Sexual Difference, Animal Difference: Derrida and Difference Worthy of its Name

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Sexual Difference, Animal Difference: Derrida and Difference Worthy of its Name"

Transcription

1 H Y P A 0 B Dispatch:..0 Journal: HYPA CE: Nikhil Journal Name Manuscript No. Author Received: No. of pages: Op: Sumesh Sexual Difference, Animal Difference: Derrida and Difference Worthy of its Name KELLY OLIVER 0 Hypatia vol., no. (Spring, 0) r by Kelly Oliver (BWUS.PDF -Feb-0 : 00 Bytes PAGES n operator=m.chackalayil) I challenge the age-old binary opposition between human and animal, not as philosophers sometimes do by claiming that humans are also animals, or that animals are capable of suffering or intelligence, but rather by questioning the very category of the animal itself. This category groups a nearly infinite variety of living beings into one concept measured in terms of humans animals are those creatures that are not human. In addition, I argue that the binary opposition between human and animal is intimately linked to the binary opposition between man and woman. Furthermore, I suggest that thinking through animal differences or differences among various living creatures opens up the possibility of thinking beyond the dualist notion of sexual difference and enables thinking toward a multiplicity of sexual differences. Reading the history of philosophy, feminists have pointed out that female, woman, and femininity often fall on the side of the animal in the human animal divide, as the frequent generic use of the word man suggests. From Plato through Hegel, Freud and beyond, women have been associated with Nature and instincts to procreate, which place them in the vicinity of the animal realm. We could say that since woman s alliance with the serpent in Genesis, Judeo-Christian traditions have remained suspicious of woman s proximity to animals. In this essay, following Derrida s first posthumously published book L animal que donc je suis (The Animal That Therefore I Am [More to Follow]) (Derrida 0), I want to take a different tack in tracing the origin of what is sometimes called the war between the sexes. Rather than try to separate woman from animal and align her with the other side of the divide, whether it is man or

2 Kelly Oliver 0 (BWUS.PDF -Feb-0 : 00 Bytes PAGES n operator=m.chackalayil) human, I will explore sexual difference from the side of animal difference. In other words, rather than try to introduce sexual difference into the history of philosophy or Western intellectual and cultural traditions by insisting on splitting man or human into two sexes as some feminist thinkers have done, I will suggest thinking beyond the category animal to multitudes of various animals. I question the age-old binary opposition between human and animal, not as philosophers sometimes do by claiming that humans are also animals, or that animals are capable of suffering or intelligence, but rather by questioning the very category of the animal itself. This category groups a nearly infinite variety of living beings into one concept measured in terms of humans animals are those creatures that are not human; other than being self-motivating lifeforms, morphologically and behaviorally, they may have little else in common. By exploding the general category animal and thereby opening thought to various animals no longer subsumed by this overly general category, we may also explode the other pole of the binary, namely human. If animals are infinitely more diverse than the binary opposition human animal suggests, then perhaps human is also more diverse than the binary allows. In this essay, I am particularly concerned with the sexual difference of man. By considering the multitudes of animal sexes, sexualities, and reproductive practices, perhaps we can expand our ways of thinking about the sexes, sexualities, and reproductive practices of man. This project, then, is a thought experiment of sorts with pedagogical effects that may help us to think beyond the sexual binary man woman. My argument is based on the following premises: first, the human animal binary erases differences among vast varieties of living creatures and among vast varieties of human cultures and individuals; second, within Judeo-Christian myths and philosophies the binary opposition between human and animal is intimately linked to the binary opposition between man and woman; third, if we move beyond the overly general concept animal to considerations of multiple species and even individuals, then we might be able to move beyond the concept human to considerations of cultural and individual differences; fourth, in terms sexual difference specifically, if we consider various sexes, sexualities, and reproductive practices of animals, we might be able to reconsider sexes, sexualities, and reproductive practices of humans beyond the tight binary man woman or homosexual heterosexual. My thesis, then, is that the binary oppositions human animal and man woman are intimately linked such that exploding the first has consequences for the second. Furthermore, my aim is to open the conceptual landscape onto differences erased by these traditional binary oppositions. To this end, I may invoke examples of the sexual practices of worms or ants or monkeys, not in order to suggest that humans are physically like these creatures or vice versa, but rather to challenge the conceptual framework that restricts us to thinking in binary terms that limit concepts to pairs,

3 Hypatia 0 (BWUS.PDF -Feb-0 : 00 Bytes PAGES n operator=m.chackalayil) especially since these pairs so easily become oppositions, hierarchies, or wars. The argument, then, is that by changing the way that we conceive of one concept in a traditional binary, we also change the way that we conceive of the other. So, by changing the way that we conceive of the animal, we change the way that we conceive of the human; and by changing the way that we conceive of man, we change the way that we conceive of woman. Furthermore, insofar as the histories of these binaries are essentially linked, by changing the relation between the two terms of the first, we change the relations between the two terms of the second. Indeed, a broader goal of this project is to move beyond thinking in pairs or in terms of two in order to move to thinking in terms of real diversity. A true ethics of difference requires moving beyond the couple toward multitudes of differences. The hope is that thinking through animal differences or differences among various living creatures opens up the possibility of thinking beyond the dualist notion of sexual difference so ingrained in our culture and enables thinking toward a multiplicity of sexual differences. In turn, dismantling the concept of animal not only opens up nearly infinite multitudes of differences among living creatures, but also opens up differences on the other side of the human animal divide to nearly infinite multitudes of differences among human beings. Differences among animals can help us to see differences among men (sic), not only obvious cultural differences, but perhaps not so obvious multitudes of sexual differences. In this sense, then, this is a pedagogical project in which animals might teach us something about our own possibilities, possibilities for thinking differently about sex, sexuality, and reproductive practices (and the relations among them). I have chosen to stage my argument through an engagement with Jacques Derrida s first posthumously published book, L animal que donc je suis, for two reasons. First, Derrida s analysis of the history of philosophy on the question of the animal is provocative, insightful, and challenges us to think beyond dualisms. Second, my hope is that this essay will be a contribution to Derrida studies that opens up new ways of reading this work in relation to his earlier work, particularly in terms of sexual difference. Derrida s philosophy can help us to rethink our conceptions of difference in general and sexual difference in particular. Throughout his work, he is concerned to deconstruct binary oppositions in order to open up philosophy and thought to multiplicity. This is why in his engagement with various philosophers, he challenges theories and rhetorics that reduce all difference to one, two, or dialectical relations among three terms. Finding resources within the history of philosophy itself, he challenges the philosophical tendency to reduce and fix into manageable systems and categories that erase or disavow multiple differences. In this regard, the subtle movements of his thought toward multiplicity and away from dogmatic fixity can benefit this project of rethinking sexual differences beyond binary oppositions.

