Defending the Argument. Robert H. Bass

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Defending the Argument. Robert H. Bass"

Transcription

1 A Dialogue on Ayn Rand s Ethics Rejoinder to Chris Cathcart, Egoism and Rights and Robert L. Campbell, Altruism in Auguste Comte and Ayn Rand (Spring 2006) Defending the Argument Robert H. Bass Introduction I would like to thank Robert L. Campbell (2006) and Chris Cathcart (2006) for their thoughtful responses to my article. As will become evident, I am unconvinced that either has uncovered major weaknesses, but I am grateful for the opportunity to reply and clarify matters that may remain at issue between us. I have certainly learned from them both. Campbell Robert L. Campbell focuses upon my rejection of Ayn Rand s argument that altruism in morality is inconsistent with respect for individual rights in politics (Campbell 2006, 357). I find his response a bit puzzling, but I will try to sort it out. Before doing so, however, I must take issue with Campbell s remark about my insensitivity to the ancient ethical tradition to which Rand s moral theory largely belongs (357). I assume he means the ancient ethical tradition of eudaemonism, shared in different ways by Plato, Aristotle, the Stoics and a multitude of other thinkers. Much of my own work has been within that tradition (see, for example, Bass 2004), so I hope the insensitivity is only alleged. Since he offers no specific evidence, it is difficult to know how to respond. I suspect he may diagnose insensitivity on the basis of what he supposes to be insufficient respect for Rand. If so, I would say the attitude to Rand is not the product of lack of sensitivity, but rather, in part, a matter of The Journal of Ayn Rand Studies 7, no. 2 (Spring 2006):

2 372 The Journal of Ayn Rand Studies Vol. 7, No. 2 sensitivity to some of the tradition s insights that Rand should have absorbed, but did not. In particular, from Aristotle, she might have learned a more subtle and nuanced moral psychology, and a better, and less instrumental, understanding of the virtues. 1 Turning to the main body of Campbell s reply, I find it puzzling that he chose to focus upon such a small portion of my article, only about ten percent of the total, and further, that his focus is not upon a section in which any of my central arguments were developed. So far as I can see, Campbell could be correct on every point of his criticism without seriously damaging my main theses, which have to do with the incompatibility of egoism and rights. Campbell s objections to my treatment of Rand s argument about altruism and individual rights seem to be threefold. First, I should have addressed Comte, who coined the term, altruism, and characterized it in the same way that Rand did. She was true to the intentions of the founder (367). Second, he expresses dissatisfaction with the usage I prefer, the ordinary or garden-variety sense, 2 according to which altruism means that the interests of others matter in their own right, apart from the way they might impact upon one s own interests, and therefore that... it could be appropriate, desirable or morally required, on some occasions to act on behalf of others, even at some cost to one s own interests (Bass 2006, 331). He thinks my usage represents a wide and smeary range of views, which is watered down from Comte s crisp and uncompromising formulation (Campbell 2006, 362). Third, he demands an accounting for insistence upon the smeary meaning, when the term is still quite capable of bearing a Comtean meaning (367). With regard to the first point, I overlooked the fact that Rand had correctly cited Comte s use of altruism in just the sense she gives the term. I had said that [i]t is a doctrine that has never been held... by any of the thinkers she castigated as espousers of altruism (Bass 2006, 331). Campbell corrects me by pointing out that Rand had not neglected to castigate Comte. So, what I should have said is that it is a doctrine that has been held by hardly any of the thinkers she castigated as espousers of altruism. That may sound flippant, but I really think it is sufficient. What

3 Bass Defending the Argument 373 Rand condemns as altruism is still not a doctrine held by most of the people she calls altruists. On the second point, Campbell provides interesting intellectual history as to how altruism came to be associated with doctrines and practices much less sharply defined than Comte s conception, and, though I have reservations about a point or two, I appreciate his scholarship. However, I do not think the process is so much a matter of the unjustified watering down of a term as of taking a term that was nearly useless, for lack of application, and pressing it into service to apply to a range of real positions. The so-called smeary range of views is at least a range of views that are actually held. Plainly, for example, the altruists typically criticized by Rand thinkers such as Kant, Marx, Mill, Spencer, Dewey and Rawls are people who hold some position or other in the wide and smeary range, while only one, Comte himself, actually holds the Comtean position. This suggests that Rand s own usage was ambiguous: When offering definitions, she gives the Comtean formulation; when offering examples, she cites thinkers to whom the Comtean formulation does not apply. On the third point, there might be some reason for making altruism bear the Comtean meaning, but apart from the fact that the term could bear that meaning, I do not see that Campbell has given us any reason that it should. Perhaps if one had some doctrine about the proprietary rights of coiners of terms, one would be reluctant to use a term differently than its coiner intended, but it is hard to imagine what would warrant that doctrine. Another possibility is that there is an argument that all the more moderate views in the smeary range logically collapse into the immoderate Comtean view, so that any step away from egoism leaves one without the intellectual or moral resources to resist demands for all-consuming sacrifice for others. Some thinkers friendly to Rand may suppose this, but I have never seen a serious attempt to explain why we should accept the rather 3 remarkable conclusion that if the interests of others matter at all, then one s own interests have no importance whatsoever. If that is Campbell s view, it would be nice to see the argument. In its absence, we are well-justified in employing altruism for the wide and smeary range that includes actual positions rather than narrowing down our

4 374 The Journal of Ayn Rand Studies Vol. 7, No. 2 meaning to a crisp and uncompromising formulation that applies to hardly anything. 4 Cathcart Chris Cathcart addresses some of the central issues connected to my argument in Egoism versus Rights, and for the opportunity to clarify and amplify my position, I am grateful. Assessing his remarks is complicated somewhat by the fact that our disagreement depends partly upon his fusion of interpretive and substantive concerns. My main interest is in the substantive issues, but they cannot be adequately considered in the form in which he presents them, in complete abstraction from the interpretive matters. This interpenetration can be illustrated with Cathcart s first point. According to my equal-interests argument the Argument, as I call it, in which an agent must select either the rights-violating or the rights-respecting option from a pair that are equally good in terms of the agent s interests there is a contradiction in the position of the rights-respecting egoist. The rights-respecting option must be judged to be both morally better and not morally better than the rightsviolating option. Cathcart observes that this does not resemble an agent deliberating as heroes do from any of Rand s novels (2006, 352), and suggests that this indicates a misunderstanding, on my part, of Rand s egoism. My interpretation is different. First, the Argument was meant to show an inconsistency in the theory of rights-respecting egoism, not necessarily to portray a course of deliberation, so the deliberations of Rand s heroes are only tangentially relevant. Second, he apparently takes it for granted that Rand s fictional heroes are really egoists who respect rights, and draws the conclusion that if the Argument indicates otherwise, that betrays a misunderstanding of egoism. My inclination is the reverse: if Rand s heroes can be counted upon to respect rights in equal-interests situations, then they are not really egoists. The fact that Rand meant her heroes to be exemplars of rights-respecting egoism carries little weight. Interpretive questions figure also in the main points of Cathcart s reply. The first is that Rand s egoism is not consequentialist

