Contents 1. ProtoSociology. An International Journal of Interdisciplinary Research

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Contents 1. ProtoSociology. An International Journal of Interdisciplinary Research"

Transcription

1 Contents 1 ProtoSociology An International Journal of Interdisciplinary Research Volume 25, 2008 Philosophy of Mathematics Set Theory, Measuring Theories, and Nominalism w w w.pr o t o s o c i o l o g y.de

2 2 Contents 2008 Gerhard Preyer Frankfurt am Main Erste Auflage / first published 2008 ISSN Bibliografische Information Der Deutschen Bibliothek Die Deutsche Bibliothek verzeichnet diese Publikation in der Deutschen National bibliografie; detaillierte bibliografische Daten sind im Internet über ddb.de abrufbar. Alle Rechte vorbehalten. Das Werk einschließlich aller seiner Teile ist urheberrechtlich geschützt. Je de Verwertung außerhalb der engen Grenzen des Urheberrechtsgesetzes ist ohne Zustimmung der Zeitschirft und seines Herausgebers unzulässig und strafbar. Das gilt insbesondere für Vervielfältigungen, Über setzungen, Mikroverfil mungen und die Einspeisung und Verarbeitung in elektronischen Systemen. Bibliographic information published by Die Deutsche Bibliothek Die Deutsche Bibliothek lists this publication in the Deutsche Nationalbiblio grafie; detailed bibliographic data are available in the Internet at All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrievalsystem, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, without the prior permission of ProtoSociology.

3 Contents 3 ProtoSociology An International Journal of Interdisciplinary Research Volume 25, 2008 Philosophy of Mathematics Set Theory, Measuring Theories, and Nominalism Contents Part I Set Theory, Inconsistency, and Measuring Theories Douglas Patterson Representationalism and Set-Theoretic Paradox... 7 Mark Colyvan Who s Afraid of Inconsistent Mathematics? Andrew Arana Logical and Semantic Puritiy Wilhelm K. Essler On Using Measuring Numbers according to Measuring Theories Part II The Challenge of Nominalism Jody Azzouni The Compulsion to Believe: Logical Inference and Normativity Otávio Bueno Nominalism and Mathematical Intuition Yvonne Raley Jobless Objects: Mathematical Posits in Crisis

4 4 Contents Susan Vineberg Is Indispensability Still a Problem for Fictionalism? Part III Historical Background Madeline Muntersbjorn Mill, Frege and the Unity of Mathematics Descartes on Mathematical Essences On Contemporary Philosophy and Sociology Nicholas Rescher Presumption an the Judgement of Elites Steven I. Miller, Marcel Fredericks, Frank J. Perino Social Science Research and Policymaking: Meta-Analysis and Paradox Adam Sennet Hidden Indexicals and Pronouns Nikola Kompa Review: Stephen Schiffer, The Things We Mean J. Gregory Keller Agency Implies Weakness of Will Contributors Impressum On ProtoSociology Published Volumes Cooperations/Announcements

5 160 Descartes on Mathematical Essences Abstract Descartes seems to hold two inconsistent accounts of the ontological status of mathematical essences. Meditation Five apparently develops a platonist view about such essences, while the Principles seems to advocate some form of conceptualism. We argue that Descartes was neither a platonist nor a conceptualist. Crucial to our interpretation is Descartes dispositional nativism. We contend that his doctrine of innate ideas allows him to endorse a hybrid view which avoids the drawbacks of Gassendi s conceptualism without facing the difficulties of platonism. We call this hybrid view quasi-platonism. Our interpretation explains Descartes account of the nature of mathematical essences, dissolves the tension between the two texts, and highlights the benefits of Descartes view. Descartes seems to provide two prima facie inconsistent accounts of true and immutable mathematical essences. Meditation Five suggests that Descartes was a platonist about mathematical essences. The Principles suggests that he held some kind of conceptualist view about such essences. We argue that, despite recent defenses of either Descartes platonism or conceptualism, he was neither a platonist nor a conceptualist. 1 Crucial to our interpretation of Descartes is his dispositional nativism. We contend that his doctrine of innate ideas allows him to endorse a hybrid view that we will call quasi-platonism which avoids the pitfalls of Gassendi s conceptualism without falling into the troubles of platonism. Descartes account of the nature of mathematical essences is explained, the tension between the two texts dissolved, and the benefits of Descartes considered view are explored. 1. Ideas of Mathematics qua Ideas of True and Immutable Essences What are ideas of mathematics according to Descartes? Or what do they rep- 1 For a neo-platonic interpretation of Cartesian mathematical essences, see (Schmaltz 1991) and (Rozemond 2008), and for a conceptualist interpretation, see (Chappell 1997), (Nolan 1997) and (Nolan 1998).

6 Descartes on Mathematical Essences 161 resent? Descartes answer to these questions is very clear, although its implications aren t. Ideas of mathematical objects, like the ideas of God and the mind, are ideas of true and immutable essences (T&IEs) and they are contrasted with ideas of fictitious essences (FEs). This contrast emerges, inter alia, in a letter to Mersenne, dated 16 June 1641, where Descartes writes that the ideas of God, mind, body, triangle [ ] represent true, immutable and eternal essences (CSMK, 183), and that these ideas are to be distinguished from ideas that represent FEs (CSMK, 184). In Meditation Five and First Set of Replies, the fact that the idea of God, like the idea of a triangle, represents a T&IE rather than a FE is the bulwark of Descartes ontological proof. Distinguishing between FEs and T&IEs becomes then crucial for Descartes. A FE, Descartes claims, is an essence put together by the intellect (CSM II, 83). 2 To Caterus complaint that the ontological argument proves God s existence only if we already assume it, Descartes replies that deriving the property of something from its essence is question-begging only in the case of FEs (CSM II, 83 4; 46 and 263). In the Letter to Mersenne just mentioned, he explains: [ ] if from a constructed idea I were to infer what I explicitly put into it when I was constructing it, I would obviously be begging the question; but it is not the same if I draw out from an innate idea something which was implicitly contained in it but which I did not at first notice in it. (CSMK, 184, emphasis added.) In Meditation Five, Descartes writes that the innate ideas of God and the triangle [ ] are not my invention but have their own true and immutable natures (CSM II, 44 5, emphasis added). And as a way of further explicating the notion of T&IE, he adds: When, for example, I imagine a triangle, [ ] there is [ ] a determinate [ ] essence [ ] of the triangle which is immutable and eternal, and not invented by me or dependent on my mind (CSM II, 44 5, emphasis added). Ultimately, according to Descartes, an important feature of T&IEs (as opposed to FEs) is that they have properties I clearly recognize whether I want or not (CSM II, 45 6). 3 2 Examples are: winged horse, existing lion, triangle inscribed in a square. 3 It has been noticed in the literature that Descartes may have failed to give a successful criterion for distinguishing T&IEs from FEs. (Wilson 1978), for instance, argued that Descartes gives two different criteria for distinguishing T&IEs from FEs: (i) Ideas of T&IEs imply unforeseen and unalterable consequences (see CSM II, 45). (ii) Ideas of T&IEs cannot be analyzed into component ideas (see CSM II, 83 84). Neither criterion, according to Wilson, is adequate. (i) fails because we can easily conjure up an idea of an invented essence that has unalterable and unforeseen implications. (For example, we can conjure up the term Onk, and define

7 162 If ideas of mathematics are ideas of objects having T&IEs, and the truth of mathematical propositions depends on their conformity to the essence of things (CSM II, 262), it becomes crucial to understand Descartes conception of the ontological status of these essences. Are the latter abstract objects, distinct from both particular things and finite minds? Are they immanent in particular objects? Or are they modes of conceiving of particular things, which have no separate existence from either particular objects or finite minds? 2. Descartes on the Ontological Status of T&IEs: Two Opposing Accounts Descartes offers two prima facie inconsistent accounts of the nature of T&IEs. Some passages suggest that he held a platonist view of mathematical essences, where platonism is defined as follows: Platonism: T&IEs are abstract entities. They exist outside space and time and they are prior to, independent of, and distinct from both particular existing things and the human mind. They would exist (or subsist ) even if there were no finite minds and no material things. In Meditation Five, Descartes writes: [ ] when I imagine a triangle, even if no such figure exists or has ever existed anywhere outside my thought, there is still a determinate [ ] essence, or form of the triangle which is immutable and eternal, and not invented by me or dependent on my mind. (CSM II, 45, emphasis added.) This passage suggests that Descartes held a platonist view, according to which the essence of a triangle is an extra-mental, abstract entity. Certainly Gassendi interpreted Descartes as holding this view. In criticizing the passage, Gassendi takes himself to be opposing the view that there is a universal nature [of triit as the first non-terrestrial life form to be discovered by man. Reproduction and nourishment would be necessary properties of Onk, whether I want it or not, even if Onk has an invented essence; see (Wilson 1978, ) (ii) fails also because the notion of an existing lion [which is an example of a FE] and that of a triangle [which is an example of a T&IE] seem to be equally analyzable (Wilson 1978, 173). See also (Doney 1993). For an illuminating discussion of these issues, see (Edelberg 1990).