4 Kelly Oliver 0 (BWUS.PDF -Feb-0 : 00 Bytes PAGES n operator=m.chackalayil) In addition to arguing that the differences among animals have pedagogical value for thinking about the differences among men, I present a pedagogical reading of Derrida with an eye to what his writings can teach us about sexual difference. The hope is that this analysis can shed new light on aspects of Derrida s thought that remain cryptic, if suggestive. Moreover, by putting his latest work in the context of some of his earlier work, an evolution of thought may emerge. By taking on some of the most problematic aspects of his latest work, namely his insistence on pure concepts (such as hospitality, forgiveness, and gifts) worthy of their names, hopefully this essay can provide a useful interpretation of these notions (pure, worthy of its name) that remain puzzling and unexplained in Derrida s own work. Finally, by applying Derrida s theory of the pure concept worthy of its name to the concept of difference something that Derrida never does himself I attempt to open up the concept of difference itself onto multiple differences. This is how my reading of Derrida works in the service of my broader thesis about animal difference(s) and sexual difference(s). DERRIDA S FLIRTATION WITH PHILOSOPHY ON THE QUESTION OF SEX To set the stage for my investigation into Derrida s latest work, in which he identifies a connection between animal and sexual difference, I look back to some texts where he takes up the question of sexual difference head-on, or as he might say, frontally. The issue of sexual difference is a recurring theme throughout his work. Notably, Derrida s deconstruction of various philosophers, including Hegel, Nietzsche, and Heidegger, often revolve around the erasure or negation of sexual difference in their writings. For example, in Glas, Derrida challenges Hegel s dialectical logic, which operates through the famous triple movement from position to negation to overcoming and preserving the negative moment in the final synthesis; by demonstrating that when applied to sexual difference, the dialectical method makes woman the mere negation of man, a moment necessarily overcome by the final movement of the dialectic, which reasserts the privilege of man, Derrida calls into question Hegel s entire dialectical logic. In his readings of Heidegger, Derrida challenges what he sees as a second traditional tactic with regard to sexual difference, neutralization or erasure; Dasein is sexually neuter, and as Derrida points out, Heidegger avoids talking about sexual difference, even when confronted with it in the texts upon which he comments (for example, Nietzsche s). If Hegel negates sexual difference and turns woman into man s opposite, Heidegger erases sexual difference by conceiving of a neutered or neutral Dasein. Derrida suggests that the ontological-ontic distinction that grounds Heidegger s thinking can be maintained only through the erasure of sexual difference; and once Derrida resexualizes these texts, they can no longer maintain their centrifugal force.

5 Hypatia 0 (BWUS.PDF -Feb-0 : 00 Bytes PAGES n operator=m.chackalayil) Derrida s deconstructive method, as it has come to be called, works by using resources from the history of philosophy in order to criticize or challenge that very history; he questions philosophers for erasing or disavowing sexual difference (and other types of differences) at the same time that he finds some resources in philosophy for rethinking sexual difference outside of the oppositional binary man woman. For example, in Heidegger s privileging of ontological difference over sexual difference, Derrida sees another, subtler stance on the issue of the difference between the sexes. Derrida argues that on close reading, what Heidegger erases is not sexuality or even sexual difference per se, but rather sexual difference conceived in terms of opposition (see Derrida, ). In other words, what Heidegger rejects is the tradition of turning difference into opposition, precisely the tradition that makes sexual difference into a war between the sexes. Derrida s project throughout his writings is to imagine difference differently such that this too often deadly dualism explodes into a multiplication of differences, or difference worthy of its name that does not settle into two warring opposites. Derrida asks: How did difference get deposited into the two? Or again, if one insisted on consigning difference within dual opposition, how does multiplication get arrested in difference? And in sexual difference? (, ). Derrida s analysis raises many more questions: Why are other types of difference unremarked? Why is sexual difference marked and then reduced to a binary or primary difference between two? How does difference in general, and sexual difference in particular, become conceived as opposition or war? How can we open the field to multiple differences and unlock the stranglehold of two warring opponents? In the section that follows, I will try to show that Derrida s latest work suggests, at least implicitly, that looking to the binary human animal may hold answers to some of these questions. DIFFERENCE WORTHY OF ITS NAME, OR UNREMARKED DIFFERENCE Before we turn back to the human animal opposition, it will be helpful to continue to explore some of Derrida s comments on sexual difference, starting with the relation between marked or remarked difference and what he calls the gift, which I will explain momentarily. In terms of sexual difference, Derrida insists that ultimately its marking and remarking must remain fluid. In other words, the metaphysical question what is it? can be answered always only precariously and provisionally. He argues that in order to challenge the notion of male firstness of Western metaphysics, it is necessary to leave open all categories of sexual demarcation (compare Derrida, ); otherwise, we cannot escape the binary opposition in which either the male or the female must take priority and dominate over the other. The very marking of difference the answer to the question what is it? must be open to constant

6 Kelly Oliver 0 (BWUS.PDF -Feb-0 : 00 Bytes PAGES n operator=m.chackalayil) remarking, which means that on the level of metaphysics (and therefore also on the levels of ethics and politics), it remains ultimately undecidable ; we cannot know for certain the correct answer to the question what is it? ; rather we can always only speculate given the cultural tools available to us. Derrida s work suggests that considering metaphysical questions ultimately undecidable has the practical effect of making us continually reevaluate what we know and how we act. So, while the realms of politics and even ethics may require that we make decisions based on what we believe or imagine things to be, we must be ready to revise not only those decisions but also what we believe and imagine. In this way, although undecidability is not synonymous with multiplicity, making it an operative principle gives rise to multiplicity beyond binary oppositions. In his later work, Derrida moves from insisting on undecidability to what he calls hyperbolic ethics, which is motivated by what he calls pure concepts such as the gift, hospitality, forgiveness, and democracy, concepts whose meaning and value are infinitely deferred into some (im)possible future that we imagine will be better (more ethical) than the past, what Derrida calls democracy to come. This future meaning is related to past meanings in all of their heterogeneity, which any careful etymology will help reveal. The differences at the heart of the word difference itself are instructive for how future conceptions of difference might be informed by multiple meanings that have been left behind to facilitate fixing difference into binary oppositions. Perhaps this is why, when discussing the concept of woman and femininity in Choreographies, Derrida says Such recognition [of phallogocentrism or the complicity of Western metaphysics with a notion of male firstness] should not make of either the truth value or femininity an object of knowledge (at stake are the norms of knowledge and knowledge as norm); still less should it make of them a place to inhabit, a home. It should rather permit the invention of an other inscription, one very old and very new, a displacement of bodies and places that is quite different (, ). Like Heidegger and Nietzsche before him, Derrida looks to past meanings of words in order to open up alternative futures for concepts of giving, hospitality, forgiveness, democracy, and most importantly for my purposes here, difference itself. Although Derrida does not do so explicitly, it will be instructive to apply his analysis of the gift (hospitality, forgiveness, and so on) to difference, specifically to sexual difference. Throughout his work, Derrida maintains that the gift a true or pure gift cannot be given out of duty or from expectations; it cannot be given from a position of sovereignty within an economy of exchange. As he describes it, then, what we usually think of as gifts are contaminated forms of true or pure giving, which cannot even be identified as such without falling into ruin as gift. He makes the same moves with hospitality and forgiveness. A pure hospitality or a pure forgiveness must be given without any expectations

