Truth, Assertion, and the Horizontal: Frege on The Essence of Logic William W. Taschek

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Truth, Assertion, and the Horizontal: Frege on The Essence of Logic William W. Taschek"

Transcription

1 Truth, Assertion, and the Horizontal: Frege on The Essence of Logic William W. Taschek In the opening to his late essay, Der Gedanke, Frege asserts without qualification that the word true points the way for logic. But in a short piece from his Nachlass entitled My Basic Logical Insights, Frege writes that the word true makes an unsuccessful attempt to point to the essence of logic, asserting instead that what really pertains to logic lies not in the word true but in the assertoric force with which the sentence is uttered. Properly understanding what Frege takes to be at issue here is crucial for understanding his conception of logic and, in particular, what he takes to be its normative status vis-à-vis judgement, assertion, and inference. In this paper, I focus my attention on clarifying the latter claim and Frege s motivations for making it, exposing what I take to be a fundamental tension in Frege s conception of logic. Finally, I discuss whether Frege s deployment of the horizontal in his mature Begriffsschrift helps to resolve this tension. 1. Logic: truth and assertoric force Anyone having more than a superficial acquaintance with the writings of Gottlob Frege will be familiar with a number of passages in which he identifies logic as a science essentially and distinctively concerned with truth. They range from fairly early in his career to quite late. A passage from the earlier of two posthumously published manuscripts that Frege labelled Logic is already characteristic. 1 Frege begins by stating that the task of logic is to establish laws of valid inference not a surprising claim for the author of the recently published Begriffsschrift (Frege 1879). This claim immediately leads him to contrast the subject matter of logic with that of psychology, at which point he writes: there is a sharp divide between these disciplines, and it is marked by the word true. Psychology is concerned with truth in the way every science is, in that its goal is to extend the domain of truths; but in the field it investigates 1 Frege [between 1879 and 1891]. But also compare Frege 1893, p. 202; 1897, pp. 126, 227 8; 1918, p ; and 1919, pp All translations of Frege s work are from Beaney 1997, except where stated otherwise. Page numbers for quotations are in parentheses, following the quotation, and refer to the translated source. Dates appearing in square brackets are dates assigned by the editors of Frege s Nachlass. Mind, Vol April 2008 doi: /mind/fzn039 Taschek 2008

2 376 William W. Taschek it does not study the property true as, in its field, physics focuses on the properties heavy, warm, etc. This is what logic does. It would not perhaps be besides the mark to say that the laws of logic are nothing other than an unfolding of the content of the word true. Anyone who failed to grasp the meaning of this word what marks it off from others cannot attain to a clear idea of what the task of logic is. (p. 3) Given the steady supply of passages similar to this one, it would hardly seem risky to conclude that for Frege the notion of truth plays an essential role in characterizing what is distinctive about logic. But as safe as this claim in all its schematic vagueness might at first appear, Frege s Nachlass contains an important set of remarks that casts serious doubt on whether, for Frege, the notion of truth does or, indeed, can play such a central role in characterizing the essence of logic. The remarks occur in the set of jottings to which the editors of the Nachlass assign the date Frege himself entitled them, My Basic Logical Insights, and beneath this title he wrote, The following may be of some use as a key to the understanding of my results (Frege 1915, p. 322). The manuscript is striking as a whole, but for the time being consider the following central passage. After arguing that attaching the words is true to a sentential clause as predicate adds nothing to the thought expressed by the original sentence, Frege writes: This may lead us to think that the word true has no sense at all. But in that case a sentence in which true occurred as a predicate would have no sense either. All one can say is: the word true has a sense that contributes nothing to the sense of the whole sentence in which it occurs as predicate. But it is precisely for this reason that this word seems fitted to indicate the essence of logic. Because of the particular sense that it carried, any other adjective would be less suitable for this purpose. So the word true seems to make the impossible possible: namely, to allow what corresponds to the assertoric force to assume the form of a contribution to the thought. And although this attempt miscarries, or rather through the very fact that it miscarries, it indicates what is characteristic of logic. And this, from what we have said, seems something essentially different from what is characteristic of aesthetics and ethics. For there is no doubt that the word beautiful actually does indicate the essence of aesthetics, as does good that of ethics, whereas true only makes an abortive attempt to indicate the essence of logic, since what logic is really concerned with is not contained in the word true at all but in the assertoric force with which a sentence is uttered. (p. 323) If we are to take these remarks seriously, then contrary to what we were led to believe by the various passages alluded to earlier it would seem that logic is not in its essence concerned with what is contained in

3 Truth, Assertion, and the Horizontal 377 the word true, but with the assertoric force with which a sentence is uttered. If these remarks do not explicitly contradict Frege s earlier (and later) claims, then, at the very least, they raise serious interpretive difficulties about how we are to reconcile them with the various truth-orientated pronouncements concerning the goal, the task, the aim, and essence of logic that Frege makes both before and after these remarks were written. How, for example, are we to understand Frege s repeated assertion that the laws of logic are the laws of truth? Moreover, what sense are we to make of his repeated analogy between the way in which logic is distinctively concerned with truth and the way in which physics is distinctively concerned with such properties as heat and weight? Finally, and perhaps most importantly, if the word true does not in fact indicate the essence of logic, then how are we now to assess Frege s oft-repeated charge that psychologism s failure lies precisely in its inability to respect the central and distinctive role that truth plays in logic? Indeed, if we locate the essence of logic in assertoric force, will we not thereby have smoothed the way for a psychologistic understanding of logic? Of course, we always have the option of dismissing Frege s remarks in My Basic Logical Insights as an aberration. Frege was always struggling against what he viewed as the logical imperfections of ordinary language to find a way to articulate his views about logic. And perhaps, in the end, Frege found the strategy he adopted here misguided. After all, we do not find Frege, in the later Der Gedanke, insisting that it is not truth but assertoric force that best indicates the essence of logic. There, rather, he appears to revert to his truth-orientated way of characterizing that essence. 2 Nevertheless, I think it would be a serious mistake to dismiss these important remarks. First of all, as Frege goes on to say a bit further on in the My Basic Logical Insights manuscript, it is precisely due to the logical imperfection of ordinary language that we seem to find ourselves obliged to deploy the word true. While it may be that its use cannot precisely capture the distinctive concern of logic, it would seem that it is the best tool we currently have to gesture toward what really does indicate the essence of logic the assertoric force with which a sentence is uttered. Frege writes: How is it then that this word true, though it seems devoid of content, cannot be dispensed with? Would it not be possible, at least in laying the foundations of logic, to avoid this word altogether, when it can only create 2 Frege 1918, see especially pp And the same goes for his even later remarks in the Notes for Ludwig Darmstaedter, Frege 1919, especially pp

4 378 William W. Taschek confusion? That we cannot do so is due to the imperfection of language. If our language were logically more perfect, we would perhaps have no further need for logic, or we might read it off from the language. But we are far from being in such a position. Work in logic just is, to a large extent, a struggle against the logical defects of language, and yet language remains for us an indispensable tool. Only after our logical work has been completed shall we possess a more perfect instrument. (p. 323) It would seem, then, that Frege felt that he had little choice but to use and to emphasize the centrality of the word true for logic. And so it is no surprise that he does so again in Der Gedanke even if the remarks in My Basic Logical Insights express what Frege took to be a deep insight about the nature of logic. But why did he there not just talk about assertoric force as he did in My Basic Logical Insights? My own surmise is that Frege felt that he had not yet found a way to say that logic s principal concern is with assertoric force that he felt would not be misunderstood as introducing an element of psychologism. He found the rhetoric of truth in this connection more compelling, perhaps essential especially in the context of his anti-psychologistic polemics, which, it is worth noting, provide the context for nearly all of the remarks in which he writes that the essence of logic is bound up with the notion of truth. A second reason for not dismissing Frege s remarks in My Basic Logical Insights is that this is not in fact the only place in which he suggests that the essence of logic is centrally bound up with assertoric force. With considerably less fanfare, he comes very close to making the same claim in the later Logic manuscript, where he writes: If I assert that the sum of 2 and 3 is 5, then I thereby assert that it is true that 2 and 3 make 5. So I assert that it is true that my idea of Cologne Cathedral agrees with reality, if I assert that it agrees with reality. Therefore, it is really by using the form of an assertoric sentence that we assert the truth, and to do this we do not need the word true. Indeed, we can say that even where we use the form of expression it is true that the essential thing is really the assertoric form of the sentence. (pp ) Essential, that is, so far as logic is concerned. The move here from reflection on the redundancy property of the truth predicate to a focus on the importance and fundamental status of assertion clearly anticipates the later discussion. 3 3 While it is true that in this passage Frege mentions the assertoric form of the sentence and not the assertoric force with which it is uttered, and while it is also true that in his later writings Frege emphasized that assertoric form does not suffice for assertion, he nevertheless did often write as if the assertoric form of an uttered sentence contained assertoric force unless this was somehow cancelled. Cf. for example Frege 1892, p. 158, and 1918, p This was more common earlier in his career.