5 Bass Defending the Argument 375 (Cathcart 2006, 352). The relevance is clear enough, since I do take her egoism to be consequentialist, at least to the extent of having the feature that rights are conceived solely as means to some further good (Bass 2006, 339). Since I doubt the hermeneutic questions can be resolved here, I shall briefly explain my interpretation, without hoping to settle the matter, and then explain why it makes little difference to the real issues. Rand certainly made claims that appear consequentialist. For example, she says that [r]eality confronts man with a great many musts, but all of them are conditional; the formula of realistic necessity is: You must, if and the if stands for man s choice: if you want to achieve a certain goal (1982, ). That appears to say that there are no musts, and therefore no moral musts, independent of some goal to be pursued. Elsewhere, she makes it clear that she thinks that the only thing fundamentally suited to be a goal by which to direct oneself is staying alive, a reading confirmed in secondary sources. Leonard Peikoff (1991) writes that morality is a means to survival (339), and man needs [morality] for one reason only... in order to survive (214). Further, remaining alive is the goal of values and of all proper action (213; emphasis in original). More could be cited along these lines, but it must be admitted that many passages may seem to bear a contrary interpretation. I think the weight of evidence favors the consequentialists (and survivalists), but I do not expect to make that case here at a length or depth sufficient to lay all doubt to rest. In an important sense, though, the interpretive issues do not much matter. What is central to my Argument is the attempt to show that egoism and rights are incompatible. Whether Rand s theory and rights are compatible is a distinct, and, for my purposes, much less important, question. This is crucial, because I do not take it for granted that Rand s theory is a form of egoism, especially if, as Cathcart supposes, it is a nonconsequentialist, moralized-interest theory. Thus, my view is that whether or not Cathcart is correct about the first two points of his reply that Rand s ethics is not consequentialist and that it expresses a moralized-interest theory he is mistaken to think that non-consequentialist or moralized-interest theories can be

6 376 The Journal of Ayn Rand Studies Vol. 7, No. 2 forms of egoism, and therefore mistaken about the second two points: There is no sound reason for calling Rand s theory, if it is really a nonconsequentialist, moralized-interest theory, a form of egoism, nor does any unitary moral principle find expression in both egoism and rights. The important issues turn not upon the interpretation of Rand but upon the questions of whether a non-consequentialist or moralized-interest theory can be a form of egoism, since Cathcart (2006, ) thinks that [t]he Argument shows the incompatibility between all consequentialist theories... and rights. 5 There seem to be three distinguishable strands to Cathcart s case that egoism need not be consequentialist. One stems from the briefly cited article, Deontological Egoism, by Keith Burgess-Jackson (2003). However, that attempt to show that there is conceptual space for a non-consequentialist egoism fails since, in Burgess-Jackson s favored version, an act may be wrong, even when it is known that doing it would be best for one s interests. 6 A second strand consists of hints and remarks made in passing to the effect that Rand s theory does not sound like a consequentialist theory. The remarks seem innocent of the fact that there are sophisticated as well as unsophisticated forms of consequentialism. At most, what is shown is that Rand was not an unsophisticated consequentialist. It is not shown that she was not a sophisticated 7 consequentialist, and therefore, not shown that she or other egoists have some non-consequentialist loophole through which to escape the force of the Argument. A third strand appears in Cathcart s objection to my insistence that egoist theories be framed in terms of non-moralized interests, which do not presuppose moral concepts or preconditions for their identification. As I understand it, the appeal to moralized interests in characterizing Rand s theory is meant to be a reason for denying that her theory is consequentialist rather than an independent reason for supposing it to be immune to the Argument. If so, there may be a confusion, for it is not obvious that interests cannot be both moralized and just a matter of promoting a favored consequence. Then, the problem of reconciling consequentialism and rights would remain in 8 full force, even with a moralized-interest theory. Be that as it may,

7 Bass Defending the Argument 377 I am happy to have the opportunity to explain further why egoists should not resort to moralized-interest theories. My concern is not that there is something objectionable about allowing moral conditions to enter into the identification of interests, nor is it even, fundamentally, over whether Rand offers us a moralized-interest theory, though I believe that is not what she meant to do. Rather, the problem is that the appeal to moralized interests trivializes egoism. If interests cannot be identified independently of moral conditions, egoism has been tacitly abandoned. To see this point, consider a theorist who has a completely free hand in specifying the content of interests. Let us call her view a promiscuous theory of interests. There will, of course, be no problem if she says that any degree of respect for rights can be squared with action that is in the interests of the agent. For example, she can simply hold that respect for rights is a highest-order interest, more self-interestedly important than anything that might come into conflict with it. The reason she can do that is that any claim whatsoever can be squared with acting in one s interests for a promiscuous theory. Knowingly and deliberately going to one s own ruin to prevent a cabbage from being eaten could count as being in one s interests if the theory need only say that ruin for the sake of cabbage-saving is in one s interests. No version of egoism can be so permissive about the content of interests. Restrictions must be imposed somehow, but whence are the restrictions to come? The short answer is that we will need a more restrictive theory of self-interest. The first step is uncontroversial. Suppose an agent is faced with a pair of options. Why is one of them, or neither, more in her interests? The answer has to be something like this: The theory of self-interest must, on one hand, identify a class of basic or core interests, and on the other, must say that other things count as being in an agent s interests by virtue of standing in the right relation to the basic or core interests. Actions are favored or not by virtue of their relation to the core interests. Let us call the specification of basic or core interests a List. Now, why do items on the List count as being in the agent s interests? Plainly, it will not do to say that they are in the agent s

8 378 The Journal of Ayn Rand Studies Vol. 7, No. 2 interests because they stand in the right relation to items on the List. We may be able to rule out an interest in cabbage-saving at the cost of slow death by torture because it doesn t stand in the right relation to items on the List if we have something else there, but how are we to rule out cabbage-saving (even at high cost) as itself an item on the List? That is, how are we to avoid a promiscuous theory? The theory stands in need of further articulation. Without further constraint, the structure in which there is a List of basic concerns and in which other things are recommended (or not) in terms of their relation to the basic concerns might amount to a theory of value, but not to a theory of self-interest. What is needed is some reason, other than a relation to further interests, to classify items on the List as self-interested. The only workable possibility I know is to apply the test of immediate plausibility: For any item on the List, it must be immediately plausible that it is in the interests of the agent. Credible candidates include longevity, happiness, pleasure, health, wealth, exemption from pain or suffering and the like. Why must List items pass the test of immediate plausibility? Consider the alternative. Suppose there is something that belongs on the List that it is not immediately plausible to regard as being in the agent s interests. Then, some case will have to be presented as to why it counts as being in the agent s interests. How will that argument proceed except by linking it to something that is immediately plausible to regard as being in the interests of the agent? But then, if its self-interested character must be validated by affecting a linkage to immediately plausible objects of interest, the new item will not be needed on the List of basic interests, after all. Now, I think we can see what the moralized-interest theorist is trying to do. He is trying to propose items for the List of basic interests, while denying that they must pass the test of immediate plausibility. If all interests must pass the test of immediate plausibility or be explained in terms of something that does, then we will not have a moralized-interest theory. On the other hand, he must avoid the trivialization involved in a promiscuous theory of interests or in the conversion of the theory of self-interest to a theory of value. The moralized-interest theorist needs a further constraint that cannot, ex