7 Hypatia 0 (BWUS.PDF -Feb-0 : 00 Bytes PAGES n operator=m.chackalayil) for reciprocation, outside of any sort of economy of exchange monetary, in kind, psychological, or otherwise and without being contaminated by notions of sovereignty that turn giving, hospitality, or forgiveness into narcissistic power-plays I am in a position to give this to you, and so forth. It seems that Derrida uses the notions of pure gift, hospitality, and forgiveness in order to invoke the quality of deferral inherent in these notions; in other words, as Levinas might say, there is always one more gift, invitation, or olive-branch, to give. In addition to the qualification pure, he frequently uses the phrase worthy of its name, as in hospitality or forgiveness worthy of its name. This phrase adds both the dimension of value, dignity, or ethics worthy and the dimension of the name or word itself. Given that Derrida is fond of multiplying the meaning of words, demonstrating their heterogeneous etymologies, and exploiting meanings that seem at odds with one another, this idiomatic expression worthy of its name casts a strange shadow on his hyperbolic ethics. Since my interest is in how this hyperbolic ethics of pure concepts worthy of their names plays out in terms of sexual difference, I can only begin to scratch at the surface of Derrida s writings on these profound issues. But consider what it could mean to think along Derridian lines about the concept of difference itself; what would it mean to imagine a pure difference, one worthy of its name? This question may seem odd, even out of place, in relation to Derrida s project until we consider that the erasure or negation of radical we could say pure difference or alterity is precisely the operation that contaminates our everyday forms of gift-giving, hospitality, and forgiveness. In several places Derrida explicitly discusses sexual difference in terms of the gift. For example, in Women in the Beehive, he says: If the gift is calculated, if you know what you are going to give to whom, if you know what you want to give, for what reason, to whom, in view of what, etc. there is no longer any gift.... When we speak here of sexual difference, we must distinguish between opposition and difference. Opposition is two, opposition is man/woman. Difference, on the other hand, can be an indefinite number of sexes and once there is sexual difference in its classical sense an opposition of two the arrangement is such that the gift is impossible. All that you can call gift love, jouissance is absolutely forbidden, is forbidden by the dual opposition.... This does not mean that there is the gift only beyond sexuality but that the gift is beyond sexual duality. (0, ) From this passage, we learn that the gift cannot be calculated, self-conscious, represented, marked, or remarked. Love and joy, like the gift or as forms of gifts,

8 Kelly Oliver 0 (BWUS.PDF -Feb-0 : 00 Bytes PAGES n operator=m.chackalayil) are also beyond any economy of exchange, including symbolic exchange or language. Let s leave aside for the moment that this radical ethical idealism seems to set up an opposition between two realms, the realm of infinite gift or responsibility, of pure concepts, and the realm of finite exchange, or contaminated actions. 0 Instead, as a thought experiment of sorts, let s follow the Derridian question what is pure difference, worthy of its name? It would have to be a difference that cannot be calculated, self-conscious, represented, marked, or remarked. In fact, it is the marking of sexual difference as two that leads Derrida to argue that binary or oppositional sexual difference is not true difference, but rather the erasure or negation of one in favor of the other. Derrida is not taking an Irigarayan path that would insist on the binary, the two, only without the opposition, erasure, or negation. Irigaray argues that we have never actually had two because the second sex has always been subsumed into the one masculine sex, and therefore the fundamental project of our age is to think sexual difference as two (a). Derrida, on the other hand, suggests that once we split sexuality or sex into two, we are already stuck at the level of a fixed binary that does not allow for multiplicity. Indeed, fixing any number of calculable differences would have a similar effect, although binaries more easily turn into oppositions or dialectics of negation, for example, man and not-man. A marked difference becomes a calculable, self-conscious, and exchangeable difference that undermines the possibility of any true encounter with another what Derrida also calls an event (for example, see Derrida 0, ). If this is the case, then it seems that only an unremarked difference leaves open the possibility of the gift, or hospitality or forgiveness, or pure difference, worthy of its name. Derrida argues as much when speaking of various figures of unconditionality without sovereignty. In Rogues, for example, he describes the pure concept worthy of its name: A gift without calculable exchange, a gift worthy of its name, would not even appear as such to the donor or donee without the risk of reconstituting, through phenomenality and thus through its phenomenology, a circle of economic reappropriation that would just as soon annul its event (0, ). He applies the same analysis to hospitality and forgiveness. If we apply it to difference, the result is that we necessarily imagine a difference that would not appear as such, an unremarked difference. In terms of sexual difference, most obviously this would mean that we cannot reduce sexual difference to anatomical differences or to genitalia; but more than this, it means that physical or phenomenal differences remain unidentified in terms of sexual difference. What makes a difference to sexual difference remains an open question. Moreover, sexual difference necessarily gives rise to sexual differences where any binary identification becomes impossible to maintain. Sexual marks are no longer seen as the property of any individual or group.

9 Hypatia 0 (BWUS.PDF -Feb-0 : 00 Bytes PAGES n operator=m.chackalayil) Rather, as Derrida describes it in Choreographies, we have a mobile of nonidentified sexual marks. There, he asks what if we were to reach... the area of a relationship to the other where the code of sexual marks would no longer be discriminating? The relationship would not be a-sexual, far from it, but would be sexual otherwise: beyond the binary difference that governs the decorum of all codes, beyond the opposition feminine-masculine, beyond bi-sexuality as well, beyond homosexuality and heterosexuality, which come to the same thing. As I dream of saving the chance that this question offers I would like to believe in the multiplicity of sexually marked voices. I would like to believe in the masses, this indeterminable number of blended voices, this mobile of nonidentified sexual marks whose choreography can carry, divide, multiply the body of each individual, whether he be classified as man or woman according to the criteria of usage. (, ) On the practical level, this way of thinking about difference presents us with twin problems:. being able to distinguish one individual or group from another, and. being able to identify individuals with one another. Both these operations differentiation and identification/generalization are necessary to language systems. On the conceptual level, they should leave us wondering how we distinguish unremarked difference from the erasure, disavowal, or negation of difference typical of Western philosophy. By insisting on unremarked or unmarked sexual difference, don t we risk disavowing sexual difference altogether? It might be helpful to consider that in Rogues, Derrida describes his insistence on the unconditionality of the incalculable as a useful lexicon that serves a pedagogical purpose in relation to traditional Western thought (0, ). There, he also suggests that this lexicon could one day be replaced by another that will help us to say better what still remains to be said about these metonymic figures of the unconditional (). He also insists that only an unconditional hospitality can give meaning and practical rationality to a concept of hospitality (). The notions of the unconditional, the pure, the incalculable, the concept worthy of its name, teach us that our practical applications are always conditioned by social and political economies that disavow and marginalize even when they embrace differences; in other words, we cannot always easily distinguish giving from taking. They also teach us that hyperbolic ethics demands that we continue to measure our everyday practices in terms of these immeasurable conceptions of gift, hospitality, forgiveness, and difference. If we do not hold ourselves to this impossible and infinitely deferred standard, we risk the dogmatism and fixity of ideology that often leads to war and violence. It is this hyperbolic aspect of unconditional ethics that makes it