5 Truth, Assertion, and the Horizontal 379 Thirdly, anyone even superficially acquainted with Frege s reflections on logic and its axiomatic formulation will have been struck by his unwavering insistence from the Begriffsschrift on that in so far as it is the goal of logic to articulate the laws of valid inference, logic must concern itself essentially with judged or asserted contents. 4 To be a wellformed Begriffsschriftsatz and therefore a potential premiss or conclusion in any inference requires being prefaced with a judgement stroke. 5 This suggests that from the very outset of his career Frege took the twin notions of judgement and assertion to play a central role in his understanding of that with which logic is essentially concerned. It is also noteworthy that in the Begriffsschrift, and the several early essays in which he explains and defends the aims and significance of that work, the notion of truth is barely mentioned. 6 And finally, despite Frege s repeated appeal to the notion of truth in characterizing the essence of logic, it is noteworthy that from 1897 on, but probably as early as 1891, Frege began to view the predicate is true as in various ways anomalous, if not downright problematic. Indeed, eventually, Frege came to think of the truth values the True and the False as objects that are the Bedeutungen of true and false sentences, respectively. In any case, given the problematic status of the word true for Frege, we need to be extremely cautious in assessing the import of the various truth-orientated characterizations of the essence of logic that Frege offers. 7 4 Even as late as 1923, two years before he died, in the Nachlass fragment Logical Generality Frege wrote emphatically: only a thought acknowledged as true can be made the premiss of an inference (Frege, [not before 1923], p. 261). 5 Cf. Frege 1893, pp Of course logic is also obliged to recognize and concern itself with unasserted contents, when they occur as parts of compound thoughts. But this is only because this is required to do justice to the logical assessments we make of our judgements, assertions, and inferences. 6 For a nice overview of the development of Frege s views on logic, the shifting vocabulary that he uses to present those views, and the central role that assertion plays throughout, see Sluga In addition to arguing (i) that the relation of truth to a thought is that of a Bedeutung to a sense (cf. Frege 1891, 1892, 1893, 1902, 1904, 1906c, 1914, 1919), we find him arguing (ii) that attaching the words is true to a sentential clause as predicate as, for example, in It is true that seawater is salty adds nothing to the thought expressed by the sentence Seawater is salty alone (cf. Frege 1893, 1906c, 1914, 1915, 1918), (iii) that the word true is sui generis and indefinable (cf. Frege 1897, 1918), and indeed, (iv) that it is a mistake to think that truth is a property of sentences or thoughts at all (cf. Frege 1918, but especially 1914, pp. 234). Each of these claims raises delicate issues, and the story about how they are all supposed to fit together is quite complicated. In what follows, I will have the opportunity to touch upon some of these claims, though, not in as much detail as they deserve. For more extended discussions of these issues, see Burge 1986 and 2005b, and Ricketts 1996.

6 380 William W. Taschek All in all, then, it seems to me that we have compelling reasons to take the remarks in My Basic Logical Insights very seriously. Indeed, I believe that they present a unique insight into Frege s distinctive understanding of the nature and status of logic. What remains to be seen is whether, or to what extent, we can reconcile these remarks with his other, truth-orientated pronouncements about the essence of logic. My own view, as will become evident, is that while we can go quite a ways toward reconciling them, in the end these prima facie conflicting pronouncements are symptomatic of a deep tension in Frege s overall conception of logic. 2. The status of logic: descriptive and normative To see what I have in mind, we need to remind ourselves of another prima facie dichotomy in the way that Frege characterizes the nature and status of logic. On the one hand, as is now well known, Frege views logic as a descriptive science, though, to be sure the maximally general science. As Frege says in the opening paragraph of Der Gedanke, The word law is used in two senses. When we speak of moral or civil laws we mean prescriptions, which ought to be obeyed but with which actual occurrences are not always in conformity. Laws of nature are general features of what happens in nature, and occurrences in nature are always in accordance with them. It is rather in this sense that I speak of laws of truth. Here of course, it is not a matter of what happens but of what is. From the laws of truth there follow prescriptions about asserting, thinking, judging, inferring. (p. 325) This passage suggests that, as with any science, the aim of logic is to identify a finite set of basic laws substantive generalizations appropriate to its subject matter, and to derive from these any other laws applying to its domain. The axioms of Frege s Begriffsschrift are these basic laws. 8 What distinguishes logic from other sciences is not, of course, that it has as its aim the establishment of such general truths for that is the aim of any science whatsoever. Nor are the laws of logic distinguished from other laws by containing some specialized or proprietary vocabulary that segregates its subject matter from that of other sciences; for the only (ineliminable) vocabulary needed to express logical laws is a vocabulary that will be required to express the laws of any 8 I use the italicized Begriffsschrift to denote Frege s early work. I use the unitalicized Begriffsschrift to refer to Frege s formal system(s) distinguishing the early Begriffsschrift, as presented in the Begriffsschrift from the mature Begriffsschrift introduced in Function and Concept and fully articulated in the Grundgesetze.

7 Truth, Assertion, and the Horizontal 381 science whatever. 9 Rather, what distinguishes logic from other sciences is the fact that its laws are in no significant way restricted with respect to subject matter. The laws of logic are laws that hold of all reality, all of what is. There is no subject matter there is, so to speak, no truth that is not subsumed under the laws of logic; and it is in this sense that they count, for Frege, as the most general laws of truth (Wahrseins). The finer details of and motivations behind this universalist conception of logic have been well described and documented by others; so I will not pursue this further here. 10 It is also noteworthy, however, that in virtually every context in which Frege lays out this picture of logic as the maximally general descriptive science, we find him also insisting on the fundamentally normative character of logic. The last sentence of the passage from Der Gedanke quoted immediately above is characteristic: From the laws of truth there follow prescriptions about asserting, thinking, judging, inferring. Here is how Frege puts it in the later Logic manuscript: Like ethics, logic can also be characterized as a normative science. How must I think in order to reach the goal, truth? We expect logic to give us the answer to this question, but we do not demand that it should go into what is particular to each branch of knowledge and its subject matter. On the contrary, the task we assign logic is only that of saying what holds with the utmost generality for all thinking, whatever its subject matter. We must assume the rules for our thinking and for our holding something true are prescribed by the laws of truth. The former are given along with the latter. (p. 228) Of course, to claim that the laws of logic articulate what holds with the utmost generality for all thinking, whatever its subject matter (my emphasis) is, as Frege fully realizes, potentially quite misleading. Unless we keep squarely in mind that what is at issue here is what holds prescriptively for all thinking, we are likely to take the laws of logic to be descriptive laws of thinking and, thereby, fall into the morass of psychologism. So, as Frege points out later in this same text, if we call [the laws of logic] laws of thought, or, better, laws of judgement, we must not forget we are concerned here with laws which, like principles of morals or laws of the state, prescribe how we are to act, and do not, like laws of nature, define the actual course of events. Thinking, as it actually takes place, is not always in agreement with the laws of logic any more than people s actual behaviour is always in agreement with the moral law. (pp ) 9 There is, possibly, a noteworthy exception here. It is far from clear that every science requires names of courses-of-values. 10 Cf. especially van Heijenoort 1967, Ricketts 1986 and 1996, and Goldfarb 2001.

8 382 William W. Taschek Notice first the interesting shift in emphasis here from characterizing the laws of logic as prescriptive laws of thinking to prescriptive laws of judgement. This is noteworthy because it suggests a connection a connection I will be emphasizing later between Frege s commitment to viewing logic as essentially normative and his claim in My Basic Logical Insights that the essence of logic is best indicated not by the word true but by reflecting on the assertoric force with which sentences are uttered. Since assertion just is, for Frege, the public manifestation of judgement, and since logic, understood now in its normative guise, articulates prescriptive laws governing judgement and, so, assertion Frege s claim that the essence of logic is located in assertoric force can be understood as, in effect, suggesting that the essence of logic is to be found in its normative role vis-à-vis judgement and assertion and not, or at least not exclusively, in its descriptive role. But I am getting ahead of myself here. If we are properly to appreciate Frege s understanding of the normative status of logic, there are two intimately related issues about which we need to get clearer. On the one hand, we need to understand the sense in which Frege thought that the relevant prescriptions follow from, as he sometimes puts it, the laws of logic qua descriptive generalizations. On the other hand, we need a clearer sense of the distinctive kind of normative force that Frege understood the laws of logic have over judgement and inference. At first glance, it can look as if Frege thought that there is nothing distinctively prescriptive about logical laws as such, as opposed, say, to the laws of any other science. For example, Frege says in a passage from the later Logic manuscript, almost immediately following the last quote, that We could with equal justice think of laws of geometry and laws of physics as laws of thought or laws of judgement, namely as prescriptions to which our judgements must conform in a different domain if they are to remain in agreement with the truth. (p. 247) This suggests that Frege held that from any law, any general truth, there follows a prescription that one ought to think in accordance with it. In this case, logical laws are not distinctive in virtue of their issuing in prescriptions about how one ought to judge, but are distinctive only in virtue of the maximal generality of their subject matter and, so, only in the maximal scope of their prescriptive influence. A similar suggestion seems to be implicit in the following important passage from the Preface to the Grundgesetze: That the logical laws should be guiding principles for thought in the attainment of truth is generally admitted at the outset; but it is easily forgotten.

