich, the concept of truth amounts to nothing more than the acceptances of each instance of this principle. To be precise, although we are presumably also inclined to accept the principle itself, the minimalist explains truth in terms of its instances. As Horwich (1998b, 6) puts it: [minimalism] contains no more than what is expressed by uncontroversial instances of the equivalence schema. And [i]t can be argued [... ] that our underived inclination to accept these biconditionals is the source of everything else we do with the truth predicate (Horwich 2010, 36, emphasis omitted). Our inclination to accept each instance may be `underived', the minimalist nevertheless owes us an explanation as to why we need true in the rst place. And in order to be in accordance with (ES), this explanation must get by without the claim that truth is a substantial property. The explanation Horwich oers is strikingly simple. The only reason why we need to employ true is because it is a device with which we can express blind ascriptions and certain generalisations, which are otherwise inexpressible. Here are two examples: (1) What is written on the blackboard in the room next to this one is true. (2) Jess tries to believe only true things. To begin with, the truth predicate isn't eliminable from these sentences. In any case, expressing the same proposition without the use of the truth predicate would be hopelessly complicated. Assume for example that (1) is a convenient abbreviation of (1'): (1') If what is written on the blackboard next door is God is dead, then God is dead, if what is written on the blackboard next door is The Northern Euro is more stable than the Southern Euro, then the Northern Euro is more stable than the Southern Euro... 1 Horwich (2010, 36). 2

5 For several reasons the propositions expressed by (1) and (1') aren't cognitively equivalent, i.e. not everyone who believes either of these propositions is thereby committed to believe the other. 2 One reason is the apparent fact that (1') involves concepts a given subject doesn't possess. 3 Another reason is this: the conjunction in (1') is innite, but innitely long conjunctions are not among the things believable by humans (although one may be inclined to accept each of its conjuncts). The situation is a bit dierent in the case of (2) because we are indeed able to express the same proposition with the non-truth-theoretic part of our language. Jess, say, wants to believe < = 27> 4 i = 27 and she wants to believe <grass is green> i grass is green and so forth. From this we may (in case the list is reasonably long) generalise to: Jess wants to believe <p> i p. This gives us (via (ES)) the original claim that Jess tries to believe only true things. But this is exactly how the minimalist explains the situation. The truth predicate is, according to him, just a convenient device which we need in order to state claims like (1) and (2). In terms of utility of the truth predicate, only one other type of use besides blind ascriptions and generalisations seems to exist. Sentences which involve the truth predicate but do not belong to the two classes just discussed are those sentences in which truth is ascribed directly to ordinary sentences. Among these three classes of how one might use the truth predicate this is probably the least problematic. Consider, for example, (3): (3) <Snow is white> is true. In this example the truth predicate indeed seems to be eliminable. To say that <snow is white> is true is always as appropriate as just to say that snow is white (and it seems as if it expresses the same proposition). This is what motivated redundancy approaches to truth, approaches which claimed the truth predicate to be negligible. But redundancy theorists miss the importance of the use of the predicate as in examples like (1) and (2), in which it isn't redundant and not even in principle eliminable. According to Horwich, a theory of truth serves three purposes. 5 It explains the function of truth, its conceptual aspects and its nature. Examples (1)(3) give a rough impression of how the minimalist explains the function of the truth predicate: it is needed to formulate generalisationsalso those of logic: a conjunction is true i both conjuncts are true, for instanceand it is needed when the proposition ascribed is actually unknown or too complicated to formulate. Regarding the nature of truth, the minimalist position might be summarised thus: there is no underlying nature of truth. This is to be understood as follows: every non- 2 Horwich takes propositional truth to be conceptually basic and denes sentential truth using that notion (Horwich 1998b, ). In accordance with this usage, I'll formulate examples in terms of propositions in the following. 3 This is the case because, since (1') is an endless conjunction with an endless number of concepts, it couldn't be grasped by subjects with a nite repertoire of concepts. 4 Propositions are indicated by angle brackets. Read S hopes <p> as S hopes that p (cf. Horwich 2010, 5). 5 Cf. Horwich (1998b, 36). Strictly speaking, Horwich distinguishes ve ways in which the question `What is the minimalist conception of truth about?' might be understood. I omit understanding and meaning here. 3

6 deationary theory of truth oers an explanation of what truth is in form of the schema: x is true i F 1 (x),..., F n (x). Deationary theories on the other hand have it that (ES) instances are conceptually basic. There cannot be any reduction of the biconditional, i.e. truth can't be explained in the form of the schema deployed by non-deationists. Moreover, the truth predicate denotes only a `logical property' (this is Field's (1992) phrase), as opposed to a `substantive property'. 6 Horwich's view on the property denoted by the truth predicate and his view on the function of the predicate are closely related. On the one hand, the truth predicate is supercially similar to other predicates, i.e. those predicates that denote analysable or `naturalistic' properties. The equivalence axiomsinstances of the truth predicate, however, belong to the realm of the apriori. They are, as Horwich puts it, in this respect `on a par with instances of fundamental logical laws'. On the other hand, the truth predicate is therefore dierent from other predicatestruth has no underlying nature. It is because of this combination of (dis-)similarities that we may, for lack of a better term, conclude that truth is a logical property. 2 Objections to Minimalism 2.1 The Generalisation Problem Minimalism today is something like the received view within deationism. It is, however, important to bear in mind that there are still a great variety of objections against the thesis. Before I turn to one of the most persistent objections, the Liar paradox, I shall briey reference at another objection. A still hotly debated objection is one which concerns the conceptual aspects of truth the Generalisation Problem. 7 Roughly put, a minimalist theory doesn't prove generalisations concerning truth, although it proves each single instance of a general rule. That is, only equipped with a minimalist theory we are unable, some opponents claim, to derive Every sentence of the form if p, then p is true from the (innitely) long list of instances of the very same generalisation: (4) If pigeons y, then pigeons y (5) If the moon consists of cheese, then the moon consists of cheese (... ) Horwich had replied some objections at greater length, most recently in his comprehensive book on the two closely intertwined notions of truth and meaning (Horwich 2010). The Generalisation Problemcurrently the most important criticism of minimalismis one such objection. At others however, Horwich had so far only given very rough sketches 6 See the Postscript to Horwich's (1998) for a discussion of properties, especially section 1, 5 and 8 (Horwich 1998b, ). 7 The issue was rst raised by Gupta (1993). Meanwhile, it has been developed variously (e.g., by Soames 1997). See Armour-Garb (2010) and Raatikainen (2005) for recent discussions. 4

7 of responses. Of these, the Liar paradox is the most prominent example. Although never spelled out in detail, Horwich indicated what an appropriate response might look like. His arguments are convincing and once they are cashed out in detail, they prove the opponents wrong in this respect. This is the reason why I intend to focus on the Liar in the following. 2.2 The Liar Consider the following proposition: (λ) <λ is false> The minimalist theory together with classical logic yields a contradiction when applied to the Liar: the proposition is true i the proposition is false. There are also other Liar-like propositions which every theory of truth faces. The socalled Strengthened Liar, for instance, mainly serves the purpose of questioning theories that allow truth value gaps. 8 Since Horwich denies them anyway (1998b, 7677), we may set this variant of the Liar aside. Another closely related pathological proposition is the Truthteller: (τ) <τ is true> This proposition will become important later on when we discuss Horwich's early responses to the Liar. In contrast to the Liar, (τ) induces no paradox. Nevertheless, it seems to be ill-formed in a way similar to the paradoxes. In the case of the Truthteller, one may, roughly speaking, `choose' which truth value one wants the proposition to have. If true, then it is true indeed (because that is what (τ) `says of itself'). If, on the other hand, it is assumed to be false, then, in accordance with the assumption, what the proposition saysnamely that it is trueis false. So whatever truth value one might assume the proposition to have, the chosen assumption will always be `fullled' by the expressed content itself. 2.3 Solutions to the Liar Paradox Non-paradoxical Instances Minimalism, as described so far, therefore needs to be modied accordingly in order to prevent contradictions like the ones induced by the Liar and other pathologies like those exemplied by (τ). There are a great variety of options open to the minimalist and in particular to Horwich, but each has its own diculties (cf. Horwich 1998b, 41). Firstly, he could deny that (λ) is a proposition at all. Secondly, he could deny that truth can be ascribed to propositions which themselves involve the truth-theoretic part of a given language. Thirdly, he could alter the logic and endorse a paraconsistent logic or a 8 For the pretty obvious reason that `gappy' propositions, i.e. propositions that are neither true nor false, are not true. That is why the Strengthened Liar is immune to responses given to normal Liar paradoxes. Mutatis mutandis, the same applies to sentences. 5