10 Kelly Oliver 0 (BWUS.PDF -Feb-0 : 00 Bytes PAGES n operator=m.chackalayil) pedagogical; our ethical ideal is like a hyperbola that necessarily remains out of reach and for this very reason can continue to guide our actions. The implications of what Derrida describes as hyperbolic ethics for conceiving of an ethics of difference are immense. First, an ethics of difference cannot be fixed into a set system of discernible characteristics. Rather, what counts as different or distinct must remain an open question. Second, for this reason, an ethics of difference cannot begin with the binary, nor can it begin with one or three, other numbers favored by philosophers. The binary, however, is especially prone to becoming opposition because it easily leads to giving priority to one pole of the binary over the other; the history of philosophy bears this out insofar as dualisms and binaries of all sorts have become hierarchies that privilege one over the other. In terms of sexual difference, thinking of difference as an open rather than closed system means imagining the possibilities of multiple sexes, sexualities, and even multiple reproductive practices. If we begin to ask why one characteristic determines the difference between beings, and furthermore how that characteristic becomes privileged, the floodgate may open onto all sorts of other differences that could come into play in sexual difference. Certainly, advances in reproductive technologies, along with research on intersex infants and the regime of male female binaries in medical science indicate that our multifarious realities do not easily fit into the model of the heterosexual couple defined as one man and one woman. In addition, alternative sexualities articulated through transgender and transsexuality movements suggest that real bodies are already breaking out of the claustrophobic categories male female or man woman. My argument is that challenging the human animal binary from the side of the animal can help to explode the man woman binary. Perhaps then our changing conceptual life can begin to catch up to our changing embodied life as diverse beings living among infinite variation in multitudes of creatures. ANIMAL PEDAGOGY Although it may not be obvious at first, Derrida s latest work on the animal also has a pedagogical dimension, particularly in relation to multiplying sexual differences. One of the central arguments of L animal que donc je suis is that the concept or name animal is an abomination, a chimera, because it defines all living creatures in relation to humans animals are those creatures that are not human. In so doing, it erases vast, even infinite, differences among species and individuals. The concept animal operates as the negation of human such that the negation of that negation we are not mere animals quickly leads to the notion that human beings are superior to animals. All animals are defined by virtue of their relation with humans, who stand opposed to the animal as the superior term of the human animal binary. Some of those creatures we call

11 0 Hypatia 0 (BWUS.PDF -Feb-0 : 00 Bytes PAGES n operator=m.chackalayil) animals, however, have more in common with human beings than they do with other animals; and taken as a whole, what we call the animal kingdom is populated with creatures that overall may have less rather than more in common. Derrida s criticisms revolve around various philosophers use of the animal, with the definitive article and singular noun that brands or marks all animals as one, and moreover marks them as opposed to humans. Within these philosophies, it is against this animal other that humans set themselves apart as human (and against woman that he sets himself apart as man). Moreover, the two binaries human animal and man woman are intimately connected in the history of Judeo-Christian thought; I will return to this claim momentarily. As we have seen, in remarks on sexual difference in Choreographies and elsewhere, Derrida not only challenges traditional philosophies that negate or erase the feminine, but also points to places where philosophers open up the possibility of thinking sexual difference otherwise. It turns out, however, that their limited attempts to acknowledge sexual difference continues to be based on an absolute limit between human and animal that perpetuates oppositional thinking that either negates or erases animal difference(s). When they do not set up man against woman, they set up man against animal. In other words, if woman does not serve as man s other in these myths of origin, then the animal does. Here again, Derrida uses the resources of philosophy against itself. He finds in those very philosophers who might be seen to open up philosophy to its others a counter-movement that continually forecloses the very possibilities for openness. In terms of sexual difference and animal difference, one is played off against the other such that opening one is premised precisely on closing the other. In this regard, we might say that philosophy is taking two steps forward and one step back. So while we may follow its lead up to a point, we must also be aware that philosophy s can be a dangerous dance. For example, recall Derrida s suggestion that Heidegger s neuter Dasein is presented as an antidote to thinking of sexual difference in oppositional terms. Heidegger posits that Dasein is before any binary opposition; Derrida argues that he places an absolute oppositional limit between Dasein and animals, which, like all oppositions, effaces the differences and leads back, following the most resistant metaphysico-dialectic tradition, to the homogeneous (, ). Dasein is not just different from other animals; it is ontologically different, specifically because it has hands for taking and giving. Derrida concludes: Man s hand then will be a thing apart not as separable organ but because it is different, dissimilar from all prehensile organs (paws, claws, talons); man s hand is far from these in an infinite way through the abyss of being (, ). The difference is not a mere ontic difference but rather an ontological one. The very distinction between ontic and ontological, however, which is foundational to Heidegger s thought, is presupposed and supported by

12 Kelly Oliver 0 (BWUS.PDF -Feb-0 : 00 Bytes PAGES n operator=m.chackalayil) the absolute limit drawn between man and animal, a limit that Derrida argues is based on supposition rather than evidence. Heidegger maintains that Dasein is distinctive in that it can grasp in a way that gives and not merely takes; but Derrida challenges the assumption that only humans give, saying Nothing is less assured than the distinction between giving and taking (, ). Indeed, for Derrida, ethics requires that we unceasingly question that very distinction. When is a gift really a gift? In what ways do we take by giving? As he does with Heidegger, Derrida also sees in Levinas s writings a moment that subverts the priority of man over woman, but it too is still based on the opposition between human and animal. For example, Derrida points out that Levinas reads the Genesis myth of origin as presenting a neuter earth creature first, and sexual difference second, after a rib is taken from the first creature to create a second (see, 0). Derrida concludes: It is not feminine sexuality that would be second but only the relationship to sexual difference. At the origin, on this side of and therefore beyond any sexual mark, there was humanity in general... (, 0). Derrida quickly points out that even this view risks privileging the masculine as first and dominant. In L animal, however, he engages Levinas on a different score, one that demonstrates how Levinas s ethical relation retains a form of humanism that is maintained against animal difference. Levinas describes the face-to-face encounter that commands us to be ethical as uniquely human. And when asked in an interview whether or not an animal has a face, he says that he cannot respond to this question (Levinas, ). Derrida works Levinas s non-response to the question in relation to a traditional division between humans and animals, namely that humans can respond while animals merely react (see Derrida 0, 0 ). Earlier in L animal, he has shown that for Descartes the distinction is even more specific: humans can respond to questions whereas animals cannot. So, in terms of man s distinctive ability to respond to questions, what does it mean when Levinas says that he cannot answer the question? Derrida follows this track in order to challenge Levinas s latent humanism and man s unique possession of the face, and therefore, of ethics. Derrida suggests that both of these nondialectical, nonhumanist, nonoppositional thinkers, Heidegger and Levinas, in the very moments at which their thinking promises to take us beyond the sexual binary, fall back into a dialectical logic of opposition in terms of humans versus animals. At the moment when their philosophies offer the possibility of a nondialectical relationship of difference that is not reduced to opposition or even to a binary, they support their openness to sexual difference with close-mindedness in terms of animal difference. In other words, within these philosophies, sexual difference is avowed only if animal differences are disavowed through the general and fixed category of the animal. Releasing us from one binary trades on reinstating the other. So, how can we begin to think