8 Descartes on Mathematical Essences 163 angle] before [any particular triangle existed] and before the intellect performed the abstraction (CSM II, 222, emphasis added) Anthony Kenny, over the years, has defended this platonist interpretation of Descartes. According to Kenny, Descartes is the founder of modern platonism because [ ] the geometer s triangle is an eternal creature of God, with its own immutable nature and properties, a real thing lacking only the perfection of actual existence. 4 Kenny s argument is that given Descartes claim that all eternal truths have been created by God (CSMK, 23 and CSM II, 261) by efficient causality (CSMK, 25); and given passages such as the one quoted above from Meditation Five, Cartesian essences are abstract entities independent of both particular existing things and the human mind. 5 Hence, Descartes is a platonist about essences. 6 Assuming that this is Descartes considered view, his modern platonism would have to answer the question that mars any kind of platonism, viz., how can a finite mind which is spatially located have knowledge of abstract objects that exist outside space? One could argue that since the Cartesian mind is a thinking un-extended substance that isn t spatially located, in principle there would be no problem in explaining its access to these abstract objects. The unlocated mind sees or grasps these objects with the mind s eyes (whatever that is). This may be right but the original problem is not so easily disposed of. The analogy with seeing does not help much, since it only goes so far. The mind can t see these objects since it is in no causal connection with them. Moreover, no mechanism that explains how the mind is connected to these objects has been provided. And without some such mechanism, no account of the possibility of mathematical knowledge is on offer. Such mechanism had better be reliable as well; otherwise, the resulting account of mathematical knowledge wouldn t even be minimally adequate. Interestingly, we can t find a single place where Descartes tackled these issues. And maybe that s a hint that his position on mathematical objects didn t raise these problems. Various other passages, however, suggest a rather different interpretation of Descartes views on mathematical essences. According to these passages, 4 (Kenny 1970, p. 697). 5 For Descartes identification of essences with eternal truths see, for example, Letter to Mersenne, May 27, 1630 (CSMK 25 26) and (Schmaltz 1991). 6 (Kenny 1970, 693 7). For other platonist readings of Descartes view of eternal essences, see (Wilson 1978) and (Curley 1978). For interesting criticisms of Kenny s interpretation, see (Chappell 1997) and (Nolan 1997). More recently, a neoplatonist reading of Cartesian essences has been offered by (Schmaltz 1991) and (Rozemond 2008).

9 164 Descartes held what could be called a conceptualist view of essences, where conceptualism is defined as follows: Conceptualism (broadly construed): T&IEs are not distinct from existences. Numbers, for example, are nothing distinct from the things numbered. When considered in the abstract or in general, they are merely modes of thinking of things. In his discussion of number, duration and order in the Principles, Descartes very carefully specifies: We shall have a very distinct understanding of duration, order and number, provided we do not mistakenly tack on to them any concept of substance. Instead we should regard the duration of a thing simply as a mode under which we conceive the thing in so far as it continues to exist. And similarly we should not regard order or number as anything separate from the things which are ordered and numbered but should think of them simply as modes under which we consider the things in question. (Principles I.55, CSM I, 211; emphasis added.) Later in the Principles, Descartes insists that the distinction between quantity or number and the thing that has quantity or number is only conceptual (see Principles II.8, CSM I 226). Finally, in a letter to an unknown correspondent, Descartes writes about the essence of a triangle: [ ] when I think of the essence of a triangle, and of the existence of the same triangle, these two thoughts, as thoughts, even taken objectively differ modally in the strict sense of the term mode ; but the case is not the same with the triangle existing outside thought, in which it seems to me manifest that essence and existence are in no way distinct. The same is the case with all universals. Thus, when I say Peter is a man, the thought by which I think of Peter differs modally from the thought by which I think of man, but in Peter himself being a man is nothing other than being Peter. (CSMK, , emphasis added) All these passages suggest that the distinction between the existence and essence of a triangle is conceptual rather than real. Although the ideas of the essence and existence of a triangle are two different ideas capable of existing independently of one another (they differ modally, as Descartes puts it), being a triangle is nothing other than being this or that particular triangle. Essence and existence are not really distinct. Essences do not exist in a realm separate from existing things. 7 7 For Descartes definition of real distinction, modal distinction and conceptual distinction, see Principles, I (CSM I, ). Further evidence can be found in (Descartes 1975, 58).

10 Descartes on Mathematical Essences 165 The problem consists in assessing what brand of conceptualism we ought to attribute to Descartes based on the above texts. One may wonder whether, or to what extent, Descartes conceptualism is the same as Gassendi s. According to Gassendi, essences are nothing but the way in which the finite mind classifies, or conceives of, things after having formed the idea based on the observed similarities among things. In particular, for Gassendi, a triangle is a kind of mental rule which you use to find out whether something deserves to be called a triangle (CSM II, 223), and whose nature is not distinct from the intellect which, after seeing material triangles, has formed [it] (CSM II, 223). Similarly, Descartes suggests that essences and universals are only modes of thought that we use for thinking of all individual items which resemble each other (CSM I, 212). However, there are some fundamental differences between Gassendi and Descartes. First of all, by saying that the triangle, when considered in the abstract, is nothing but a mode of thinking of particular things, Descartes doesn t mean to suggest that the essence of the triangle, for example, is abstracted in the sense of extracted from observation of particulars. Rather, he means that the triangle is conceived in abstraction from (i.e. independently of) any particular triangles. Secondly, the essence of a triangle, for both Gassendi and Descartes, is whatever particular triangles have in common. But for Descartes, what these particulars have in common is a function of the idea of the triangle; and, therefore any property we attribute to triangles is grounded in the idea and belongs necessarily to them. Gassendi s view is the opposite. The idea is based on the observed similarities among particular things and therefore any property we attribute to them doesn t necessarily belong to them. Consequently, Gassendi s conceptualism is best understood as the view that essences are ideas that neither designate abstract entities nor correspond exactly to the nature of physical objects. It s worth noting that conceptualism à la Gassendi faces at least two problems. First, if mathematical objects are nothing but modes of thinking, it is unclear why they describe so successfully the physical world. Secondly, given the empiricist view on the origin of mathematical ideas, it is unclear how a conceptualist can explain the necessity of mathematical statements. Alan Gewirth has defended a different conceptualist interpretation of Descartes. He argues that Descartes conceptualism is a form of Aristotelianism since on the Aristotelian interpretation, mathematical essences are quantitative abstractions from natural substances; so, numbers are not really distinct

11 166 from the things numbered. 8 Gewirth means that, according to Aristotle, essences are in the objects; and in knowing essences, the mind abstracts from particular objects so that there is no real distinction between essences and things. Notice, however, that this view counts as conceptualist only to the extent that essences qua abstractions from finite things are not really distinct from them. The distinction between particular things and essences is conceptual because essences exist only where they are instantiated. However, essences aren t mere ideas because they are literally present in things. 9 In conclusion, different passages in Descartes writings, and different interpretations of them, suggest that Descartes may have held any of the following three accounts of essences: (1) Platonism: Essences are abstract entities, distinct from particular things and finite minds. (2) Aristotelianism: Essences are in the objects. So they aren t mere ideas. But given that there are no non-instantiated essences, the distinction between particular objects and essences is only conceptual. (3) Conceptualism (à la Gassendi): essences are nothing but ideas that neither designate abstract entities nor correspond exactly to the nature of physical objects. What is Descartes considered view? In what follows, we argue that Descartes held a theory of mathematical essences that (1) ought not to be identified with any of the three proposals above; (2) dissolves the difficulties raised for both platonism and conceptualism (à la Gassendi) and (3) dissolves the prima facie inconsistencies between the passages from Meditation Five and the Principles. 3. Descartes Quasi-Platonism Tad Schmaltz, in his Platonism and Descartes View of Immutable Essences, pointed out that there is no overt effort in the literature to resolve the tension between the two seemingly different accounts of essences that Descartes 8 (Gewirth 1970, 678). 9 In the past (Gueroult 1984), and more recently (Chappell 1997) and (Nolan 1997), have defended a conceptualist reading of Descartes view on essences.

12 Descartes on Mathematical Essences 167 offers in different texts. As he puts it, Kenny did not confront the apparent implications of the Principles that immutable essences cannot be distinct from created material and mental substances, while Gewirth and Gueroult failed to explain the contention in Meditation V that immutable essences can be identified with properties neither of finite minds nor of particular bodies. 10 Schmaltz s view is that the two accounts above can be reconciled by attributing to eternal essences and truths the same ontological status that laws have, viz., that of divine decrees or moral entities. Like laws of nature, eternal essences and truths are divine commands imprinted in the heart of man rather than being special entities created by God. 11 We are sympathetic with Schmaltz s proposal to reconcile these two accounts but we believe that there is a more straightforward way to do so. Descartes was, as we will call it, a quasi-platonist about essences: his quasi-platonism consists precisely in his avoiding the pitfalls of Gassendi s conceptualism without falling into the difficulties of platonism. This quasi-platonism can be more simply explained within the framework of Descartes dispositional nativism. Here s our view. 12 Dispositional nativism, broadly construed, is the view that an idea is innate if, and only if, the mind has the innate disposition to form that idea under appropriate circumstances. The locus classicus of Descartes endorsement of dispositional nativism is a passage from the Comments on a Certain Broadsheet where Descartes claims that ideas are innate in the mind in the same way in which certain diseases are innate in certain families. As children of those families are not born with the disease but with the disposition to contract it later 10 (Schmaltz 1991, 134). 11 See, for example, Letter to Mersenne, 15 April 1630 (CSMK, 23). In support of the ontological status of eternal truths and laws as moral entities, Schmaltz refers to Descartes Sixth Replies (CSM II, 294). See (Schmaltz 1991, 138). 12 We don t deny that there are sparse suggestions in (Schmaltz 1991) that Descartes doctrine of innate ideas may offer a solution to the problems of reconciling the two sets of texts. However, Schmaltz overall underplays the role of dispositional nativism in explaining the consistency of Descartes view. His aim is to avoid the platonic interpretation of Descartes without thereby falling into the Charybdis of the abstractionist interpretation of Gueroult and Gewirth (Schmaltz 1991, ). According to Schmaltz, the abstractionist interpretation cannot accommodate the claim in Meditation V that the immutable essence of a triangle does not depend on human thought (ibid., p. 163). However, when Schmaltz does draw a connection between the innateness of ideas of essences and the claim that essences are divine decrees (see, for example, ibid., p. 162), he doesn t expand on this proposal.