9 Truth, Assertion, and the Horizontal 383 The ambiguity of the word law is fatal here. In one sense it states what is, in the other it prescribes what should be. Only in the latter sense can the logical laws be called laws of thought, in laying down how one should think. Any law that states what is can be conceived as prescribing that one should think in accordance with it, and is therefore in that sense a law of thought. This holds for geometrical and physical laws no less than for logical ones. The latter then only deserve the name laws of thought with more right if it should be meant by this that they are the most general laws, which prescribe universally how one should think if one is to think at all. (p. 202) A bit later he adds: Anyone who has once recognized a law of truth has thereby also recognized a law that prescribes how judgements should be made, wherever, whenever, and by whomever they may be. (p. 204) From these passages, it would seem that Frege is suggesting that the normative status of the laws of logic, their normative authority over our thinking, is immediately consequent upon their status for us as general truths. In this respect, the normative authority that the laws of logic have over our thinking is not different in kind from that which derives from our acceptance of any law, whether in physics, geometry, or psychology. To be sure, there is a difference in scope, but not a difference in kind. If this is right, then the laws of logic cannot be distinguished from the laws of physics or, for that matter, any other special science on the grounds that the former are, apart from scope, in some distinctive sense prescriptive vis-à-vis judgement while the latter are not. 3. The distinctive normativity of logic Perhaps this is indeed Frege s view; there is certainly textual support for supposing so. However, I am inclined to think that this cannot be quite right. As the concluding remarks in the first of the two passages from the Grundgesetze just quoted reveal, Frege clearly thinks that the laws of logic do have a proprietary claim to the title laws of thought, conceived of normatively. The question, then, is whether Frege believed that this proprietary status is to be or even can be accounted for simply on the basis of what we might call logic s maximal descriptive scope. What the concluding remark of that passage says, recall, is that the laws of logic deserve to be called laws of thought (in the normative sense) with more right than, say, the laws of physics, only if they are taken to prescribe universally how one should think if one is to think at all (my emphasis). The implication here, I suggest, is that what is distinctive about logical laws in virtue of which they deserve to be called the laws

10 384 William W. Taschek of thought with more right than the laws of physics is not merely that they are maximally general in scope, but that in an important sense they issue in, while the laws of physics do not, constitutive norms of thinking as such. In suggesting that for Frege the norms of logic are constitutive norms of thinking as such, I am not suggesting that he held the absurd view that one cannot be counted as a thinker unless one s thoughts more importantly, one s judgements, assertions, and inferences accord with these norms. The second to last quotation above from the later Logic manuscript clearly rules this out. Rather, I am suggesting that, for Frege, if one is to count as a thinker at all, then one s judgements, assertions, and inferences must at the very least be subject to evaluation by the norms of logic. Judgements and, so also, assertions and inference are by their nature subject to evaluation by logical norms. Indeed, I would argue that the constitutive status that logical norms have for Frege vis-à-vis thinking as such has an even more profound dimension: to count as a thinker at all one must acknowledge the categorical normative authority that logic has over one s practice of judging, asserting, and inferring. For Frege, then, one s status as a thinker would be seriously compromised by a failure to acknowledge the categorical normative claim that logical principles have over one s thinking. To explicate with any precision what exactly this acknowledgement consists in would be a very tricky matter. For present purposes, however, the following clarificatory remarks should suffice to indicate what I have in mind. First of all, to acknowledge the categorical normative authority of logic over one s practice of judging, asserting, and inferring cannot consist in a judgement to the effect that such-and-such is a law of logic, or even in the judgement that the law is true, on pain of the sort of regress exposed by Lewis Carroll s (1895) parable of Achilles and the Tortoise. As we shall see, an issue closely related to this will come up again in what follows. In any case, it would be absurd to suppose that one s status as a thinker, in Frege s sense, required that one have already judged of the relevant logical norms that they are such. Rather, to acknowledge the categorical authority of logic will involve one s possessing a capacity to recognize when being sincere and reflective, and possibly with appropriate prompting logical mistakes both in one s own judgemental and inferential practice and that of others. Moreover, upon recognizing such a mistake in one s own case, one will feel an unconditional obligation to correct it. Thus, if one were to recognize or take oneself to recognize such a mistake in the case of another person, and if that person could not, even after appropriate prompting, be per-

11 Truth, Assertion, and the Horizontal 385 suaded to acknowledge it as a mistake a mistake with respect to which she felt an unconditional obligation to correct herself that would provide one with grounds to question that individual s status as a thinker. In the Preface to the Grundgesetze, for example, Frege proposes that if we were to confront anyone who appeared not to acknowledge the categorical normative claim on our thinking that issued from a law of logic, we should suppose that here we have a hitherto unknown kind of madness (Frege 1893, p. 203). 11 There is, however, another passage in the Preface to the Grundgesetze occurring toward the end of his principal argument against psychologism with respect to logic that might appear to cast doubt on my claim that Frege took logic to issue in constitutive norms vis-àvis judgement, assertion, and inference of the sort at issue here. He writes: Leaving aside logic, one can say: we are forced to make judgements by our nature and external circumstances, and if we make judgements, we cannot reject this law of identity, for example; we must recognize it if we are not to throw our thought into confusion and in the end renounce judgement altogether. I do not wish to either dispute or endorse this view and only remark that what we have here is not a logical implication. What is given is not a ground of being true, but of our holding as true. And furthermore, this impossibility of our rejecting the law does not prevent us from supposing that there are beings who do reject it; but it does prevent us from supposing that these being are right in doing so; it also prevents us from doubting whether we or they are right. (p. 204) The suggestion here that we cannot reject a logical principle without throwing thought into confusion and in the end renouncing judgement altogether appears to give expression to the very thesis about the constitutive nature of logic for thinking as such to which I have claimed Frege commits himself. But what is noteworthy about this passage is that Frege, rather than endorse it, remains explicitly agnostic about this sug- 11 An important issue in recent Frege scholarship concerns how we are best to understand Frege s claim that the basic laws of logic are self-evident and how we are to understand this selfevidence in such a way that we can see it as warranting our acceptance of these laws. At stake, of course, is the proper understanding of what Frege might have had in mind by his various and nonsystematic appeals to self-evidence here. See, for example, the discussions by Burge 1998, Jeshion 2001, Weiner 2004 in this journal. The proposal that, for Frege, to count as a thinker requires that one acknowledge the categorical normative authority of logic vis-à-vis judgement, assertion, and inference suggests that a proper account of the self-evidence to which Frege appeals will be one in which self-evidence is itself grounded in or explicated in terms of the constitutive requirement that one acknowledge the categorical normative authority of logic on one s own thinking. A proper explication of what this acknowledgement comes to would, I believe, help us to see how it grounds our commitment to the truth of the basic laws of logic. Unfortunately, developing this idea is not something I can pursue here.

12 386 William W. Taschek gestion, declining to endorse it. Moreover, he seems to suggest that there is nothing problematic in our imagining creatures that do reject logical principles. These two features of this passage might seem to suggest that we ought to be dubious about committing Frege to the constitutivity thesis. 12 A closer reading of the passage makes it clear, however, that the suggestion as issue here was introduced by Frege as a purely descriptive psychological hypothesis about our thinking and, as such, cannot plausibly be taken to give expression to the constitutivity thesis,. After all, the passage explicitly begins, Leaving logic aside. It is with respect to this suggestion qua descriptive claim about current human psychology that Frege declines to commit himself. In effect, Frege is asking: If we were to suppose it to be a psychological fact about our thinking that we cannot now fail to accept logical laws, then what would follow? What Frege says is that, even if this suggestion, as a descriptive psychological claim, were true for us, nothing would follow from it about whether or not there might be other thinking creatures who reject logical principles that we ourselves cannot. And this is certainly right. But surely, he insists, any such creature would at the very least nevertheless be mistaken. At which point he wryly remarks, If others dare to recognize and doubt a law [of truth] in the same breath, then it seems to me like trying to jump out of one s own skin, against which I can only urgently warn. Anyone who has once recognized a law of truth has thereby also recognized a law that prescribes how judgements should be made, wherever, whenever, and by whomever they may be made. (p. 204) 13 All of this shows that the passage in question cannot very plausibly be understood as one in which we find Frege declining to endorse the constitutivity claim. Indeed, Frege s final remark in the last quotation comes as close to expressing his commitment to the constitutivity claim as we are likely to want. For in it he seems precisely to be saying that to acknowledge a logical law is thereby to acknowledge the categorical normative authority of that law over judgement as such. If this is right, however, serious difficulties arise for the suggestion that the normative authority that the laws of logic have on our thinking cannot be distinguished in kind from the laws of physics or, for that matter, any other special science. First of all, it is implausible to view any prescriptions that issue from the laws of physics or geometry as constitutive of thinking in any analogous sense. Specifically, one s status 12 I want to thank Gary Ebbs for suggesting that I attend more carefully to this passage. 13 Cf. the discussion in Frege 1897, pp