9 Bass Defending the Argument 379 hypothesi, be derived from immediately plausible objects of interest. I submit that the search is hopeless. Consider what Cathcart (2006, 354) offers in trying to spell out the theory: Man s proper self-interest isn t defined in a vacuum, as a primary, but by reference to the requirements of the life of a rational, conceptual being. The basic standard by which to judge one s actions is whether it accords with one s life as a rational being. The chief virtue by which to live, the virtue that entails the other virtues and both expresses (or constitutes) one s life as a rational being as well as leads to successful living and achievement of values, is the virtue of rationality. One is acting according to one s proper self-interest when one is exercising the virtue of rationality in pursuit of successful human living. Of course, Cathcart is right that self-interest is not to be defined in a vacuum, but the question remains what kind of non-vacuum it is to be defined in. Are rationality and successful living themselves to be understood as being self-interested or not? Whether rationality is self-interested is a matter of what rationality requires, and whether successful living is self-interested is a matter of what we should be successful at doing. The moralized-interest theorist cannot be allowed, without argument, the premise that the supposed moralized interests to which he appeals are really matters of self-interest. And without that premise, his credentials as an egoist are in disarray. Moralized interests are no help to the theorist who wishes to maintain the compatibility of egoism and rights, for in moralizing them, we sever the connections that can provide assurance that we are still speaking of interests. Thus, in conclusion, neither non-consequentialism nor moralized interests confer any immunity from the Argument. The most that they might do is suffice to show that a given theory, such as Rand s, is not really a form of egoism.

10 380 The Journal of Ayn Rand Studies Vol. 7, No. 2 Notes 1. For some discussion of the way in which the Epicureans, alone among the ancient eudaemonists, appear (but may only appear) to have regarded virtue as solely instrumental, see Annas 1993, 339ff. The other ancient eudaemonists avoided this condition, and Rand s position would have been more plausible had she learned from Aristotle or the others to avoid it as well. Additionally, no one familiar with Aristotle should be tempted by the crude identification of virtue as the act by which one gains or keeps whatever it is one acts to gain or keep (Rand 1964, 25). 2. In a note, Campbell (2006, 368 n. 2) objects that appeals to common sense may not be worth much in issues related to egoism and altruism, a claim about which he may be right. However, I did not make such an appeal. First, though he puts common sense in quotes (2006, 367), he introduced the term rather than I. Second, though I did cite the ordinary or garden-variety understanding of altruism, I employed that not to settle any substantive points but to answer the question about what the term means. I would add that it is only the availability of the ordinary usage of the term that makes Rand s attack on altruist theorists look like a mistake rather than a deliberate misrepresentation. 3. Of course, when I speak in this context of others interests mattering, I mean mattering in their own right and not just as a function of the way they may fit into the interests of the agent, since that kind of mattering is acceptable to the egoist. 4. If egoism entails that all moral reasons are (somehow) self-interested, and if altruism entails that some moral reasons are based on the interests of others, then there are logically possible moral positions that do not fall into either camp. No actual view that I know of denies both of the entailed theses. For example, retributivists hold that the wicked deserve punishment, whether or not it does any good for anyone. All actual retributivists, however, seem to accept other moral claims that make their view some species of altruism. 5. I actually think this conclusion is too hasty. Impressive attempts have been made to reconcile the two. See, for example, Sumner In Burgess-Jackson s typology, moral theories are consequentialist, when rightness is a function of the production of some consequence, or teleological, when rightness is a function of the pursuit of some end, or deontological, when the rightness of an action is a function of the kind of action it is, thus, any theory that constrains the pursuit or maximization of the good, or that precludes action from certain motives (such as malevolence), would be, broadly speaking, deontological (2003, 360). This is assumed to be an exhaustive set of alternatives, for he says that [i]n the broadest sense of the word, deontological refers to any theory other than a teleological or a consequentialist theory (360). The class of teleological egoists, I submit, is probably empty. Those who think one ought to have the end of achieving one s own well-being generally suppose (or would, if they thought about it) that having the end is the best way to achieve the result, so they are really consequentialists. It would be very odd to enjoin aiming to achieve one s interests, even on the assumption that so aiming would not be best for those interests. As for deontological egoism, it denies an essential feature of egoism,

11 Bass Defending the Argument 381 that if an agent were confronted by exactly two options and if one were selfinterestedly better than the other, then it would not be wrong to select the selfinterestedly better option. On Burgess-Jackson s proposal, an act can be wrong even when it is known to be most in the agent s interests. Most moral theories have that feature, but it seems misleading to call any such theory a form of egoism. Thus, Burgess-Jackson has not identified a non-consequentialist form of egoism. The teleologists are really consequentialists, while the deontologists are not really egoists. 7. Surely, the unstated argument is not that if Rand is a consequentialist, then she is an unsophisticated consequentialist, and since she is not an unsophisticated consequentialist, she must not be a consequentialist. What would warrant that odd first premise? 8. If, for example, one believed that, because of the goodness of aggregate wellbeing, its promotion counts as contributing to individual well-being, one would be holding an entirely consequentialist, moralized-interest theory. John Stuart Mill, in an 1868 letter, expressed something close to this: in a good state of society and education, every human being s happiness [would be] a good to every other human being (quoted in Schneewind 1965, 339). References Annas, Julia The Morality of Happiness. New York: Oxford University Press. Bass, Robert Towards a Constructivist Eudaemonism. Ph.D Dissertation. Bowling Green: Bowling Green State University Egoism versus rights. The Journal of Ayn Rand Studies 7, no. 2 (Spring): Burgess-Jackson, Keith Deontological egoism. Social Theory and Practice 29, no. 3: Campbell, Robert L Altruism in Auguste Comte and Ayn Rand. The Journal of Ayn Rand Studies 7, no. 2 (Spring): Cathcart, Chris Egoism and rights. The Journal of Ayn Rand Studies 7, no. 2 (Spring): Peikoff, Leonard Objectivism: The Philosophy of Ayn Rand. New York: Dutton. Rand, Ayn The Virtue of Selfishness: A New Concept of Egoism. New York: New American Library Philosophy: Who Needs It. New York: Bobbs-Merrill. Schneewind, J. B., ed Mill s Ethical Writings. New York: Collier. Sumner, L. W The Moral Foundation of Rights. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

James Rachels. Ethical Egoism

James Rachels. Ethical Egoism James Rachels Ethical Egoism Psychological Egoism Ethical Egoism n Psychological Egoism: n Ethical Egoism: An empirical (descriptive) theory A normative (prescriptive) theory A theory about what in fact