8 paracomplete one. Fourthlyand this is Horwich's solution, he could restrict the class of correct instances of (ES). Although the characterisations dier slightly between his (1998) and his (2010), Horwich's solution is to accept that (λ) is a proposition but to exclude it from the list of `permissible' instances of the equivalence schema. This is a highly controversial move, because not only it is unclear how exactly the propositions which need to be excluded could be dened, but moreover it can be doubted if the application of the schema is restricted at all (Armour-Garb & Beall 2003). 9 In a nutshell, Horwich's strategy is this: our inclination to accept (ES) instances is indeed unrestricted, i.e. we are inclined to accept every single instance. But this inclination can beand in some cases isover-ridden. The Liar is one such example. A theory of truth therefore provides, among other things, an explanation of which instances are not accepted and why. In Horwich's terms, theories of truth have to meet three adequacy conditions in this respect: (i) they have to determine which instances are unacceptable (and (λ) needs to be among those instances), (ii) keep this list 10 as short as possible, (iii) they need to explain in simple terms what all unacceptable instances have in common (Horwich 1998b, 42). An early solution of his is to restrict the axioms of the equivalence schema to nonparadoxical instances (Horwich 1998b, 40). Regarding the proposed adequacy conditions, it seems to be the case that condition (i) is met: putting (λ) into the schema yields paradoxical results, which is why (λ) is among the excluded instances. Conditions (ii) and (iii), however, are not fullled. Consider both in turn. Condition (iii) requires that the theory explains in simple terms the commonalities among the excluded instances of (ES). But the exclusion of paradoxical instances is, so to say, only descriptively adequate, if at all. At best, the solution tells us what instances are to be excluded. But it oers no explanation as to why these particular instances are excluded, i.e. it doesn't explain what the underlying reason is. (Except if the claim that all these instances are paradoxical counts as an explanation, which is highly dubious.) Even worse, condition (ii) is admittedly metthe list of excluded instances is short indeedbut the list is too short. The criterion misses pathological propositions like the Truthteller. We saw above that the Truthteller doesn't yield paradoxes. Nevertheless, it is an analoguously pathological proposition for it has highly counterintuitive consequences. I will demonstrate in the next section that Horwich's modied reply fares better in this respect. It is taken for granted by Horwich that it is an empirical fact that our otherwise general inclinations are over-ridden in certain cases: [i]nstead of linking the meaning of true with the disposition to wholeheartedly accept a certain restricted class of instances, we might link it with the defeasible inclination to accept any instance. We might suppose that, in paradoxical cases, this inclination is over-ridden; but that it nonetheless continues 9 I'll return to that issue below. 10 Actually, it is not a list but rather a specication of the underlying criteria which justify the exclusion (see below), i.e. the excluded instances are dened intensional rather than extensional. 6

9 to existsustaining the sense of paradox. (2010, 47, emphasis original) Two questions arise in view of this claim. Is the claim true in general? And how does Horwich's theory depend on the (general) truth of the empirical observation? Regarding the rst question, an armative answer is sometimes called into question. The problem is that dialetheists, logicians who believe in true contradictions, have a somewhat dierent view on the Liar than those favouring classical logic. From their point of view, (λ) is both true and false. 11 In fact, this solution to the paradox motivates, as it were, dialetheism in the rst place. But this view is perfectly compatible with the unrestricted application of (ES). We may therefore say that Horwich is wrong in assuming that the rejection of some of (ES)'s instances is equally distributed. Quite the contrary, there are some competent speakers of English who endorse even those controversial instances. What implications that has for Horwich's general claim, however, is a completely dierent matter. I therefore now turn to the second question. How serious an issue is the observation just discussed? Not serious at all, as I will argue. It depends on what one expects a theory of truth to achieve. Apparently, views on that issue dier signicantly among theorists. We may, for example, distinguish between approaches that try to capture someone's everyday use of true (or an approximation thereof) and those approaches that deal only with formal languages. Theories of the latter kind are in a sense revisionary (e.g., Tarski 1944, esp. pp ), while theories of the former kind only give an account of true (and, for that matter, of truth) as it gures in natural languages. Horwich's theory is of the natural language type: [... ] we face up to the fact that there was never any reason [... ] to expect the truth predicate's meaning to be xed by an explicit denition (2010, 2627). Hence, the desired theory of truth has to be in accordance with everyday use of the truth predicate. Whether this aim is achieved does not depend on the status of the Liar, for the Liar is an articial proposition, not part of everyday discourse. In any case, dialetheists' claim that propositions can both be true and false deviates signicantly from common use of the truth predicate. It is because of this reason that the de facto plausible claim that Liar-involving instances of the biconditional are sometimes accepted is no counterexample to a theory which gives an account of normal uses of it. 12 Notice that one's view on how to deal with rejections of certain instances of (ES) does not only depend on what the theory is expected to achieve but also depends on background assumptions held in neighbouring areas of truth. Those may be held for totally independent reasons. Consider, for example, classical logic. Some hold that the Liar gives the minimalist reason to endorse dialetheism (Beall & Armour-Garb 2003). 11 In order to avoid triviality, dialetheists reject ex falso quodlibet. So although there could be dialetheia, (sentences used to express) propositions that are true and false, ψ (for any arbitrary ψ) isn't derivable in a dialetheic logic (cf. Priest 2006): φ φ ψ. 12 This view isn't chauvinistic in any way either, because most theories that are supposed to be in accordance with the discourse need to allow exceptions to their general claims. Examples include the formulation of functional roles in terms of typical behavioural dispositions or grammars of natural languages. 7

10 But equally one may successfully reason the other way round: from the independently justied assumption that classical logic holds one couldwith further assumptionsinfer that the Liar yields contradiction and therefore instances of the equivalence schema must be restricted in some form or other Ungrounded Propositions Horwich's early proposal of how to restrict the instances of (ES)the exclusion of nonparadoxical instanceshas its drawbacks. In particular, it does not provide a solution to the Truthteller. The Truthteller isn not paradoxical and (ES) instances involving (τ) would therefore count as acceptable, which is highly counterintuitive: (τ a ) <τ is true> is true i τ is true (τ b ) <τ is true> is false i τ is false In his recent work Horwich's response to the Liar is basically still the same, but has been slightly modied: [a]n approach to the paradox that promises to avoid these defects [which a Tarskian solution faces] would be to identify true 0, true 1, etc., i.e. to have a single predicate but to restrict, in something like the way that Tarski does, instantiation of the equivalence schemaapplying it only to a certain privileged subset of propositions: those that are `grounded', in a sense to be specied. (2010, 90, emphasis omitted) His solution now is to regard only those instances of (ES) as acceptable that apply the truth predicate to grounded propositions. How the notion of groundedness is to be dened precisely and as formally correct is a matter which need not be presented here. A comprehensive account on groundedness has recently been given by Leitgeb (2005). The main idea is this: groundedness is dened as a property of sentences. Sentences are grounded if, and only if, they either refer to non-truth-theoretic facts or to sentences which are (perhaps via a long chain) themselves grounded. All other sentences are ungrounded. The notion of groundedness can now be incorporated into a theory of truth that takes propositions to be the truth bearers in the following straightforward way. All those propositions are ungrounded which are expressible by ungrounded sentences. Horwich is not explicit on this, but in light of his discussion of why propositions are the bearers of truth (as opposed, for instance, to sentences) this reconstruction of his argument seems to be justied. Propositions like the Liar or the Truthteller refer to truth-theoretic facts only, they arenot even indirectlygrounded in any non-semantic facts. Uncontroversial instances in the sense in question are those which involve grounded propositions. Regarding this response we need to ask ourselves: does this formulation exclude all potentially problematic instances of (ES)? And can the response really be regarded as a solution? Presumably, the answer to the rst question is armative. All known problematic cases are based on sentences that are ungrounded in one way 8