13 168 in life, so we are not born with certain ideas but with the disposition to form them later in life. 13 Despite the problems one may raise against a dispositional form of nativism, the pressing issue at this point is: How does Descartes dispositional nativism (however spelled out) relate to his quasi-platonism? We take Descartes considered view at least with regard to mathematical essences to be as follows. Essences, when considered in the abstract, are only modes of conceiving things as opposed to being either immanent forms (contra Aristotle) or forms subsisting in a third realm (contra Plato). By claiming that essences are modes of thought, Descartes is distancing himself from (at least orthodox) Platonism and Aristotelianism. However, in claiming that essences are modes of thought, Descartes is not endorsing a conceptualism à la Gassendi, according to which essences are ideas formed by the finite mind after having observed particular things. Rather, these essences are God-given or innate ideas; they are God s way of predisposing our minds to think of, and represent, things in certain ways. 14 So Descartes view that essences are nothing but universal ideas implicitly encloses three criticisms: (a) it opposes platonism about mathematics, since it denies that numbers are prior to, independent of, and distinct from both material things and the human mind; (b) it opposes Aristotelianism for universals are modes of thinking that do not have a common foundation in things; 15 and, (c) it opposes Gassendi s conceptualism because, according to Descartes, essences are to be identified with innate ideas. It follows that Descartes view cannot be identical to any of (1)-(3) above. But one could object that claiming that, according to Descartes, essences are to be identified with innate ideas doesn t per se rule out platonism because ideas can be abstract objects that the finite mind apprehends. Alternatively, one could inquire, are innate ideas abstracta, according to Descartes? Answers to this question may vary depending on one s views on what Des- 13 See CSM I For a detailed account of Descartes dispositional nativism, see (De Rosa 2000) and (De Rosa 2004). 14 (Chappell 1997) and (Nolan 1997) have defended a similar view. Despite apparent similarities between our readings of Descartes, our argumentative strategies are different. According to Nolan and Chappell, Descartes is a conceptualist. But, according to us, Descartes view is more nuanced since it contains elements of platonism. One of the authors (De Rosa) is currently writing a second paper on the topic that explains the theoretical reasons why Descartes cannot be regarded as either a conceptualist or a platonist. 15 See on this, for example, (Bolton 1998).

14 Descartes on Mathematical Essences 169 cartes account of ideas is. If one is inclined to explain the intentionality of ideas by postulating an object of thought that mediates the mind-world relation, then it is easy to think of ideas as abstract objects that the finite mind apprehends. However, there are good grounds to believe that this was not Descartes considered view. According to Descartes, ideas of T&IEs are general ideas, and these ideas are mental representations (as opposed to abstracta) with an intentional content whose properties mislead us into thinking that Descartes is postulating abstract objects. In particular, we contend that we make the mistake of inferring that Descartes is postulating abstract objects when he talks about ideas of T&IEs because of two features he attributes to the content of these ideas: (a) the mind cannot manipulate the intentional content of these ideas. And (b) these ideas are prior to, and independent of, the material things they represent. Let us consider features (a) and (b) in turn. In several places, Descartes talks of ideas of mathematics as having a content that hasn t been put together by the intellect and, hence, is real to the extent that it is mind independent (CSM II, 45 and CSM II, 83 86). These are the passages that provide the strongest support for the platonist interpretation of Descartes. However, it is possible to read the text in an alternative way. By saying that ideas of mathematics are ideas of true and immutable essences that are not dependent on the mind, Descartes is saying that ideas of mathematics are ideas whose representational contents include properties such that if they were removed the idea would cease to be what it is. For example, the representational content of the idea of triangle implies true and immutable properties such as having three angles, having the sum of the interior angles equal to two right angles and so on. It is easy to mistake the features of these ideas for the features of abstract objects that these ideas would stand for. It is the immutability of the properties of the representational content of ideas through which we conceptualize objects that suggests realism about essences and (given Descartes mechanism and anti-aristotelianism) a platonist kind of realism according to which there are abstract entities that the mind simply apprehends. Certainly platonism would explain the mind independence of the content of these ideas, but inferring platonism from mind independence is hardly the only possible explanation. The mind independence and realism of the content of these ideas can also be explained by the mind s inability to conceptualize objects in ways other than the ways in which it does. In conclusion, the mistake consists in passing off the immutable character of the represen-

15 170 tational content through which our mind conceptualizes things for abstract objects of which sensible things are mere copies and which the mind simply apprehends. 16 It is also undeniable that Descartes argues in several places that ideas of geometrical figures, for example, are in the mind prior to, and independently of, the actual existence of the objects they represent. Besides the passages from Meditation Five quoted above, there are other places where Descartes maintains that we would have the idea of triangle even if no particular triangle ever existed. Gassendi raised the question as to whether Descartes thought that one could have the idea of triangle (CSM II, 223), of God and the self (CSM II, 216) if one never had any senses. In reply, Descartes writes: 17 I do not doubt that the mind [ ] would have had exactly the same ideas of God and itself that it now has, with the sole difference that they would have been much purer and clearer. The senses often impede the mind in many of its operations, and in no case do they help in the perception of ideas. The only thing that prevents all of us noticing equally well that we have these ideas is that we are too occupied with perceiving the images of corporeal things. (CSM II, 258, emphasis added.) According to Descartes, the senses play either no or, at best, an obstructive role in our having the ideas of God, the self and the triangle. We would have these ideas even if we had never had any senses. This is established by the fact that we have clear and distinct ideas of things of which either no instances can be found in the material world (such as the idea of God and the self) or 16 For a similar reasoning see (Nolan 1997, ). Nolan s argument is as follows. When Descartes talks about immutable essences that do not depend on the mind he only means to say that the ideas of geometrical objects being innate, as opposed to invented, ideas do not depend on the mind causally. Rather, they causally depend on God. But denying that these ideas are causally dependent on our mind does not imply denial of their ontological dependence on the mind. Conceptualism is then vindicated. Despite some similarity, our argument is different. We agree with Nolan that the mind-independence of ideas of mathematical essences does not justify attributing to Descartes a platonist kind of realism according to which there is a realm of abstract entities that are distinct from God, finite minds and things. But we are not so sure that this reasoning proves conceptualism. We want to say that, according to Descartes, the content of these ideas is mind-independent because we cannot manipulate it. And we cannot manipulate it because these ideas are given to us by God. But if God gives us these ideas, they must also be in God s mind. Needless to say, this conclusion threatens Nolan s conceptualist interpretation. 17 Although Descartes answer addresses only the ideas of God and the soul, what he says here can be easily extended to the idea of triangle too.

16 Descartes on Mathematical Essences 171 no instances need to be found in the material world (such as the ideas of the triangle and the chiliagon). Moreover, in the same set of replies to Gassendi, Descartes makes the stronger point that the idea of triangle cannot depend on the existence of particular triangles because it is the precondition for recognizing particular shapes in space as triangles in the first place (see CSM II, ). This feature of geometrical ideas, viz., the fact that they exist in the mind innately as the precondition for recognizing shapes in space can be, again, easily conflated with the platonist view that there is a world of abstract entities that exist prior to, and independently of, particular and sensible things. Descartes claim that ideas of geometrical figures are prior to, and independent of, particular things together with Descartes talk of these ideas as ideas of essences engenders the conclusion that Cartesian essences are prior to, and independent of particular things (in the same way in which the platonist s abstract entities are). However, this reasoning is sound only on pain of ignoring Descartes claim that essences are nothing but our ways of thinking of things in abstraction from them. And if essences are nothing but ways of conceiving of things, then their being prior to, and independent of, particular things are properties belonging to the ideas alone and cannot transitively be attributed to essences. The mistake consists in passing off the innate character of the ideas for the ontological status of the essences they would stand for. This concludes the presentation of our interpretation of Descartes view on mathematical essences. But why should we call this view quasi-platonism? The label seems to be misleading since platonism suggests the postulation of abstract objects and we ve argued that Descartes apparent belief in abstract entities is only the result of the features of general ideas. After all, one may argue, Descartes view on essences is conceptualist to the extent that he grants them a being of reason and the features that he attributes to universal ideas (nativism and realism) don t suffice to make him a platonist of any sort. However, since platonism about mathematical essences is indeed associated with realism and nativism (more commonly than conceptualism maybe), we believe that quasi-platonism is an appropriate way to describe Descartes position on mathematical essences. The prefix quasi indicates the non-genuine character of his platonism; but the term platonism (better than conceptualism) brings about the associations to the properties of realism and being prior to/ independent of particular things that Descartes attributed to innate ideas. Moreover, the term quasi-platonism better captures Descartes belief that