13 Truth, Assertion, and the Horizontal 387 as a thinker is in no way compromised by failing to acknowledge the truth of a law of physics or even geometry. If we were to confront someone who failed to acknowledge the truth of some law of physics that we ourselves accepted, there is no temptation nor is it plausible to suppose Frege would be tempted to suggest that here we have a hitherto unknown type of madness. To be sure, if I do acknowledge the truth of a law of physics or, for that matter, of any other special science I do thereby find myself under an obligation to think in accordance with it. But what can this mean except that I am under a logical obligation to have my other judgements be consistent with this one and, in particular, to be willing to acknowledge as true all instances of the general claim? This, though, is an essentially logical obligation; it does not in any sense derive from the law of physics itself, independently of the normative demands of logic. The normative demands of logic must, so to speak, already be in place for there to be any obligation, once one has committed oneself to the truth of a laws of physics, to think in accordance with that law. The latter obligation presupposes wholly general logical obligations. I suggest, then, that Frege did take the normative status of the laws of logic to be distinct in kind from the normative status of laws in the specialized sciences and not merely distinct in scope. These last reflections show that there is, in fact, something quite peculiar, if not incoherent, in the idea that a constitutive prescription about how one ought to judge can be immediately grounded in our acceptance of any true generalization independently, that is, of our already acknowledging the normative demands logic places on our thinking. The problem for Frege is that this would seem to be just as true for those generalizations that he took to express logical laws, as it is for the laws of physics. On Frege s universalist conception of logic, when I accept a logical law, I acknowledge as true a substantive generalization. To be sure, it is maximally general with respect to subject matter. But so what? Here, as before, by judging the law as true, I find myself under an obligation to think in accordance with it. But again, there seems to be no way to understand this obligation except as grounded in a prior logical obligation to have all my other judgements be consistent with this one and, in particular, to accept all instances of this general truth. What, if anything, grounds this prior obligation? Here again, we cannot allow that it is itself grounded in my acceptance of some other substantive logical law on pain of the sort of regress exposed by Carroll s parable of Achilles and the Tortoise to which we have already alluded. Eventually, we must find ourselves acknowledging

14 388 William W. Taschek a commitment to a logical norm concerning judgements in effect, a rule of inference 14 where this commitment cannot itself consist in (or be grounded upon) our accepting as true some further substantive law. If this is right, then the prescriptive force of any substantive logical law must itself be viewed as grounded in our prior commitment to some fundamentally non-descriptive normative logical principles, which themselves are not grounded in our acceptance of any more fundamental substantive claim. Is this a problem for Frege? Yes and no. On the one hand, Frege was quite clear to distinguish rules of inference from logical axioms in his formal system. And it appears that he was also fairly clear about the ineliminability of rules of inference though, so far as I can tell, there is no place where he explicitly addresses this issue. 15 To this extent, then, he seems to have acknowledged and taken into account even if only inchoately an irreducible normative element in logic. Indeed, there are places in Frege s published work where he appears to commit himself more straightforwardly to the idea that the essence of logic is revealed, in the first instance, by reflecting on its constitutive normative status vis-à-vis our practice of judgement assertion, and inference. This is, perhaps, most readily seen in the context of the specific critique of psychologism that Frege mounts in the Preface to the Grundgesetze. In general, Frege s criticisms of psychologism consist in his pointing out how, in one way or another, a psychologisitic approach to logic fails to capture something that belongs to the essence of logic. In the Grundgesetze, he clearly takes himself to have shown that psychologism is committed to a conception of logical laws that is incapable of doing justice to the constitutive prescriptive role that the laws of logic play vis-à-vis thinking as such. In particular, psychologism cannot support a conception of judgement or assertion according to which they are constitutively subject to normative governance by the laws of logic in the way Frege conceived them to be. Rather, the psychologistic conception of logical law forces an assimilation of judgement and assertion to non-cognitive attitudes and their expression of the sort exemplified by matters of subjective taste and their expression in yuks and yums. 16 A psychologistic logician is committed to supposing that failure to acknowledge the categorical normative claim of a logical principle on 14 It is noteworthy that Frege s rules of inference are always couched in terms of assertions. The permissions they encode are explicitly restricted to expressions prefaced by the judgement stroke. 15 See for example Frege 1914, p This theme is also developed at length in Frege 1897, pp. 230ff. The discussion in Ricketts 1986 is especially helpful as well.

15 Truth, Assertion, and the Horizontal 389 one s judgement merely exposes a difference in psychological laws governing one s practice of judging those laws are valid for them, these for us. But as we have noted already, Frege takes it to be obvious that such a failure would manifest a hitherto unknown type of madness. It is precisely in this connection that the claim Frege makes about assertoric force in My Basic Logical Insights comes into its own. If the laws of logic just are those laws that issue in constitutive norms governing judgement and assertion, then if we are to understand their distinctive status, their essence, we need to appreciate fully the aim that is constitutive of our practice of assertion. And it is just this that is revealed in the assertoric force with which a sentence is uttered. To utter a sentence with assertoric force is just to express a judgement. For Frege, the notion of judgement is fundamental. Throughout his career, Frege consistently explicates the notion of judgement as the acknowledgment [Anerkennung] of the truth of a thought. 17 Frege insists, however, that this explication is not any sort of definition, and that acknowledgement is not itself a species of judgement. It would be a mistake precisely the sort of mistake that Frege s insistence that this is not a definition was intended to forestall if, for example, we supposed that understanding the nature of judgement required a prior and independent grasp of the notion of truth or, for that matter, of thought. And in particular, it would be a mistake if we were to allow this explication to seduce us into understanding truth as if it were a substantive property of thoughts. For this might in turn lead us to assimilate judgement to predicating truth of a thought. But Frege repeatedly inveighs against making this mistake. That this is a mistake, Frege took to be clearly exposed by reflecting on the redundancy feature of the ordinary truth predicate when applied to thoughts. The following passage from the 1914 Logic in Mathematics manuscript is characteristic. He begins by allowing that, Of course treating truth as a property of sentences or of thoughts is in accordance with linguistic usage. If we say The sentence 3 > 2 is true the corresponding thing holds of the thought. Still the predicate true is quite different from other predicates such as green, salty, rational, for what we mean by the sentence, The thought that 3 > 2 is true can more simply be said by the sentence 3 is greater than 2. Thus we do not need the word true at all 17 Though it has become standard to translate Anerkennen (and its cognates) in this context using recognize (and its cognates), I prefer to translate it using acknowledge (and its cognates). To my ear, recognize is most naturally heard as a factive, while acknowledge is not. In any case, Frege clearly allowed that one could make mistakes in judgement judging a thought to be true when in fact it is not. See, for example, Frege [between 1879 and 1891], p. 2; 1924/25, pp ; 1914, p. 234; 1918, p For a comprehensive discussion of these and related issues, see Kremer 2000.

16 390 William W. Taschek to say this. And we see that really nothing at all is added to the sense by this predicate. In order to put something forward as true, we do not need a special predicate: we only need the assertoric force with which the sentence is uttered. (p. 233) He then adds, If a man says something with assertoric force that he knows to be false, then he is lying. This is not so with an actor on the stage, when he says something false. He is not lying, because assertoric force is lacking. And if an actor on the stage says it is true that 3 is greater than 2 he is no more making an assertion than if he says 3 is greater than 2. Whether an assertion is being made, therefore, has nothing at all to do with the world true ; it is solely a matter of the assertoric force with which the sentence is uttered. (p. 234) The word true is neither necessary to express a thought, nor is it sufficient, when attached as a predicate to a thought or sentence, to effect an assertion. But now it will hardly be surprising to find that it is this very line of reasoning that leads Frege to his conclusion, in My Basic Logical Insights, that it is not the word true but the assertoric force with which a sentence is uttered that correctly indicates the essence of logic. After offering his standard elucidatory explication of judgement as the acknowledgement of a thought as true, Frege proceeds to point out the redundancy feature of the predicate true. This then leads him to conclude: If I assert it is true that seawater is salty, I assert the same thing as if I assert seawater is salty. This enables us to recognize that the assertion is not to be found in the word true, but in the assertoric force with which the sentence is uttered. (pp ) It is precisely this insight, he goes on to claim, that leads us to see that it is not the word true that indicates the essence of logic but the assertoric force with which a sentence is uttered. To be sure as Frege s elucidatory explication of judgement reveals it is fundamental to our understanding of judgement and assertion that we appreciate that their aim is truth. Judgements, and so assertions, are by their nature subject to assessment as correct or incorrect. So when, in My Basic Logical Insights, Frege declares that the essence of logic is to be found in the assertoric force with which thoughts can be expressed, it is all but inevitable that he should take the essence of logic to be fundamentally normative. Of course, the notion of correctness constitutive of judgement is inextricably bound up with the notion of truth. But, for Frege, we have no independent grip on the notion of truth apart from our appreciation of it as the constitutive aim of the norm of correctness for judgement. And, for Frege, our

