Logic & Proofs. Chapter 3 Content. Sentential Logic Semantics. Contents: Studying this chapter will enable you to:

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Logic & Proofs. Chapter 3 Content. Sentential Logic Semantics. Contents: Studying this chapter will enable you to:"

Transcription

1 Sentential Logic Semantics Contents: Truth-Value Assignments and Truth-Functions Truth-Value Assignments Truth-Functions Introduction to the TruthLab Truth-Definition Logical Notions Truth-Trees Studying this chapter will enable you to: 1. Explain what a truth-value assignment is. 2. Give the truth-conditions for the logical connectives. 3. Determine the truth-value of a formula relative to a given truth-value assignment. 4. Construct a truth-table for a given formula or argument. 5. Use truth-tables to analyze arguments and formulae. 6. Explain what tautological, contingent, and contradictory formulae are. 7. Find a counterexample to an invalid argument, using a truth-table or truth-tree. Chapter 3 Content

2 Truth-Value Assignments and Truth-Functions Truth-Value Assignments As we mentioned earlier, our primary interest in sentential logic has to do with the TRUTH-VALUES of formulae. We have learned how the basic expressions of sentential logic combine, in accordance with the syntactic rules, to form compound formulae. The syntactic rules allow us to determine, for any particular expression, whether or not that expression constitutes a well-formed formula. Similarly, the semantic rules for sentential logic will allow us to determine the truth-value of any formula, given that we know the truth-values of all the atomic formulae involved. Great, but what if we don't know the truth-values of all the atomic formulae? Well, we can still determine what the truth-value of the formula will be for any possible assignment of truth-values to atomic formulae. Such an assignment of truth-values to atomic formulae is, appropriately enough, a truth-value assignment. Before we get to the definition itself, there's just one thing we ought to mention explicitly: we make the assumption that there are just two truth-values, truth and falsity. Since we will refer to these two truthvalues quite a bit, we abbreviate them as follows: t for truth and f for falsity. That said, here is the definition: Definition Truth-Value Assignment A TRUTH-VALUE ASSIGNMENT specifies a unique truth-value (either t or f) for each atomic formula. So, how do we go about determining the truth-value of any formula of sentential logic, relative to a given truth-value assignment? Obviously, if our formula is atomic, all we need to do is to see what truth-value it has been assigned in order to determine what its truth-value is on that assignment. What about compound formulae? You may recall that we've mentioned that the logical connectives are all TRUTH-FUNCTIONAL. This means that the truth-value of a compound formula is a FUNCTION of the truth-values of its parts a function determined by the formula's main connective. In order to see how this works, let us proceed to take a look at the semantics of the connectives. Page 1 of 23

3 Truth-Functions We have informally discussed the truth-functions we take to correspond to the logical connectives. So far, we have relied on an intuitive understanding of the truth-functions these connectives represent, but it is time to make explicit the truth-functions at work. We will use TRUTH-TABLES to represent them. Recall our first example of a conjunction from the previous chapter: John ran and Mary laughed. Now, this sentence is considered to be true just in case it is both true that John ran, and true that Mary laughed. If John didn't run, the conjunction is false, and similarly if Mary didn't laugh. This intuitive and informal understanding of the TRUTH-CONDITIONS of conjunction, that a conjunction is true just in case both of its conjuncts are true, and false otherwise, is precisely what we want to capture. We can do this in a tabular form, by specifying the truth-value of a conjunction for each possible combination of truthvalues t (true) and f (false) that the two conjuncts can take on. Here's the truth-table for this particular conjunction: After looking only briefly at the above truth-table, it should be pretty clear what is going on, but it can not hurt to go through it explicitly. In our truth-table, we have three columns: one for the conjunction itself, plus one for each of the two atomic formulae appearing in the conjunction. As for rows, this truthtable has four (not including the header row, where we specify the atomic formulae and the compound formula), just enough to include every possible combination of the truthvalues t and f that the two atomic formulae can have. The entries in the conjunction's column specify the truth-value of the conjunction given that the conjuncts have the truthvalues indicated in the same row. Each of the rows in the truth-table thus represents a set of truth-value assignments the set of truth-value assignments where the atomic formulae listed in the truth-table are assigned the truth-values specified on that row. The first row of the truth-table thus represents all truth-value assignments where the atomic formulae J and M are both assigned the truth-value t. This includes the truth-value assignments where J, M, and, say, R are all assigned the truth-value t as well as the truth-value assignments where J and M are assigned t, but R is assigned f, and so on for every atomic formula not mentioned in the truth-table. Now, in the truth-table above, we listed some specific atomic formulae. The truth-table thus tells us what the truth-value of the conjunction of those two particular atomic formulae will be on any truth-value assignment. We would like, however, to have a way to represent the relationship between the truth-value of a conjunction and the truth-values Page 2 of 23

4 of its conjuncts in a general way, rather than just specific instances of the relationship. We can do this with a truth-table by using variables in place of specific formulae for the conjuncts, as follows: Definition Characteristic Truth-table for Conjunction This truth-table, since it doesn't mention any specific formulae, we call the CHARACTERISTIC TRUTH-TABLE for conjunction. Let us go on to take a look at the characteristic truth-tables for the other connectives. Later on, we will see how to construct a truth-table for any formula of sentential logic. Here is the truth-table for disjunction: Definition Characteristic Truth-table for Disjunction The truth-table specifies that a disjunction is true on any truth-value assignment where either one or both of the disjuncts is true, and false just in case both of the disjuncts are false. Recall our example disjunction from the last chapter: John ran or Mary laughed. The truth-table tells us that this sentence will be false only if it is both false that John ran, and false that Mary laughed. If either of the two disjuncts is true, including the case where both disjuncts are true (as we decided that the symbol should reflect the inclusive understanding of disjunction), then the sentence as a whole is true as well. This brings us to another kind of argumentative step we can take, involving the elimination of disjunction. It's a little more complicated than the ones we have seen so far. The idea goes like this: if we know that (P Q), and we know that R follows from P, and that R also follows from Q, then R can be inferred from (P Q), since at least one of P or Q must be true, and either way, R must be true. The step looks like this: Page 3 of 23

5 (P1) (P Q) (P2) Assuming P, R (P3) Assuming Q, R (C) R We'll return to the notion of assumptions in the next chapter. For now, it is enough to grasp the intuitive notion underlying this argumentative step, -elimination. Moving on to the last of our binary connectives, here is the truth-table for the conditional: Definition Characteristic Truth-table for the Conditional As you can see, a conditional is false just in case its antecedent is true, and its consequent false. If either the antecedent is false or the consequent true, then the conditional as a whole is true. The notion of assumption that we've just seen plays a role in argumentation allowing the introduction of a conditional: since a conditional is false only if its antecedent is true and its consequent is false, we may infer a conditional if we know that the consequent follows from the (assumption of) the antecedent. Here is -introduction: (P1) Assuming P, Q (C) (P Q) Our final connective is negation. Since negation is a unary connective, we only have one component formula to worry about in the truth-table. The characteristic truth-table for negation thus has only two rows, since the single formula can only be either true or false. Here is the truth-table itself: Definition Characteristic Truth-table for Negation Now that we have seen the truth-tables for each of the connectives, we should turn our attention to some mathematical, or rather metamathematical matters before we get any further. Page 4 of 23

6 See the online version for interactive material here! Page 5 of 23

7 Introduction to the TruthLab The TRUTHLAB is the application you will use to complete a variety of semantic exercises in this course. The TruthLab runs directly in your web browser, so it is important that the browser you are using meets the system requirements stated on the Test and Configure page (the link to this page can be found at the top of the course syllabus). Tip: If you haven't already verified that your browser meets the requirements stated on the Test and Configure page, and passes the tests provided there, please take a moment to do that now! If your browser is correctly configured, launching and running the TruthLab is as simple as clicking a link every problem that can be worked in the TruthLab will be followed by a link that says Click here to open this problem in the TruthLab, like the following: Chase truth up the parse tree of the formula ((L & A) & B) to determine its truthvalue when L is true, A is true, and B is true. See the online version to try this problem in the TruthLab! Clicking on such a link will launch the TruthLab. Once you click the link, a new browser window or frame will appear as the TruthLab applet begins downloading: After a moment or two required for Java to start up, if necessary, and the TruthLab applet to finish loading the TruthLab itself will open in a new Java applet window (not a regular browser window). Here is what the TruthLab looks like, running in Safari on a Mac (the menu bar and other details may look slightly different if you are using a different browser or operating system): Page 6 of 23