11 or other. 13 In light of the contrast between the two responses to the Liar paradox, the recent response may be regarded as a solution. It is not just posited which (ES) instances are excluded (i.e. the paradoxical ones), but in addition to it an explanation is provided why these very (ES) instances (i.e. the ungrounded ones) are excluded: because they don't refer to non-truth-theoretic facts. Also, we may regard (without circularity) the elegant exclusion of (λ) and (τ) itself as an indication that the proposed response is a proper solution. The minimalist holds that propositions are the primary truth bearers. (λ) expresses a proposition, as we saw above. Accordingly, it has a truth value, i.e. the True or the False (due to Horwich's adherence to the bivalence principle (1998, 7883, 2005, ch. 4)). In order to keep this viewthe combination of propositions as truth bearers and bivalencecoherent, Horwich connects it with his epistemic approach to vagueness. According to this approach, the truth value of a proposition involving a borderline case is unknownalthough it is known that it has one of the classical values (Horwich 2005, ch. 4). Horwich asks us to think of (λ) as a similar case in which the truth value is unknown for epistemic reasons (Horwich 2010, 91, n. 11). 14 Recall Horwich's three conditions which an approach to the Liar has to meet. The proposal that the truth predicate is only applicable to grounded propositions provides an explanation of the underlying reason for rejecting some of (ES)'s instances. This is not to say that people, when they reject applying the biconditional, reject it because they are aware of the ungroundedness of the proposition in question. The notion of groundedness here only serves the purpose of explanation from our point of view, i.e. it provides of explanation of what all rejected instances (dialetheistic intuitions aside) have in common. From a theory of truth that gives an account of truth as it gures in natural languages we can't expect more (or less) than that. Such a theory is successful if its predictions t to the data. I shall now look at how a minimalist achieves this end. Besides the minimalist's claims about the nature and function of truth he oers an account of the use of true. And it is precisely in this respect that the Liar is expected to be a problem, because the corresponding sentence seems to be syntactically well formed but is nevertheless deviant. One would normally refrain from applying () is true to 13 All so-far discussed are ungrounded due to their self-referentiality. There are other problematic cases that may be formulated without invoking self-referentiality. The Endless Cycle is an example of this kind: consider an endless set of Truthtellers, all saying that `the next sentence is true'. Each single sentence is ungrounded, since its truth/falsity always depends on the truth-theoretic facts of the language; nowhere in the chain appears a sentence that refers to non-semantic facts of the world. They are therefore captured by Horwich's modied response. 14 Note that the explanations for why (λ) and, respectively, a vague proposition have either of the two classical truth values dier signicantly. Very roughly put, the explanations are: (i) meaning supervenes on use; the supervenience base of vague predicates is unknown due to limited epistemic capacities; we are therefore sure that vague propositions have (classical) truth values, although we cannot know which; (ii) bivalence is independently justied; (λ) is a proposition and thus truth-apt; truth is explained in terms of instances of the equivalence schema; there is no such instance of (λ); we are therefore sure that the Liar has a (classical) truth value, although we cannot know which. Further dissimilarities arise if Horwich allows for margin of error principles in the case of vague predicates. It is not obvious how such principles would apply to (λ). Here, however, is not the right place to discuss such further issues. 9

12 things like this proposition. Recall the minimalist's core idea that our use of true is explained in the way that each instance of (ES) is normally accepted and that this underived inclination is an inexplicable fact. In order to stick to classical logic, the LEM, the bivalence principle and the status of (λ) as expressing a proposition, the minimalist restricts the application conditions of (ES) in such a way that it does not apply to the Liar and other controversial propositions Why Restrict the Equivalence Schema? Recently, the minimalist's position has been challenged by a more general worry to the eect that the minimalist is in need of a reason why (λ)-involving instances should be excluded from the list of axioms in the rst place. (This is a more general claim because the debate concerning the Liar normally turns on the question of how exactly the list of permissible (ES) instances is to be restricted.) Armour-Garb & Beall discuss several proposals which they all reject as inappropriate. They conclude that a minimalist must either propose other strategies to restrict (ES) or accept the view that (λ) is true. In reviewing the strength of Armour-Garb & Beall's challenge, I will focus on one particular aspect: the correct denition of negation. Armour-Garb & Beall appeal to a framework in which negation is characterised in the way it contributes to the content of contradictions. 15 There are three kinds of negation: explosive, partial and null accounts. Given an explosive account of negation, φ φ entails ψ (for arbitrary ψ). 16 A minimalist, Armour-Garb & Beall claim, needs either an null account or an explosive account of negation in order for his theory to succeed. But apparently, both face problems. I shall restrict myself to examining the explosive notion of negation in the following. As we saw above, explosive negation is no reasonable option for dialetheists because the conjunction of both theses would entail trivialism, i.e. anything would be derivable within the theorya consequence even dialetheists like to avoid. Focussing on one particular strategy the minimalist might pursue, Armour-Garb & Beall (2003, ) say: [i]t is important to note that if the minimalist is to establish the explosive view by appeal to principles of reasoning to which our inferential behaviour conforms, her grounds must be that our inferential behaviour conforms to such principles in all cases. [... ] For simplicity, let us focus on DS [Disjunctive Syllogism] alone. To establish that inferential behaviour conforms to DS, one must establish the absence of [... ] behaviour in which both φ and φ ψ are accepted but ψ is not 15 They give Routly & Routley (1995) and Priest (1998) credit for this account. 16 The other two accounts are: Partial: φ φ has some but not full content; it entails some things but not everything. Null: φ φ has no content; it entails nothing (except, perhaps, itself). (Armour-Garb & Beall 2003, 392) 10