17 172 these innate ideas are God-given and, hence, must also be present, in some sense, in God s mind. 18 Of course, how one refers to Descartes position is, ultimately, only a terminological issue. As long as it s clear what position he held, no misunderstanding should emerge. Descartes was neither a platonist nor a conceptualist, but he developed an interesting alternative between these two extremes. And that s what the term quasi-platonism is meant to convey. 4. Benefits of Descartes Quasi-Platonism and the Eternity of Mathematical Truths In this section, we will discuss some of the benefits Descartes view on essences has over platonism and Gassendi s version of conceptualism, and how Descartes quasi-platonism is compatible with the eternity of mathematicaltruths. Descartes view fares better than platonism in explaining the possibility of mathematical knowledge for several reasons. First, the problem of explaining mathematical knowledge is simply dissolved, since the objects of mathematics are ideas, or ways of thinking of the physical world. 19 As Descartes writes to Mersenne, there is no single truth that the mind cannot understand if it turns to consider it, because these truths are inborn in our minds (CSMK, 23). Secondly, Descartes provides a method/mechanism (namely, the skeptical method of doubt) through which the mind can turn to consider the ideas and truths of mathematics inborn in our minds. Thirdly, assuming that the method of doubt can isolate the class of genuinely inborn, clear and distinct ideas, these ideas are reliable indicators of truth given the non-deceiving nature of God. So, for example, in Meditation Five and First Set of Replies, Descartes claims that every property we clearly and distinctly understand to belong to the true and immutable essence of a triangle really does in fact belong to it (CSM II, 45). This is obtained, in particular, by drawing conclusions from the content of mathematical ideas. Given the ideas of natural number, one cannot deny that = 4 without facing a contradiction (CSM II, 25). Or we can draw 18 This is precisely the reason why Marleen Rozemond, in (Rozemond 2008), calls Descartes view neo-platonist and argues, contra (Nolan 1997), that Cartesian essences must be something more than ideas in the minds of human beings. 19 This point is fleshed out, in a more contemporary context, in (Bueno 2005).

18 Descartes on Mathematical Essences 173 out from the idea of the triangle that its three angles equal two right angles (CSMK, 184). Also Descartes view fares better than Gassendi s conceptualism in explaining the usefulness of mathematics for scientific theories. If geometrical objects, according to Gassendi, are nothing but modes of thinking of things that do not exactly correspond to them, it is unclear why they describe so successfully the physical world. But, according to Descartes, (i) what particular triangles (for example) have in common is a function of the idea of triangle; and therefore any property we attribute to triangles is grounded in the idea and belongs necessarily to them. And (ii) given the existence and non-deceiving nature of God, material things possess all the properties which I clearly and distinctly understand, that is, all those which viewed in general terms are comprised within the subject of pure mathematics (CSM II, 55). So, according to Descartes, the language of mathematics describes successfully the physical world because it captures its true nature. Moreover, Descartes quasi-platonism explains the necessity of mathematical statements better than Gassendi s conceptualism. Since, according to Gassendi, the truth of mathematical statements is grounded in the observation of things such statements are only empirical generalizations. According to Descartes, instead, mathematical truths are grounded on ideas. And since any property we attribute to mathematical objects is grounded on the idea of these objects and belongs necessarily to them, mathematical truths are necessary truths. 20 However, one may object that even if Descartes can explain the necessity of mathematical truths better than Gassendi, he (like Gassendi) cannot explain the eternity and immutability of mathematical truths. After all, mathematical essences are mental entities and the latter are neither eternal nor immutable. Descartes has at least two possible explanations of the eternity and immutability of mathematical truths. First, the eternity of mathematical truths may be read as a function of the immutability of the content of the innate ideas through which we conceptualize objects. Given that the content of these ideas contains the description of the essential properties of things, and these ideas are God-given and not subject to our manipulation, essences are said to be eternal or immutable According to us, the claim that mathematical truth is a matter of conceptual entailment among ideas is compatible with the Cartesian view that eternal truths ultimately depend on God s will. After all, God imprinted mathematical ideas, among others, in our minds. 21 This view has been defended by (Bennett 1994) and (Chappell 1997). See also (Wilson 1975, ).

19 174 Secondly, if eternity is to be taken literally rather than as a synonym of immutability, we may say that mathematical essences qua ideas are eternal because they depend on the will and understanding of God (see CSM II, 261). This second alternative makes a virtue of what is generally taken to be a vice of Descartes account of the eternity of mathematical truths. It is a common objection that Descartes doctrine of the creation of eternal truths together with his voluntarism is inconsistent with their eternity. 22 But if what grounds the truth of mathematical statements is God s will and God s will is unchangeable, there is no room for any change in the truth-values of mathematical statements. As a result, mathematical truths are indeed eternal. 23 Note that we shouldn t interpret Descartes voluntarism as the view that it is possible for God to will that eternal truths be otherwise, for two reasons. First, the claim that it is possible for God to will that eternal truths be otherwise presupposes (at least under one reading of it) that there are possibilities prior to God s willing them to be so, and that God decided to will one rather than the others. But Descartes claims that it is self-contradictory to suppose that the will of God was not indifferent from eternity with respect to everything which has happened or will ever happen; for it is impossible to imagine that anything is thought of in the divine intellect as good or true [ ] prior to the decision of the divine will to make it so (CSM II, 291). Descartes further explains that if some reason for something s being good has existed prior to its preordination, this would have determined God to prefer those things which it was best to do (CSM II, 294). 24 In conclusion, since divine indifference is the precondition of God s freedom, the scope of what s possible is determined by what God actually wills. Still, one may insist, the freedom of God s will is certainly compatible with a change in God s will. This is certainly true in principle. However, and this is our second reason, in a letter to Mersenne, Descartes replies to the objection that God could change the eternal truths: Yes, he can if his will can change (CSMK, 23). However, in many places Descartes firmly denies that God s will can change (see, e.g., CSM II, 281 and CSM II, 294). Thus, taking the if above as an only if, the eternal truths can t change either. Notice that the move above namely our grounding the eternity and immutability of mathematical truths on God s will and understanding brings out another reason why we believe Descartes is a quasi-platonist rather than 22 See, for example, CSM II, 281 and CSM II, See, for example, CSM I, 93, CSM I, 211, and CSM I, For a detailed defense of this view, see (Kaufman 2002).

20 Descartes on Mathematical Essences 175 a full-fledged conceptualist. Conceptualist readings, like (Nolan 1997) and (Chappell 1997), maintain that mathematical essences are primarily ideas in human minds. However, we believe that this reading doesn t do full justice to Descartes view that these essences are created by God. If God created these essences as ideas in human minds, they must also exist in God, either as divine decrees, as (Schmaltz 1991) suggests, or as objective beings in God s mind, as (Rozemond 2008) claims. So, ultimately, even if essences are ideas in human minds, they are also ontologically dependent on God, and in this respect, Descartes position is quasi-platonist. 5. The Textual Inconsistency Dissolved Let us now show that Meditation Five is consistent with the Principles in light of Descartes quasi-platonism and dispositional nativism. Undeniably, some passages in Meditation Five seem to indicate that T&IEs are platonic essences subsisting in an extra-mental and extra-physical realm, since Descartes suggests that they are prior to, and independent of, material things and human minds. However, in the Fifth Replies, Descartes emphasizes that the idea of the triangle and the like do not come from the senses. In light of this point, we can legitimately interpret Descartes claim in Meditation Five that T&IEs are independent of the existence of particular things and finite minds as simply making the negative point that the content of mathematical ideas is not a construct of the mind based on the observation of things. 25 The innateness of the idea of triangle explains why Descartes says that this is the idea of an object that has a T&IE. The innateness of these ideas explains, moreover, why we have the idea of the triangle even if no triangle ever existed or was ever observed by us. Again, the claim in Meditation Five that we have these ideas even if no particular object existed doesn t necessarily commit Descartes to platonism. The claim that the idea of triangle is the precondition for perceiving things in space as triangles is mistaken for the claim that the idea of triangle stands for an abstract object existing prior to particular traingles. Needless to say, the view that Cartesian essences are nothing but the innate ideas implicitly guiding our representation of things is compatible with 25 For a similar point, see (Schmaltz 1991).