8 Note: The TruthLab is a moderately sized Java applet, so it may take a little while to download, particularly the first time. It should normally not take more than approximately 5 to 30 seconds to load when using a reliable, high-speed internet connection. If you are using dial-up or have an otherwise slower or unreliable connection, the TruthLab may take significantly longer to load. It may also be sluggish in responding to clicks/ commands in such circumstances, as it communicates frequently with the OLI servers. For this reason, we strongly recommend that working in the TruthLab be avoided when using an unreliable or non-broadband internet connection if at all possible. Please take a moment now to verify that you are able to launch the TruthLab by clicking the link following the problem above. Don't worry about finishing the problem but do take a moment to explore the interface! Page 7 of 23

9 Note: If you have any difficulty launching the TruthLab, get help right away! If you are in an in-class session, tell your instructor. If you are working outside of a class meeting, you can contact OLI technical help by clicking on the help link on any course page. If your instructor has provided instructions on what you are expected to do in the event of technical issues, be sure to follow those instructions. In addition to using the TruthLab, however, we do recommend that you take the time to do a few problems (e.g., those involving truth-table and truth-tree construction) the old fashioned way with pencil and paper as well. Take a few moments to explore the Lab, then once you are ready, on to the truth-definition! Page 8 of 23

10 Truth-Definition We promised earlier on that parse trees were going to come in handy when it comes to semantics. Indeed, they do. They offer a handy way to exploit the truth-functional character of the logical connectives in order to determine the truth-value of any formula on a particular assignment. To put it succinctly, we can "chase truth" up the parse tree of a given formula, matching rows of the truth-tables to applications of syntactic rules in the tree. Let us look at an example: Movie Chasing Truth Text/printable version available as a separate PDF! That is really all there is to it: just replace the atomic formulae in the parse tree with the truth-values assigned to each on the given assignment. For each application of a syntactic rule in the tree (from the bottom up), find the corresponding row in the connective's truth-table, and replace the subformula with the resulting truth-value. Once you get to the top, you have the truth-value for the formula as a whole. Page 9 of 23 See the online version for interactive material here! Of course, if you are interested in more than just a single truth-value assignment, say if you wanted to determine whether a formula is true on every truth-value assignment, things start getting a bit messy: for our example ((P & Q) R), you need to draw eight separate parse trees one for each possible truth-value assignment to the three atomic formulae (we will explain how we got this number in just a bit) in order to classify the formula. Describing this is painful enough, actually doing it would be horrible. Fortunately, we have already seen a means for avoiding such a state of affairs the truth-tables we used to present the truth-conditions for the connectives. We can also use truth-tables to provide a neat and compact presentation of the truth-values of a given formula on any truth-value assignment. In order to construct a truth-table for an arbitrary formula of sentential logic, the first thing you need to do is to count the number of different sentential letters that occur as subformulae of the given formula. This will tell you how many rows you need in your truth-table. As we have seen, if there is only a single atomic formula, you will need two rows, and with two atomic formulae, you will need four rows. See if you can determine how many rows are needed for larger numbers of atomic formulae, then read on. Now that you have thought about it, you can see that every additional atomic formula involved is going to double the number of rows you'll need in your truth-table. Thus, for a formula containing three atomic formulae, you need a truth-table with eight rows, for four you need sixteen rows, five atomic formulae would require thirty two rows, and so on. In general, you need 2 n rows in a truth-table for a formula containing n different atomic formulae as subformulae.

11 There are many different ways to go about constructing a truth-table. We will demonstrate one method in a moment, but it doesn't really matter how you go about constructing it, so long as you end up with the right thing. What you end up with for a given formula should include the following: For each subformula in the parse tree (including the formula itself), you should have a corresponding column in your truth-table; for each possible truth-value assignment to the atomic subformulae, you should have a corresponding row in your truth-table, along with a header row where the subformulae are specified. The columns are usually ordered by traversing the parse tree from bottom to top, and from left to right, so you start out at the left of the table with atomic formulae, and work your way to the formula as a whole in the rightmost column. At this point, we should probably look at an example, because it really is much more straightforward than it may sound: Movie Truth-tables I Text/printable version available as a separate PDF! As this example demonstrates, constructing a truth-table is pretty simple. Once complete, it shows us the truth-value of our formula ((P & Q) R) on every possible truth-value assignment. If we want to find its truth-value on a particular assignment, we just have to find the row where the truth-values assigned to P, Q, and R match the assignment in question, and the above truth-table will tell us whether our formula is true or false on that assignment. Let us take a look at one more example, just to make sure we have the hang of it all. This time, we construct the truth-table for the formula ( P Q): Movie Truth-tables II Text/printable version available as a separate PDF! We hope to have made it evident that all we need to determine the truth-value of any formula on a given truth-value assignment is the truth-value assignment itself, thanks to the truth-functional nature of the connectives. See the online version for interactive material here! No matter how complicated a formula, we can always determine its parse tree and "chase truth up the tree of grammar". This insight can be given a precise mathematical formulation (and proof, for that matter): given a truth-value assignment σ for atomic formulae, there is a (unique) truth-value assignment σ * for all formulae, extending σ and assigning the correct truth-values to Page 10 of 23

12 complex formulae. We can formulate this in terms of a definition of truth and falsity on σ *. Here is the definition: Definition Truth and Falsity Relative to a Truth-Value Assignment 1. If φ is an atomic formula (sentential letter) of sentential logic, then φ is true on σ * just in case σ assigns the value t to φ, and false otherwise. 2. If φ is a formula of the form ψ, then φ is true on σ * just in case ψ is false on σ *, and false otherwise. 3. If φ is a formula of the form (ψ & ρ), then φ is true on σ * just in case both ψ and ρ are true on σ *, and false otherwise. 4. If φ is a formula of the form (ψ ρ), then φ is true on σ * just in case either ψ is true on σ * or ρ is true on σ *, and false otherwise. 5. If φ is a formula of the form (ψ ρ), then φ is true on σ * just in case either ψ is false on σ * or ρ is true on σ *, and false otherwise. If this definition seems simple, good! All it does is mathematically characterize the truthconditions we have presented informally by means of the characteristic truth-tables of the connectives. It gives us everything we need to determine the truth-value of any formula on any truth-value assignment, and that was captured quite efficiently by the truth-tables. Now that we have seen how we can use truth-tables to determine the truth-values of formulae on particular assignments, let us move on and look at some central logical notions from a semantic perspective. Page 11 of 23

13 Logical Notions We are going to put the definition of truth to use in order to characterize some central logical notions. For example, a formula is to be considered LOGICALLY TRUE if and only if it is true "independent of matters of fact", where the "facts" are given by a truth-value assignment. This gives us the following definition: Definition Tautology A formula is called LOGICALLY TRUE or a TAUTOLOGY just in case it is true on every truth-value assignment. If, on the other hand, a formula is always false, it is called you guessed it, CONTRADICTORY: Definition Contradictory Formula A formula is called a CONTRADICTORY just in case it is false on every truthvalue assignment. Finally, we have everything in between: Definition Contingent Formula A formula is called a CONTINGENT just in case it is true on some truth-value assignments, and false on others. We have already seen quite a few contingent formulae, including all the atomic formulae, so we won't worry about any examples there. As an example of a tautology, on the other hand, consider the formula (P P). This formula has only one atomic subformula, P, so it's pretty easy to tell that it will be true whether P is assigned t on a given assignment (because that will make the left-hand disjunct true) or f (since that will make the righthand disjunct true). You have probably realized that the negation of any tautology is going to be false on every truth-value assignment, and hence a contradictory. Similarly, the negation of a contradictory is a tautology. The negation of a contingent, however, will also be contingent. We will see in just a bit how useful these classifications for formulae can be when we consider inferences and arguments from a semantic perspective. As you will recall from the introduction, we consider an argument to be a good argument just in case its premises are all true, and those premises furthermore support the conclusion. The kind of support we are most interested in is, of course, validity, which we can now characterize in terms of truth-value assignments: Page 12 of 23

14 Definition Validity An argument is VALID just in case any truth-value assignment that makes all the premises true also makes the conclusion true. With the concept of validity defined, we can now characterize an important relationship in terms of validity: Definition Logical Consequence If an argument with premises φ 1,...,φ n and conclusion ψ is valid, then ψ is a LOGICAL CONSEQUENCE of φ 1,...,φ n. With a precise characterization of validity, we can also provide a precise characterization of invalidity: Definition Invalidity An argument is INVALID just in case it is not valid, i.e., if there is some truthvalue assignment that makes the premises true, but the conclusion false. Definition Counterexample A truth-value assignment that makes the premises of an argument true and its conclusion false is called a COUNTEREXAMPLE to the argument. Now that we know how to use truth-tables to determine the truth-value of a formula on any truth-value assignment, we can apply this technique to the premises and conclusion of an argument, symbolized as formulae of sentential logic, in order to determine whether or not an argument is valid. We just need to be careful to ensure that we take into consideration all the right truth-value assignments. Consider the following conversation: It's raining outside. If it's raining outside, then Kant won't stop at the grocery store to buy ice cream. Page 13 of 23 If Kant doesn't stop at the grocery store to buy ice cream, then we will have to be content with cookies for dessert.