More information

In Defense of The Wide-Scope Instrumental Principle. Simon Rippon

In Defense of The Wide-Scope Instrumental Principle. Simon Rippon In Defense of The Wide-Scope Instrumental Principle Simon Rippon Suppose that people always have reason to take the means to the ends that they intend. 1 Then it would appear that people s intentions to

More information

Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly *

Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly * Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly * Ralph Wedgwood 1 Two views of practical reason Suppose that you are faced with several different options (that is, several ways in which you might act in a

More information

Consider... Ethical Egoism. Rachels. Consider... Theories about Human Motivations

Consider... Ethical Egoism. Rachels. Consider... Theories about Human Motivations Consider.... Ethical Egoism Rachels Suppose you hire an attorney to defend your interests in a dispute with your neighbor. In a court of law, the assumption is that in pursuing each client s interest,

More information

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism? Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism? Author: Terence Rajivan Edward, University of Manchester. Abstract. In the sixth chapter of The View from Nowhere, Thomas Nagel attempts to identify a form of idealism.

More information

A Review on What Is This Thing Called Ethics? by Christopher Bennett * ** 1

A Review on What Is This Thing Called Ethics? by Christopher Bennett * ** 1 310 Book Review Book Review ISSN (Print) 1225-4924, ISSN (Online) 2508-3104 Catholic Theology and Thought, Vol. 79, July 2017 http://dx.doi.org/10.21731/ctat.2017.79.310 A Review on What Is This Thing

More information

Let us begin by first locating our fields in relation to other fields that study ethics. Consider the following taxonomy: Kinds of ethical inquiries

Let us begin by first locating our fields in relation to other fields that study ethics. Consider the following taxonomy: Kinds of ethical inquiries ON NORMATIVE ETHICAL THEORIES: SOME BASICS From the dawn of philosophy, the question concerning the summum bonum, or, what is the same thing, concerning the foundation of morality, has been accounted the

More information

Are There Reasons to Be Rational?

Are There Reasons to Be Rational? Are There Reasons to Be Rational? Olav Gjelsvik, University of Oslo The thesis. Among people writing about rationality, few people are more rational than Wlodek Rabinowicz. But are there reasons for being

More information

Reason Papers Vol. 36, no. 1

Reason Papers Vol. 36, no. 1 Gotthelf, Allan, and James B. Lennox, eds. Metaethics, Egoism, and Virtue: Studies in Ayn Rand s Normative Theory. Pittsburgh, PA: University of Pittsburgh Press, 2011. Ayn Rand now counts as a figure

More information

A lonelier contractualism A. J. Julius, UCLA, January

A lonelier contractualism A. J. Julius, UCLA, January A lonelier contractualism A. J. Julius, UCLA, January 15 2008 1. A definition A theory of some normative domain is contractualist if, having said what it is for a person to accept a principle in that domain,

More information

CRUCIAL TOPICS IN THE DEBATE ABOUT THE EXISTENCE OF EXTERNAL REASONS

CRUCIAL TOPICS IN THE DEBATE ABOUT THE EXISTENCE OF EXTERNAL REASONS CRUCIAL TOPICS IN THE DEBATE ABOUT THE EXISTENCE OF EXTERNAL REASONS By MARANATHA JOY HAYES A THESIS PRESENTED TO THE GRADUATE SCHOOL OF THE UNIVERSITY OF FLORIDA IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS

More information

Utilitarianism: For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), pp Reprinted in Moral Luck (CUP, 1981).

Utilitarianism: For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), pp Reprinted in Moral Luck (CUP, 1981). Draft of 3-21- 13 PHIL 202: Core Ethics; Winter 2013 Core Sequence in the History of Ethics, 2011-2013 IV: 19 th and 20 th Century Moral Philosophy David O. Brink Handout #14: Williams, Internalism, and

More information

From the Categorical Imperative to the Moral Law

From the Categorical Imperative to the Moral Law From the Categorical Imperative to the Moral Law Marianne Vahl Master Thesis in Philosophy Supervisor Olav Gjelsvik Department of Philosophy, Classics, History of Arts and Ideas UNIVERSITY OF OSLO May

More information

Consequentialism, Incoherence and Choice. Rejoinder to a Rejoinder.

Consequentialism, Incoherence and Choice. Rejoinder to a Rejoinder. 1 Consequentialism, Incoherence and Choice. Rejoinder to a Rejoinder. by Peter Simpson and Robert McKim In a number of books and essays Joseph Boyle, John Finnis, and Germain Grisez (hereafter BFG) have

More information

A Contractualist Reply

A Contractualist Reply A Contractualist Reply The Harvard community has made this article openly available. Please share how this access benefits you. Your story matters Citation Scanlon, T. M. 2008. A Contractualist Reply.

More information

2 FREE CHOICE The heretical thesis of Hobbes is the orthodox position today. So much is this the case that most of the contemporary literature

2 FREE CHOICE The heretical thesis of Hobbes is the orthodox position today. So much is this the case that most of the contemporary literature Introduction The philosophical controversy about free will and determinism is perennial. Like many perennial controversies, this one involves a tangle of distinct but closely related issues. Thus, the

More information

SUMMARIES AND TEST QUESTIONS UNIT 6

SUMMARIES AND TEST QUESTIONS UNIT 6 SUMMARIES AND TEST QUESTIONS UNIT 6 Textbook: Louis P. Pojman, Editor. Philosophy: The quest for truth. New York: Oxford University Press, 2006. ISBN-10: 0199697310; ISBN-13: 9780199697311 (6th Edition)

More information

Act Consequentialism s Compelling Idea and Deontology s Paradoxical Idea

Act Consequentialism s Compelling Idea and Deontology s Paradoxical Idea Professor Douglas W. Portmore Act Consequentialism s Compelling Idea and Deontology s Paradoxical Idea I. Some Terminological Notes Very broadly and nontraditionally construed, act consequentialism is

More information

RESPONSE TO ADAM KOLBER S PUNISHMENT AND MORAL RISK

RESPONSE TO ADAM KOLBER S PUNISHMENT AND MORAL RISK RESPONSE TO ADAM KOLBER S PUNISHMENT AND MORAL RISK Chelsea Rosenthal* I. INTRODUCTION Adam Kolber argues in Punishment and Moral Risk that retributivists may be unable to justify criminal punishment,

More information

Ethical Reasoning and the THSEB: A Primer for Coaches

Ethical Reasoning and the THSEB: A Primer for Coaches Ethical Reasoning and the THSEB: A Primer for Coaches THSEB@utk.edu philosophy.utk.edu/ethics/index.php FOLLOW US! Twitter: @thseb_utk Instagram: thseb_utk Facebook: facebook.com/thsebutk Co-sponsored

More information

Chapter 2: Reasoning about ethics

Chapter 2: Reasoning about ethics Chapter 2: Reasoning about ethics 2012 Cengage Learning All Rights reserved Learning Outcomes LO 1 Explain how important moral reasoning is and how to apply it. LO 2 Explain the difference between facts

More information

PHIL%13:%Ethics;%Fall%2012% David%O.%Brink;%UCSD% Syllabus% Part%I:%Challenges%to%Moral%Theory 1.%Relativism%and%Tolerance.