13 Hypatia 0 (BWUS.PDF -Feb-0 : 00 Bytes PAGES n operator=m.chackalayil) beyond the binary logic of man woman or human animal such that we can acknowledge multiple differences on both sides of the dash? NAMING THE ANIMALS, OR THE FALL BEFORE THE FALL Like Levinas, in L animal, Derrida also returns to the Genesis myth of creation, but his concern is with man s naming the animals. Derrida argues that in the first version of the two creation stories in Genesis, Adam, who is not yet gendered and whose rib is not yet taken to make woman, does not name the animals. It is in the second version of the creation myth that Adam both names the animals and is given woman as his companion. It is noteworthy that Adam needs a companion only because none of the other animals provides him with company or a proper mate they are not good enough for him. His sovereignty and dominion over the animals leaves him lonely and with no companion worthy of his stature among the animals. Derrida associates both Adam s sovereignty and his loneliness with his God-given right to name the animals, through which he lords over them. It is also noteworthy (something Derrida does not point out), that in this second version of the story, Adam names woman in the same way that he names other animals; indeed, he names her twice, first he calls her woman, and after they eat from the tree of knowledge, he calls her Eve (see Genesis : and :). His right to name her is evidence of his dominion over her, akin to his dominion over animals. Derrida argues that the naming of animals, particularly the word or name animal itself, is a type of Fall before the Fall. He calls it a contretemps, a notion that plays on both a sense of embarrassment and of a time between or before time. He suggests that naming marks and thereby produces both animal difference and sexual difference; the marking and remarking of these differences is precisely the forbidden knowledge that leads to Adam and Eve s expulsion from paradise. If this is the case, however, then there is a kind of Fall before the Fall in that naming marks the knowledge of man s difference, particularly his nakedness, which not only distinguishes him from the animals but also makes him aware of his sex and of his anatomical differences from woman. In other words, it sets up the possibility of the serpent leading both man and woman to the knowledge that they are naked in a way that other animals are not, that to be naked in this way is to be ashamed, and in particular that they are different in terms of their genitalia, which they feel compelled to cover with aprons made from fig leaves (see Genesis :). Both animal and sexual difference arrive at the same time as shame, heralded first by the sovereign operation of naming and next by the serpent. Man learns that unlike other animals, he marks and remarks his territory with words or names. Moreover, an animal, the snake, teaches man that he is distinct from other animals and from woman. This knowledge of his difference ushers in everything that we associate with

14 Kelly Oliver 0 (BWUS.PDF -Feb-0 : 00 Bytes PAGES n operator=m.chackalayil) humanity, from clothing and culture to time itself. Thus, within the Judeo- Christian tradition, animal difference and sexual difference are intimately associated from the beginning of time. DERRIDA S PUSSYCAT Derrida exploits the connection between animal difference and sexual difference throughout L animal, most notably in the scene with his pussycat, which he remarks is a female cat, and in front of which he is ashamed of being naked. This scene marks a complicated maneuver within Derrida s thinking about the animal. First, he describes a kind of face-to-face encounter with an animal a cat that he says is looking at his naked sex. Next, he inscribes this event with sexuality and sexual difference, which he claims has been denied to animals. Not only is he rebuking animal difference, but he is also rebuking sexual difference (although in the problematic way of attributing it now to a cat rather than to a woman). He describes the shame he feels in front of his female cat, which shatters assumptions about the binaries human animal and man woman. He plays on this notion of shame as one distinctive mark of humanity, since only humans are ashamed of being nude. In this case, though, he is ashamed in front of a cat, to which he attributes a gaze that not only makes him aware of his nudity and of his sex (like the snake in Genesis did with Adam), but that also makes him ashamed of the word animal insofar as it separates humans from all other creatures, whose differences are thereby denied. He further complicates the issue of sexual difference by calling the cat a chat-chatte (for example, in Derrida 0, ); a neologism that is translated as pussycat (with its obvious suggestion of slang names for women s genitals), but which literally means male-female cat or boy-girl cat. Like Adam before the creation of woman, this cat s gender is ambiguous or not yet marked as one or the other gender. It is a cat of one or the other sex, or of one and the other sex (Derrida 0, ). Derrida insists that his is a real cat and not a metaphorical or figurative cat; rather it is a being that he can encounter through shared bodily mortal existence: If I say it is a real cat that sees me naked, it is in order to mark its unsubstitutable singularity. When it responds in its name [Quand il répond à son nom (0, ) also can mean when it responds to its name] (whatever respond means, and that will be our question), it doesn t do so as the exemplar of a species called cat, even less so of an animal genus or realm. It is true that I identify it as a male or female cat. But even before that identification, I see it as this irreplaceable living being that one day

15 Hypatia 0 (BWUS.PDF -Feb-0 : 00 Bytes PAGES n operator=m.chackalayil) enters my space, enters this place where it can encounter me, see me, even see me naked. Nothing can ever take away from me the certainty that what we have here is an existence that refuses to be conceptualized. (0, ) This passage suggests that, although like Heidegger, when push comes to shove, Derrida makes ontological difference before sexual difference, he resists deciding which comes first. What he is trying to describe is a naked encounter with another creature before or beyond concepts and the names that betoken them, including male or female. He also suggests, however, that this nakedness may be impossible how do we encounter each other without clothing ourselves, even cats, in words? For example, doesn t the requirement that an encounter be face-to-face or frontal already privilege human interaction (which relies more on sight than smell) over animal interaction? (compare Derrida 0, ). Moreover, Derrida suggests that perhaps nudity, like pure hospitality or forgiveness, should remain untenable... might we say nudity worthy of its name? (0, ; 0, ). Throughout his writing, Derrida complicates the connections among ontological difference, animal difference, and sexual difference in ways that do not allow for identifying logical or chronological primacy. Indeed, he insists on an intimate association between animal difference and sexual difference that not only suggests that the human animal binary and the sex binary are mutually constitutive, but also suggests that by opening up animal differences to the vast varieties of animals, we might also open up sexual differences to varieties of sexes, sexualities, and genders. In L animal, Derrida describes a series of metonymical associations between sexual difference and animal difference through which hierarchies are maintained that privilege human over animal and man over woman. These metonymies revolve around the notion that humans are distinct from animals in terms of their upright posture or erect stance, which recalls man s erection as what distinguishes him from woman. The metonymy between erect posture and erect phallus leads Derrida to conclude that the modesty or shame that separates humans from animals is concentrated on man s genitals as the distinctive trait that supposedly gives him the right to dominate animals and women. His physical up-rightness both in terms of his stance and his sex give him the moral right to dominate. Derrida argues that this distinctive trait is inseparable from man s sovereignty as giving himself the right to lord over animals. He suggests that the metonymy breaks down, however, when we consider that man s erection (like the so-called instinctive reactions of animals) cannot be feinted or dissimulated: My hypothesis is that the criterion itself, the distinctive trait, is inseparable from the experience of giving itself the right, of the