15 Alas, we will thus have to be content with cookies for dessert. Interpreting this as an argument, we can symbolize it as follows: R (R K) ( K S) S We can make a truth-table for all the premises plus the conclusion by first noting the atomic formulae that occur as subformulae of any premise or of the conclusion, then setting up the truth-table for all such atomic formulae. We include a column for each of the premises and also the conclusion. Here's what the resulting table looks like: In order to determine whether the argument is valid or not, we now look for any rows in this truth-table where all the premises are true. In this case, there is only one such row the third one since the conclusion is true on this row, the argument is valid. See the online version for interactive material here! Despite the fact that we have just introduced it as such, we don't actually need to include the concept of validity as an independent notion: we can instead define validity in terms of tautologies. How? Well, since being tautologous is a property of formulae, and validity is a property of arguments, we need a way to "transform" an argument into a formula a formula that will be a tautology if the argument is valid, and not if it is invalid. If you think about this for a minute, the following definition should come as no surprise: Definition Conditional Analogue The CONDITIONAL ANALOGUE of an argument with premises φ 1,...,φ n and conclusion χ is the formula ((φ 1 & (... & φ n )) χ). Given this definition, we can now restate our above claim precisely: we do so by formulating it as a metamathematical proposition. Page 14 of 23

16 Proposition An argument with premises φ 1,...,φ n and conclusion χ is valid if and only if its conditional analogue ((φ 1 & (... & φ n )) χ) is a tautology. Proof: Before presenting the proof let us make a few remarks. First of all, note that this proposition is metamathematical, which means simply that it is a claim about the formal system of sentential logic, as contrasted with a claim expressed in the language of sentential logic. This reflective concern with the properties of logics and logical systems is deeply characteristic of modern work in logic. Secondly, the proof of a statement such as this involving the phrase if and only if (called BICONDITIONALS, and we will return to discuss these in more detail in a later chapter) divides into two parts: the if part, and the only if part. Here we will establish that if an argument is valid, its conditional analogue is a tautology. We leave the other part of the proof as an exercise for the reader. On to the proof: Assume that the argument with premises φ 1,...,φ n and conclusion χ is valid. Assume also, in order to obtain a contradiction, that its conditional analogue ((φ 1 & (... & φ n )) χ) is not a tautology. That means there is a truth-value assignment σ on which the conditional analogue is false. Using the appropriate clauses of the truth-definition, then premise φ i, for each i from 1 through n, is true on σ, and conclusion χ is false on σ. Thus σ is a counterexample to the argument, contradicting the assumption that the argument is valid. See the online version for interactive material here! Since we have proved our claim, we could simply define an argument to be valid just in case its conditional analogue is a tautology: these two notions are equivalent, so it doesn't really make a difference whether or not we include the concept of validity (for an argument) as a basic notion we can always define it in terms of tautologies instead. Truth-tables are all we need to determine the truth-value of a formula on any truthvalue assignment, and they are all we need to find a truth-value assignment that gives a particular formula a given truth-value, and in particular, all we need in order to find a counterexample to an argument. It might be nice, however, to have a way of working backwards, if you will, from the desired truth-value for the formula to a truthvalue assignment on which the formula has that desired truth-value and hence a more efficient and direct technique for finding counterexamples. Let's head on to the next section and look at a technique that will allow us to do just these things. Page 15 of 23

17 Truth-Trees We can approach the problem of finding a truth-value assignment that assigns a particular truth-value to a given formula (and hence counterexamples) in much the same fashion as we approach the problem of determining whether or not a given expression is a well-formed formula using trees. The big difference is that while we make use of the syntactic rules when constructing parse trees, we will use the definition of truth with respect to a truth-value assignment in order to construct TRUTH-TREES. There is one basic and very useful fact about the definition of truth: a formula is true just in case its negation is false, and vice versa. We can exploit this fact to ensure that we only need to worry about constructing trees for formulae that we want to be true (hence the term truth-tree). If we want to find a truth-value assignment that makes some formula false, all we need to do is to find a truth-value assignment that makes its negation true. If our goal is to find a counterexample to a given argument, then, all we need to do is to find a truth-value assignment that makes the premises and the negated conclusion of the argument true. Now, just as we break formulae down into their immediate subformulae in parse trees, we are going to break the truth of formulae down into the truth of their immediate and possibly negated subformulae in truth-trees. Branches serve a very distinctive purpose in truth-trees, though: each branch corresponds to a set of truth-value assignments. Which truth-value assignments? Those that make all the formulae on that branch true. We will make this more precise by introducing truth-tree rules for each connective in turn. Starting with conjunction, we know that a conjunction (φ & ψ) is true just in case both φ and ψ are true. We thus know that any truth-value assignment that makes (φ & ψ) true must make both of φ and ψ true as well. We have broken down the truth-conditions for the original formula into truth-conditions for two smaller pieces. Just like the subformulae in a parse tree, these two smaller pieces can be added to our truth-tree. Unlike a parse tree, however, they do not end up on different branches. Since the truth of each subformula is guaranteed by the truth of the formula as a whole, both subformulae go on the same branch. Graphically, we can just write the two subformulae immediately below the original formula. It can also be very helpful to indicate in some fashion that you have already dealt with the original formula, such as putting a check mark next to it, or underlining it, or something similar. This way, you can keep track of which formulae in the tree have already been broken down, and which have not. (This becomes more important when analyzing arguments using truth-trees, but it is a good idea to get in the habit of checking them off right from the beginning.) Next, we know that a disjunction is true just in case either one of its disjuncts is true. Thus, for a disjunction (φ ψ), we have two sets of truth-value assignments to consider: those where φ is true, and those where ψ is true. Since the truth of the disjunction can only guarantee the truth of one of these disjuncts, this tells us that the tree for the disjunction will branch, unlike the one for conjunction. The truth-tree for disjunction will thus look much like the parse tree for the same formula, the only difference being that we will add in a check mark next to the formula we have just broken down. Page 16 of 23

18 On to consider our next binary connective, the conditional. We know that a conditional is true just in case either its antecedent is false or its consequent is true. As we mentioned earlier, however, the fact that a formula is true just in case its negation is false and vice versa allows us to reinterpret these truth-conditions as follows: a conditional (φ ψ) is true just in case either the negation of its antecedent (i.e, φ) is true or its consequent (i.e, ψ) is true. If we compare this to the truth-conditions for disjunction, it's easy to determine that the truth-tree for a conditional must branch, and which formulae must be at the ends of those branches. Let us take a look at our truth-tree rules so far: Definition Truth-Tree Construction Rules See the online version for interactive material here! How about our final connective, negation? We pointed out and exploited the fact that a formula is true just in case its negation is false and vice versa, but how are we going to use this fact to deal with negation in truth-trees? Consider for a moment the fact that each branch of a truth-tree corresponds to a set of truth-value assignments, namely, the set of truth-value assignments that make all the formulae appearing on that branch true. This being the case, we thus know that if an atomic formula appears on a particular branch, then that formula must be true on each of the corresponding truth-value assignments, and hence that each such assignment assigns the value t to that atomic formula. Now consider again the fact that a formula is false just in case its negation is true if the negation of an atomic formula appears on the branch, then we know that the truth-value assignments in question must make this negation true, and hence must assign the value f to the atomic formula. Great, so how does this help us figure out what to do with negation in truth-trees? Well, we know that as soon as we have broken down a formula to the point where all we have left is the negation of an atomic formula, we are done. This tells us everything we need to know about the truth-value assignments in question, i.e., that they must assign the value f to that atomic formula. All that is left, then, is to worry about the negations of formulae other than atomic ones. In that light, there are going to be exactly four rules we need in order to deal with negation in the context of truth-trees: One for negated conjunctions; one for negated disjunctions; one for negated conditionals; finally, one for negated negations. Why not see if you can extrapolate the rules from the ones we have presented above and the truth-conditions of the connectives: See the online version for interactive material here! Page 17 of 23