13 accepted. [... T]here are various problems that immediately confront such a task[.] (emphasis omitted) So the idea is that, since inferences that are disjunctive syllogisms are based on explosive negation, one may show explosive negation to be, at least, very likely if there are no apparent counterexamples to our general conformity to the syllogism. Armour-Garb & Beall claim to have shown that such counterexamples do indeed exist. Obviously, dialetheists themselves are a counterexample. I argued above that, when empirical examples are concerned, dialetheists intuitions are to be ignored, for they are exceptions and therefore not counterevidence when the existence of dialetheia themselves are in question. Armour-Garb & Beall are aware of this response and admit that besides dialetheists no one shows deviant inferential behaviour as regards DS (2003, 397). Allegedly, however, the minimalist's theory has no means to explain this fact: 17 the only answer that the minimalist can provide which would serve her purposes [explaining the absence of counterexamples concerning DS conformity] invokes a prior stance on the truth status of [the Liar sentence] Lthat L is neither true nor false [... ] (Armour-Garb & Beall 2003, 397). This, however, isn't the only option available to the minimalist. Recall how Horwich handles the Liar. Although (for epistemic reasons) we don't know what it is, (λ) has a determinate truth value. The epistemic problems, again, are explained in terms of the ungroundedness of (λ): the truth predicate may only be applied to propositions that are grounded in non-truth-theoretic facts. In other words, there is an explanation of why everyone (dialetheists aside) rejects accepting (λ). This explanation neither involves a `prior stance on the truth status' nor the concept of truth itself, i.e. the explanation is non-circular. Having established this, we can now see how a minimalist might `build up' his justication of explosive negation. There are no known cases in which DS does not hold in actual human reasoning. DS presupposes an explosive notion of negation. 18 Hence, we would be better expect negation to be explosive The Status of the Liar The Liar is one among a great variety of responses provoked by minimalism. The most promising strategy in favour of minimalism is to point to linguistic practice, as is done by Horwich. 20 From an analysis of true, i.e. an analysis of the use of the truth predicate, we may then proceed to other (alleged) aspects of truththe concept and the nature, if 17 For the sake of argument, I accept this requirement. However, one may reasonably doubt whether a theory of truth really can be expected to provide explanations for human inferential behaviour. One may, for instance, regard inferential behaviour as a brute fact or as adaptive evolutionary development (to be explained by cognitive sciences, say). Presumably, the concept of truth isn't needed in both cases (as is required if DS is supposed to support minimalism). 18 Armour-Garb & Beall (2003, 396, n. 31) explicitly admit the latter. 19 Following Armour-Garb & Beall's example, the argument was formulated in terms of syllogisms. However, analoguous arguments may be applied to every justication recurring to inferential behaviour in which ungrounded propositions gure. 20 The counterpart to his theory of truth is his theory of meaning (e.g., Horwich 1998a, Horwich 2005), which compliments the former, and vice versa. 11

14 any. In the context of the Liar, exactly this rst step is concerned. Especially dialetheists disagree with minimalists on the status of the Liar in human inferences. And, as we saw above, there is indeed a huge dierence: at least dialetheists regard (λ) as true (and false, for that matter). They are exceptions and minimalists need to account for those exceptions. The given overview indicates how they might do so. I have shown how a minimalist theory of truth can be defended against objections based on Liar paradoxes, without being comitted to dialetheism. Horwich's early responsethe exclusion of paradoxical (ES) instancesis inappropriate in this respect. A slighly modied response, however, fares much better. If an account of groundedness, formulated in terms of propositions, is incorporated into a minimalist theory of truth, (λ)-involving instances (and related pathological propositions) may be successfully excluded within an approach based on classical logic (including LEM). In addition, I have shown that the prior assumption that the range of (ES) instances needs to be restricted is independently justied. Horwich is therefore not commited to dialetheism in order to defend a minimalist conception of truth. 12

15 References Armour-Garb, B. (2010), `Horwichian minimalism and the generalization problem', Analysis 70, Armour-Garb, B. & Beall, J. (2003), `Minimalism and the dialetheic challenge', Australasian Journal of Philosophy 81, Beall, J. & Armour-Garb, B. (2003), `Should deationists be dialetheists?', Noûs 37, Field, H. (1992), `Critical notice: Paul Horwich's Truth', Philosophy of Science 59, Gupta, A. (1993), `Minimalism', Philosophical Perspectives 7, Horwich, P. (1998a), Meaning, Clarendon Press, Oxford. Horwich, P. (1998b), Truth, 2. edn, Oxford University Press, Oxford. Horwich, P. (2005), Reections on Meaning, Clarendon Press, Oxford. Horwich, P. (2010), Truth Meaning Reality, Clarendon Press, Oxford. Leitgeb, H. (2005), `What truth depends on', Journal of Philosophical Logic 34, Priest, G. (1998), `What is so bad about contradictions?', Journal of Philosophy 95, Priest, G. (2006), In Contradiction, Oxford University Press, Oxford. Raatikainen, P. (2005), `On Horwich's way out', Analysis 65, Routly, R. & Routley, V. (1995), `Negation and contradiction', Rivista Colombiana de Matematicas 19, Soames, S. (1997), `The truth about deationism', Philosophical Issues 8, 144. Tarski, A. (1944), `The semantic conception of truth and the foundations of semantics', Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 4,

Horwich and the Liar

Horwich and the Liar Horwich and the Liar Sergi Oms Sardans Logos, University of Barcelona 1 Horwich defends an epistemic account of vagueness according to which vague predicates have sharp boundaries which we are not capable

More information

Paradox of Deniability

Paradox of Deniability 1 Paradox of Deniability Massimiliano Carrara FISPPA Department, University of Padua, Italy Peking University, Beijing - 6 November 2018 Introduction. The starting elements Suppose two speakers disagree

More information

Understanding Truth Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002

Understanding Truth Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002 1 Symposium on Understanding Truth By Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002 2 Precis of Understanding Truth Scott Soames Understanding Truth aims to illuminate

More information

Williams on Supervaluationism and Logical Revisionism

Williams on Supervaluationism and Logical Revisionism Williams on Supervaluationism and Logical Revisionism Nicholas K. Jones Non-citable draft: 26 02 2010. Final version appeared in: The Journal of Philosophy (2011) 108: 11: 633-641 Central to discussion

More information

Figure 1 Figure 2 U S S. non-p P P

Figure 1 Figure 2 U S S. non-p P P 1 Depicting negation in diagrammatic logic: legacy and prospects Fabien Schang, Amirouche Moktefi schang.fabien@voila.fr amirouche.moktefi@gersulp.u-strasbg.fr Abstract Here are considered the conditions

More information

Can Negation be Defined in Terms of Incompatibility?

Can Negation be Defined in Terms of Incompatibility? Can Negation be Defined in Terms of Incompatibility? Nils Kurbis 1 Abstract Every theory needs primitives. A primitive is a term that is not defined any further, but is used to define others. Thus primitives

More information

A Liar Paradox. Richard G. Heck, Jr. Brown University

A Liar Paradox. Richard G. Heck, Jr. Brown University A Liar Paradox Richard G. Heck, Jr. Brown University It is widely supposed nowadays that, whatever the right theory of truth may be, it needs to satisfy a principle sometimes known as transparency : Any

More information

Maudlin s Truth and Paradox Hartry Field

Maudlin s Truth and Paradox Hartry Field Maudlin s Truth and Paradox Hartry Field Tim Maudlin s Truth and Paradox is terrific. In some sense its solution to the paradoxes is familiar the book advocates an extension of what s called the Kripke-Feferman

More information

Chadwick Prize Winner: Christian Michel THE LIAR PARADOX OUTSIDE-IN

Chadwick Prize Winner: Christian Michel THE LIAR PARADOX OUTSIDE-IN Chadwick Prize Winner: Christian Michel THE LIAR PARADOX OUTSIDE-IN To classify sentences like This proposition is false as having no truth value or as nonpropositions is generally considered as being

More information

Varieties of Apriority

Varieties of Apriority S E V E N T H E X C U R S U S Varieties of Apriority T he notions of a priori knowledge and justification play a central role in this work. There are many ways in which one can understand the a priori,

More information

Automated Reasoning Project. Research School of Information Sciences and Engineering. and Centre for Information Science Research

Automated Reasoning Project. Research School of Information Sciences and Engineering. and Centre for Information Science Research Technical Report TR-ARP-14-95 Automated Reasoning Project Research School of Information Sciences and Engineering and Centre for Information Science Research Australian National University August 10, 1995

More information

Epistemicism and the Liar

Epistemicism and the Liar Epistemicism and the Liar Forthcoming in Synthese Jamin Asay University of Hong Kong asay@hku.hk Abstract One well known approach to the soritical paradoxes is epistemicism, the view that propositions

More information

ON USING INCONSISTENT EXPRESSIONS

ON USING INCONSISTENT EXPRESSIONS Published in Erkenntnis 77 (1), pp.133-148, available at www.springerlink.com, DOI 10.1007/s10670-011-9310-2. ON USING INCONSISTENT EXPRESSIONS Arvid Båve, Stockholm University Abstract: The paper discusses

More information

Can logical consequence be deflated?