PHIL%13:%Ethics;%Fall%2012% David%O.%Brink;%UCSD% Syllabus% Part%I:%Challenges%to%Moral%Theory 1.%Relativism%and%Tolerance. Draftof8)27)12 PHIL%13:%Ethics;%Fall%2012% David%O.%Brink;%UCSD% Syllabus% Hereisalistoftopicsandreadings.Withinatopic,dothereadingsintheorderinwhich theyarelisted.readingsaredrawnfromthethreemaintexts

More information

-- did you get a message welcoming you to the cours reflector? If not, please correct what s needed.

-- did you get a message welcoming you to the cours reflector? If not, please correct what s needed. 1 -- did you get a message welcoming you to the coursemail reflector? If not, please correct what s needed. 2 -- don t use secondary material from the web, as its quality is variable; cf. Wikipedia. Check

More information

A Case against Subjectivism: A Reply to Sobel

A Case against Subjectivism: A Reply to Sobel A Case against Subjectivism: A Reply to Sobel Abstract Subjectivists are committed to the claim that desires provide us with reasons for action. Derek Parfit argues that subjectivists cannot account for

More information

Notes on Moore and Parker, Chapter 12: Moral, Legal and Aesthetic Reasoning

Notes on Moore and Parker, Chapter 12: Moral, Legal and Aesthetic Reasoning Notes on Moore and Parker, Chapter 12: Moral, Legal and Aesthetic Reasoning The final chapter of Moore and Parker s text is devoted to how we might apply critical reasoning in certain philosophical contexts.

More information

Philosophical Ethics. Consequentialism Deontology (Virtue Ethics)

Philosophical Ethics. Consequentialism Deontology (Virtue Ethics) Consequentialism Deontology (Virtue Ethics) Consequentialism Deontology (Virtue Ethics) Consequentialism the value of an action (the action's moral worth, its rightness or wrongness) derives entirely from

More information

Professional Ethics. Today s Topic Ethical Egoism PHIL Picture: Ursa Major. Illustration: Cover art from Ayn Rand s The Fountainhead

Professional Ethics. Today s Topic Ethical Egoism PHIL Picture: Ursa Major. Illustration: Cover art from Ayn Rand s The Fountainhead Professional Ethics PHIL 3340 Today s Topic Ethical Egoism Illustration: Cover art from Ayn Rand s The Fountainhead Picture: Ursa Major Quiz #1 1. State in one sentence the central difference between psychological

More information

Challenges to Traditional Morality

Challenges to Traditional Morality Challenges to Traditional Morality Altruism Behavior that benefits others at some cost to oneself and that is motivated by the desire to benefit others Some Ordinary Assumptions About Morality (1) People

More information

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory Western University Scholarship@Western 2015 Undergraduate Awards The Undergraduate Awards 2015 Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory David Hakim Western University, davidhakim266@gmail.com

More information

A CONTRACTUALIST READING OF KANT S PROOF OF THE FORMULA OF HUMANITY. Adam Cureton

A CONTRACTUALIST READING OF KANT S PROOF OF THE FORMULA OF HUMANITY. Adam Cureton A CONTRACTUALIST READING OF KANT S PROOF OF THE FORMULA OF HUMANITY Adam Cureton Abstract: Kant offers the following argument for the Formula of Humanity: Each rational agent necessarily conceives of her

More information

Harman s Moral Relativism

Harman s Moral Relativism Harman s Moral Relativism Jordan Wolf March 17, 2010 Word Count: 2179 (including body, footnotes, and title) 1 1 Introduction In What is Moral Relativism? and Moral Relativism Defended, 1 Gilbert Harman,

More information

Democracy and epistemology: a reply to Talisse

Democracy and epistemology: a reply to Talisse Democracy and epistemology: a reply to Talisse Annabelle Lever * Department of Political Science, University of Geneva, Switzerland Forthcoming in Critical Review of Social and Political Philosophy, Spring

More information

DOES CONSEQUENTIALISM DEMAND TOO MUCH?

DOES CONSEQUENTIALISM DEMAND TOO MUCH? DOES CONSEQUENTIALISM DEMAND TOO MUCH? Shelly Kagan Introduction, H. Gene Blocker A NUMBER OF CRITICS have pointed to the intuitively immoral acts that Utilitarianism (especially a version of it known

More information

NOT SO PROMISING AFTER ALL: EVALUATOR-RELATIVE TELEOLOGY AND COMMON-SENSE MORALITY

NOT SO PROMISING AFTER ALL: EVALUATOR-RELATIVE TELEOLOGY AND COMMON-SENSE MORALITY NOT SO PROMISING AFTER ALL: EVALUATOR-RELATIVE TELEOLOGY AND COMMON-SENSE MORALITY by MARK SCHROEDER Abstract: Douglas Portmore has recently argued in this journal for a promising result that combining

More information

in Social Science Encyclopedia (Routledge, forthcoming, 2006). Consequentialism (Blackwell Publishers, forthcoming, 2006)

in Social Science Encyclopedia (Routledge, forthcoming, 2006). Consequentialism (Blackwell Publishers, forthcoming, 2006) in Social Science Encyclopedia (Routledge, forthcoming, 2006). Consequentialism Ethics in Practice, 3 rd edition, edited by Hugh LaFollette (Blackwell Publishers, forthcoming, 2006) Peter Vallentyne, University

More information

Received: 30 August 2007 / Accepted: 16 November 2007 / Published online: 28 December 2007 # Springer Science + Business Media B.V.

Received: 30 August 2007 / Accepted: 16 November 2007 / Published online: 28 December 2007 # Springer Science + Business Media B.V. Acta anal. (2007) 22:267 279 DOI 10.1007/s12136-007-0012-y What Is Entitlement? Albert Casullo Received: 30 August 2007 / Accepted: 16 November 2007 / Published online: 28 December 2007 # Springer Science

More information

TWO NO, THREE DOGMAS OF PHILOSOPHICAL THEOLOGY

TWO NO, THREE DOGMAS OF PHILOSOPHICAL THEOLOGY 1 TWO NO, THREE DOGMAS OF PHILOSOPHICAL THEOLOGY 1.0 Introduction. John Mackie argued that God's perfect goodness is incompatible with his failing to actualize the best world that he can actualize. And

More information

PARFIT'S MISTAKEN METAETHICS Michael Smith

PARFIT'S MISTAKEN METAETHICS Michael Smith PARFIT'S MISTAKEN METAETHICS Michael Smith In the first volume of On What Matters, Derek Parfit defends a distinctive metaethical view, a view that specifies the relationships he sees between reasons,

More information

* I am indebted to Jay Atlas and Robert Schwartz for their helpful criticisms

* I am indebted to Jay Atlas and Robert Schwartz for their helpful criticisms HEMPEL, SCHEFFLER, AND THE RAVENS 1 7 HEMPEL, SCHEFFLER, AND THE RAVENS * EMPEL has provided cogent reasons in support of the equivalence condition as a condition of adequacy for any definition of confirmation.?