19 Here are all the truth-tree rules we need: Definition Truth-Tree Construction Rules There is just one thing to note about these rules: they must be used to extend every branch of the tree on which the formula in question is located. In other words, if you are applying a rule to a formula that already has more than one branch growing out of it, you must extend each such branch before you can check off the formula. Just to make sure this is absolutely clear, here is an example: There are a few other things we ought to mention regarding truth-trees. First, though it might be intuitive, we should spell out how to read a truth-value assignment from a truth-tree. Each branch of the tree corresponds to a set of truth-value assignments, namely, the truth-value assignments that make all the formulae appearing on the branch true. Because we've applied the truth-tree rules to them, we don't need to worry explicitly about any formulae that have been checked off which means that the only formulae we need to worry about once we are done constructing the tree is atomic formulae and the negations of atomic formulae. Given that, the first thing to do in determining the truth-value assignment specified by the branch is to go along the branch, and make a note of every such atomic formula and negation of an atomic formula on that branch. The truth-value assignments that correspond to the branch are all those that assign t to the atomic formulae appearing on the branch and f to atomic formulae whose negations appear on the branch. Page 18 of 23

20 Now would be a good time for an example. Consider the formula (P & (Q P)). We will try to find a truth-value assignment that makes this formula false, so to do that we construct the truth-tree for the formula's negation. Here is the completed tree: The only atomic formula or negation of an atomic formula appearing on the left-hand branch is P, which tells us that assigning f to P is enough to make (P & (Q P)) false. We can see that this is correct by looking at the truth-table for the formula all the rows where P is false make the formula false: Similarly, the atomic formulae and negations thereof on the right-hand branch are P and Q, which tells us that if we assign t to P and f to Q, this will also make the formula's negation true, and hence the formula itself false. Here's the truth-table again to highlight this: It is worth pointing out that while we went to the trouble of completing the tree for (P & (Q P)), we really didn't have to. If you consider the tree after just one step, i.e., the application of the rule for negated conjunctions to the formula as a whole, note that the left-hand branch of the tree is already complete every formula on the branch is either atomic, the negation of an atomic formula, or checked off. We could have stopped at that point and read our truth-value assignment from this branch, not even worrying about completing the right-hand branch of the tree! There's one hitch to reading off assignments: what happens if both some formula and its negation appear on the same branch of a truth-tree? Since no truth-value assignment can make any formula both true and false, and so cannot make both a formula and its negation true, then we obviously cannot associate a truth-value assignment with such a branch. Thus, if a formula and its negation ever do appear in the same branch, we CLOSE OFF that branch, marking it with an asterisk to indicate that the branch does not represent any possible truth-value assignments. Such a branch is, unsurprisingly, referred to as Page 19 of 23

21 CLOSED. A branch that is not closed is, equally unsurprisingly, referred to as OPEN. A tree is COMPLETED once every formula on any open branch is either an atomic formula, the negation of an atomic formula, or has been analyzed (i.e., broken down and checked off). Note that this means in particular that if all of the branches of a tree are closed, then that tree is completed. So, what does all this about closed and open branches and completed trees have to do with using truth-trees to analyze the logical character of formulae and arguments? It is, on the surface, rather simple: if a formula has a truth-tree that contains only closed branches, then that formula isn't true on any truth-value assignments, and hence is contradictory. We already know that if a formula is a tautology, its negation will be contradictory. Consequently, if a formula is a tautology, then its negation will have a closed truth-tree. As an example, consider the truth-tree for the negation of the tautology (P P): The only branch in the tree is closed, which means there are no truth-value assignments that make (P P) true, and thus none that make (P P) false. (It's also worth noting that the formula and its negation that closed the branch in the first place are P and P, illustrating an important point: if any formula and its negation appear on a branch, the branch can be closed immediately. It need not be an atomic formula and its negation you can save yourself a lot of work if you remember to check for any formula-and-its-negation pairs after each rule application and close all branches as soon as possible.) As for arguments, just remember the connection between an argument and the logical character of its conditional analogue to see how to apply truth-trees to the analysis of arguments. These considerations are true, but don't establish the connection between the syntactic considerations and the semantic interpretation rigorously enough. We will come back to this quite important issue at the end of this section. See the online version for interactive material here! It can't hurt to summarize everything we discussed regarding truth-trees so far into a procedure for generating a completed truth-tree. Here's that procedure: Definition Procedure for Generating Truth-Trees 1. Start by writing down the formula for which you want to generate a truth-tree. 2. Based on the syntactic form of the expression, apply the appropriate truth-tree rule, putting a check mark next to the formula to indicate that it has been analyzed. Page 20 of 23

22 3. For each open branch, determine whether the branch contains both any formula φ and its negation φ. If any branch does contain a formula and its negation, mark the branch closed. If all branches in the tree are closed, you are done. Otherwise, continue to the next step. 4. If the only formulae on open branches that do not have check marks next to them are atomic formulae or negations of atomic formulae, you are done. Otherwise, continue to the next step. 5. Choose an unchecked formula on an open branch in the truth-tree that is not atomic and not the negation of an atomic formula, and apply this procedure to that formula, starting with step 2. Let us use this procedure to construct a truth-tree for the formula ( (A & B) & ( (A B) (A & B))): Movie Truth-Trees Text/printable version available as a separate PDF! Our final example: consider the formula ((P Q) (P & Q)) and decide whether there are any truth-value assignments that make this formula false by constructing the truth-tree for its negation. Here is the completed tree: Page 21 of 23 See the online version for interactive material here! Since the formula ((P Q) (P & Q)) is a conditional, then it could be taken to be the conditional analogue of the following argument: (P Q) (P & Q) As such, the truth-tree for the formula demonstrates that the argument is not valid: each open branch provides a counterexample. The first open branch contains Q and P, while the second contains P and Q. That tells us that two truth-value assignments are counterexamples: the assignment where Q is assigned t and P is assigned f is the first,

23 and the assignment where P is assigned t and Q is assigned f is the other, as we can clearly see in the truth-table: When it comes to arguments, however, just as we can use either the individual premises and conclusion in a truth-table, rather than the conditional analogue, we can use the individual premises and conclusion in a truth-tree in order to test for validity. The only difference is that in the truth-tree, we list the premises and the negation of the conclusion; in essence, we consider the negation of the conditional analogue, but skip the first step in analyzing the negation; instead we try to obtain a counterexample to the argument directly. Let us consider the following argument as an example: (A B) (B C) (A C) The completed tree for this argument is shown below. Note that the tree is closed, which demonstrates that the conditional analogue is in fact a tautology, and the argument is valid: If you like, complete the truth-table yourself to verify what the closed tree says: there are no truth-value assignments that make the premises true and the conclusion false. Page 22 of 23 See the online version for interactive material here! Before heading on to the exercises, let us indulge in a little bit of metamathematical reflection. We have specified a thoroughly syntactic, indeed quite mechanical procedure and interpreted the completed truth-tree obtained via this procedure in a semantic way, supporting or refuting the claim that a particular formula is a tautology of that a given argument is valid. Why are we justified in interpreting the completed tree in this way, and can we be sure that the procedure always yields a completed tree in finitely many steps?

24 We will come back to these issues, and address them thoroughly in a later chapter devoted to metamathematical issues. For the time being, however, do not forget the questions, or their significance! Page 23 of 23

Chapter 8 - Sentential Truth Tables and Argument Forms

Chapter 8 - Sentential Truth Tables and Argument Forms Logic: A Brief Introduction Ronald L. Hall Stetson University Chapter 8 - Sentential ruth ables and Argument orms 8.1 Introduction he truth-value of a given truth-functional compound proposition depends

More information

What are Truth-Tables and What Are They For?