16 Kelly Oliver 0 (BWUS.PDF -Feb-0 : 00 Bytes PAGES n operator=m.chackalayil) right as erection in general in the process of humanization. To the interior of a general phenomenon of erection as a passage to the verticality right [right verticality] of the upright station which distinguishes man from other mammals, it is necessary still to distinguish sexual erection from standing erect, and overall in that, of an alternating rhythm of erection and of detumesence which the male cannot dissimulate in the face-toface of copulation (another trait massively distinctive of the human accomplishment). That where this difference of desire cannot be spontaneously feinted or naturally dissimulated, the modesty (la pudeur) carries itself properly, this is to say in stopping or concentrating its metonymy on the phallic zone. (0, 0) The question of whether an animal can pretend or dissimulate is at the center of Derrida s engagement with Lacan in L animal. Lacan argues that while animals can pretend (for example, play dead), they cannot cover their tracks or feint a feint; unlike humans, they can t pretend to pretend or engage in secondorder lying. This is because they are capable only of reactions and not responses; their pretense is a reaction to their environment. Derrida challenges the distinction between reaction and response, suggesting that we cannot so easily distinguish between the two, even in humans. What we take to be human response also contains elements of reaction. Furthermore, Derrida indicates that man s erection is just as much a reaction as any animal s in that it cannot be feinted. However, given the attention on enabling and maintaining erections and the various artificial means of doing so, we might wonder why Derrida holds onto the phallus as the place where man cannot escape his animal nature. His invocation of the phallic zone as the concentration and end point of the metonymy between the posture that distinguishes man from animals and man s sex, however, along with the modesty and shame attached to the genitals and thereby metonymically to the very distinction between man and animal, not to mention the slippage between standing upright and moral rights, blurs the boundaries between nature and culture. Since Freud, the essential distinction between humans and animals turns on another twist of the phallic zone, namely castration. Within orthodox psychoanalytic theory, man s psyche is formed through the circuit of desire that revolves around the Oedipal Complex, where it is the fear of castration that carries the weight of the law that separates humans from animals; out of fear of punishment, humans give up their incestuous impulses while animals do not. Put another way, man is cut off from the source of satisfaction, which must be continually displaced and deferred. The unfulfillable nature of desire constitutes man as human. On this scenario (which takes us back at least to Hegel if

17 Hypatia 0 (BWUS.PDF -Feb-0 : 00 Bytes PAGES n operator=m.chackalayil) not all the way back to the ancient Greeks), man s desire makes him distinct from animals, which have instinctual needs but not desires. Thus, man s sense of lack motivates everything that we take to be his unique ability for progress and self-improvement. Paradoxically, then, what the animal lacks that man possesses is lack itself. Discussing various instantiations of this paradoxical position, Derrida challenges the reasoning through which it is a fault or failing in man, a lack, that gives him the right to dominate animals. He says: [I]t is paradoxically on the basis of a fault or failing in man that the latter will be made a subject who is master of nature and of the animal. From within the pit of that lack, an eminent lack, a quite different lack from that he assigns to the animal, man installs or claims in a single movement what is proper to him (the peculiarity of a man whose property it is not to have anything that is exclusively his) and his superiority over what is called animal life. This last superiority, infinite and par excellence, has as its property the fact of being at one and the same time unconditional and sacrificial. (0, ) Within this twisted logic, animals are sacrificed both as proof of humans superiority over them and as penance for humans fault or lack. Within this way of thinking, humans are unique among animals because only they can sin; only they can be evil; only they can lie; paradoxically, only they can be beastly. According to Derrida, one of humanity s greatest bestialities is the invention and use of the word animal, a word that men have given themselves the right to give (Derrida 0, 0). He concludes this agreement concerning philosophical sense and common sense that allows one to speak blithely of the Animal in the general singular is perhaps one of the greatest, and most symptomatic idiocies [bêtises] of those who call themselves humans.... One cannot speak moreover, it has never been done of the bêtise or bestiality of an animal. It would be an anthropomorphic projection of something that remains reserved to man, as the single assurance finally, and the single risk, of what is proper to man (0, ). Derrida argues that philosophers continue to use this nonsensical general singular category to corral all living creatures without regard for the most basic differences, including and most particularly sexual differences; or as Derrida says, the great philosophers continue to use an animal whose sexuality is as a matter of principle left undifferentiated (0, ). THE SEX OF INSECTS AND SEX TO COME Within the history of philosophy, the word animal stands in for all living creatures whether they are cats, birds, or barnacles and whether they are male or

The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel s Idealism

The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel s Idealism The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel s Idealism What is a great mistake? Nietzsche once said that a great error is worth more than a multitude of trivial truths. A truly great mistake

More information

Review of This Is Not Sufficient: An Essay on Animality and Human Nature in Derrida. Leonard Lawlor Columbia University Press pp.

Review of This Is Not Sufficient: An Essay on Animality and Human Nature in Derrida. Leonard Lawlor Columbia University Press pp. 97 Between the Species Review of This Is Not Sufficient: An Essay on Animality and Human Nature in Derrida Leonard Lawlor Columbia University Press 2007 192 pp., hardcover University of Dallas fgarrett@udallas.edu

More information

H U M a N I M A L I A 3:1

H U M a N I M A L I A 3:1 H U M a N I M A L I A 3:1 Samantha Noll Metaphysical Separatism and its Discontents Kelly Oliver. Animal Lessons: How They Teach Us to Be Human. New York: Columbia University Press, 2009. 376 pp. $29.50

More information

FIRST STUDY. The Existential Dialectical Basic Assumption of Kierkegaard s Analysis of Despair

FIRST STUDY. The Existential Dialectical Basic Assumption of Kierkegaard s Analysis of Despair FIRST STUDY The Existential Dialectical Basic Assumption of Kierkegaard s Analysis of Despair I 1. In recent decades, our understanding of the philosophy of philosophers such as Kant or Hegel has been

More information

Contemporary Theology I: Hegel to Death of God Theologies

Contemporary Theology I: Hegel to Death of God Theologies Contemporary Theology I: Hegel to Death of God Theologies ST503 LESSON 16 of 24 John S. Feinberg, Ph.D. Experience: Professor of Biblical and Systematic Theology, Trinity Evangelical Divinity School. At

More information

A Multitude of Selves: Contrasting the Cartesian and Nietzschean views of selfhood

A Multitude of Selves: Contrasting the Cartesian and Nietzschean views of selfhood A Multitude of Selves: Contrasting the Cartesian and Nietzschean views of selfhood One s identity as a being distinct and independent from others is vital in order to interact with the world. A self identity

More information

Theology of the Body! 1 of! 9

Theology of the Body! 1 of! 9 Theology of the Body! 1 of! 9 JOHN PAUL II, Wednesday Audience, November 14, 1979 By the Communion of Persons Man Becomes the Image of God Following the narrative of Genesis, we have seen that the "definitive"

More information

THEOLOGY IN THE FLESH

THEOLOGY IN THE FLESH 1 Introduction One might wonder what difference it makes whether we think of divine transcendence as God above us or as God ahead of us. It matters because we use these simple words to construct deep theological

More information

INTRODUCTION TO THINKING AT THE EDGE. By Eugene T. Gendlin, Ph.D.