21 176 the view of the Principles according to which triangularity is nothing but a mode of thought. But the emphasis on the innateness of the modes of thought explains the sense in which we should interpret the conceptualism suggested by the Principles. By claiming that essences are modes of thought, Descartes is making the negative point that they are neither platonic nor aristotelian forms, rather than the positive point that essences are constructs of the finite mind based on the observation of things. And the innateness of the modes of thoughts prevents the inference from the negative point to the positive point. That s why Descartes brand of conceptualism is different from Gassendi s. In conclusion, the innateness of ideas of mathematics provides a coherent interpretation of both the Principles and Meditation Five by attributing to Descartes a hybrid view that isn t identical with either platonism or conceptualism. 6. Conclusion Our analysis of the ontological status of T&IEs established that they are not, contrary to what some passages seem to suggest, entities subsisting in an abstract third realm. Rather they are innate or God-given modes of thinking of things. T&IEs are engraved in the mind and, unknowingly to us, guide our thoughts rather than being the object of these thoughts. As a result, Descartes is neither a platonist nor a conceptualist about mathematical essences. His dispositional nativism allows him to hold a hybrid view, quasi-platonism, that has the benefits of solving the textual inconsistency without falling into the troubles of either platonism or conceptualism. 26 References CSM: John Cottingham, Robert Stoothoff and Dugald Murdoch (eds.), The Philosophical Writings of Descartes, volumes I-II. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, We wish to thank Martha Bolton, John Carriero, Dan Garber, Paul Lodge, Antonia Lolordo, Steven Nadler, Alan Nelson, Larry Nolan, Andrew Pessin, Marleen Rozemond, and Tad Schmaltz for helpful comments on earlier versions of this work.

22 Descartes on Mathematical Essences 177 CSMK: John Cottingham, Robert Stoothoff, Dugald Murdoch and Anthony Kenny (ed.), The Philosophical Writings of Descartes. The Correspondence, volume III. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, Bennett, J Descartes s Theory of Modality. The Philosophical Review 103: Bolton, M Universals, Essences, and Abstract Entities. In The Cambridge History of the Seventeenth Century Philosophy, edited by D. Garber. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Bueno, O Dirac and the Dispensability of Mathematics, Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 36: Chappell, V Descartes Ontology. Topoi 16: Curley, E.M. (1978): Descartes Against the Skeptics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Descartes, R Entretien avec Burman. Paris: Librairie Philosophique J. Vrin. De Rosa, R On Fodor s Claim that Classical Empiricists and Rationalists Agree on the Innateness of Ideas. Proto Sociology 14: De Rosa, R The Question-Begging Status of the Anti-Nativist Arguments. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 69: Doney, W On Descartes Reply to Caterus. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 67: Edelberg, W The Fifth Meditation. The Philosophical Review 99: Gewirth, A The Cartesian Circle Reconsidered. Journal of Philosophy 67: Gewirth, A Descartes: Two Disputed Questions. Journal of Philosophy 68: Gueroult, M Descartes Philosophy Interpreted According to the Order of Reasons. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. Kaufman, D Descartes s Creation Doctrine and Modality. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 80: Kenny, A Descartes. New York: Random House. Kenny, A The Cartesian Circle and the Eternal Truths. Journal of Philosophy 67: Nolan, L The Ontological Status of Cartesian Natures. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 78: Nolan, L Descartes Theory of Universals. Philosophical Studies 89: Rozemond, M Descartes Ontology of the Eternal Truths. Forthcoming in Contemporary Perspectives on Early Modern Philosophy: Essays in Honor of Vere Chappell, edited by P. Hoffman, D. Owen and G. Yaffe. Broadview Press. Schmaltz, T. M Platonism and Descartes View of Immutable Essences. Archiv für Geschichte Der Philosophie 73: Wilson, M Descartes. London: Routledge.

23 178

From the fact that I cannot think of God except as existing, it follows that existence is inseparable from God, and hence that he really exists.

From the fact that I cannot think of God except as existing, it follows that existence is inseparable from God, and hence that he really exists. FIFTH MEDITATION The essence of material things, and the existence of God considered a second time We have seen that Descartes carefully distinguishes questions about a thing s existence from questions

More information

Kolumne. ProtoSociology. An International Journal of Interdisciplinary Research. Concepts Contemporary and Historical Perspectives

Kolumne. ProtoSociology. An International Journal of Interdisciplinary Research. Concepts Contemporary and Historical Perspectives Kolumne 1 ProtoSociology An International Journal of Interdisciplinary Research Volume 30, 2013 Concepts Contemporary and Historical Perspectives www.protosociology.de ProtoSociology Volume 30/2013: Concepts

More information

CARTESIAN IDEA OF GOD AS THE INFINITE

CARTESIAN IDEA OF GOD AS THE INFINITE FILOZOFIA Roč. 67, 2012, č. 4 CARTESIAN IDEA OF GOD AS THE INFINITE KSENIJA PUŠKARIĆ, Department of Philosophy, Saint Louis University, USA PUŠKARIĆ, K.: Cartesian Idea of God as the Infinite FILOZOFIA

More information

Cartesian Sensations. Raffaella De Rosa* Rutgers University-Newark

Cartesian Sensations. Raffaella De Rosa* Rutgers University-Newark Philosophy Compass 4/5 (2009): 780 792, 10.1111/j.1747-9991.2009.00252.x Cartesian Sensations Raffaella De Rosa* Rutgers University-Newark Abstract Descartes maintained that sensations of color and the

More information

Introduction to Philosophy Russell Marcus Queens College http://philosophy.thatmarcusfamily.org Excerpts from the Objections & Replies to Descartes Meditations on First Philosophy A. To the Cogito. 1.

More information

In Part I of the ETHICS, Spinoza presents his central

In Part I of the ETHICS, Spinoza presents his central TWO PROBLEMS WITH SPINOZA S ARGUMENT FOR SUBSTANCE MONISM LAURA ANGELINA DELGADO * In Part I of the ETHICS, Spinoza presents his central metaphysical thesis that there is only one substance in the universe.

More information

Descartes Theory of Contingency 1 Chris Gousmett

Descartes Theory of Contingency 1 Chris Gousmett Descartes Theory of Contingency 1 Chris Gousmett In 1630, Descartes wrote a letter to Mersenne in which he stated a doctrine which was to shock his contemporaries... It was so unorthodox and so contrary

More information

On Force in Cartesian Physics

On Force in Cartesian Physics On Force in Cartesian Physics John Byron Manchak June 28, 2007 Abstract There does not seem to be a consistent way to ground the concept of force in Cartesian first principles. In this paper, I examine

More information

Mikhael Dua. Tacit Knowing. Michael Polanyi s Exposition of Scientific Knowledge. Herbert Utz Verlag Wissenschaft München

Mikhael Dua. Tacit Knowing. Michael Polanyi s Exposition of Scientific Knowledge. Herbert Utz Verlag Wissenschaft München Mikhael Dua Tacit Knowing Michael Polanyi s Exposition of Scientific Knowledge Herbert Utz Verlag Wissenschaft München Bibliografische Information Der Deutschen Bibliothek Die Deutsche Bibliothek verzeichnet

More information

How Do We Know Anything about Mathematics? - A Defence of Platonism

How Do We Know Anything about Mathematics? - A Defence of Platonism How Do We Know Anything about Mathematics? - A Defence of Platonism Majda Trobok University of Rijeka original scientific paper UDK: 141.131 1:51 510.21 ABSTRACT In this paper I will try to say something

More information

Descartes, Leibniz, Spinoza: Concept of Substance Chapter 3 Spinoza and Substance. (Woolhouse)

Descartes, Leibniz, Spinoza: Concept of Substance Chapter 3 Spinoza and Substance. (Woolhouse) Descartes, Leibniz, Spinoza: Concept of Substance Chapter 3 Spinoza and Substance Detailed Argument Spinoza s Ethics is a systematic treatment of the substantial nature of God, and of the relationship

More information

Descartes Atomism of Thought: A Solution to the Puzzle about True and Immutable Natures

Descartes Atomism of Thought: A Solution to the Puzzle about True and Immutable Natures Res Cogitans 2018 vol. 13, no.2, 1-30 Descartes Atomism of Thought: A Solution to the Puzzle about True and Immutable Natures Steven Burgess Central to Descartes philosophy is a view about immutable essences

More information

Cartesian Aseity in the Third Meditation

Cartesian Aseity in the Third Meditation University of Utah Abstract: In his Mediations, Descartes introduces a notion of divine aseity that, given some other commitments about causation and knowledge of the divine, must be different than the

More information

Adding Substance to the Debate: Descartes on Freedom of the Will

Adding Substance to the Debate: Descartes on Freedom of the Will Essays in Philosophy Volume 14 Issue 2 Cartesian Virtue and Freedom Article 6 July 2013 Adding Substance to the Debate: Descartes on Freedom of the Will Brian Collins University of Iowa Follow this and

More information

ProtoSociology An International Journal of Interdisciplinary Research

ProtoSociology An International Journal of Interdisciplinary Research ProtoSociology An International Journal of Interdisciplinary Research Volume 27, 2011 Modernization in Times of Globalization II www.protosociology.de 2011 Gerhard Preyer Frankfurt am Main http://www.protosociology.de

More information

An International Journal of Interdisciplinary Research

An International Journal of Interdisciplinary Research An International Journal of Interdisciplinary Research Vol. 18-19, 2003 Understanding the Social II: Philosophy of Sociality P Edited by: Raimo Tuomela, Gerhard Preyer, and Georg Peter P Layout and Technical

More information

DESCARTES ON THE OBJECTIVE REALITY OF MATERIALLY FALSE IDEAS

DESCARTES ON THE OBJECTIVE REALITY OF MATERIALLY FALSE IDEAS DESCARTES ON MATERIALLY FALSE IDEAS 385 DESCARTES ON THE OBJECTIVE REALITY OF MATERIALLY FALSE IDEAS BY DAN KAUFMAN Abstract: The Standard Interpretation of Descartes on material falsity states that Descartes

More information

Cartesian Rationalism

Cartesian Rationalism Cartesian Rationalism René Descartes 1596-1650 Reason tells me to trust my senses Descartes had the disturbing experience of finding out that everything he learned at school was wrong! From 1604-1612 he

More information

Cartesian Rationalism

Cartesian Rationalism Cartesian Rationalism René Descartes 1596-1650 Reason tells me to trust my senses Descartes had the disturbing experience of finding out that everything he learned at school was wrong! From 1604-1612 he

More information

A teleological account of Cartesian sensations?