What are Truth-Tables and What Are They For? PY114: Work Obscenely Hard Week 9 (Meeting 7) 30 November, 2010 What are Truth-Tables and What Are They For? 0. Business Matters: The last marked homework of term will be due on Monday, 6 December, at

More information

Artificial Intelligence: Valid Arguments and Proof Systems. Prof. Deepak Khemani. Department of Computer Science and Engineering

Artificial Intelligence: Valid Arguments and Proof Systems. Prof. Deepak Khemani. Department of Computer Science and Engineering Artificial Intelligence: Valid Arguments and Proof Systems Prof. Deepak Khemani Department of Computer Science and Engineering Indian Institute of Technology, Madras Module 02 Lecture - 03 So in the last

More information

Semantic Entailment and Natural Deduction

Semantic Entailment and Natural Deduction Semantic Entailment and Natural Deduction Alice Gao Lecture 6, September 26, 2017 Entailment 1/55 Learning goals Semantic entailment Define semantic entailment. Explain subtleties of semantic entailment.

More information

An alternative understanding of interpretations: Incompatibility Semantics

An alternative understanding of interpretations: Incompatibility Semantics An alternative understanding of interpretations: Incompatibility Semantics 1. In traditional (truth-theoretic) semantics, interpretations serve to specify when statements are true and when they are false.

More information

INTERMEDIATE LOGIC Glossary of key terms

INTERMEDIATE LOGIC Glossary of key terms 1 GLOSSARY INTERMEDIATE LOGIC BY JAMES B. NANCE INTERMEDIATE LOGIC Glossary of key terms This glossary includes terms that are defined in the text in the lesson and on the page noted. It does not include

More information

2.1 Review. 2.2 Inference and justifications

2.1 Review. 2.2 Inference and justifications Applied Logic Lecture 2: Evidence Semantics for Intuitionistic Propositional Logic Formal logic and evidence CS 4860 Fall 2012 Tuesday, August 28, 2012 2.1 Review The purpose of logic is to make reasoning

More information

Chapter 9- Sentential Proofs

Chapter 9- Sentential Proofs Logic: A Brief Introduction Ronald L. Hall, Stetson University Chapter 9- Sentential roofs 9.1 Introduction So far we have introduced three ways of assessing the validity of truth-functional arguments.

More information

An Introduction to. Formal Logic. Second edition. Peter Smith, February 27, 2019

An Introduction to. Formal Logic. Second edition. Peter Smith, February 27, 2019 An Introduction to Formal Logic Second edition Peter Smith February 27, 2019 Peter Smith 2018. Not for re-posting or re-circulation. Comments and corrections please to ps218 at cam dot ac dot uk 1 What

More information

PART III - Symbolic Logic Chapter 7 - Sentential Propositions

PART III - Symbolic Logic Chapter 7 - Sentential Propositions Logic: A Brief Introduction Ronald L. Hall, Stetson University 7.1 Introduction PART III - Symbolic Logic Chapter 7 - Sentential Propositions What has been made abundantly clear in the previous discussion

More information

2.3. Failed proofs and counterexamples

2.3. Failed proofs and counterexamples 2.3. Failed proofs and counterexamples 2.3.0. Overview Derivations can also be used to tell when a claim of entailment does not follow from the principles for conjunction. 2.3.1. When enough is enough

More information

UC Berkeley, Philosophy 142, Spring 2016

UC Berkeley, Philosophy 142, Spring 2016 Logical Consequence UC Berkeley, Philosophy 142, Spring 2016 John MacFarlane 1 Intuitive characterizations of consequence Modal: It is necessary (or apriori) that, if the premises are true, the conclusion

More information

Logic: A Brief Introduction

Logic: A Brief Introduction Logic: A Brief Introduction Ronald L. Hall, Stetson University PART III - Symbolic Logic Chapter 7 - Sentential Propositions 7.1 Introduction What has been made abundantly clear in the previous discussion

More information

LGCS 199DR: Independent Study in Pragmatics

LGCS 199DR: Independent Study in Pragmatics LGCS 99DR: Independent Study in Pragmatics Jesse Harris & Meredith Landman September 0, 203 Last class, we discussed the difference between semantics and pragmatics: Semantics The study of the literal

More information

Logic Appendix: More detailed instruction in deductive logic

Logic Appendix: More detailed instruction in deductive logic Logic Appendix: More detailed instruction in deductive logic Standardizing and Diagramming In Reason and the Balance we have taken the approach of using a simple outline to standardize short arguments,

More information

Day 3. Wednesday May 23, Learn the basic building blocks of proofs (specifically, direct proofs)

Day 3. Wednesday May 23, Learn the basic building blocks of proofs (specifically, direct proofs) Day 3 Wednesday May 23, 2012 Objectives: Learn the basics of Propositional Logic Learn the basic building blocks of proofs (specifically, direct proofs) 1 Propositional Logic Today we introduce the concepts

More information

1.2. What is said: propositions

1.2. What is said: propositions 1.2. What is said: propositions 1.2.0. Overview In 1.1.5, we saw the close relation between two properties of a deductive inference: (i) it is a transition from premises to conclusion that is free of any

More information

Logic I or Moving in on the Monkey & Bananas Problem

Logic I or Moving in on the Monkey & Bananas Problem Logic I or Moving in on the Monkey & Bananas Problem We said that an agent receives percepts from its environment, and performs actions on that environment; and that the action sequence can be based on

More information

1. Introduction Formal deductive logic Overview

1. Introduction Formal deductive logic Overview 1. Introduction 1.1. Formal deductive logic 1.1.0. Overview In this course we will study reasoning, but we will study only certain aspects of reasoning and study them only from one perspective. The special

More information

prohibition, moral commitment and other normative matters. Although often described as a branch

prohibition, moral commitment and other normative matters. Although often described as a branch Logic, deontic. The study of principles of reasoning pertaining to obligation, permission, prohibition, moral commitment and other normative matters. Although often described as a branch of logic, deontic

More information

Artificial Intelligence. Clause Form and The Resolution Rule. Prof. Deepak Khemani. Department of Computer Science and Engineering

Artificial Intelligence. Clause Form and The Resolution Rule. Prof. Deepak Khemani. Department of Computer Science and Engineering Artificial Intelligence Clause Form and The Resolution Rule Prof. Deepak Khemani Department of Computer Science and Engineering Indian Institute of Technology, Madras Module 07 Lecture 03 Okay so we are

More information

A Romp through the Foothills of Logic: Session 2

A Romp through the Foothills of Logic: Session 2 A Romp through the Foothills of Logic: Session 2 You might find it easier to understand this podcast if you first watch the short podcast Introducing Truth Tables. (Slide 2) Right, by the time we finish

More information

Logic for Computer Science - Week 1 Introduction to Informal Logic

Logic for Computer Science - Week 1 Introduction to Informal Logic Logic for Computer Science - Week 1 Introduction to Informal Logic Ștefan Ciobâcă November 30, 2017 1 Propositions A proposition is a statement that can be true or false. Propositions are sometimes called

More information

4.1 A problem with semantic demonstrations of validity

4.1 A problem with semantic demonstrations of validity 4. Proofs 4.1 A problem with semantic demonstrations of validity Given that we can test an argument for validity, it might seem that we have a fully developed system to study arguments. However, there

More information

HANDBOOK. IV. Argument Construction Determine the Ultimate Conclusion Construct the Chain of Reasoning Communicate the Argument 13

HANDBOOK. IV. Argument Construction Determine the Ultimate Conclusion Construct the Chain of Reasoning Communicate the Argument 13 1 HANDBOOK TABLE OF CONTENTS I. Argument Recognition 2 II. Argument Analysis 3 1. Identify Important Ideas 3 2. Identify Argumentative Role of These Ideas 4 3. Identify Inferences 5 4. Reconstruct the

More information

HANDBOOK (New or substantially modified material appears in boxes.)

HANDBOOK (New or substantially modified material appears in boxes.) 1 HANDBOOK (New or substantially modified material appears in boxes.) I. ARGUMENT RECOGNITION Important Concepts An argument is a unit of reasoning that attempts to prove that a certain idea is true by

More information

Constructive Logic, Truth and Warranted Assertibility

Constructive Logic, Truth and Warranted Assertibility Constructive Logic, Truth and Warranted Assertibility Greg Restall Department of Philosophy Macquarie University Version of May 20, 2000....................................................................