INTRODUCTION TO THINKING AT THE EDGE. By Eugene T. Gendlin, Ph.D. INTRODUCTION TO THINKING AT THE EDGE By Eugene T. Gendlin, Ph.D. "Thinking At the Edge" (in German: "Wo Noch Worte Fehlen") stems from my course called "Theory Construction" which I taught for many years

More information

3 Supplement. Robert Bernasconi

3 Supplement. Robert Bernasconi 3 Supplement Robert Bernasconi In Of Grammatology Derrida took up the term supplément from his reading of both Jean-Jacques Rousseau and Claude Lévi-Strauss and used it to formulate what he called the

More information

Understanding Truth Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002

Understanding Truth Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002 1 Symposium on Understanding Truth By Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002 2 Precis of Understanding Truth Scott Soames Understanding Truth aims to illuminate

More information

We Are Made of Meat. An Interview with Matthew Calarco. Leonardo Caffo

We Are Made of Meat. An Interview with Matthew Calarco. Leonardo Caffo We Are Made of Meat An Interview with Matthew Calarco Leonardo Caffo PhD Student in Philosophy at University of Turin, Italy doi: 10.7358/rela-2013-002-caff leonardo.caffo@unito.it LC: Why do you think

More information

QUESTION 47. The Diversity among Things in General

QUESTION 47. The Diversity among Things in General QUESTION 47 The Diversity among Things in General After the production of creatures in esse, the next thing to consider is the diversity among them. This discussion will have three parts. First, we will

More information

Resolutio of Idealism into Atheism in Fichte

Resolutio of Idealism into Atheism in Fichte Maria Pia Mater Thomistic Week 2018 Resolutio of Idealism into Atheism in Fichte Introduction Cornelio Fabro s God in Exile, traces the progression of modern atheism from its roots in the cogito of Rene

More information

Creation Revisited Series. Creation Revisited

Creation Revisited Series. Creation Revisited Creation Revisited The creation story in Genesis, or the two accounts of creation recorded in Genesis, is the topic for this series of Life Worship Notes. My reconsideration of creation was inspired and

More information

2 FREE CHOICE The heretical thesis of Hobbes is the orthodox position today. So much is this the case that most of the contemporary literature

2 FREE CHOICE The heretical thesis of Hobbes is the orthodox position today. So much is this the case that most of the contemporary literature Introduction The philosophical controversy about free will and determinism is perennial. Like many perennial controversies, this one involves a tangle of distinct but closely related issues. Thus, the

More information

1/10. Descartes Laws of Nature

1/10. Descartes Laws of Nature 1/10 Descartes Laws of Nature Having traced some of the essential elements of his view of knowledge in the first part of the Principles of Philosophy Descartes turns, in the second part, to a discussion

More information

Phenomenal Knowledge, Dualism, and Dreams Jesse Butler, University of Central Arkansas

Phenomenal Knowledge, Dualism, and Dreams Jesse Butler, University of Central Arkansas Phenomenal Knowledge, Dualism, and Dreams Jesse Butler, University of Central Arkansas Dwight Holbrook (2015b) expresses misgivings that phenomenal knowledge can be regarded as both an objectless kind

More information

The Theology of the Body Part One The Original Unity of Man and Woman (In the Book of Genesis)

The Theology of the Body Part One The Original Unity of Man and Woman (In the Book of Genesis) The Theology of the Body Part One The Original Unity of Man and Woman (In the Book of Genesis) 1. A CONFLICT SETS THE STAGE Jesus Conflict With the Pharisees When Jesus spoke of marriage, in the gospels

More information

Environmental Ethics. Key Question - What is the nature of our ethical obligation to the environment? Friday, April 20, 12

Environmental Ethics. Key Question - What is the nature of our ethical obligation to the environment? Friday, April 20, 12 Environmental Ethics Key Question - What is the nature of our ethical obligation to the environment? I. Definitions Environment 1. Environment as surroundings Me My Environment Environment I. Definitions

More information

A Philosophical Critique of Cognitive Psychology s Definition of the Person

A Philosophical Critique of Cognitive Psychology s Definition of the Person A Philosophical Critique of Cognitive Psychology s Definition of the Person Rosa Turrisi Fuller The Pluralist, Volume 4, Number 1, Spring 2009, pp. 93-99 (Article) Published by University of Illinois Press

More information

CHRISTIAN MORALITY: A MORALITY OF THE DMNE GOOD SUPREMELY LOVED ACCORDING TO jacques MARITAIN AND john PAUL II

CHRISTIAN MORALITY: A MORALITY OF THE DMNE GOOD SUPREMELY LOVED ACCORDING TO jacques MARITAIN AND john PAUL II CHRISTIAN MORALITY: A MORALITY OF THE DMNE GOOD SUPREMELY LOVED ACCORDING TO jacques MARITAIN AND john PAUL II Denis A. Scrandis This paper argues that Christian moral philosophy proposes a morality of

More information

Phil 114, Wednesday, April 11, 2012 Hegel, The Philosophy of Right 1 7, 10 12, 14 16, 22 23, 27 33, 135, 141

Phil 114, Wednesday, April 11, 2012 Hegel, The Philosophy of Right 1 7, 10 12, 14 16, 22 23, 27 33, 135, 141 Phil 114, Wednesday, April 11, 2012 Hegel, The Philosophy of Right 1 7, 10 12, 14 16, 22 23, 27 33, 135, 141 Dialectic: For Hegel, dialectic is a process governed by a principle of development, i.e., Reason

More information

Morally Adaptive or Morally Maladaptive: A Look at Compassion, Mercy, and Bravery

Morally Adaptive or Morally Maladaptive: A Look at Compassion, Mercy, and Bravery ESSAI Volume 10 Article 17 4-1-2012 Morally Adaptive or Morally Maladaptive: A Look at Compassion, Mercy, and Bravery Alec Dorner College of DuPage Follow this and additional works at: http://dc.cod.edu/essai

More information

BENJAMIN R. BARBER. Radical Excess & Post-Modernism Presentation By Benedetta Barnabo Cachola

BENJAMIN R. BARBER. Radical Excess & Post-Modernism Presentation By Benedetta Barnabo Cachola BENJAMIN R. BARBER Radical Excess & Post-Modernism Presentation By Benedetta Barnabo Cachola BENJAMIN R. BARBER An internationally renowned political theorist, Dr. Barber( b. 1939) brings an abiding concern

More information

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory Western University Scholarship@Western 2015 Undergraduate Awards The Undergraduate Awards 2015 Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory David Hakim Western University, davidhakim266@gmail.com

More information

Introduction: Goddess and God in Our Lives

Introduction: Goddess and God in Our Lives Introduction: Goddess and God in Our Lives People who reject the popular image of God as an old white man who rules the world from outside it often find themselves at a loss for words when they try to

More information

Heidegger's What is Metaphysics?