17 Truth, Assertion, and the Horizontal 391 appreciation of truth as a norm of correctness for judgement is ultimately bound up with our appreciation of judgements as constitutively subject to normative governance by the laws of logic. It is in just this sense, then, that for Frege as he puts it in Der Gedanke The meaning of the word true is spelled out in the laws of truth (p. 326). Or, as we saw Frege write already in the earlier of the two Logic manuscripts, It would not perhaps be besides the mark to say that the laws of logic are nothing other than an unfolding of the content of the word true (p. 3). 4. Final reflections: Frege s horizontal It cannot be denied that Frege recognized an ineliminable normative element in logic. He sought to accommodate this in his formal system through his inference rules together, of course, with his insistence that logic is concerned, in the first instance, only with judged (and not merely judgeable) contents. But it also cannot be denied that Frege felt committed to an ineliminable descriptive element in logic as well. This shows itself in his unwavering insistence that an ideal formulation of logic will be axiomatic and include, as substantive general axioms, logical laws precisely those laws he calls laws of truth. But how, given the ways in which Frege has exposed the problematic nature of the ordinary language predicate true, and given his suggestion that a more adequate conception of the notion of truth involves appreciating its status as a constitutive norm of judgement, are we to understand Frege s repeated characterization of these laws of logic as substantive laws of truth? In particular, how, if at all, can we rescue Frege s repeated analogy between the way in which the laws of physics concern themselves with such fundamental properties as heat and weight and the way in which the laws of logic concern themselves with truth? The laws of physics will clearly contain predicates whose sense will oblige us to recognize such fundamental properties as heat and mass. But in what sense, if any, do the laws of logic contain predicates that oblige us to recognize a property of truth? If truth were a property of thoughts, we might expect the laws of logic to be laws concerning when this property holds of, or what follows from its holding of, various thoughts. But we know already that Frege was keen to deny that the word true picked out any such property and that language is misleading precisely to the extent that it seduces us into understanding truth in this way. Moreover, it is plain from Frege s mature Begriffsschrift, as presented and deployed in the

18 392 William W. Taschek Grundgesetze, that Frege s logic at no point finds itself obliged to deploy a predicate whose extension is the set of all true thoughts or all true sentences. In this sense, then, it is quite clear that Frege does not deploy a truth predicate in anything like the modern semantic sense. So how does Frege want us to think of the laws of logic, in their descriptive guise, as substantive laws of truth? While it certainly is true that Frege s axiomatic formulation of logic contains no truth predicate in the modern sense (nor, in its presentation, is he obliged to appeal to any), is it right to conclude that his logic is not concerned in a substantive way with truth? Or, to put this another way, is it right to conclude that his logic contains nothing at all worth calling a truth predicate? What about the expression in Frege s mature Begriffsschrift that he called the horizontal? 18 Frege s horizontal, recall, is the descendent of what, in the Begriffsschrift, Frege called the content stroke (Inhaltsstrich). According to the rules of formation set forth in the Begriffsschrift, the content stroke (a longish dash ) can prefix an expression A only if A expresses a judgeable content. And in the Begriffsschrift it is only to an expression prefaced with a content stroke (e.g. A ) that one can legitimately attach the vertical stroke that Frege (both there and later) calls the judgement stroke (Urteilsstrich) thus issuing in an expression like A, which expresses the judgement that A (Frege 1879, pp. 52 3). But once Frege introduced the distinction between Sinn and Bedeutung and more specifically identified the Bedeutung of a sentence with its truth value either the True or the False he reinterpreted the content stroke (which he now simply calls the horizontal ) as a first-level function name that issues in the value the True only when completed by an argument expression that names the True (e.g. any true sentence), and has as its value the False when completed by the name of any object except the True (which would include, of course, any false sentence). From a logical point of view, then, the horizontal of Frege s mature Begriffsschrift is a predicate expression a first-level concept name. Moreover, the only object in its extension is the True that is, the object Frege identifies with the Bedeutung of true sentences. In this quite specific sense, then, the horizontal is a kind of truth predicate: it is a predicate true of the True and of no other thing. Moreover, the horizontal is an absolutely essential feature of Frege s Begriffsschrift. Though rarely remarked upon, the negation stroke, the 18 The transformation of the Begriffsschrift s content stroke into the functor of his mature Begriffsschrift that Frege came to call the horizontal is first explained in Frege 1891, pp. 141ff., and gets fully elaborated in Frege 1893, pp. 215ff.

Frege on Truth, Judgment, and Objectivity

Frege on Truth, Judgment, and Objectivity Frege on Truth, Judgment, and Objectivity Erich H. Reck, University of California at Riverside, November 2006 SUMMARY: In Frege's writings, the notions of truth, judgment, and objectivity are all prominent

More information

Are There Reasons to Be Rational?

Are There Reasons to Be Rational? Are There Reasons to Be Rational? Olav Gjelsvik, University of Oslo The thesis. Among people writing about rationality, few people are more rational than Wlodek Rabinowicz. But are there reasons for being

More information

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction Kent State University BIBLID [0873-626X (2014) 39; pp. 139-145] Abstract The causal theory of reference (CTR) provides a well-articulated and widely-accepted account

More information

Truth At a World for Modal Propositions

Truth At a World for Modal Propositions Truth At a World for Modal Propositions 1 Introduction Existentialism is a thesis that concerns the ontological status of individual essences and singular propositions. Let us define an individual essence

More information

On Searle on Human Rights, Again! J. Angelo Corlett, San Diego State University

On Searle on Human Rights, Again! J. Angelo Corlett, San Diego State University On Searle on Human Rights, Again! J. Angelo Corlett, San Diego State University With regard to my article Searle on Human Rights (Corlett 2016), I have been accused of misunderstanding John Searle s conception

More information

Lonergan on General Transcendent Knowledge. In General Transcendent Knowledge, Chapter 19 of Insight, Lonergan does several things:

Lonergan on General Transcendent Knowledge. In General Transcendent Knowledge, Chapter 19 of Insight, Lonergan does several things: Lonergan on General Transcendent Knowledge In General Transcendent Knowledge, Chapter 19 of Insight, Lonergan does several things: 1-3--He provides a radical reinterpretation of the meaning of transcendence

More information

THE MEANING OF OUGHT. Ralph Wedgwood. What does the word ought mean? Strictly speaking, this is an empirical question, about the

THE MEANING OF OUGHT. Ralph Wedgwood. What does the word ought mean? Strictly speaking, this is an empirical question, about the THE MEANING OF OUGHT Ralph Wedgwood What does the word ought mean? Strictly speaking, this is an empirical question, about the meaning of a word in English. Such empirical semantic questions should ideally

More information

This is a longer version of the review that appeared in Philosophical Quarterly Vol. 47 (1997)

This is a longer version of the review that appeared in Philosophical Quarterly Vol. 47 (1997) This is a longer version of the review that appeared in Philosophical Quarterly Vol. 47 (1997) Frege by Anthony Kenny (Penguin, 1995. Pp. xi + 223) Frege s Theory of Sense and Reference by Wolfgang Carl

More information

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori PHIL 83104 November 2, 2011 Both Boghossian and Harman address themselves to the question of whether our a priori knowledge can be explained in

More information

McCLOSKEY ON RATIONAL ENDS: The Dilemma of Intuitionism

McCLOSKEY ON RATIONAL ENDS: The Dilemma of Intuitionism 48 McCLOSKEY ON RATIONAL ENDS: The Dilemma of Intuitionism T om R egan In his book, Meta-Ethics and Normative Ethics,* Professor H. J. McCloskey sets forth an argument which he thinks shows that we know,

More information

PHILOSOPHY OF LOGIC AND LANGUAGE OVERVIEW FREGE JONNY MCINTOSH 1. FREGE'S CONCEPTION OF LOGIC

PHILOSOPHY OF LOGIC AND LANGUAGE OVERVIEW FREGE JONNY MCINTOSH 1. FREGE'S CONCEPTION OF LOGIC PHILOSOPHY OF LOGIC AND LANGUAGE JONNY MCINTOSH 1. FREGE'S CONCEPTION OF LOGIC OVERVIEW These lectures cover material for paper 108, Philosophy of Logic and Language. They will focus on issues in philosophy

More information

2 FREE CHOICE The heretical thesis of Hobbes is the orthodox position today. So much is this the case that most of the contemporary literature

2 FREE CHOICE The heretical thesis of Hobbes is the orthodox position today. So much is this the case that most of the contemporary literature Introduction The philosophical controversy about free will and determinism is perennial. Like many perennial controversies, this one involves a tangle of distinct but closely related issues. Thus, the

More information

DISCUSSION PRACTICAL POLITICS AND PHILOSOPHICAL INQUIRY: A NOTE

DISCUSSION PRACTICAL POLITICS AND PHILOSOPHICAL INQUIRY: A NOTE Practical Politics and Philosophical Inquiry: A Note Author(s): Dale Hall and Tariq Modood Reviewed work(s): Source: The Philosophical Quarterly, Vol. 29, No. 117 (Oct., 1979), pp. 340-344 Published by:

More information

PROSPECTS FOR A JAMESIAN EXPRESSIVISM 1 JEFF KASSER

PROSPECTS FOR A JAMESIAN EXPRESSIVISM 1 JEFF KASSER PROSPECTS FOR A JAMESIAN EXPRESSIVISM 1 JEFF KASSER In order to take advantage of Michael Slater s presence as commentator, I want to display, as efficiently as I am able, some major similarities and differences