Can logical consequence be deflated? Can logical consequence be deflated? Michael De University of Utrecht Department of Philosophy Utrecht, Netherlands mikejde@gmail.com in Insolubles and Consequences : essays in honour of Stephen Read,

More information

Semantic Pathology and the Open Pair

Semantic Pathology and the Open Pair Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Vol. LXXI, No. 3, November 2005 Semantic Pathology and the Open Pair JAMES A. WOODBRIDGE University of Nevada, Las Vegas BRADLEY ARMOUR-GARB University at Albany,

More information

Intersubstitutivity Principles and the Generalization Function of Truth. Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh. Shawn Standefer University of Melbourne

Intersubstitutivity Principles and the Generalization Function of Truth. Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh. Shawn Standefer University of Melbourne Intersubstitutivity Principles and the Generalization Function of Truth Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh Shawn Standefer University of Melbourne Abstract We offer a defense of one aspect of Paul Horwich

More information

Comments on Truth at A World for Modal Propositions

Comments on Truth at A World for Modal Propositions Comments on Truth at A World for Modal Propositions Christopher Menzel Texas A&M University March 16, 2008 Since Arthur Prior first made us aware of the issue, a lot of philosophical thought has gone into

More information

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW DISCUSSION NOTE BY CAMPBELL BROWN JOURNAL OF ETHICS & SOCIAL PHILOSOPHY DISCUSSION NOTE MAY 2015 URL: WWW.JESP.ORG COPYRIGHT CAMPBELL BROWN 2015 Two Versions of Hume s Law MORAL CONCLUSIONS CANNOT VALIDLY

More information

This Magic Moment: Horwich on the Boundaries of Vague Terms

This Magic Moment: Horwich on the Boundaries of Vague Terms This Magic Moment: Horwich on the Boundaries of Vague Terms Consider the following argument: (1) Bertrand Russell was old at age 3 10 18 nanoseconds (that s about 95 years) (2) He wasn t old at age 0 nanoseconds

More information

Programme. Sven Rosenkranz: Agnosticism and Epistemic Norms. Alexandra Zinke: Varieties of Suspension

Programme. Sven Rosenkranz: Agnosticism and Epistemic Norms. Alexandra Zinke: Varieties of Suspension Suspension of Belief Mannheim, October 2627, 2018 Room EO 242 Programme Friday, October 26 08.4509.00 09.0009.15 09.1510.15 10.3011.30 11.4512.45 12.4514.15 14.1515.15 15.3016.30 16.4517.45 18.0019.00

More information

WHY THERE REALLY ARE NO IRREDUCIBLY NORMATIVE PROPERTIES

WHY THERE REALLY ARE NO IRREDUCIBLY NORMATIVE PROPERTIES WHY THERE REALLY ARE NO IRREDUCIBLY NORMATIVE PROPERTIES Bart Streumer b.streumer@rug.nl In David Bakhurst, Brad Hooker and Margaret Little (eds.), Thinking About Reasons: Essays in Honour of Jonathan

More information

how to be an expressivist about truth

how to be an expressivist about truth Mark Schroeder University of Southern California March 15, 2009 how to be an expressivist about truth In this paper I explore why one might hope to, and how to begin to, develop an expressivist account

More information

Can Negation be Defined in Terms of Incompatibility?

Can Negation be Defined in Terms of Incompatibility? Can Negation be Defined in Terms of Incompatibility? Nils Kurbis 1 Introduction Every theory needs primitives. A primitive is a term that is not defined any further, but is used to define others. Thus

More information

Scott Soames: Understanding Truth

Scott Soames: Understanding Truth Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Vol. LXV, No. 2, September 2002 Scott Soames: Understanding Truth MAlTHEW MCGRATH Texas A & M University Scott Soames has written a valuable book. It is unmatched

More information

Necessity and Truth Makers

Necessity and Truth Makers JAN WOLEŃSKI Instytut Filozofii Uniwersytetu Jagiellońskiego ul. Gołębia 24 31-007 Kraków Poland Email: jan.wolenski@uj.edu.pl Web: http://www.filozofia.uj.edu.pl/jan-wolenski Keywords: Barry Smith, logic,

More information

Review of "The Tarskian Turn: Deflationism and Axiomatic Truth"

Review of The Tarskian Turn: Deflationism and Axiomatic Truth Essays in Philosophy Volume 13 Issue 2 Aesthetics and the Senses Article 19 August 2012 Review of "The Tarskian Turn: Deflationism and Axiomatic Truth" Matthew McKeon Michigan State University Follow this

More information

Remarks on a Foundationalist Theory of Truth. Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh

Remarks on a Foundationalist Theory of Truth. Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh For Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Remarks on a Foundationalist Theory of Truth Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh I Tim Maudlin s Truth and Paradox offers a theory of truth that arises from

More information

Truth At a World for Modal Propositions

Truth At a World for Modal Propositions Truth At a World for Modal Propositions 1 Introduction Existentialism is a thesis that concerns the ontological status of individual essences and singular propositions. Let us define an individual essence

More information

Some proposals for understanding narrow content

Some proposals for understanding narrow content Some proposals for understanding narrow content February 3, 2004 1 What should we require of explanations of narrow content?......... 1 2 Narrow psychology as whatever is shared by intrinsic duplicates......

More information

THE INEXPRESSIBILITY OF TRUTH

THE INEXPRESSIBILITY OF TRUTH THE INEXPRESSIBILITY OF TRUTH By EMIL BĂDICI A DISSERTATION PRESENTED TO THE GRADUATE SCHOOL OF THE UNIVERSITY OF FLORIDA IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY

More information

Vol. II, No. 5, Reason, Truth and History, 127. LARS BERGSTRÖM

Vol. II, No. 5, Reason, Truth and History, 127. LARS BERGSTRÖM Croatian Journal of Philosophy Vol. II, No. 5, 2002 L. Bergström, Putnam on the Fact-Value Dichotomy 1 Putnam on the Fact-Value Dichotomy LARS BERGSTRÖM Stockholm University In Reason, Truth and History

More information

Ayer on the criterion of verifiability

Ayer on the criterion of verifiability Ayer on the criterion of verifiability November 19, 2004 1 The critique of metaphysics............................. 1 2 Observation statements............................... 2 3 In principle verifiability...............................

More information

Appeared in: Al-Mukhatabat. A Trilingual Journal For Logic, Epistemology and Analytical Philosophy, Issue 6: April 2013.