More information

Logicola Truth Evaluation Exercises

Logicola Truth Evaluation Exercises Logicola Truth Evaluation Exercises The Logicola exercises for Ch. 6.3 concern truth evaluations, and in 6.4 this complicated to include unknown evaluations. I wanted to say a couple of things for those

More information

A BRIEF INTRODUCTION TO LOGIC FOR METAPHYSICIANS

A BRIEF INTRODUCTION TO LOGIC FOR METAPHYSICIANS A BRIEF INTRODUCTION TO LOGIC FOR METAPHYSICIANS 0. Logic, Probability, and Formal Structure Logic is often divided into two distinct areas, inductive logic and deductive logic. Inductive logic is concerned

More information

KRISHNA KANTA HANDIQUI STATE OPEN UNIVERSITY Patgaon, Ranigate, Guwahati SEMESTER: 1 PHILOSOPHY PAPER : 1 LOGIC: 1 BLOCK: 2

KRISHNA KANTA HANDIQUI STATE OPEN UNIVERSITY Patgaon, Ranigate, Guwahati SEMESTER: 1 PHILOSOPHY PAPER : 1 LOGIC: 1 BLOCK: 2 GPH S1 01 KRISHNA KANTA HANDIQUI STATE OPEN UNIVERSITY Patgaon, Ranigate, Guwahati-781017 SEMESTER: 1 PHILOSOPHY PAPER : 1 LOGIC: 1 BLOCK: 2 CONTENTS UNIT 6 : Modern analysis of proposition UNIT 7 : Square

More information

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW DISCUSSION NOTE BY CAMPBELL BROWN JOURNAL OF ETHICS & SOCIAL PHILOSOPHY DISCUSSION NOTE MAY 2015 URL: WWW.JESP.ORG COPYRIGHT CAMPBELL BROWN 2015 Two Versions of Hume s Law MORAL CONCLUSIONS CANNOT VALIDLY

More information

Overview of Today s Lecture

Overview of Today s Lecture Branden Fitelson Philosophy 12A Notes 1 Overview of Today s Lecture Music: Robin Trower, Daydream (King Biscuit Flower Hour concert, 1977) Administrative Stuff (lots of it) Course Website/Syllabus [i.e.,

More information

On Truth At Jeffrey C. King Rutgers University

On Truth At Jeffrey C. King Rutgers University On Truth At Jeffrey C. King Rutgers University I. Introduction A. At least some propositions exist contingently (Fine 1977, 1985) B. Given this, motivations for a notion of truth on which propositions

More information

Reductio ad Absurdum, Modulation, and Logical Forms. Miguel López-Astorga 1

Reductio ad Absurdum, Modulation, and Logical Forms. Miguel López-Astorga 1 International Journal of Philosophy and Theology June 25, Vol. 3, No., pp. 59-65 ISSN: 2333-575 (Print), 2333-5769 (Online) Copyright The Author(s). All Rights Reserved. Published by American Research

More information

A. Problem set #3 it has been posted and is due Tuesday, 15 November

A. Problem set #3 it has been posted and is due Tuesday, 15 November Lecture 9: Propositional Logic I Philosophy 130 1 & 3 November 2016 O Rourke & Gibson I. Administrative A. Problem set #3 it has been posted and is due Tuesday, 15 November B. I am working on the group

More information

Quantificational logic and empty names

Quantificational logic and empty names Quantificational logic and empty names Andrew Bacon 26th of March 2013 1 A Puzzle For Classical Quantificational Theory Empty Names: Consider the sentence 1. There is something identical to Pegasus On

More information

Deduction by Daniel Bonevac. Chapter 1 Basic Concepts of Logic

Deduction by Daniel Bonevac. Chapter 1 Basic Concepts of Logic Deduction by Daniel Bonevac Chapter 1 Basic Concepts of Logic Logic defined Logic is the study of correct reasoning. Informal logic is the attempt to represent correct reasoning using the natural language

More information

HANDBOOK (New or substantially modified material appears in boxes.)

HANDBOOK (New or substantially modified material appears in boxes.) 1 HANDBOOK (New or substantially modified material appears in boxes.) I. ARGUMENT RECOGNITION Important Concepts An argument is a unit of reasoning that attempts to prove that a certain idea is true by

More information

Lecture Notes on Classical Logic

Lecture Notes on Classical Logic Lecture Notes on Classical Logic 15-317: Constructive Logic William Lovas Lecture 7 September 15, 2009 1 Introduction In this lecture, we design a judgmental formulation of classical logic To gain an intuition,

More information

Comments on Truth at A World for Modal Propositions

Comments on Truth at A World for Modal Propositions Comments on Truth at A World for Modal Propositions Christopher Menzel Texas A&M University March 16, 2008 Since Arthur Prior first made us aware of the issue, a lot of philosophical thought has gone into

More information

Module 5. Knowledge Representation and Logic (Propositional Logic) Version 2 CSE IIT, Kharagpur

Module 5. Knowledge Representation and Logic (Propositional Logic) Version 2 CSE IIT, Kharagpur Module 5 Knowledge Representation and Logic (Propositional Logic) Lesson 12 Propositional Logic inference rules 5.5 Rules of Inference Here are some examples of sound rules of inference. Each can be shown

More information

Illustrating Deduction. A Didactic Sequence for Secondary School

Illustrating Deduction. A Didactic Sequence for Secondary School Illustrating Deduction. A Didactic Sequence for Secondary School Francisco Saurí Universitat de València. Dpt. de Lògica i Filosofia de la Ciència Cuerpo de Profesores de Secundaria. IES Vilamarxant (España)

More information

What would count as Ibn Sīnā (11th century Persia) having first order logic?

What would count as Ibn Sīnā (11th century Persia) having first order logic? 1 2 What would count as Ibn Sīnā (11th century Persia) having first order logic? Wilfrid Hodges Herons Brook, Sticklepath, Okehampton March 2012 http://wilfridhodges.co.uk Ibn Sina, 980 1037 3 4 Ibn Sīnā

More information

3. Negations Not: contradicting content Contradictory propositions Overview Connectives

3. Negations Not: contradicting content Contradictory propositions Overview Connectives 3. Negations 3.1. Not: contradicting content 3.1.0. Overview In this chapter, we direct our attention to negation, the second of the logical forms we will consider. 3.1.1. Connectives Negation is a way

More information

Study Guides. Chapter 1 - Basic Training

Study Guides. Chapter 1 - Basic Training Study Guides Chapter 1 - Basic Training Argument: A group of propositions is an argument when one or more of the propositions in the group is/are used to give evidence (or if you like, reasons, or grounds)

More information

Complications for Categorical Syllogisms. PHIL 121: Methods of Reasoning February 27, 2013 Instructor:Karin Howe Binghamton University

Complications for Categorical Syllogisms. PHIL 121: Methods of Reasoning February 27, 2013 Instructor:Karin Howe Binghamton University Complications for Categorical Syllogisms PHIL 121: Methods of Reasoning February 27, 2013 Instructor:Karin Howe Binghamton University Overall Plan First, I will present some problematic propositions and

More information

Logic and Pragmatics: linear logic for inferential practice

Logic and Pragmatics: linear logic for inferential practice Logic and Pragmatics: linear logic for inferential practice Daniele Porello danieleporello@gmail.com Institute for Logic, Language & Computation (ILLC) University of Amsterdam, Plantage Muidergracht 24

More information

Ling 98a: The Meaning of Negation (Week 1)

Ling 98a: The Meaning of Negation (Week 1) Yimei Xiang yxiang@fas.harvard.edu 17 September 2013 1 What is negation? Negation in two-valued propositional logic Based on your understanding, select out the metaphors that best describe the meaning

More information

The way we convince people is generally to refer to sufficiently many things that they already know are correct.