A teleological account of Cartesian sensations? Synthese (2007) 156:311 336 DOI 10.1007/s11229-006-0010-4 ORIGINAL ARTICLE A teleological account of Cartesian sensations? Raffaella De Rosa Received: 19 May 2005 / Accepted: 22 March 2006 / Published

More information

15 Does God have a Nature?

15 Does God have a Nature? 15 Does God have a Nature? 15.1 Plantinga s Question So far I have argued for a theory of creation and the use of mathematical ways of thinking that help us to locate God. The question becomes how can

More information

Time 1867 words Principles of Philosophy God cosmological argument

Time 1867 words Principles of Philosophy God cosmological argument Time 1867 words In the Scholastic tradition, time is distinguished from duration. Whereas duration is an attribute of things, time is the measure of motion, that is, a mathematical quantity measuring the

More information

Leibniz on Justice as a Common Concept: A Rejoinder to Patrick Riley. Andreas Blank, Tel Aviv University. 1. Introduction

Leibniz on Justice as a Common Concept: A Rejoinder to Patrick Riley. Andreas Blank, Tel Aviv University. 1. Introduction Leibniz on Justice as a Common Concept: A Rejoinder to Patrick Riley Andreas Blank, Tel Aviv University 1. Introduction I n his tercentenary article on the Méditation sur la notion commune de la justice,

More information

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism? Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism? Author: Terence Rajivan Edward, University of Manchester. Abstract. In the sixth chapter of The View from Nowhere, Thomas Nagel attempts to identify a form of idealism.

More information

New Aristotelianism, Routledge, 2012), in which he expanded upon

New Aristotelianism, Routledge, 2012), in which he expanded upon Powers, Essentialism and Agency: A Reply to Alexander Bird Ruth Porter Groff, Saint Louis University AUB Conference, April 28-29, 2016 1. Here s the backstory. A couple of years ago my friend Alexander

More information

Two kinds of necessity in Descartes: Conditional and absolute

Two kinds of necessity in Descartes: Conditional and absolute Filosofia Unisinos Unisinos Journal of Philosophy 18(2):98-106, may/aug 2017 Unisinos doi: 10.4013/fsu.2017.182.04 Two kinds of necessity in Descartes: Conditional and absolute Dois tipos de necessidade

More information

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006 In Defense of Radical Empiricism Joseph Benjamin Riegel A thesis submitted to the faculty of the University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of

More information

Class #14: October 13 Gödel s Platonism

Class #14: October 13 Gödel s Platonism Philosophy 405: Knowledge, Truth and Mathematics Fall 2010 Hamilton College Russell Marcus Class #14: October 13 Gödel s Platonism I. The Continuum Hypothesis and Its Independence The continuum problem

More information

! Jumping ahead 2000 years:! Consider the theory of the self.! What am I? What certain knowledge do I have?! Key figure: René Descartes.

! Jumping ahead 2000 years:! Consider the theory of the self.! What am I? What certain knowledge do I have?! Key figure: René Descartes. ! Jumping ahead 2000 years:! Consider the theory of the self.! What am I? What certain knowledge do I have?! What is the relation between that knowledge and that given in the sciences?! Key figure: René

More information

1/8. Descartes 3: Proofs of the Existence of God

1/8. Descartes 3: Proofs of the Existence of God 1/8 Descartes 3: Proofs of the Existence of God Descartes opens the Third Meditation by reminding himself that nothing that is purely sensory is reliable. The one thing that is certain is the cogito. He

More information

The Ontological Argument for the existence of God. Pedro M. Guimarães Ferreira S.J. PUC-Rio Boston College, July 13th. 2011

The Ontological Argument for the existence of God. Pedro M. Guimarães Ferreira S.J. PUC-Rio Boston College, July 13th. 2011 The Ontological Argument for the existence of God Pedro M. Guimarães Ferreira S.J. PUC-Rio Boston College, July 13th. 2011 The ontological argument (henceforth, O.A.) for the existence of God has a long

More information

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. The Physical World Author(s): Barry Stroud Source: Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, New Series, Vol. 87 (1986-1987), pp. 263-277 Published by: Blackwell Publishing on behalf of The Aristotelian

More information

Duns Scotus on Divine Illumination

Duns Scotus on Divine Illumination MP_C13.qxd 11/23/06 2:29 AM Page 110 13 Duns Scotus on Divine Illumination [Article IV. Concerning Henry s Conclusion] In the fourth article I argue against the conclusion of [Henry s] view as follows:

More information

THE MEANING OF OUGHT. Ralph Wedgwood. What does the word ought mean? Strictly speaking, this is an empirical question, about the

THE MEANING OF OUGHT. Ralph Wedgwood. What does the word ought mean? Strictly speaking, this is an empirical question, about the THE MEANING OF OUGHT Ralph Wedgwood What does the word ought mean? Strictly speaking, this is an empirical question, about the meaning of a word in English. Such empirical semantic questions should ideally

More information

Descartes and Malebranche on Thought, Sensation and the Nature of the Mind

Descartes and Malebranche on Thought, Sensation and the Nature of the Mind DESCARTES AND MALEBRANCHE ON THE NATURE OF THE MIND 387 Descartes and Malebranche on Thought, Sensation and the Nature of the Mind ANTONIA LOLORDO* ONE OFTEN-DISCUSSED ASPECT of Malebranche s philosophy

More information

Lecture Notes Comments on a Certain Broadsheet G. J. Mattey December 4, 2008

Lecture Notes Comments on a Certain Broadsheet G. J. Mattey December 4, 2008 Lecture Notes Comments on a Certain Broadsheet G. J. Mattey December 4, 2008 This short work was published in 1648, in response to some published criticisms of Descartes. The work mainly analyzes and rebuts

More information

Descartes: A Guide for the Perplexed

Descartes: A Guide for the Perplexed Praxis, Vol. 3, No. 1, Spring 2011 ISSN 1756-1019 Descartes: A Guide for the Perplexed Reviewed by Chistopher Ranalli University of Edinburgh Descartes: A Guide for the Perplexed By Justin Skirry. New

More information

I. HYLOMORPHISM AND THE REAL DISTINCTION BETWEEN MIND AND BODY

I. HYLOMORPHISM AND THE REAL DISTINCTION BETWEEN MIND AND BODY ON DESCARTES Most of my work on Descartes has centered on his account of human beings. If there is any unifying theme that has emerged from my various papers on Descartes, it is that he retains three important

More information

Van Fraassen: Arguments Concerning Scientific Realism

Van Fraassen: Arguments Concerning Scientific Realism Aaron Leung Philosophy 290-5 Week 11 Handout Van Fraassen: Arguments Concerning Scientific Realism 1. Scientific Realism and Constructive Empiricism What is scientific realism? According to van Fraassen,

More information

Coordination Problems

Coordination Problems Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Vol. LXXXI No. 2, September 2010 Ó 2010 Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, LLC Coordination Problems scott soames

More information

Wiley is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Noûs.

Wiley is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Noûs. Descartes: The Epistemological Argument for Mind-Body Distinctness Author(s): Margaret D. Wilson Source: Noûs, Vol. 10, No. 1, Symposium Papers to be Read at the Meeting of the Western Division of the

More information

Spinoza on the Essence, Mutability and Power of God

Spinoza on the Essence, Mutability and Power of God University of Pennsylvania ScholarlyCommons Scholarship at Penn Libraries Penn Libraries January 1998 Spinoza on the Essence, Mutability and Power of God Nicholas E. Okrent University of Pennsylvania,

More information

On the epistemological status of mathematical objects in Plato s philosophical system

On the epistemological status of mathematical objects in Plato s philosophical system On the epistemological status of mathematical objects in Plato s philosophical system Floris T. van Vugt University College Utrecht University, The Netherlands October 22, 2003 Abstract The main question

More information

WHY IS GOD GOOD? EUTYPHRO, TIMAEUS AND THE DIVINE COMMAND THEORY

WHY IS GOD GOOD? EUTYPHRO, TIMAEUS AND THE DIVINE COMMAND THEORY Miłosz Pawłowski WHY IS GOD GOOD? EUTYPHRO, TIMAEUS AND THE DIVINE COMMAND THEORY In Eutyphro Plato presents a dilemma 1. Is it that acts are good because God wants them to be performed 2? Or are they

More information

Issue 4, Special Conference Proceedings Published by the Durham University Undergraduate Philosophy Society

Issue 4, Special Conference Proceedings Published by the Durham University Undergraduate Philosophy Society Issue 4, Special Conference Proceedings 2017 Published by the Durham University Undergraduate Philosophy Society An Alternative Approach to Mathematical Ontology Amber Donovan (Durham University) Introduction

More information

Divisibility, Logic, Radical Empiricism, and Metaphysics

Divisibility, Logic, Radical Empiricism, and Metaphysics Abstract: Divisibility, Logic, Radical Empiricism, and Metaphysics We will explore the problem of the manner in which the world may be divided into parts, and how this affects the application of logic.