More information

Faults and Mathematical Disagreement

Faults and Mathematical Disagreement 45 Faults and Mathematical Disagreement María Ponte ILCLI. University of the Basque Country mariaponteazca@gmail.com Abstract: My aim in this paper is to analyse the notion of mathematical disagreements

More information

part one MACROSTRUCTURE Cambridge University Press X - A Theory of Argument Mark Vorobej Excerpt More information

part one MACROSTRUCTURE Cambridge University Press X - A Theory of Argument Mark Vorobej Excerpt More information part one MACROSTRUCTURE 1 Arguments 1.1 Authors and Audiences An argument is a social activity, the goal of which is interpersonal rational persuasion. More precisely, we ll say that an argument occurs

More information

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory Western University Scholarship@Western 2015 Undergraduate Awards The Undergraduate Awards 2015 Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory David Hakim Western University, davidhakim266@gmail.com

More information

Bertrand Russell Proper Names, Adjectives and Verbs 1

Bertrand Russell Proper Names, Adjectives and Verbs 1 Bertrand Russell Proper Names, Adjectives and Verbs 1 Analysis 46 Philosophical grammar can shed light on philosophical questions. Grammatical differences can be used as a source of discovery and a guide

More information

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View Chapter 98 Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View Lars Leeten Universität Hildesheim Practical thinking is a tricky business. Its aim will never be fulfilled unless influence on practical

More information

THE NATURE OF NORMATIVITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY OF LOGIC REBECCA V. MILLSOP S

THE NATURE OF NORMATIVITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY OF LOGIC REBECCA V. MILLSOP S THE NATURE OF NORMATIVITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY OF LOGIC REBECCA V. MILLSOP S I. INTRODUCTION Immanuel Kant claims that logic is constitutive of thought: without [the laws of logic] we would not think at

More information

Ramsey s belief > action > truth theory.

Ramsey s belief > action > truth theory. Ramsey s belief > action > truth theory. Monika Gruber University of Vienna 11.06.2016 Monika Gruber (University of Vienna) Ramsey s belief > action > truth theory. 11.06.2016 1 / 30 1 Truth and Probability

More information

THE FREGE-GEACH PROBLEM AND KALDERON S MORAL FICTIONALISM. Matti Eklund Cornell University

THE FREGE-GEACH PROBLEM AND KALDERON S MORAL FICTIONALISM. Matti Eklund Cornell University THE FREGE-GEACH PROBLEM AND KALDERON S MORAL FICTIONALISM Matti Eklund Cornell University [me72@cornell.edu] Penultimate draft. Final version forthcoming in Philosophical Quarterly I. INTRODUCTION In his

More information

Comments on Truth at A World for Modal Propositions

Comments on Truth at A World for Modal Propositions Comments on Truth at A World for Modal Propositions Christopher Menzel Texas A&M University March 16, 2008 Since Arthur Prior first made us aware of the issue, a lot of philosophical thought has gone into

More information

Causing People to Exist and Saving People s Lives Jeff McMahan

Causing People to Exist and Saving People s Lives Jeff McMahan Causing People to Exist and Saving People s Lives Jeff McMahan 1 Possible People Suppose that whatever one does a new person will come into existence. But one can determine who this person will be by either

More information

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg 1 In Search of the Ontological Argument Richard Oxenberg Abstract We can attend to the logic of Anselm's ontological argument, and amuse ourselves for a few hours unraveling its convoluted word-play, or

More information

Unifying the Categorical Imperative* Marcus Arvan University of Tampa

Unifying the Categorical Imperative* Marcus Arvan University of Tampa Unifying the Categorical Imperative* Marcus Arvan University of Tampa [T]he concept of freedom constitutes the keystone of the whole structure of a system of pure reason [and] this idea reveals itself

More information

What Lurks Beneath the Integrity Objection. Bernard Williams s alienation and integrity arguments against consequentialism have

What Lurks Beneath the Integrity Objection. Bernard Williams s alienation and integrity arguments against consequentialism have What Lurks Beneath the Integrity Objection Bernard Williams s alienation and integrity arguments against consequentialism have served as the point of departure for much of the most interesting work that

More information

Philosophical Perspectives, 16, Language and Mind, 2002 THE AIM OF BELIEF 1. Ralph Wedgwood Merton College, Oxford

Philosophical Perspectives, 16, Language and Mind, 2002 THE AIM OF BELIEF 1. Ralph Wedgwood Merton College, Oxford Philosophical Perspectives, 16, Language and Mind, 2002 THE AIM OF BELIEF 1 Ralph Wedgwood Merton College, Oxford 0. Introduction It is often claimed that beliefs aim at the truth. Indeed, this claim has

More information

Lecture 4. Before beginning the present lecture, I should give the solution to the homework problem

Lecture 4. Before beginning the present lecture, I should give the solution to the homework problem 1 Lecture 4 Before beginning the present lecture, I should give the solution to the homework problem posed in the last lecture: how, within the framework of coordinated content, might we define the notion

More information

Logical Mistakes, Logical Aliens, and the Laws of Kant's Pure General Logic Chicago February 21 st 2018 Tyke Nunez

Logical Mistakes, Logical Aliens, and the Laws of Kant's Pure General Logic Chicago February 21 st 2018 Tyke Nunez Logical Mistakes, Logical Aliens, and the Laws of Kant's Pure General Logic Chicago February 21 st 2018 Tyke Nunez 1 Introduction (1) Normativists: logic's laws are unconditional norms for how we ought

More information

CONSCIOUSNESS, INTENTIONALITY AND CONCEPTS: REPLY TO NELKIN

CONSCIOUSNESS, INTENTIONALITY AND CONCEPTS: REPLY TO NELKIN ----------------------------------------------------------------- PSYCHE: AN INTERDISCIPLINARY JOURNAL OF RESEARCH ON CONSCIOUSNESS ----------------------------------------------------------------- CONSCIOUSNESS,

More information

Moral requirements are still not rational requirements

Moral requirements are still not rational requirements ANALYSIS 59.3 JULY 1999 Moral requirements are still not rational requirements Paul Noordhof According to Michael Smith, the Rationalist makes the following conceptual claim. If it is right for agents

More information

How to Write a Philosophy Paper

How to Write a Philosophy Paper How to Write a Philosophy Paper The goal of a philosophy paper is simple: make a compelling argument. This guide aims to teach you how to write philosophy papers, starting from the ground up. To do that,

More information

CHAPTER 2 THE LARGER LOGICAL LANDSCAPE NOVEMBER 2017

CHAPTER 2 THE LARGER LOGICAL LANDSCAPE NOVEMBER 2017 CHAPTER 2 THE LARGER LOGICAL LANDSCAPE NOVEMBER 2017 1. SOME HISTORICAL REMARKS In the preceding chapter, I developed a simple propositional theory for deductive assertive illocutionary arguments. This

More information

Précis of Empiricism and Experience. Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh

Précis of Empiricism and Experience. Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh Précis of Empiricism and Experience Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh My principal aim in the book is to understand the logical relationship of experience to knowledge. Say that I look out of my window

More information

Understanding Truth Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002

Understanding Truth Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002 1 Symposium on Understanding Truth By Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002 2 Precis of Understanding Truth Scott Soames Understanding Truth aims to illuminate

More information

The Quality of Mercy is Not Strained: Justice and Mercy in Proslogion 9-11

The Quality of Mercy is Not Strained: Justice and Mercy in Proslogion 9-11 The Quality of Mercy is Not Strained: Justice and Mercy in Proslogion 9-11 Michael Vendsel Tarrant County College Abstract: In Proslogion 9-11 Anselm discusses the relationship between mercy and justice.

More information

HANDBOOK. IV. Argument Construction Determine the Ultimate Conclusion Construct the Chain of Reasoning Communicate the Argument 13

HANDBOOK. IV. Argument Construction Determine the Ultimate Conclusion Construct the Chain of Reasoning Communicate the Argument 13 1 HANDBOOK TABLE OF CONTENTS I. Argument Recognition 2 II. Argument Analysis 3 1. Identify Important Ideas 3 2. Identify Argumentative Role of These Ideas 4 3. Identify Inferences 5 4. Reconstruct the

More information

Etchemendy, Tarski, and Logical Consequence 1 Jared Bates, University of Missouri Southwest Philosophy Review 15 (1999):

Etchemendy, Tarski, and Logical Consequence 1 Jared Bates, University of Missouri Southwest Philosophy Review 15 (1999): Etchemendy, Tarski, and Logical Consequence 1 Jared Bates, University of Missouri Southwest Philosophy Review 15 (1999): 47 54. Abstract: John Etchemendy (1990) has argued that Tarski's definition of logical

More information

Varieties of Apriority

Varieties of Apriority S E V E N T H E X C U R S U S Varieties of Apriority T he notions of a priori knowledge and justification play a central role in this work. There are many ways in which one can understand the a priori,

More information

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006 In Defense of Radical Empiricism Joseph Benjamin Riegel A thesis submitted to the faculty of the University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of