More information

24.02 Moral Problems and the Good Life

24.02 Moral Problems and the Good Life MIT OpenCourseWare http://ocw.mit.edu 24.02 Moral Problems and the Good Life Fall 2008 For information about citing these materials or our Terms of Use, visit: http://ocw.mit.edu/terms. Three Moral Theories

More information

The view that all of our actions are done in self-interest is called psychological egoism.

The view that all of our actions are done in self-interest is called psychological egoism. Egoism For the last two classes, we have been discussing the question of whether any actions are really objectively right or wrong, independently of the standards of any person or group, and whether any

More information

Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords

Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords ISBN 9780198802693 Title The Value of Rationality Author(s) Ralph Wedgwood Book abstract Book keywords Rationality is a central concept for epistemology,

More information

Mind Association. Oxford University Press and Mind Association are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Mind.

Mind Association. Oxford University Press and Mind Association are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Mind. Mind Association Agent-Centred Restrictions, Rationality, and the Virtues Author(s): Samuel Scheffler Source: Mind, New Series, Vol. 94, No. 375 (Jul., 1985), pp. 409-419 Published by: Oxford University

More information

16RC1 Cahana. Medical professionalism: Where does it come from? A review of different moral theories. Alex Cahana. Introduction

16RC1 Cahana. Medical professionalism: Where does it come from? A review of different moral theories. Alex Cahana. Introduction 16RC1 Cahana Medical professionalism: Where does it come from? A review of different moral theories Alex Cahana Department of Anaesthesiology and Pain Medicine, Department Bioethics & Humanities University

More information

Divine command theory

Divine command theory Divine command theory Today we will be discussing divine command theory. But first I will give a (very) brief overview of the discipline of philosophy. Why do this? One of the functions of an introductory

More information

DEONTOLOGY AND ECONOMICS. John Broome

DEONTOLOGY AND ECONOMICS. John Broome DEONTOLOGY AND ECONOMICS John Broome I am very grateful to Shelly Kagan for extremely penetrating comments. Abstract. In The Moral Dimension, Amitai Etzioni claims that people often act for moral motives,

More information

EUROANESTHESIA 2007 Munich, Germany, 9-12 June 2007

EUROANESTHESIA 2007 Munich, Germany, 9-12 June 2007 EUROANESTHESIA 2007 Munich, Germany, 9-12 June 2007 WHERE DO THE PRINCIPLES OF BIOMEDICAL ETHICS COME FROM? 16RC1 ALEX CAHANA Postoperative and Interventional Pain Program, Department Anesthesiology, Pharmacology

More information

SPS103 LAW AND ETHICS

SPS103 LAW AND ETHICS SPS103 LAW AND ETHICS Full Course Title: Law and Ethics Pravo i etika Course Code: Course Level/BiH cycle: SPS103 I cycle; 1 st year ECTS credit value: 6 Student work-load: For the whole semester: Lectures

More information

WHY THERE REALLY ARE NO IRREDUCIBLY NORMATIVE PROPERTIES

WHY THERE REALLY ARE NO IRREDUCIBLY NORMATIVE PROPERTIES WHY THERE REALLY ARE NO IRREDUCIBLY NORMATIVE PROPERTIES Bart Streumer b.streumer@rug.nl In David Bakhurst, Brad Hooker and Margaret Little (eds.), Thinking About Reasons: Essays in Honour of Jonathan

More information

TWO APPROACHES TO INSTRUMENTAL RATIONALITY

TWO APPROACHES TO INSTRUMENTAL RATIONALITY TWO APPROACHES TO INSTRUMENTAL RATIONALITY AND BELIEF CONSISTENCY BY JOHN BRUNERO JOURNAL OF ETHICS & SOCIAL PHILOSOPHY VOL. 1, NO. 1 APRIL 2005 URL: WWW.JESP.ORG COPYRIGHT JOHN BRUNERO 2005 I N SPEAKING

More information

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea. Book reviews World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Naturalism, by Michael C. Rea. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2004, viii + 245 pp., $24.95. This is a splendid book. Its ideas are bold and

More information

SUNK COSTS. Robert Bass Department of Philosophy Coastal Carolina University Conway, SC

SUNK COSTS. Robert Bass Department of Philosophy Coastal Carolina University Conway, SC SUNK COSTS Robert Bass Department of Philosophy Coastal Carolina University Conway, SC 29528 rbass@coastal.edu ABSTRACT Decision theorists generally object to honoring sunk costs that is, treating the

More information

Sidgwick on Practical Reason

Sidgwick on Practical Reason Sidgwick on Practical Reason ONORA O NEILL 1. How many methods? IN THE METHODS OF ETHICS Henry Sidgwick distinguishes three methods of ethics but (he claims) only two conceptions of practical reason. This

More information

Happiness and Personal Growth: Dial.

Happiness and Personal Growth: Dial. TitleKant's Concept of Happiness: Within Author(s) Hirose, Yuzo Happiness and Personal Growth: Dial Citation Philosophy, Psychology, and Compara 43-49 Issue Date 2010-03-31 URL http://hdl.handle.net/2433/143022

More information

Final Paper. May 13, 2015

Final Paper. May 13, 2015 24.221 Final Paper May 13, 2015 Determinism states the following: given the state of the universe at time t 0, denoted S 0, and the conjunction of the laws of nature, L, the state of the universe S at

More information

Ethics is subjective.

Ethics is subjective. Introduction Scientific Method and Research Ethics Ethical Theory Greg Bognar Stockholm University September 22, 2017 Ethics is subjective. If ethics is subjective, then moral claims are subjective in

More information

In-Class Kant Review Dialogue 1

In-Class Kant Review Dialogue 1 1 Kant Review Dialogue 1 Micah Tillman 05 April, 2010, slightly revised 18 March, 2011 Tedrick: Hey Kant! In-Class Kant Review Dialogue 1 Why, hello there Fredward. Tedrick: It s Tedrick. Fredward is my

More information

The Prospective View of Obligation

The Prospective View of Obligation The Prospective View of Obligation Please do not cite or quote without permission. 8-17-09 In an important new work, Living with Uncertainty, Michael Zimmerman seeks to provide an account of the conditions

More information

Understanding Truth Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002

Understanding Truth Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002 1 Symposium on Understanding Truth By Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002 2 Precis of Understanding Truth Scott Soames Understanding Truth aims to illuminate

More information

What Lurks Beneath the Integrity Objection. Bernard Williams s alienation and integrity arguments against consequentialism have

What Lurks Beneath the Integrity Objection. Bernard Williams s alienation and integrity arguments against consequentialism have What Lurks Beneath the Integrity Objection Bernard Williams s alienation and integrity arguments against consequentialism have served as the point of departure for much of the most interesting work that

More information

Against Maximizing Act - Consequentialism

Against Maximizing Act - Consequentialism Against Maximizing Act - Consequentialism Forthcoming in Moral Theories (edited by Jamie Dreier, Blackwell Publishers, 2004) 1. Introduction Maximizing act consequentialism holds that actions are morally

More information

Unifying the Categorical Imperative* Marcus Arvan University of Tampa

Unifying the Categorical Imperative* Marcus Arvan University of Tampa Unifying the Categorical Imperative* Marcus Arvan University of Tampa [T]he concept of freedom constitutes the keystone of the whole structure of a system of pure reason [and] this idea reveals itself

More information

Kant The Grounding of the Metaphysics of Morals (excerpts) 1 PHIL101 Prof. Oakes. Section IV: What is it worth? Reading IV.2.