More information

MEDITATIONS ON THE FIRST PHILOSOPHY: THE ONTOLOGICAL ARGUMENT

MEDITATIONS ON THE FIRST PHILOSOPHY: THE ONTOLOGICAL ARGUMENT MEDITATIONS ON THE FIRST PHILOSOPHY: THE ONTOLOGICAL ARGUMENT René Descartes Introduction, Donald M. Borchert DESCARTES WAS BORN IN FRANCE in 1596 and died in Sweden in 1650. His formal education from

More information

Introductory Kant Seminar Lecture

Introductory Kant Seminar Lecture Introductory Kant Seminar Lecture Intentionality It is not unusual to begin a discussion of Kant with a brief review of some history of philosophy. What is perhaps less usual is to start with a review

More information

Introduction. I. Proof of the Minor Premise ( All reality is completely intelligible )

Introduction. I. Proof of the Minor Premise ( All reality is completely intelligible ) Philosophical Proof of God: Derived from Principles in Bernard Lonergan s Insight May 2014 Robert J. Spitzer, S.J., Ph.D. Magis Center of Reason and Faith Lonergan s proof may be stated as follows: Introduction

More information

Ethics Demonstrated in Geometrical Order

Ethics Demonstrated in Geometrical Order Ethics Demonstrated in Geometrical Order Benedict Spinoza Copyright Jonathan Bennett 2017. All rights reserved [Brackets] enclose editorial explanations. Small dots enclose material that has been added,

More information

1/7. The Postulates of Empirical Thought

1/7. The Postulates of Empirical Thought 1/7 The Postulates of Empirical Thought This week we are focusing on the final section of the Analytic of Principles in which Kant schematizes the last set of categories. This set of categories are what

More information

Review of Constructive Empiricism: Epistemology and the Philosophy of Science

Review of Constructive Empiricism: Epistemology and the Philosophy of Science Review of Constructive Empiricism: Epistemology and the Philosophy of Science Constructive Empiricism (CE) quickly became famous for its immunity from the most devastating criticisms that brought down

More information

2017 Philosophy. Higher. Finalised Marking Instructions

2017 Philosophy. Higher. Finalised Marking Instructions National Qualifications 07 07 Philosophy Higher Finalised Marking Instructions Scottish Qualifications Authority 07 The information in this publication may be reproduced to support SQA qualifications only

More information

BEGINNINGLESS PAST AND ENDLESS FUTURE: REPLY TO CRAIG. Wes Morriston. In a recent paper, I claimed that if a familiar line of argument against

BEGINNINGLESS PAST AND ENDLESS FUTURE: REPLY TO CRAIG. Wes Morriston. In a recent paper, I claimed that if a familiar line of argument against Forthcoming in Faith and Philosophy BEGINNINGLESS PAST AND ENDLESS FUTURE: REPLY TO CRAIG Wes Morriston In a recent paper, I claimed that if a familiar line of argument against the possibility of a beginningless

More information

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 4: Skepticism. Part 1: The Scope of Skepticism and Two Main Types of Skeptical Argument

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 4: Skepticism. Part 1: The Scope of Skepticism and Two Main Types of Skeptical Argument 1. The Scope of Skepticism Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 4: Skepticism Part 1: The Scope of Skepticism and Two Main Types of Skeptical Argument The scope of skeptical challenges can vary in a number

More information

Who or what is God?, asks John Hick (Hick 2009). A theist might answer: God is an infinite person, or at least an

Who or what is God?, asks John Hick (Hick 2009). A theist might answer: God is an infinite person, or at least an John Hick on whether God could be an infinite person Daniel Howard-Snyder Western Washington University Abstract: "Who or what is God?," asks John Hick. A theist might answer: God is an infinite person,

More information

Leibniz, Principles, and Truth 1

Leibniz, Principles, and Truth 1 Leibniz, Principles, and Truth 1 Leibniz was a man of principles. 2 Throughout his writings, one finds repeated assertions that his view is developed according to certain fundamental principles. Attempting

More information

Spinoza and the Axiomatic Method. Ever since Euclid first laid out his geometry in the Elements, his axiomatic approach to

Spinoza and the Axiomatic Method. Ever since Euclid first laid out his geometry in the Elements, his axiomatic approach to Haruyama 1 Justin Haruyama Bryan Smith HON 213 17 April 2008 Spinoza and the Axiomatic Method Ever since Euclid first laid out his geometry in the Elements, his axiomatic approach to geometry has been

More information

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy Res Cogitans Volume 5 Issue 1 Article 20 6-4-2014 Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy Kevin Harriman Lewis & Clark College Follow this and additional works at: http://commons.pacificu.edu/rescogitans

More information

Deflationary Nominalism s Commitment to Meinongianism

Deflationary Nominalism s Commitment to Meinongianism Res Cogitans Volume 7 Issue 1 Article 8 6-24-2016 Deflationary Nominalism s Commitment to Meinongianism Anthony Nguyen Reed College Follow this and additional works at: http://commons.pacificu.edu/rescogitans

More information

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction Kent State University BIBLID [0873-626X (2014) 39; pp. 139-145] Abstract The causal theory of reference (CTR) provides a well-articulated and widely-accepted account

More information

Reply to Kit Fine. Theodore Sider July 19, 2013

Reply to Kit Fine. Theodore Sider July 19, 2013 Reply to Kit Fine Theodore Sider July 19, 2013 Kit Fine s paper raises important and difficult issues about my approach to the metaphysics of fundamentality. In chapters 7 and 8 I examined certain subtle

More information

PHILOSOPHY 4360/5360 METAPHYSICS. Methods that Metaphysicians Use

PHILOSOPHY 4360/5360 METAPHYSICS. Methods that Metaphysicians Use PHILOSOPHY 4360/5360 METAPHYSICS Methods that Metaphysicians Use Method 1: The appeal to what one can imagine where imagining some state of affairs involves forming a vivid image of that state of affairs.

More information

24.01 Classics of Western Philosophy

24.01 Classics of Western Philosophy 1 Plan: Kant Lecture #2: How are pure mathematics and pure natural science possible? 1. Review: Problem of Metaphysics 2. Kantian Commitments 3. Pure Mathematics 4. Transcendental Idealism 5. Pure Natural

More information

DESCARTES AND THE CREATION OF THE ETERNAL TRUTHS

DESCARTES AND THE CREATION OF THE ETERNAL TRUTHS DESCARTES AND THE CREATION OF THE ETERNAL TRUTHS A Thesis by CALE JOSEPH HARFOUSH Submitted to the Office of Graduate Studies of Texas A&M University in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the

More information

First Principles. Principles of Reality. Undeniability.

First Principles. Principles of Reality. Undeniability. First Principles. First principles are the foundation of knowledge. Without them nothing could be known (see FOUNDATIONALISM). Even coherentism uses the first principle of noncontradiction to test the

More information

THE STUDY OF UNKNOWN AND UNKNOWABILITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY

THE STUDY OF UNKNOWN AND UNKNOWABILITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY THE STUDY OF UNKNOWN AND UNKNOWABILITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY Subhankari Pati Research Scholar Pondicherry University, Pondicherry The present aim of this paper is to highlights the shortcomings in Kant

More information

1/12. The A Paralogisms

1/12. The A Paralogisms 1/12 The A Paralogisms The character of the Paralogisms is described early in the chapter. Kant describes them as being syllogisms which contain no empirical premises and states that in them we conclude

More information

Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible?

Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible? Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible? Anders Kraal ABSTRACT: Since the 1960s an increasing number of philosophers have endorsed the thesis that there can be no such thing as

More information

BELIEF POLICIES, by Paul Helm. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, Pp. xiii and 226. $54.95 (Cloth).

BELIEF POLICIES, by Paul Helm. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, Pp. xiii and 226. $54.95 (Cloth). BELIEF POLICIES, by Paul Helm. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1994. Pp. xiii and 226. $54.95 (Cloth). TRENTON MERRICKS, Virginia Commonwealth University Faith and Philosophy 13 (1996): 449-454

More information

Spinoza s Modal-Ontological Argument for Monism

Spinoza s Modal-Ontological Argument for Monism Spinoza s Modal-Ontological Argument for Monism One of Spinoza s clearest expressions of his monism is Ethics I P14, and its corollary 1. 1 The proposition reads: Except God, no substance can be or be

More information

5 A Modal Version of the

5 A Modal Version of the 5 A Modal Version of the Ontological Argument E. J. L O W E Moreland, J. P.; Sweis, Khaldoun A.; Meister, Chad V., Jul 01, 2013, Debating Christian Theism The original version of the ontological argument

More information

Contemporary Theology I: Hegel to Death of God Theologies

Contemporary Theology I: Hegel to Death of God Theologies Contemporary Theology I: Hegel to Death of God Theologies ST503 LESSON 16 of 24 John S. Feinberg, Ph.D. Experience: Professor of Biblical and Systematic Theology, Trinity Evangelical Divinity School. At

More information

Spinoza, Ethics 1 of 85 THE ETHICS. by Benedict de Spinoza (Ethica Ordine Geometrico Demonstrata) Translated from the Latin by R. H. M.