More information

Broad on Theological Arguments. I. The Ontological Argument

Broad on Theological Arguments. I. The Ontological Argument Broad on God Broad on Theological Arguments I. The Ontological Argument Sample Ontological Argument: Suppose that God is the most perfect or most excellent being. Consider two things: (1)An entity that

More information

ON WRITING PHILOSOPHICAL ESSAYS: SOME GUIDELINES Richard G. Graziano

ON WRITING PHILOSOPHICAL ESSAYS: SOME GUIDELINES Richard G. Graziano ON WRITING PHILOSOPHICAL ESSAYS: SOME GUIDELINES Richard G. Graziano The discipline of philosophy is practiced in two ways: by conversation and writing. In either case, it is extremely important that a

More information

1. Introduction Formal deductive logic Overview

1. Introduction Formal deductive logic Overview 1. Introduction 1.1. Formal deductive logic 1.1.0. Overview In this course we will study reasoning, but we will study only certain aspects of reasoning and study them only from one perspective. The special

More information

Reply to Robert Koons

Reply to Robert Koons 632 Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic Volume 35, Number 4, Fall 1994 Reply to Robert Koons ANIL GUPTA and NUEL BELNAP We are grateful to Professor Robert Koons for his excellent, and generous, review

More information

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. The Physical World Author(s): Barry Stroud Source: Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, New Series, Vol. 87 (1986-1987), pp. 263-277 Published by: Blackwell Publishing on behalf of The Aristotelian

More information

Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods

Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods delineating the scope of deductive reason Roger Bishop Jones Abstract. The scope of deductive reason is considered. First a connection is discussed between the

More information

If we can t assert this, we undermine the truth of the scientific arguments too. So, Kanterian says: A full

If we can t assert this, we undermine the truth of the scientific arguments too. So, Kanterian says: A full Edward Kanterian: Frege: A Guide for the Perplexed. London/New York: Continuum, 2012. ISBN 978-0- 8264-8764-3; $24.95, 14.99 (paperback); 248 pages. Gottlob Frege s Begriffsschrift founded modern logic.

More information

TWO APPROACHES TO INSTRUMENTAL RATIONALITY

TWO APPROACHES TO INSTRUMENTAL RATIONALITY TWO APPROACHES TO INSTRUMENTAL RATIONALITY AND BELIEF CONSISTENCY BY JOHN BRUNERO JOURNAL OF ETHICS & SOCIAL PHILOSOPHY VOL. 1, NO. 1 APRIL 2005 URL: WWW.JESP.ORG COPYRIGHT JOHN BRUNERO 2005 I N SPEAKING

More information

Remarks on the philosophy of mathematics (1969) Paul Bernays

Remarks on the philosophy of mathematics (1969) Paul Bernays Bernays Project: Text No. 26 Remarks on the philosophy of mathematics (1969) Paul Bernays (Bemerkungen zur Philosophie der Mathematik) Translation by: Dirk Schlimm Comments: With corrections by Charles

More information

Does Deduction really rest on a more secure epistemological footing than Induction?

Does Deduction really rest on a more secure epistemological footing than Induction? Does Deduction really rest on a more secure epistemological footing than Induction? We argue that, if deduction is taken to at least include classical logic (CL, henceforth), justifying CL - and thus deduction

More information

In Kant s Conception of Humanity, Joshua Glasgow defends a traditional reading of

In Kant s Conception of Humanity, Joshua Glasgow defends a traditional reading of Glasgow s Conception of Kantian Humanity Richard Dean ABSTRACT: In Kant s Conception of Humanity, Joshua Glasgow defends a traditional reading of the humanity formulation of the Categorical Imperative.

More information

An Inferentialist Conception of the A Priori. Ralph Wedgwood

An Inferentialist Conception of the A Priori. Ralph Wedgwood An Inferentialist Conception of the A Priori Ralph Wedgwood When philosophers explain the distinction between the a priori and the a posteriori, they usually characterize the a priori negatively, as involving

More information

Primitive Concepts. David J. Chalmers

Primitive Concepts. David J. Chalmers Primitive Concepts David J. Chalmers Conceptual Analysis: A Traditional View A traditional view: Most ordinary concepts (or expressions) can be defined in terms of other more basic concepts (or expressions)

More information

The unity of the normative

The unity of the normative The unity of the normative The Harvard community has made this article openly available. Please share how this access benefits you. Your story matters Citation Scanlon, T. M. 2011. The Unity of the Normative.

More information

Can Rationality Be Naturalistically Explained? Jeffrey Dunn. Abstract: Dan Chiappe and John Vervaeke (1997) conclude their article, Fodor,

Can Rationality Be Naturalistically Explained? Jeffrey Dunn. Abstract: Dan Chiappe and John Vervaeke (1997) conclude their article, Fodor, Can Rationality Be Naturalistically Explained? Jeffrey Dunn Abstract: Dan Chiappe and John Vervaeke (1997) conclude their article, Fodor, Cherniak and the Naturalization of Rationality, with an argument

More information

Ayer and Quine on the a priori

Ayer and Quine on the a priori Ayer and Quine on the a priori November 23, 2004 1 The problem of a priori knowledge Ayer s book is a defense of a thoroughgoing empiricism, not only about what is required for a belief to be justified

More information

Universal Injuries Need Not Wound Internal Values A Response to Wysman

Universal Injuries Need Not Wound Internal Values A Response to Wysman A Response to Wysman Jordan Bartol In his recent article, Internal Injuries: Some Further Concerns with Intercultural and Transhistorical Critique, Colin Wysman provides a response to my (2008) article,

More information

FREGE AND SEMANTICS. Richard G. HECK, Jr. Brown University

FREGE AND SEMANTICS. Richard G. HECK, Jr. Brown University Grazer Philosophische Studien 75 (2007), 27 63. FREGE AND SEMANTICS Richard G. HECK, Jr. Brown University Summary In recent work on Frege, one of the most salient issues has been whether he was prepared

More information

Sidgwick on Practical Reason

Sidgwick on Practical Reason Sidgwick on Practical Reason ONORA O NEILL 1. How many methods? IN THE METHODS OF ETHICS Henry Sidgwick distinguishes three methods of ethics but (he claims) only two conceptions of practical reason. This

More information

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW DISCUSSION NOTE BY CAMPBELL BROWN JOURNAL OF ETHICS & SOCIAL PHILOSOPHY DISCUSSION NOTE MAY 2015 URL: WWW.JESP.ORG COPYRIGHT CAMPBELL BROWN 2015 Two Versions of Hume s Law MORAL CONCLUSIONS CANNOT VALIDLY

More information

Summary of Kant s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals

Summary of Kant s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals Summary of Kant s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals Version 1.1 Richard Baron 2 October 2016 1 Contents 1 Introduction 3 1.1 Availability and licence............ 3 2 Definitions of key terms 4 3

More information

On Some Alleged Consequences Of The Hartle-Hawking Cosmology. In [3], Quentin Smith claims that the Hartle-Hawking cosmology is inconsistent with

On Some Alleged Consequences Of The Hartle-Hawking Cosmology. In [3], Quentin Smith claims that the Hartle-Hawking cosmology is inconsistent with On Some Alleged Consequences Of The Hartle-Hawking Cosmology In [3], Quentin Smith claims that the Hartle-Hawking cosmology is inconsistent with classical theism in a way which redounds to the discredit

More information

Russell on Denoting. G. J. Mattey. Fall, 2005 / Philosophy 156. The concept any finite number is not odd, nor is it even.

Russell on Denoting. G. J. Mattey. Fall, 2005 / Philosophy 156. The concept any finite number is not odd, nor is it even. Russell on Denoting G. J. Mattey Fall, 2005 / Philosophy 156 Denoting in The Principles of Mathematics This notion [denoting] lies at the bottom (I think) of all theories of substance, of the subject-predicate

More information

The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel s Idealism

The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel s Idealism The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel s Idealism What is a great mistake? Nietzsche once said that a great error is worth more than a multitude of trivial truths. A truly great mistake

More information

From Necessary Truth to Necessary Existence

From Necessary Truth to Necessary Existence Prequel for Section 4.2 of Defending the Correspondence Theory Published by PJP VII, 1 From Necessary Truth to Necessary Existence Abstract I introduce new details in an argument for necessarily existing

More information

Self-Evidence and A Priori Moral Knowledge

Self-Evidence and A Priori Moral Knowledge Self-Evidence and A Priori Moral Knowledge Colorado State University BIBLID [0873-626X (2012) 33; pp. 459-467] Abstract According to rationalists about moral knowledge, some moral truths are knowable a

More information

What is the Frege/Russell Analysis of Quantification? Scott Soames

What is the Frege/Russell Analysis of Quantification? Scott Soames What is the Frege/Russell Analysis of Quantification? Scott Soames The Frege-Russell analysis of quantification was a fundamental advance in semantics and philosophical logic. Abstracting away from details

More information

Philosophical Issues, vol. 8 (1997), pp

Philosophical Issues, vol. 8 (1997), pp Philosophical Issues, vol. 8 (1997), pp. 313-323. Different Kinds of Kind Terms: A Reply to Sosa and Kim 1 by Geoffrey Sayre-McCord University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill In "'Good' on Twin Earth"