Kant The Grounding of the Metaphysics of Morals (excerpts) 1 PHIL101 Prof. Oakes. Section IV: What is it worth? Reading IV.2. Kant The Grounding of the Metaphysics of Morals (excerpts) 1 PHIL101 Prof. Oakes Section IV: What is it worth? Reading IV.2 Kant s analysis of the good differs in scope from Aristotle s in two ways. In

More information

what makes reasons sufficient?

what makes reasons sufficient? Mark Schroeder University of Southern California August 2, 2010 what makes reasons sufficient? This paper addresses the question: what makes reasons sufficient? and offers the answer, being at least as

More information

How should I live? I should do whatever brings about the most pleasure (or, at least, the most good)

How should I live? I should do whatever brings about the most pleasure (or, at least, the most good) How should I live? I should do whatever brings about the most pleasure (or, at least, the most good) Suppose that some actions are right, and some are wrong. What s the difference between them? What makes

More information

Annotated List of Ethical Theories

Annotated List of Ethical Theories Annotated List of Ethical Theories The following list is selective, including only what I view as the major theories. Entries in bold face have been especially influential. Recommendations for additions

More information

Lecture 6 Workable Ethical Theories I. Based on slides 2011 Pearson Education, Inc. Publishing as Pearson Addison-Wesley

Lecture 6 Workable Ethical Theories I. Based on slides 2011 Pearson Education, Inc. Publishing as Pearson Addison-Wesley Lecture 6 Workable Ethical Theories I Participation Quiz Pick an answer between A E at random. (thanks to Rodrigo for suggesting this quiz) Ethical Egoism Achievement of your happiness is the only moral

More information

CLIMBING THE MOUNTAIN SUMMARY CHAPTER 1 REASONS. 1 Practical Reasons

CLIMBING THE MOUNTAIN SUMMARY CHAPTER 1 REASONS. 1 Practical Reasons CLIMBING THE MOUNTAIN SUMMARY CHAPTER 1 REASONS 1 Practical Reasons We are the animals that can understand and respond to reasons. Facts give us reasons when they count in favour of our having some belief

More information

David Ethics Bites is a series of interviews on applied ethics, produced in association with The Open University.

David Ethics Bites is a series of interviews on applied ethics, produced in association with The Open University. Ethics Bites What s Wrong With Killing? David Edmonds This is Ethics Bites, with me David Edmonds. Warburton And me Warburton. David Ethics Bites is a series of interviews on applied ethics, produced in

More information

Molinism and divine prophecy of free actions

Molinism and divine prophecy of free actions Molinism and divine prophecy of free actions GRAHAM OPPY School of Philosophical, Historical and International Studies, Monash University, Clayton Campus, Wellington Road, Clayton VIC 3800 AUSTRALIA Graham.Oppy@monash.edu

More information

Ethical Theory for Catholic Professionals

Ethical Theory for Catholic Professionals The Linacre Quarterly Volume 53 Number 1 Article 9 February 1986 Ethical Theory for Catholic Professionals James F. Drane Follow this and additional works at: http://epublications.marquette.edu/lnq Recommended

More information

Historic Roots. o St. Paul gives biblical support for it in Romans 2, where a law is said to be written in the heart of the gentiles.

Historic Roots. o St. Paul gives biblical support for it in Romans 2, where a law is said to be written in the heart of the gentiles. Historic Roots Natural moral law has its roots in the classics; o Aristotle, in Nichomacheon Ethics suggests that natural justice is not the same as that which is just by law. Our laws may vary culturally

More information

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori PHIL 83104 November 2, 2011 Both Boghossian and Harman address themselves to the question of whether our a priori knowledge can be explained in

More information

Are Humans Always Selfish? OR Is Altruism Possible?

Are Humans Always Selfish? OR Is Altruism Possible? Are Humans Always Selfish? OR Is Altruism Possible? This debate concerns the question as to whether all human actions are selfish actions or whether some human actions are done specifically to benefit

More information

KANTIAN ETHICS (Dan Gaskill)

KANTIAN ETHICS (Dan Gaskill) KANTIAN ETHICS (Dan Gaskill) German philosopher Immanuel Kant (1724-1804) was an opponent of utilitarianism. Basic Summary: Kant, unlike Mill, believed that certain types of actions (including murder,

More information

Evaluating actions The principle of utility Strengths Criticisms Act vs. rule

Evaluating actions The principle of utility Strengths Criticisms Act vs. rule UTILITARIAN ETHICS Evaluating actions The principle of utility Strengths Criticisms Act vs. rule A dilemma You are a lawyer. You have a client who is an old lady who owns a big house. She tells you that

More information

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction Kent State University BIBLID [0873-626X (2014) 39; pp. 139-145] Abstract The causal theory of reference (CTR) provides a well-articulated and widely-accepted account

More information

AN OUTLINE OF CRITICAL THINKING

AN OUTLINE OF CRITICAL THINKING AN OUTLINE OF CRITICAL THINKING LEVELS OF INQUIRY 1. Information: correct understanding of basic information. 2. Understanding basic ideas: correct understanding of the basic meaning of key ideas. 3. Probing:

More information

Tuesday, September 2, Idealism

Tuesday, September 2, Idealism Idealism Enlightenment Puzzle How do these fit into a scientific picture of the world? Norms Necessity Universality Mind Idealism The dominant 19th-century response: often today called anti-realism Everything

More information

Reply to Gauthier and Gibbard

Reply to Gauthier and Gibbard Reply to Gauthier and Gibbard The Harvard community has made this article openly available. Please share how this access benefits you. Your story matters Citation Scanlon, Thomas M. 2003. Reply to Gauthier

More information

Legal Positivism: the Separation and Identification theses are true.