Appeared in: Al-Mukhatabat. A Trilingual Journal For Logic, Epistemology and Analytical Philosophy, Issue 6: April 2013. Appeared in: Al-Mukhatabat. A Trilingual Journal For Logic, Epistemology and Analytical Philosophy, Issue 6: April 2013. Panu Raatikainen Intuitionistic Logic and Its Philosophy Formally, intuitionistic

More information

Logic & Proofs. Chapter 3 Content. Sentential Logic Semantics. Contents: Studying this chapter will enable you to:

Logic & Proofs. Chapter 3 Content. Sentential Logic Semantics. Contents: Studying this chapter will enable you to: Sentential Logic Semantics Contents: Truth-Value Assignments and Truth-Functions Truth-Value Assignments Truth-Functions Introduction to the TruthLab Truth-Definition Logical Notions Truth-Trees Studying

More information

Informalizing Formal Logic

Informalizing Formal Logic Informalizing Formal Logic Antonis Kakas Department of Computer Science, University of Cyprus, Cyprus antonis@ucy.ac.cy Abstract. This paper discusses how the basic notions of formal logic can be expressed

More information

ON PROMOTING THE DEAD CERTAIN: A REPLY TO BEHRENDS, DIPAOLO AND SHARADIN

ON PROMOTING THE DEAD CERTAIN: A REPLY TO BEHRENDS, DIPAOLO AND SHARADIN DISCUSSION NOTE ON PROMOTING THE DEAD CERTAIN: A REPLY TO BEHRENDS, DIPAOLO AND SHARADIN BY STEFAN FISCHER JOURNAL OF ETHICS & SOCIAL PHILOSOPHY DISCUSSION NOTE APRIL 2017 URL: WWW.JESP.ORG COPYRIGHT STEFAN

More information

2 Why Truthmakers GONZALO RODRIGUEZ-PEREYRA 1. INTRODUCTION

2 Why Truthmakers GONZALO RODRIGUEZ-PEREYRA 1. INTRODUCTION 2 Why Truthmakers GONZALO RODRIGUEZ-PEREYRA 1. INTRODUCTION Consider a certain red rose. The proposition that the rose is red is true because the rose is red. One might say as well that the proposition

More information

Faults and Mathematical Disagreement

Faults and Mathematical Disagreement 45 Faults and Mathematical Disagreement María Ponte ILCLI. University of the Basque Country mariaponteazca@gmail.com Abstract: My aim in this paper is to analyse the notion of mathematical disagreements

More information

Epistemic two-dimensionalism

Epistemic two-dimensionalism Epistemic two-dimensionalism phil 93507 Jeff Speaks December 1, 2009 1 Four puzzles.......................................... 1 2 Epistemic two-dimensionalism................................ 3 2.1 Two-dimensional

More information

Understanding Deflationism

Understanding Deflationism 1 Understanding Deflationism by Scott Soames Philosophical Perspectives Volume 17, 2003 2 Understanding Deflationism Scott Soames A Deflationary Conception of Deflationism. My aim here will be to say what

More information

Etchemendy, Tarski, and Logical Consequence 1 Jared Bates, University of Missouri Southwest Philosophy Review 15 (1999):

Etchemendy, Tarski, and Logical Consequence 1 Jared Bates, University of Missouri Southwest Philosophy Review 15 (1999): Etchemendy, Tarski, and Logical Consequence 1 Jared Bates, University of Missouri Southwest Philosophy Review 15 (1999): 47 54. Abstract: John Etchemendy (1990) has argued that Tarski's definition of logical

More information

Reply to Robert Koons

Reply to Robert Koons 632 Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic Volume 35, Number 4, Fall 1994 Reply to Robert Koons ANIL GUPTA and NUEL BELNAP We are grateful to Professor Robert Koons for his excellent, and generous, review

More information

Shieva Kleinschmidt [This is a draft I completed while at Rutgers. Please do not cite without permission.] Conditional Desires.

Shieva Kleinschmidt [This is a draft I completed while at Rutgers. Please do not cite without permission.] Conditional Desires. Shieva Kleinschmidt [This is a draft I completed while at Rutgers. Please do not cite without permission.] Conditional Desires Abstract: There s an intuitive distinction between two types of desires: conditional

More information

Verificationism. PHIL September 27, 2011

Verificationism. PHIL September 27, 2011 Verificationism PHIL 83104 September 27, 2011 1. The critique of metaphysics... 1 2. Observation statements... 2 3. In principle verifiability... 3 4. Strong verifiability... 3 4.1. Conclusive verifiability

More information

KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST. Arnon Keren

KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST. Arnon Keren Abstracta SPECIAL ISSUE VI, pp. 33 46, 2012 KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST Arnon Keren Epistemologists of testimony widely agree on the fact that our reliance on other people's testimony is extensive. However,

More information

THE SEMANTIC REALISM OF STROUD S RESPONSE TO AUSTIN S ARGUMENT AGAINST SCEPTICISM

THE SEMANTIC REALISM OF STROUD S RESPONSE TO AUSTIN S ARGUMENT AGAINST SCEPTICISM SKÉPSIS, ISSN 1981-4194, ANO VII, Nº 14, 2016, p. 33-39. THE SEMANTIC REALISM OF STROUD S RESPONSE TO AUSTIN S ARGUMENT AGAINST SCEPTICISM ALEXANDRE N. MACHADO Universidade Federal do Paraná (UFPR) Email:

More information

What is the Frege/Russell Analysis of Quantification? Scott Soames

What is the Frege/Russell Analysis of Quantification? Scott Soames What is the Frege/Russell Analysis of Quantification? Scott Soames The Frege-Russell analysis of quantification was a fundamental advance in semantics and philosophical logic. Abstracting away from details

More information

Troubles with Trivialism

Troubles with Trivialism Inquiry, Vol. 50, No. 6, 655 667, December 2007 Troubles with Trivialism OTÁVIO BUENO University of Miami, USA (Received 11 September 2007) ABSTRACT According to the trivialist, everything is true. But

More information

Penultimate Draft: Final Revisions not included. Published in Philosophical Books, 1995.

Penultimate Draft: Final Revisions not included. Published in Philosophical Books, 1995. 1 Penultimate Draft: Final Revisions not included. Published in Philosophical Books, 1995. LYNCH ON THE VALUE OF TRUTH MATTHEW MCGRATH The University of Missouri-Columbia Few of us will deny that if a

More information

Definite Descriptions and the Argument from Inference

Definite Descriptions and the Argument from Inference Philosophia (2014) 42:1099 1109 DOI 10.1007/s11406-014-9519-9 Definite Descriptions and the Argument from Inference Wojciech Rostworowski Received: 20 November 2013 / Revised: 29 January 2014 / Accepted:

More information

The Correspondence theory of truth Frank Hofmann

The Correspondence theory of truth Frank Hofmann 1. draft, July 2003 The Correspondence theory of truth Frank Hofmann 1 Introduction Ever since the works of Alfred Tarski and Frank Ramsey, two views on truth have seemed very attractive to many people.

More information

Does Deduction really rest on a more secure epistemological footing than Induction?

Does Deduction really rest on a more secure epistemological footing than Induction? Does Deduction really rest on a more secure epistemological footing than Induction? We argue that, if deduction is taken to at least include classical logic (CL, henceforth), justifying CL - and thus deduction

More information

WRIGHT S ARGUMENT FROM NEUTRALITY. Max Kölbel

WRIGHT S ARGUMENT FROM NEUTRALITY. Max Kölbel , 108 Cowley Road, Oxford OX4 1JF, UK and 350 Main Street, Malden, MA 02148, USA. Ratio (new series) X 1 April 1997 0034 0006 WRIGHT S ARGUMENT FROM NEUTRALITY Max Kölbel Abstract In the first chapter

More information

Quantificational logic and empty names

Quantificational logic and empty names Quantificational logic and empty names Andrew Bacon 26th of March 2013 1 A Puzzle For Classical Quantificational Theory Empty Names: Consider the sentence 1. There is something identical to Pegasus On

More information

From Necessary Truth to Necessary Existence

From Necessary Truth to Necessary Existence Prequel for Section 4.2 of Defending the Correspondence Theory Published by PJP VII, 1 From Necessary Truth to Necessary Existence Abstract I introduce new details in an argument for necessarily existing