The way we convince people is generally to refer to sufficiently many things that they already know are correct. Theorem A Theorem is a valid deduction. One of the key activities in higher mathematics is identifying whether or not a deduction is actually a theorem and then trying to convince other people that you

More information

Announcements The Logic of Quantifiers Logical Truth & Consequence in Full Fol. Outline. Overview The Big Picture. William Starr

Announcements The Logic of Quantifiers Logical Truth & Consequence in Full Fol. Outline. Overview The Big Picture. William Starr Announcements 10.27 The Logic of Quantifiers Logical Truth & Consequence in Full Fol William Starr 1 Hang tight on the midterm We ll get it back to you as soon as we can 2 Grades for returned HW will be

More information

Fr. Copleston vs. Bertrand Russell: The Famous 1948 BBC Radio Debate on the Existence of God

Fr. Copleston vs. Bertrand Russell: The Famous 1948 BBC Radio Debate on the Existence of God Fr. Copleston vs. Bertrand Russell: The Famous 1948 BBC Radio Debate on the Existence of God Father Frederick C. Copleston (Jesuit Catholic priest) versus Bertrand Russell (agnostic philosopher) Copleston:

More information

Introduction Symbolic Logic

Introduction Symbolic Logic An Introduction to Symbolic Logic Copyright 2006 by Terence Parsons all rights reserved CONTENTS Chapter One Sentential Logic with 'if' and 'not' 1 SYMBOLIC NOTATION 2 MEANINGS OF THE SYMBOLIC NOTATION

More information

A romp through the foothills of logic Session 3

A romp through the foothills of logic Session 3 A romp through the foothills of logic Session 3 It would be a good idea to watch the short podcast Understanding Truth Tables before attempting this podcast. (Slide 2) In the last session we learnt how

More information

Today s Lecture 1/28/10

Today s Lecture 1/28/10 Chapter 7.1! Symbolizing English Arguments! 5 Important Logical Operators!The Main Logical Operator Today s Lecture 1/28/10 Quiz State from memory (closed book and notes) the five famous valid forms and

More information

Truth At a World for Modal Propositions

Truth At a World for Modal Propositions Truth At a World for Modal Propositions 1 Introduction Existentialism is a thesis that concerns the ontological status of individual essences and singular propositions. Let us define an individual essence

More information

Philosophy 1100: Introduction to Ethics. Critical Thinking Lecture 2. Background Material for the Exercise on Inference Indicators

Philosophy 1100: Introduction to Ethics. Critical Thinking Lecture 2. Background Material for the Exercise on Inference Indicators Philosophy 1100: Introduction to Ethics Critical Thinking Lecture 2 Background Material for the Exercise on Inference Indicators Inference-Indicators and the Logical Structure of an Argument 1. The Idea

More information

Artificial Intelligence Prof. P. Dasgupta Department of Computer Science & Engineering Indian Institute of Technology, Kharagpur

Artificial Intelligence Prof. P. Dasgupta Department of Computer Science & Engineering Indian Institute of Technology, Kharagpur Artificial Intelligence Prof. P. Dasgupta Department of Computer Science & Engineering Indian Institute of Technology, Kharagpur Lecture- 9 First Order Logic In the last class, we had seen we have studied

More information

(Refer Slide Time 03:00)

(Refer Slide Time 03:00) Artificial Intelligence Prof. Anupam Basu Department of Computer Science and Engineering Indian Institute of Technology, Kharagpur Lecture - 15 Resolution in FOPL In the last lecture we had discussed about

More information

ILLOCUTIONARY ORIGINS OF FAMILIAR LOGICAL OPERATORS

ILLOCUTIONARY ORIGINS OF FAMILIAR LOGICAL OPERATORS ILLOCUTIONARY ORIGINS OF FAMILIAR LOGICAL OPERATORS 1. ACTS OF USING LANGUAGE Illocutionary logic is the logic of speech acts, or language acts. Systems of illocutionary logic have both an ontological,

More information

Logic is the study of the quality of arguments. An argument consists of a set of

Logic is the study of the quality of arguments. An argument consists of a set of Logic: Inductive Logic is the study of the quality of arguments. An argument consists of a set of premises and a conclusion. The quality of an argument depends on at least two factors: the truth of the

More information

VAGUENESS. Francis Jeffry Pelletier and István Berkeley Department of Philosophy University of Alberta Edmonton, Alberta, Canada

VAGUENESS. Francis Jeffry Pelletier and István Berkeley Department of Philosophy University of Alberta Edmonton, Alberta, Canada VAGUENESS Francis Jeffry Pelletier and István Berkeley Department of Philosophy University of Alberta Edmonton, Alberta, Canada Vagueness: an expression is vague if and only if it is possible that it give

More information

derosset, Louis (2013) "What is Weak Ground?," Essays in Philosophy: Vol. 14: Iss. 1, Article

derosset, Louis (2013) What is Weak Ground?, Essays in Philosophy: Vol. 14: Iss. 1, Article Essays in Philosophy Volume 14 Issue 1 Grounding Relation(s) Article 2 January 2013 What is Weak Ground? Louis derosset University of Vermont Follow this and additional works at: https://commons.pacificu.edu/eip

More information

What is the Frege/Russell Analysis of Quantification? Scott Soames

What is the Frege/Russell Analysis of Quantification? Scott Soames What is the Frege/Russell Analysis of Quantification? Scott Soames The Frege-Russell analysis of quantification was a fundamental advance in semantics and philosophical logic. Abstracting away from details

More information

Workbook Unit 3: Symbolizations

Workbook Unit 3: Symbolizations Workbook Unit 3: Symbolizations 1. Overview 2 2. Symbolization as an Art and as a Skill 3 3. A Variety of Symbolization Tricks 15 3.1. n-place Conjunctions and Disjunctions 15 3.2. Neither nor, Not both

More information

Intersubstitutivity Principles and the Generalization Function of Truth. Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh. Shawn Standefer University of Melbourne

Intersubstitutivity Principles and the Generalization Function of Truth. Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh. Shawn Standefer University of Melbourne Intersubstitutivity Principles and the Generalization Function of Truth Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh Shawn Standefer University of Melbourne Abstract We offer a defense of one aspect of Paul Horwich

More information

10 CERTAINTY G.E. MOORE: SELECTED WRITINGS

10 CERTAINTY G.E. MOORE: SELECTED WRITINGS 10 170 I am at present, as you can all see, in a room and not in the open air; I am standing up, and not either sitting or lying down; I have clothes on, and am not absolutely naked; I am speaking in a

More information

Foreknowledge, evil, and compatibility arguments

Foreknowledge, evil, and compatibility arguments Foreknowledge, evil, and compatibility arguments Jeff Speaks January 25, 2011 1 Warfield s argument for compatibilism................................ 1 2 Why the argument fails to show that free will and

More information

Is the law of excluded middle a law of logic?

Is the law of excluded middle a law of logic? Is the law of excluded middle a law of logic? Introduction I will conclude that the intuitionist s attempt to rule out the law of excluded middle as a law of logic fails. They do so by appealing to harmony

More information

Does Deduction really rest on a more secure epistemological footing than Induction?

Does Deduction really rest on a more secure epistemological footing than Induction? Does Deduction really rest on a more secure epistemological footing than Induction? We argue that, if deduction is taken to at least include classical logic (CL, henceforth), justifying CL - and thus deduction

More information

1. Lukasiewicz s Logic

1. Lukasiewicz s Logic Bulletin of the Section of Logic Volume 29/3 (2000), pp. 115 124 Dale Jacquette AN INTERNAL DETERMINACY METATHEOREM FOR LUKASIEWICZ S AUSSAGENKALKÜLS Abstract An internal determinacy metatheorem is proved

More information

Truth and Modality - can they be reconciled?

Truth and Modality - can they be reconciled? Truth and Modality - can they be reconciled? by Eileen Walker 1) The central question What makes modal statements statements about what might be or what might have been the case true or false? Normally

More information

Methods of Proof for Boolean Logic

Methods of Proof for Boolean Logic Chapter 5 Methods of Proof for Boolean Logic limitations of truth table methods Truth tables give us powerful techniques for investigating the logic of the Boolean operators. But they are by no means the

More information

Exercise Sets. KS Philosophical Logic: Modality, Conditionals Vagueness. Dirk Kindermann University of Graz July 2014

Exercise Sets. KS Philosophical Logic: Modality, Conditionals Vagueness. Dirk Kindermann University of Graz July 2014 Exercise Sets KS Philosophical Logic: Modality, Conditionals Vagueness Dirk Kindermann University of Graz July 2014 1 Exercise Set 1 Propositional and Predicate Logic 1. Use Definition 1.1 (Handout I Propositional

More information

Etchemendy, Tarski, and Logical Consequence 1 Jared Bates, University of Missouri Southwest Philosophy Review 15 (1999):

Etchemendy, Tarski, and Logical Consequence 1 Jared Bates, University of Missouri Southwest Philosophy Review 15 (1999): Etchemendy, Tarski, and Logical Consequence 1 Jared Bates, University of Missouri Southwest Philosophy Review 15 (1999): 47 54. Abstract: John Etchemendy (1990) has argued that Tarski's definition of logical

More information

Philosophy 220. Truth Functional Properties Expressed in terms of Consistency

Philosophy 220. Truth Functional Properties Expressed in terms of Consistency Philosophy 220 Truth Functional Properties Expressed in terms of Consistency The concepts of truth-functional logic: Truth-functional: Truth Falsity Indeterminacy Entailment Validity Equivalence Consistency

More information

Informalizing Formal Logic

Informalizing Formal Logic Informalizing Formal Logic Antonis Kakas Department of Computer Science, University of Cyprus, Cyprus antonis@ucy.ac.cy Abstract. This paper discusses how the basic notions of formal logic can be expressed

More information

Some proposals for understanding narrow content

Some proposals for understanding narrow content Some proposals for understanding narrow content February 3, 2004 1 What should we require of explanations of narrow content?......... 1 2 Narrow psychology as whatever is shared by intrinsic duplicates......