Legal Positivism: the Separation and Identification theses are true. PHL271 Handout 3: Hart on Legal Positivism 1 Legal Positivism Revisited HLA Hart was a highly sophisticated philosopher. His defence of legal positivism marked a watershed in 20 th Century philosophy of

More information

DISCUSSION PRACTICAL POLITICS AND PHILOSOPHICAL INQUIRY: A NOTE

DISCUSSION PRACTICAL POLITICS AND PHILOSOPHICAL INQUIRY: A NOTE Practical Politics and Philosophical Inquiry: A Note Author(s): Dale Hall and Tariq Modood Reviewed work(s): Source: The Philosophical Quarterly, Vol. 29, No. 117 (Oct., 1979), pp. 340-344 Published by:

More information

Kant. Deontological Ethics

Kant. Deontological Ethics Kant 1 Deontological Ethics An action's moral value is determined by the nature of the action itself and the agent's motive DE contrasts with Utilitarianism which says that the goal or consequences of

More information

Deontological Ethics. Kant. Rules for Kant. Right Action

Deontological Ethics. Kant. Rules for Kant. Right Action Deontological Ethics Kant An action's moral value is determined by the nature of the action itself and the agent's motive DE contrasts with Utilitarianism which says that the goal or consequences of an

More information

PROFESSIONAL ETHICS IN SCIENCE AND ENGINEERING

PROFESSIONAL ETHICS IN SCIENCE AND ENGINEERING PROFESSIONAL ETHICS IN SCIENCE AND ENGINEERING CD5590 LECTURE 1 Gordana Dodig-Crnkovic Department of Computer Science and Engineering Mälardalen University 2005 1 Course Preliminaries Identifying Moral

More information

Reactions & Debate. Non-Convergent Truth

Reactions & Debate. Non-Convergent Truth Reactions & Debate Non-Convergent Truth Response to Arnold Burms. Disagreement, Perspectivism and Consequentialism. Ethical Perspectives 16 (2009): 155-163. In Disagreement, Perspectivism and Consequentialism,

More information

What God Could Have Made

What God Could Have Made 1 What God Could Have Made By Heimir Geirsson and Michael Losonsky I. Introduction Atheists have argued that if there is a God who is omnipotent, omniscient and omnibenevolent, then God would have made

More information

A CONSEQUENTIALIST RESPONSE TO THE DEMANDINGNESS OBJECTION Nicholas R. Baker, Lee University THE DEMANDS OF ACT CONSEQUENTIALISM

A CONSEQUENTIALIST RESPONSE TO THE DEMANDINGNESS OBJECTION Nicholas R. Baker, Lee University THE DEMANDS OF ACT CONSEQUENTIALISM 1 A CONSEQUENTIALIST RESPONSE TO THE DEMANDINGNESS OBJECTION Nicholas R. Baker, Lee University INTRODUCTION We usually believe that morality has limits; that is, that there is some limit to what morality

More information

GS SCORE ETHICS - A - Z. Notes

GS SCORE ETHICS - A - Z.   Notes ETHICS - A - Z Absolutism Act-utilitarianism Agent-centred consideration Agent-neutral considerations : This is the view, with regard to a moral principle or claim, that it holds everywhere and is never

More information

Dignity, Contractualism and Consequentialism

Dignity, Contractualism and Consequentialism Dignity, Contractualism and Consequentialism DAVID CUMMISKEY Bates College Kantian respect for persons is based on the special status and dignity of humanity. There are, however, at least three distinct

More information

On the Relevance of Ignorance to the Demands of Morality 1

On the Relevance of Ignorance to the Demands of Morality 1 3 On the Relevance of Ignorance to the Demands of Morality 1 Geoffrey Sayre-McCord It is impossible to overestimate the amount of stupidity in the world. Bernard Gert 2 Introduction In Morality, Bernard

More information

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View Chapter 98 Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View Lars Leeten Universität Hildesheim Practical thinking is a tricky business. Its aim will never be fulfilled unless influence on practical

More information

The ontology of human rights and obligations

The ontology of human rights and obligations The ontology of human rights and obligations Åsa Burman Department of Philosophy, Stockholm University asa.burman@philosophy.su.se If we are going to make sense of the notion of rights we have to answer

More information

FREEDOM AND THE SOURCE OF VALUE: KORSGAARD AND WOOD ON KANT S FORMULA OF HUMANITY CHRISTOPHER ARROYO

FREEDOM AND THE SOURCE OF VALUE: KORSGAARD AND WOOD ON KANT S FORMULA OF HUMANITY CHRISTOPHER ARROYO Published by Blackwell Publishing Ltd, 9600 Garsington Road, Oxford OX4 2DQ, UK, and 350 Main Street, Malden, MA 02148, USA METAPHILOSOPHY Vol. 42, No. 4, July 2011 0026-1068 FREEDOM AND THE SOURCE OF

More information

In essence, Swinburne's argument is as follows:

In essence, Swinburne's argument is as follows: 9 [nt J Phil Re115:49-56 (1984). Martinus Nijhoff Publishers, The Hague. Printed in the Netherlands. NATURAL EVIL AND THE FREE WILL DEFENSE PAUL K. MOSER Loyola University of Chicago Recently Richard Swinburne

More information

Must Consequentialists Kill?

Must Consequentialists Kill? Must Consequentialists Kill? Kieran Setiya MIT December 10, 2017 (Draft; do not cite without permission) It is widely held that, in ordinary circumstances, you should not kill one stranger in order to

More information

Contractualism and Justification 1. T. M. Scanlon. I first began thinking of contractualism as a moral theory 38 years ago, in May of

Contractualism and Justification 1. T. M. Scanlon. I first began thinking of contractualism as a moral theory 38 years ago, in May of Contractualism and Justification 1 T. M. Scanlon I first began thinking of contractualism as a moral theory 38 years ago, in May of 1979. The idea was not entirely original. I was of course familiar with

More information

DRAFT DO NOT CITE. Is Neo-Aristotelian Ethical Naturalism Compatible with Moral Universalism? A Response to Christopher Gowans

DRAFT DO NOT CITE. Is Neo-Aristotelian Ethical Naturalism Compatible with Moral Universalism? A Response to Christopher Gowans DRAFT DO NOT CITE Is Neo-Aristotelian Ethical Naturalism Compatible with Moral Universalism? A Response to Christopher Gowans 1. Introduction Max Parish University of Oklahoma Abstract: Neo-Aristotelian

More information

FISSION, FIRST PERSON THOUGHT, AND SUBJECT- BODY DUALISM* KIRK LUDWIG Indiana University ABSTRACT

FISSION, FIRST PERSON THOUGHT, AND SUBJECT- BODY DUALISM* KIRK LUDWIG Indiana University ABSTRACT EuJAP Vol. 13, No. 1, 2017 UDK 1:159.923.2 141.112 164.031 FISSION, FIRST PERSON THOUGHT, AND SUBJECT- BODY DUALISM* KIRK LUDWIG Indiana University ABSTRACT In The Argument for Subject Body Dualism from

More information

A Coherent and Comprehensible Interpretation of Saul Smilansky s Dualism

A Coherent and Comprehensible Interpretation of Saul Smilansky s Dualism A Coherent and Comprehensible Interpretation of Saul Smilansky s Dualism Abstract Saul Smilansky s theory of free will and moral responsibility consists of two parts; dualism and illusionism. Dualism is

More information