More information

1 What is conceptual analysis and what is the problem?

1 What is conceptual analysis and what is the problem? 1 What is conceptual analysis and what is the problem? 1.1 What is conceptual analysis? In this book, I am going to defend the viability of conceptual analysis as a philosophical method. It therefore seems

More information

Penultimate Draft: Final Revisions not Included. Published in Philosophical Studies, December1998. DEFLATIONISM AND THE NORMATIVITY OF TRUTH

Penultimate Draft: Final Revisions not Included. Published in Philosophical Studies, December1998. DEFLATIONISM AND THE NORMATIVITY OF TRUTH Penultimate Draft: Final Revisions not Included. Published in Philosophical Studies, December1998. DEFLATIONISM AND THE NORMATIVITY OF TRUTH Deflationist theories of truth, some critics have argued, fail

More information

The Concept of Testimony

The Concept of Testimony Published in: Epistemology: Contexts, Values, Disagreement, Papers of the 34 th International Wittgenstein Symposium, ed. by Christoph Jäger and Winfried Löffler, Kirchberg am Wechsel: Austrian Ludwig

More information

Skepticism and Internalism

Skepticism and Internalism Skepticism and Internalism John Greco Abstract: This paper explores a familiar skeptical problematic and considers some strategies for responding to it. Section 1 reconstructs and disambiguates the skeptical

More information

Theories of propositions

Theories of propositions Theories of propositions phil 93515 Jeff Speaks January 16, 2007 1 Commitment to propositions.......................... 1 2 A Fregean theory of reference.......................... 2 3 Three theories of

More information

Are There Reasons to Be Rational?

Are There Reasons to Be Rational? Are There Reasons to Be Rational? Olav Gjelsvik, University of Oslo The thesis. Among people writing about rationality, few people are more rational than Wlodek Rabinowicz. But are there reasons for being

More information

1 expressivism, what. Mark Schroeder University of Southern California August 2, 2010

1 expressivism, what. Mark Schroeder University of Southern California August 2, 2010 Mark Schroeder University of Southern California August 2, 2010 hard cases for combining expressivism and deflationist truth: conditionals and epistemic modals forthcoming in a volume on deflationism and

More information

(Some More) Vagueness

(Some More) Vagueness (Some More) Vagueness Otávio Bueno Department of Philosophy University of Miami Coral Gables, FL 33124 E-mail: otaviobueno@mac.com Three features of vague predicates: (a) borderline cases It is common

More information

CHAPTER TWO AN EXPLANATORY ROLE BORIS RÄHME FOR THE CONCEPT OF TRUTH. 1. Introduction

CHAPTER TWO AN EXPLANATORY ROLE BORIS RÄHME FOR THE CONCEPT OF TRUTH. 1. Introduction CHAPTER TWO AN EXPLANATORY ROLE FOR THE CONCEPT OF TRUTH BORIS RÄHME 1. Introduction Deflationism about truth (henceforth, deflationism) comes in a variety of versions 1 Variety notwithstanding, there

More information

British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 62 (2011), doi: /bjps/axr026

British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 62 (2011), doi: /bjps/axr026 British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 62 (2011), 899-907 doi:10.1093/bjps/axr026 URL: Please cite published version only. REVIEW

More information

VAGUENESS. Francis Jeffry Pelletier and István Berkeley Department of Philosophy University of Alberta Edmonton, Alberta, Canada

VAGUENESS. Francis Jeffry Pelletier and István Berkeley Department of Philosophy University of Alberta Edmonton, Alberta, Canada VAGUENESS Francis Jeffry Pelletier and István Berkeley Department of Philosophy University of Alberta Edmonton, Alberta, Canada Vagueness: an expression is vague if and only if it is possible that it give

More information

Coordination Problems

Coordination Problems Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Vol. LXXXI No. 2, September 2010 Ó 2010 Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, LLC Coordination Problems scott soames

More information

Stang (p. 34) deliberately treats non-actuality and nonexistence as equivalent.

Stang (p. 34) deliberately treats non-actuality and nonexistence as equivalent. Author meets Critics: Nick Stang s Kant s Modal Metaphysics Kris McDaniel 11-5-17 1.Introduction It s customary to begin with praise for the author s book. And there is much to praise! Nick Stang has written

More information

Rule-Following and the Ontology of the Mind Abstract The problem of rule-following

Rule-Following and the Ontology of the Mind Abstract The problem of rule-following Rule-Following and the Ontology of the Mind Michael Esfeld (published in Uwe Meixner and Peter Simons (eds.): Metaphysics in the Post-Metaphysical Age. Papers of the 22nd International Wittgenstein Symposium.

More information

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism? Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism? Author: Terence Rajivan Edward, University of Manchester. Abstract. In the sixth chapter of The View from Nowhere, Thomas Nagel attempts to identify a form of idealism.

More information

Idealism and the Harmony of Thought and Reality

Idealism and the Harmony of Thought and Reality Idealism and the Harmony of Thought and Reality Thomas Hofweber University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill hofweber@unc.edu Draft of September 26, 2017 for The Fourteenth Annual NYU Conference on Issues

More information

TRUTH-MAKERS AND CONVENTION T

TRUTH-MAKERS AND CONVENTION T TRUTH-MAKERS AND CONVENTION T Jan Woleński Abstract. This papers discuss the place, if any, of Convention T (the condition of material adequacy of the proper definition of truth formulated by Tarski) in

More information

Cognitive Significance, Attitude Ascriptions, and Ways of Believing Propositions. David Braun. University of Rochester

Cognitive Significance, Attitude Ascriptions, and Ways of Believing Propositions. David Braun. University of Rochester Cognitive Significance, Attitude Ascriptions, and Ways of Believing Propositions by David Braun University of Rochester Presented at the Pacific APA in San Francisco on March 31, 2001 1. Naive Russellianism

More information

TOWARDS A PHILOSOPHICAL UNDERSTANDING OF THE LOGICS OF FORMAL INCONSISTENCY

TOWARDS A PHILOSOPHICAL UNDERSTANDING OF THE LOGICS OF FORMAL INCONSISTENCY CDD: 160 http://dx.doi.org/10.1590/0100-6045.2015.v38n2.wcear TOWARDS A PHILOSOPHICAL UNDERSTANDING OF THE LOGICS OF FORMAL INCONSISTENCY WALTER CARNIELLI 1, ABÍLIO RODRIGUES 2 1 CLE and Department of

More information

An Introduction to. Formal Logic. Second edition. Peter Smith, February 27, 2019

An Introduction to. Formal Logic. Second edition. Peter Smith, February 27, 2019 An Introduction to Formal Logic Second edition Peter Smith February 27, 2019 Peter Smith 2018. Not for re-posting or re-circulation. Comments and corrections please to ps218 at cam dot ac dot uk 1 What

More information

How to Mistake a Trivial Fact About Probability For a. Substantive Fact About Justified Belief

How to Mistake a Trivial Fact About Probability For a. Substantive Fact About Justified Belief How to Mistake a Trivial Fact About Probability For a Substantive Fact About Justified Belief Jonathan Sutton It is sometimes thought that the lottery paradox and the paradox of the preface demand a uniform

More information

Moral requirements are still not rational requirements

Moral requirements are still not rational requirements ANALYSIS 59.3 JULY 1999 Moral requirements are still not rational requirements Paul Noordhof According to Michael Smith, the Rationalist makes the following conceptual claim. If it is right for agents

More information

Is the law of excluded middle a law of logic?