More information

Chapter 6. Fate. (F) Fatalism is the belief that whatever happens is unavoidable. (55)

Chapter 6. Fate. (F) Fatalism is the belief that whatever happens is unavoidable. (55) Chapter 6. Fate (F) Fatalism is the belief that whatever happens is unavoidable. (55) The first, and most important thing, to note about Taylor s characterization of fatalism is that it is in modal terms,

More information

Frege's Gedanken Are Not Truth Conditions

Frege's Gedanken Are Not Truth Conditions Facta Philosophica 4, 2002: 231-238 Peter Lang, Switzerland Frege's Gedanken Are Not Truth Conditions Ari Maunu 1 Thoughts as truth conditions Michael Dummett has put forward the view, amounting to orthodoxy,

More information

Wittgenstein and Moore s Paradox

Wittgenstein and Moore s Paradox Wittgenstein and Moore s Paradox Marie McGinn, Norwich Introduction In Part II, Section x, of the Philosophical Investigations (PI ), Wittgenstein discusses what is known as Moore s Paradox. Wittgenstein

More information

Williams on Supervaluationism and Logical Revisionism

Williams on Supervaluationism and Logical Revisionism Williams on Supervaluationism and Logical Revisionism Nicholas K. Jones Non-citable draft: 26 02 2010. Final version appeared in: The Journal of Philosophy (2011) 108: 11: 633-641 Central to discussion

More information

Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics 1. By Tom Cumming

Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics 1. By Tom Cumming Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics 1 By Tom Cumming Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics represents Martin Heidegger's first attempt at an interpretation of Kant's Critique of Pure Reason (1781). This

More information

Russell: On Denoting

Russell: On Denoting Russell: On Denoting DENOTING PHRASES Russell includes all kinds of quantified subject phrases ( a man, every man, some man etc.) but his main interest is in definite descriptions: the present King of

More information

Kant s Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysic of Morals

Kant s Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysic of Morals Kant s Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysic of Morals G. J. Mattey Spring, 2017/ Philosophy 1 The Division of Philosophical Labor Kant generally endorses the ancient Greek division of philosophy into

More information

The SAT Essay: An Argument-Centered Strategy

The SAT Essay: An Argument-Centered Strategy The SAT Essay: An Argument-Centered Strategy Overview Taking an argument-centered approach to preparing for and to writing the SAT Essay may seem like a no-brainer. After all, the prompt, which is always

More information

1/12. The A Paralogisms

1/12. The A Paralogisms 1/12 The A Paralogisms The character of the Paralogisms is described early in the chapter. Kant describes them as being syllogisms which contain no empirical premises and states that in them we conclude

More information

KANTIAN ETHICS (Dan Gaskill)

KANTIAN ETHICS (Dan Gaskill) KANTIAN ETHICS (Dan Gaskill) German philosopher Immanuel Kant (1724-1804) was an opponent of utilitarianism. Basic Summary: Kant, unlike Mill, believed that certain types of actions (including murder,

More information

Understanding, Modality, Logical Operators. Christopher Peacocke. Columbia University

Understanding, Modality, Logical Operators. Christopher Peacocke. Columbia University Understanding, Modality, Logical Operators Christopher Peacocke Columbia University Timothy Williamson s The Philosophy of Philosophy stimulates on every page. I would like to discuss every chapter. To

More information

THE SEMANTIC REALISM OF STROUD S RESPONSE TO AUSTIN S ARGUMENT AGAINST SCEPTICISM

THE SEMANTIC REALISM OF STROUD S RESPONSE TO AUSTIN S ARGUMENT AGAINST SCEPTICISM SKÉPSIS, ISSN 1981-4194, ANO VII, Nº 14, 2016, p. 33-39. THE SEMANTIC REALISM OF STROUD S RESPONSE TO AUSTIN S ARGUMENT AGAINST SCEPTICISM ALEXANDRE N. MACHADO Universidade Federal do Paraná (UFPR) Email:

More information

Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords

Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords ISBN 9780198802693 Title The Value of Rationality Author(s) Ralph Wedgwood Book abstract Book keywords Rationality is a central concept for epistemology,

More information

Utilitarianism: For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), pp Reprinted in Moral Luck (CUP, 1981).

Utilitarianism: For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), pp Reprinted in Moral Luck (CUP, 1981). Draft of 3-21- 13 PHIL 202: Core Ethics; Winter 2013 Core Sequence in the History of Ethics, 2011-2013 IV: 19 th and 20 th Century Moral Philosophy David O. Brink Handout #14: Williams, Internalism, and

More information

Constructive Logic, Truth and Warranted Assertibility

Constructive Logic, Truth and Warranted Assertibility Constructive Logic, Truth and Warranted Assertibility Greg Restall Department of Philosophy Macquarie University Version of May 20, 2000....................................................................

More information

A Contractualist Reply

A Contractualist Reply A Contractualist Reply The Harvard community has made this article openly available. Please share how this access benefits you. Your story matters Citation Scanlon, T. M. 2008. A Contractualist Reply.

More information

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism? Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism? Author: Terence Rajivan Edward, University of Manchester. Abstract. In the sixth chapter of The View from Nowhere, Thomas Nagel attempts to identify a form of idealism.

More information

Commentary on Sample Test (May 2005)

Commentary on Sample Test (May 2005) National Admissions Test for Law (LNAT) Commentary on Sample Test (May 2005) General There are two alternative strategies which can be employed when answering questions in a multiple-choice test. Some

More information

The Critical Mind is A Questioning Mind

The Critical Mind is A Questioning Mind criticalthinking.org http://www.criticalthinking.org/pages/the-critical-mind-is-a-questioning-mind/481 The Critical Mind is A Questioning Mind Learning How to Ask Powerful, Probing Questions Introduction

More information

Coordination Problems

Coordination Problems Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Vol. LXXXI No. 2, September 2010 Ó 2010 Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, LLC Coordination Problems scott soames

More information

Is the law of excluded middle a law of logic?

Is the law of excluded middle a law of logic? Is the law of excluded middle a law of logic? Introduction I will conclude that the intuitionist s attempt to rule out the law of excluded middle as a law of logic fails. They do so by appealing to harmony

More information

Judith Jarvis Thomson s Normativity

Judith Jarvis Thomson s Normativity Judith Jarvis Thomson s Normativity Gilbert Harman June 28, 2010 Normativity is a careful, rigorous account of the meanings of basic normative terms like good, virtue, correct, ought, should, and must.

More information

DISCUSSION THE GUISE OF A REASON

DISCUSSION THE GUISE OF A REASON NADEEM J.Z. HUSSAIN DISCUSSION THE GUISE OF A REASON The articles collected in David Velleman s The Possibility of Practical Reason are a snapshot or rather a film-strip of part of a philosophical endeavour

More information

AN OUTLINE OF CRITICAL THINKING

AN OUTLINE OF CRITICAL THINKING AN OUTLINE OF CRITICAL THINKING LEVELS OF INQUIRY 1. Information: correct understanding of basic information. 2. Understanding basic ideas: correct understanding of the basic meaning of key ideas. 3. Probing:

More information

FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. by Immanuel Kant

FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. by Immanuel Kant FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS SECOND SECTION by Immanuel Kant TRANSITION FROM POPULAR MORAL PHILOSOPHY TO THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS... This principle, that humanity and generally every

More information

Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly *

Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly * Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly * Ralph Wedgwood 1 Two views of practical reason Suppose that you are faced with several different options (that is, several ways in which you might act in a

More information

ALTERNATIVE SELF-DEFEAT ARGUMENTS: A REPLY TO MIZRAHI

ALTERNATIVE SELF-DEFEAT ARGUMENTS: A REPLY TO MIZRAHI ALTERNATIVE SELF-DEFEAT ARGUMENTS: A REPLY TO MIZRAHI Michael HUEMER ABSTRACT: I address Moti Mizrahi s objections to my use of the Self-Defeat Argument for Phenomenal Conservatism (PC). Mizrahi contends

More information

KANT S EXPLANATION OF THE NECESSITY OF GEOMETRICAL TRUTHS. John Watling

KANT S EXPLANATION OF THE NECESSITY OF GEOMETRICAL TRUTHS. John Watling KANT S EXPLANATION OF THE NECESSITY OF GEOMETRICAL TRUTHS John Watling Kant was an idealist. His idealism was in some ways, it is true, less extreme than that of Berkeley. He distinguished his own by calling

More information

Logic and Pragmatics: linear logic for inferential practice

Logic and Pragmatics: linear logic for inferential practice Logic and Pragmatics: linear logic for inferential practice Daniele Porello danieleporello@gmail.com Institute for Logic, Language & Computation (ILLC) University of Amsterdam, Plantage Muidergracht 24

More information

Speaking My Mind: Expression and Self-Knowledge by Dorit Bar-On

Speaking My Mind: Expression and Self-Knowledge by Dorit Bar-On Speaking My Mind: Expression and Self-Knowledge by Dorit Bar-On Self-ascriptions of mental states, whether in speech or thought, seem to have a unique status. Suppose I make an utterance of the form I

More information