Spinoza, Ethics 1 of 85 THE ETHICS. by Benedict de Spinoza (Ethica Ordine Geometrico Demonstrata) Translated from the Latin by R. H. M. Spinoza, Ethics 1 of 85 THE ETHICS by Benedict de Spinoza (Ethica Ordine Geometrico Demonstrata) Translated from the Latin by R. H. M. Elwes PART I: CONCERNING GOD DEFINITIONS (1) By that which is self-caused

More information

Fundamentals of Metaphysics

Fundamentals of Metaphysics Fundamentals of Metaphysics Objective and Subjective One important component of the Common Western Metaphysic is the thesis that there is such a thing as objective truth. each of our beliefs and assertions

More information

Descartes. Efficient and Final Causation

Descartes. Efficient and Final Causation 59 Descartes paul hoffman The primary historical contribution of René Descartes (1596 1650) to the theory of action would appear to be that he expanded the range of action by freeing the concept of efficient

More information

Ethics Demonstrated in Geometrical Order

Ethics Demonstrated in Geometrical Order 1 Copyright Jonathan Bennett [Brackets] enclose editorial explanations. Small dots enclose material that has been added, but can be read as though it were part of the original text. Occasional bullets,

More information

Philosophy of Mathematics Kant

Philosophy of Mathematics Kant Philosophy of Mathematics Kant Owen Griffiths oeg21@cam.ac.uk St John s College, Cambridge 20/10/15 Immanuel Kant Born in 1724 in Königsberg, Prussia. Enrolled at the University of Königsberg in 1740 and

More information

On happiness in Locke s decision-ma Title being )

On happiness in Locke s decision-ma Title being ) On happiness in Locke s decision-ma Title (Proceedings of the CAPE Internatio I: The CAPE International Conferenc being ) Author(s) Sasaki, Taku Citation CAPE Studies in Applied Philosophy 2: 141-151 Issue

More information

Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics 1. By Tom Cumming

Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics 1. By Tom Cumming Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics 1 By Tom Cumming Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics represents Martin Heidegger's first attempt at an interpretation of Kant's Critique of Pure Reason (1781). This

More information

Creation & necessity

Creation & necessity Creation & necessity Today we turn to one of the central claims made about God in the Nicene Creed: that God created all things visible and invisible. In the Catechism, creation is described like this:

More information

Hume's Representation Argument Against Rationalism 1 by Geoffrey Sayre-McCord University of North Carolina/Chapel Hill

Hume's Representation Argument Against Rationalism 1 by Geoffrey Sayre-McCord University of North Carolina/Chapel Hill Hume's Representation Argument Against Rationalism 1 by Geoffrey Sayre-McCord University of North Carolina/Chapel Hill Manuscrito (1997) vol. 20, pp. 77-94 Hume offers a barrage of arguments for thinking

More information

Sufficient Reason and Infinite Regress: Causal Consistency in Descartes and Spinoza. Ryan Steed

Sufficient Reason and Infinite Regress: Causal Consistency in Descartes and Spinoza. Ryan Steed Sufficient Reason and Infinite Regress: Causal Consistency in Descartes and Spinoza Ryan Steed PHIL 2112 Professor Rebecca Car October 15, 2018 Steed 2 While both Baruch Spinoza and René Descartes espouse

More information

Comments on Lasersohn

Comments on Lasersohn Comments on Lasersohn John MacFarlane September 29, 2006 I ll begin by saying a bit about Lasersohn s framework for relativist semantics and how it compares to the one I ve been recommending. I ll focus

More information

Are There Reasons to Be Rational?

Are There Reasons to Be Rational? Are There Reasons to Be Rational? Olav Gjelsvik, University of Oslo The thesis. Among people writing about rationality, few people are more rational than Wlodek Rabinowicz. But are there reasons for being

More information

SIMON BOSTOCK Internal Properties and Property Realism

SIMON BOSTOCK Internal Properties and Property Realism SIMON BOSTOCK Internal Properties and Property Realism R ealism about properties, standardly, is contrasted with nominalism. According to nominalism, only particulars exist. According to realism, both

More information

General Philosophy. Dr Peter Millican,, Hertford College. Lecture 4: Two Cartesian Topics

General Philosophy. Dr Peter Millican,, Hertford College. Lecture 4: Two Cartesian Topics General Philosophy Dr Peter Millican,, Hertford College Lecture 4: Two Cartesian Topics Scepticism, and the Mind 2 Last Time we looked at scepticism about INDUCTION. This Lecture will move on to SCEPTICISM

More information

II RESEMBLANCE NOMINALISM, CONJUNCTIONS

II RESEMBLANCE NOMINALISM, CONJUNCTIONS Meeting of the Aristotelian Society held at Senate House, University of London, on 22 October 2012 at 5:30 p.m. II RESEMBLANCE NOMINALISM, CONJUNCTIONS AND TRUTHMAKERS The resemblance nominalist says that

More information

Sensitivity hasn t got a Heterogeneity Problem - a Reply to Melchior

Sensitivity hasn t got a Heterogeneity Problem - a Reply to Melchior DOI 10.1007/s11406-016-9782-z Sensitivity hasn t got a Heterogeneity Problem - a Reply to Melchior Kevin Wallbridge 1 Received: 3 May 2016 / Revised: 7 September 2016 / Accepted: 17 October 2016 # The

More information

SQUARING THE CARTESIAN CIRCLE

SQUARING THE CARTESIAN CIRCLE SQUARING THE CARTESIAN CIRCLE Charles Hucnemann University of Illinois at Chicago The lasting objection against Descartes's Meditations seems to be that his reasoning is circular. On the one hand, he uses

More information

Some Good and Some Not so Good Arguments for Necessary Laws. William Russell Payne Ph.D.

Some Good and Some Not so Good Arguments for Necessary Laws. William Russell Payne Ph.D. Some Good and Some Not so Good Arguments for Necessary Laws William Russell Payne Ph.D. The view that properties have their causal powers essentially, which I will here call property essentialism, has

More information

KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST. Arnon Keren

KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST. Arnon Keren Abstracta SPECIAL ISSUE VI, pp. 33 46, 2012 KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST Arnon Keren Epistemologists of testimony widely agree on the fact that our reliance on other people's testimony is extensive. However,

More information

Paul Lodge (New Orleans) Primitive and Derivative Forces in Leibnizian Bodies

Paul Lodge (New Orleans) Primitive and Derivative Forces in Leibnizian Bodies in Nihil Sine Ratione: Mensch, Natur und Technik im Wirken von G. W. Leibniz ed. H. Poser (2001), 720-27. Paul Lodge (New Orleans) Primitive and Derivative Forces in Leibnizian Bodies Page 720 I It is

More information

Clear and Distinct Perceptions of Extension in Descartes s Meditations. Emily M. Kelahan. Chapel Hill 2007

Clear and Distinct Perceptions of Extension in Descartes s Meditations. Emily M. Kelahan. Chapel Hill 2007 Clear and Distinct Perceptions of Extension in Descartes s Meditations Emily M. Kelahan A thesis submitted to the faculty of the University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill in partial fulfillment of the

More information

A. Aristotle D. Descartes B. Plato E. Hume

A. Aristotle D. Descartes B. Plato E. Hume A. Aristotle D. Kant B. Plato E. Mill C. Confucius 1....pleasure, and freedom from pain, are the only things desirable as ends. 2. Courage is not only the knowledge of the hopeful and the fearful, but

More information

Midwest Studies in Philosophy, XXVI (2002) Presence and Likeness in Arnauld s Critique of Malebranche NANCY KENDRICK

Midwest Studies in Philosophy, XXVI (2002) Presence and Likeness in Arnauld s Critique of Malebranche NANCY KENDRICK Midwest Studies in Philosophy, XXVI (2002) Presence and Likeness in Arnauld s Critique of Malebranche NANCY KENDRICK The debate between Malebranche and Arnauld concerning the nature of ideas rests on a

More information

Huemer s Problem of Memory Knowledge

Huemer s Problem of Memory Knowledge Huemer s Problem of Memory Knowledge ABSTRACT: When S seems to remember that P, what kind of justification does S have for believing that P? In "The Problem of Memory Knowledge." Michael Huemer offers

More information

Reviewed by Colin Marshall, University of Washington

Reviewed by Colin Marshall, University of Washington Yitzhak Y. Melamed, Spinoza s Metaphysics: Substance and Thought, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2013, xxii + 232 p. Reviewed by Colin Marshall, University of Washington I n his important new study of

More information

to representationalism, then we would seem to miss the point on account of which the distinction between direct realism and representationalism was

to representationalism, then we would seem to miss the point on account of which the distinction between direct realism and representationalism was Intentional Transfer in Averroes, Indifference of Nature in Avicenna, and the Issue of the Representationalism of Aquinas Comments on Max Herrera and Richard Taylor Is Aquinas a representationalist or

More information

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras Module - 14 Lecture - 14 John Locke The empiricism of John

More information