Is the law of excluded middle a law of logic? Is the law of excluded middle a law of logic? Introduction I will conclude that the intuitionist s attempt to rule out the law of excluded middle as a law of logic fails. They do so by appealing to harmony

More information

HORWICH S MINIMALIST CONCEPTION OF TRUTH: Some Logical Difficulties

HORWICH S MINIMALIST CONCEPTION OF TRUTH: Some Logical Difficulties Logic and Logical Philosophy Volume 9 (2001), 161 181 Sten Lindström HORWICH S MINIMALIST CONCEPTION OF TRUTH: Some Logical Difficulties Aristotle s words in the Metaphysics: to say of what is that it

More information

Supervaluationism and Fara s argument concerning higher-order vagueness

Supervaluationism and Fara s argument concerning higher-order vagueness Supervaluationism and Fara s argument concerning higher-order vagueness Pablo Cobreros pcobreros@unav.es January 26, 2011 There is an intuitive appeal to truth-value gaps in the case of vagueness. The

More information

SAVING RELATIVISM FROM ITS SAVIOUR

SAVING RELATIVISM FROM ITS SAVIOUR CRÍTICA, Revista Hispanoamericana de Filosofía Vol. XXXI, No. 91 (abril 1999): 91 103 SAVING RELATIVISM FROM ITS SAVIOUR MAX KÖLBEL Doctoral Programme in Cognitive Science Universität Hamburg In his paper

More information

International Phenomenological Society

International Phenomenological Society International Phenomenological Society The Semantic Conception of Truth: and the Foundations of Semantics Author(s): Alfred Tarski Source: Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, Vol. 4, No. 3 (Mar.,

More information

Idealism and the Harmony of Thought and Reality

Idealism and the Harmony of Thought and Reality Idealism and the Harmony of Thought and Reality Thomas Hofweber University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill hofweber@unc.edu Final Version Forthcoming in Mind Abstract Although idealism was widely defended

More information

Lecture 3. I argued in the previous lecture for a relationist solution to Frege's puzzle, one which

Lecture 3. I argued in the previous lecture for a relationist solution to Frege's puzzle, one which 1 Lecture 3 I argued in the previous lecture for a relationist solution to Frege's puzzle, one which posits a semantic difference between the pairs of names 'Cicero', 'Cicero' and 'Cicero', 'Tully' even

More information

the aim is to specify the structure of the world in the form of certain basic truths from which all truths can be derived. (xviii)

the aim is to specify the structure of the world in the form of certain basic truths from which all truths can be derived. (xviii) PHIL 5983: Naturalness and Fundamentality Seminar Prof. Funkhouser Spring 2017 Week 8: Chalmers, Constructing the World Notes (Introduction, Chapters 1-2) Introduction * We are introduced to the ideas

More information

God of the gaps: a neglected reply to God s stone problem

God of the gaps: a neglected reply to God s stone problem God of the gaps: a neglected reply to God s stone problem Jc Beall & A. J. Cotnoir January 1, 2017 Traditional monotheism has long faced logical puzzles (omniscience, omnipotence, and more) [10, 11, 13,

More information

Ramsey s belief > action > truth theory.

Ramsey s belief > action > truth theory. Ramsey s belief > action > truth theory. Monika Gruber University of Vienna 11.06.2016 Monika Gruber (University of Vienna) Ramsey s belief > action > truth theory. 11.06.2016 1 / 30 1 Truth and Probability

More information

Privilege in the Construction Industry. Shamik Dasgupta Draft of February 2018

Privilege in the Construction Industry. Shamik Dasgupta Draft of February 2018 Privilege in the Construction Industry Shamik Dasgupta Draft of February 2018 The idea that the world is structured that some things are built out of others has been at the forefront of recent metaphysics.

More information

On Priest on nonmonotonic and inductive logic

On Priest on nonmonotonic and inductive logic On Priest on nonmonotonic and inductive logic Greg Restall School of Historical and Philosophical Studies The University of Melbourne Parkville, 3010, Australia restall@unimelb.edu.au http://consequently.org/

More information

WHY IS GOD GOOD? EUTYPHRO, TIMAEUS AND THE DIVINE COMMAND THEORY

WHY IS GOD GOOD? EUTYPHRO, TIMAEUS AND THE DIVINE COMMAND THEORY Miłosz Pawłowski WHY IS GOD GOOD? EUTYPHRO, TIMAEUS AND THE DIVINE COMMAND THEORY In Eutyphro Plato presents a dilemma 1. Is it that acts are good because God wants them to be performed 2? Or are they

More information

Wright on response-dependence and self-knowledge

Wright on response-dependence and self-knowledge Wright on response-dependence and self-knowledge March 23, 2004 1 Response-dependent and response-independent concepts........... 1 1.1 The intuitive distinction......................... 1 1.2 Basic equations

More information

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View Chapter 98 Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View Lars Leeten Universität Hildesheim Practical thinking is a tricky business. Its aim will never be fulfilled unless influence on practical

More information

Minimalism and Truth-Value Gaps*

Minimalism and Truth-Value Gaps* Minimalism and Truth-Value Gaps* RICHARD HOLTON, RSSS 1. INTRODUCTION Writing in 1927, Russell said: There is a tendency to use truth with a big T in the grand sense, as something noble and splendid and

More information

LOGICAL PLURALISM IS COMPATIBLE WITH MONISM ABOUT METAPHYSICAL MODALITY

LOGICAL PLURALISM IS COMPATIBLE WITH MONISM ABOUT METAPHYSICAL MODALITY LOGICAL PLURALISM IS COMPATIBLE WITH MONISM ABOUT METAPHYSICAL MODALITY Nicola Ciprotti and Luca Moretti Beall and Restall [2000], [2001] and [2006] advocate a comprehensive pluralist approach to logic,

More information

Logic and Pragmatics: linear logic for inferential practice

Logic and Pragmatics: linear logic for inferential practice Logic and Pragmatics: linear logic for inferential practice Daniele Porello danieleporello@gmail.com Institute for Logic, Language & Computation (ILLC) University of Amsterdam, Plantage Muidergracht 24

More information

Can Gödel s Incompleteness Theorem be a Ground for Dialetheism? *

Can Gödel s Incompleteness Theorem be a Ground for Dialetheism? * 논리연구 20-2(2017) pp. 241-271 Can Gödel s Incompleteness Theorem be a Ground for Dialetheism? * 1) Seungrak Choi Abstract Dialetheism is the view that there exists a true contradiction. This paper ventures

More information

A Problem for a Direct-Reference Theory of Belief Reports. Stephen Schiffer New York University

A Problem for a Direct-Reference Theory of Belief Reports. Stephen Schiffer New York University A Problem for a Direct-Reference Theory of Belief Reports Stephen Schiffer New York University The direct-reference theory of belief reports to which I allude is the one held by such theorists as Nathan

More information

Russell: On Denoting

Russell: On Denoting Russell: On Denoting DENOTING PHRASES Russell includes all kinds of quantified subject phrases ( a man, every man, some man etc.) but his main interest is in definite descriptions: the present King of

More information

THE MEANING OF OUGHT. Ralph Wedgwood. What does the word ought mean? Strictly speaking, this is an empirical question, about the

THE MEANING OF OUGHT. Ralph Wedgwood. What does the word ought mean? Strictly speaking, this is an empirical question, about the THE MEANING OF OUGHT Ralph Wedgwood What does the word ought mean? Strictly speaking, this is an empirical question, about the meaning of a word in English. Such empirical semantic questions should ideally

More information

CRUCIAL TOPICS IN THE DEBATE ABOUT THE EXISTENCE OF EXTERNAL REASONS

CRUCIAL TOPICS IN THE DEBATE ABOUT THE EXISTENCE OF EXTERNAL REASONS CRUCIAL TOPICS IN THE DEBATE ABOUT THE EXISTENCE OF EXTERNAL REASONS By MARANATHA JOY HAYES A THESIS PRESENTED TO THE GRADUATE SCHOOL OF THE UNIVERSITY OF FLORIDA IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS

More information