More information

Scott Soames: Understanding Truth

Scott Soames: Understanding Truth Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Vol. LXV, No. 2, September 2002 Scott Soames: Understanding Truth MAlTHEW MCGRATH Texas A & M University Scott Soames has written a valuable book. It is unmatched

More information

6. Truth and Possible Worlds

6. Truth and Possible Worlds 6. Truth and Possible Worlds We have defined logical entailment, consistency, and the connectives,,, all in terms of belief. In view of the close connection between belief and truth, described in the first

More information

Exposition of Symbolic Logic with Kalish-Montague derivations

Exposition of Symbolic Logic with Kalish-Montague derivations An Exposition of Symbolic Logic with Kalish-Montague derivations Copyright 2006-13 by Terence Parsons all rights reserved Aug 2013 Preface The system of logic used here is essentially that of Kalish &

More information

9 Methods of Deduction

9 Methods of Deduction M09_COPI1396_13_SE_C09.QXD 10/19/07 3:46 AM Page 372 9 Methods of Deduction 9.1 Formal Proof of Validity 9.2 The Elementary Valid Argument Forms 9.3 Formal Proofs of Validity Exhibited 9.4 Constructing

More information

Review of Philosophical Logic: An Introduction to Advanced Topics *

Review of Philosophical Logic: An Introduction to Advanced Topics * Teaching Philosophy 36 (4):420-423 (2013). Review of Philosophical Logic: An Introduction to Advanced Topics * CHAD CARMICHAEL Indiana University Purdue University Indianapolis This book serves as a concise

More information

LOGIC ANTHONY KAPOLKA FYF 101-9/3/2010

LOGIC ANTHONY KAPOLKA FYF 101-9/3/2010 LOGIC ANTHONY KAPOLKA FYF 101-9/3/2010 LIBERALLY EDUCATED PEOPLE......RESPECT RIGOR NOT SO MUCH FOR ITS OWN SAKE BUT AS A WAY OF SEEKING TRUTH. LOGIC PUZZLE COOPER IS MURDERED. 3 SUSPECTS: SMITH, JONES,

More information

MITOCW ocw f99-lec19_300k

MITOCW ocw f99-lec19_300k MITOCW ocw-18.06-f99-lec19_300k OK, this is the second lecture on determinants. There are only three. With determinants it's a fascinating, small topic inside linear algebra. Used to be determinants were

More information

3.3. Negations as premises Overview

3.3. Negations as premises Overview 3.3. Negations as premises 3.3.0. Overview A second group of rules for negation interchanges the roles of an affirmative sentence and its negation. 3.3.1. Indirect proof The basic principles for negation

More information

PHILOSOPHY OF LOGIC AND LANGUAGE OVERVIEW LOGICAL CONSTANTS WEEK 5: MODEL-THEORETIC CONSEQUENCE JONNY MCINTOSH

PHILOSOPHY OF LOGIC AND LANGUAGE OVERVIEW LOGICAL CONSTANTS WEEK 5: MODEL-THEORETIC CONSEQUENCE JONNY MCINTOSH PHILOSOPHY OF LOGIC AND LANGUAGE WEEK 5: MODEL-THEORETIC CONSEQUENCE JONNY MCINTOSH OVERVIEW Last week, I discussed various strands of thought about the concept of LOGICAL CONSEQUENCE, introducing Tarski's

More information

Friends and strangers

Friends and strangers 1997 2009, Millennium Mathematics Project, University of Cambridge. Permission is granted to print and copy this page on paper for non commercial use. For other uses, including electronic redistribution,

More information

Analyticity and reference determiners

Analyticity and reference determiners Analyticity and reference determiners Jeff Speaks November 9, 2011 1. The language myth... 1 2. The definition of analyticity... 3 3. Defining containment... 4 4. Some remaining questions... 6 4.1. Reference

More information

LTJ 27 2 [Start of recorded material] Interviewer: From the University of Leicester in the United Kingdom. This is Glenn Fulcher with the very first

LTJ 27 2 [Start of recorded material] Interviewer: From the University of Leicester in the United Kingdom. This is Glenn Fulcher with the very first LTJ 27 2 [Start of recorded material] Interviewer: From the University of Leicester in the United Kingdom. This is Glenn Fulcher with the very first issue of Language Testing Bytes. In this first Language

More information

Elements of Science (cont.); Conditional Statements. Phil 12: Logic and Decision Making Fall 2010 UC San Diego 9/29/2010

Elements of Science (cont.); Conditional Statements. Phil 12: Logic and Decision Making Fall 2010 UC San Diego 9/29/2010 Elements of Science (cont.); Conditional Statements Phil 12: Logic and Decision Making Fall 2010 UC San Diego 9/29/2010 1 Why cover statements and arguments Decision making (whether in science or elsewhere)

More information

Tutorial A03: Patterns of Valid Arguments By: Jonathan Chan

Tutorial A03: Patterns of Valid Arguments By: Jonathan Chan A03.1 Introduction Tutorial A03: Patterns of Valid Arguments By: With valid arguments, it is impossible to have a false conclusion if the premises are all true. Obviously valid arguments play a very important

More information

Future Contingents, Non-Contradiction and the Law of Excluded Middle Muddle

Future Contingents, Non-Contradiction and the Law of Excluded Middle Muddle Future Contingents, Non-Contradiction and the Law of Excluded Middle Muddle For whatever reason, we might think that contingent statements about the future have no determinate truth value. Aristotle, in

More information

Can logical consequence be deflated?

Can logical consequence be deflated? Can logical consequence be deflated? Michael De University of Utrecht Department of Philosophy Utrecht, Netherlands mikejde@gmail.com in Insolubles and Consequences : essays in honour of Stephen Read,

More information

Empty Names and Two-Valued Positive Free Logic

Empty Names and Two-Valued Positive Free Logic Empty Names and Two-Valued Positive Free Logic 1 Introduction Zahra Ahmadianhosseini In order to tackle the problem of handling empty names in logic, Andrew Bacon (2013) takes on an approach based on positive

More information

Stout s teleological theory of action

Stout s teleological theory of action Stout s teleological theory of action Jeff Speaks November 26, 2004 1 The possibility of externalist explanations of action................ 2 1.1 The distinction between externalist and internalist explanations

More information

Could have done otherwise, action sentences and anaphora

Could have done otherwise, action sentences and anaphora Could have done otherwise, action sentences and anaphora HELEN STEWARD What does it mean to say of a certain agent, S, that he or she could have done otherwise? Clearly, it means nothing at all, unless

More information

G. H. von Wright Deontic Logic

G. H. von Wright Deontic Logic G. H. von Wright Deontic Logic Kian Mintz-Woo University of Amsterdam January 9, 2009 January 9, 2009 Logic of Norms 2010 1/17 INTRODUCTION In von Wright s 1951 formulation, deontic logic is intended to

More information

A Guide to FOL Proof Rules ( for Worksheet 6)

A Guide to FOL Proof Rules ( for Worksheet 6) A Guide to FOL Proof Rules ( for Worksheet 6) This lesson sheet will be a good deal like last class s. This time, I ll be running through the proof rules relevant to FOL. Of course, when you re doing any

More information

9.1 Intro to Predicate Logic Practice with symbolizations. Today s Lecture 3/30/10

9.1 Intro to Predicate Logic Practice with symbolizations. Today s Lecture 3/30/10 9.1 Intro to Predicate Logic Practice with symbolizations Today s Lecture 3/30/10 Announcements Tests back today Homework: --Ex 9.1 pgs. 431-432 Part C (1-25) Predicate Logic Consider the argument: All

More information

Situations in Which Disjunctive Syllogism Can Lead from True Premises to a False Conclusion

Situations in Which Disjunctive Syllogism Can Lead from True Premises to a False Conclusion 398 Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic Volume 38, Number 3, Summer 1997 Situations in Which Disjunctive Syllogism Can Lead from True Premises to a False Conclusion S. V. BHAVE Abstract Disjunctive Syllogism,

More information