Heidegger's What is Metaphysics? Heidegger's What is Metaphysics? Heidegger's 1929 inaugural address at Freiburg University begins by posing the question 'what is metaphysics?' only to then immediately declare that it will 'forgo' a discussion

More information

EDEN, A MODERN MYTH. Anthony Mountain

EDEN, A MODERN MYTH. Anthony Mountain Anthony Mountain EDEN, A MODERN MYTH Jacques Ellul says some extremely interesting things in his article on "Modern Myths". 1 Instead of following many thinkers in this area and asserting, for example,

More information

Vol 2 Bk 7 Outline p 486 BOOK VII. Substance, Essence and Definition CONTENTS. Book VII

Vol 2 Bk 7 Outline p 486 BOOK VII. Substance, Essence and Definition CONTENTS. Book VII Vol 2 Bk 7 Outline p 486 BOOK VII Substance, Essence and Definition CONTENTS Book VII Lesson 1. The Primacy of Substance. Its Priority to Accidents Lesson 2. Substance as Form, as Matter, and as Body.

More information

Today we re gonna start a number of lectures on two thinkers who reject the idea

Today we re gonna start a number of lectures on two thinkers who reject the idea PHI 110 Lecture 6 1 Today we re gonna start a number of lectures on two thinkers who reject the idea of personhood and of personal identity. We re gonna spend two lectures on each thinker. What I want

More information

Lecture 4. Simone de Beauvoir ( )

Lecture 4. Simone de Beauvoir ( ) Lecture 4 Simone de Beauvoir (1908 1986) 1925-9 Studies at Ecole Normale Superieure (becomes Sartre s partner) 1930 s Teaches at Lycées 1947 An Ethics of Ambiguity 1949 The Second Sex Also wrote: novels,

More information

Rule-Following and the Ontology of the Mind Abstract The problem of rule-following

Rule-Following and the Ontology of the Mind Abstract The problem of rule-following Rule-Following and the Ontology of the Mind Michael Esfeld (published in Uwe Meixner and Peter Simons (eds.): Metaphysics in the Post-Metaphysical Age. Papers of the 22nd International Wittgenstein Symposium.

More information

obey the Christian tenet You Shall Love The Neighbour facilitates the individual to overcome

obey the Christian tenet You Shall Love The Neighbour facilitates the individual to overcome In Works of Love, Søren Kierkegaard professes that (Christian) love is the bridge between the temporal and the eternal. 1 More specifically, he asserts that undertaking to unconditionally obey the Christian

More information

1 Hans Jonas, The Imperative of Responsibility: In Search of an Ethics for the Technological Age (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984), 1-10.

1 Hans Jonas, The Imperative of Responsibility: In Search of an Ethics for the Technological Age (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984), 1-10. Introduction This book seeks to provide a metaethical analysis of the responsibility ethics of two of its prominent defenders: H. Richard Niebuhr and Emmanuel Levinas. In any ethical writings, some use

More information

Fabrizio Luciano, Università degli Studi di Padova

Fabrizio Luciano, Università degli Studi di Padova Ferdinando G. Menga, L appuntamento mancato. Il giovane Heidegger e i sentieri interrotti della democrazia, Quodlibet, 2010, pp. 218, 22, ISBN 9788874623440 Fabrizio Luciano, Università degli Studi di

More information

From tolerance to neutrality: A tacit schism

From tolerance to neutrality: A tacit schism Topic: 3. Tomonobu Imamichi From tolerance to neutrality: A tacit schism Before starting this essay, it must be stated that tolerance can be broadly defined this way: the pure acceptance of the Other as

More information

Process Thought and Bridge Building: A Response to Stephen K. White. Kevin Schilbrack

Process Thought and Bridge Building: A Response to Stephen K. White. Kevin Schilbrack Archived version from NCDOCKS Institutional Repository http://libres.uncg.edu/ir/asu/ Schilbrack, Kevin.2011 Process Thought and Bridge-Building: A Response to Stephen K. White, Process Studies 40:2 (Fall-Winter

More information

Examining the nature of mind. Michael Daniels. A review of Understanding Consciousness by Max Velmans (Routledge, 2000).

Examining the nature of mind. Michael Daniels. A review of Understanding Consciousness by Max Velmans (Routledge, 2000). Examining the nature of mind Michael Daniels A review of Understanding Consciousness by Max Velmans (Routledge, 2000). Max Velmans is Reader in Psychology at Goldsmiths College, University of London. Over

More information

EXAM PREP (Semester 2: 2018) Jules Khomo. Linguistic analysis is concerned with the following question:

EXAM PREP (Semester 2: 2018) Jules Khomo. Linguistic analysis is concerned with the following question: PLEASE NOTE THAT THESE ARE MY PERSONAL EXAM PREP NOTES. ANSWERS ARE TAKEN FROM LECTURER MEMO S, STUDENT ANSWERS, DROP BOX, MY OWN, ETC. THIS DOCUMENT CAN NOT BE SOLD FOR PROFIT AS IT IS BEING SHARED AT

More information

An Interview with Alain Badiou Universal Truths and the Question of Religion Adam S. Miller Journal of Philosophy and Scripture

An Interview with Alain Badiou Universal Truths and the Question of Religion Adam S. Miller Journal of Philosophy and Scripture the field of the question of truth. Volume 3, Issue 1 Fall 2005 An Interview with Alain Badiou Universal Truths and the Question of Religion Adam S. Miller Journal of Philosophy and Scripture JPS: Would

More information

Who or what is God?, asks John Hick (Hick 2009). A theist might answer: God is an infinite person, or at least an

Who or what is God?, asks John Hick (Hick 2009). A theist might answer: God is an infinite person, or at least an John Hick on whether God could be an infinite person Daniel Howard-Snyder Western Washington University Abstract: "Who or what is God?," asks John Hick. A theist might answer: God is an infinite person,

More information

7/31/2017. Kant and Our Ineradicable Desire to be God

7/31/2017. Kant and Our Ineradicable Desire to be God Radical Evil Kant and Our Ineradicable Desire to be God 1 Immanuel Kant (1724-1804) Kant indeed marks the end of the Enlightenment: he brought its most fundamental assumptions concerning the powers of

More information

Heidegger Introduction

Heidegger Introduction Heidegger Introduction G. J. Mattey Spring, 2011 / Philosophy 151 Being and Time Being Published in 1927, under pressure Dedicated to Edmund Husserl Initially rejected as inadequate Now considered a seminal

More information

Why I Am Not a Property Dualist By John R. Searle

Why I Am Not a Property Dualist By John R. Searle 1 Why I Am Not a Property Dualist By John R. Searle I have argued in a number of writings 1 that the philosophical part (though not the neurobiological part) of the traditional mind-body problem has a

More information

EXERCISES, QUESTIONS, AND ACTIVITIES My Answers

EXERCISES, QUESTIONS, AND ACTIVITIES My Answers EXERCISES, QUESTIONS, AND ACTIVITIES My Answers Diagram and evaluate each of the following arguments. Arguments with Definitional Premises Altruism. Altruism is the practice of doing something solely because

More information

The Boundaries of Hegel s Criticism of Kant s Concept of the Noumenal

The Boundaries of Hegel s Criticism of Kant s Concept of the Noumenal Arthur Kok, Tilburg The Boundaries of Hegel s Criticism of Kant s Concept of the Noumenal Kant conceives of experience as the synthesis of understanding and intuition. Hegel argues that because Kant is

More information

The Doctrine of Creation

The Doctrine of Creation The Doctrine of Creation Week 5: Creation and Human Nature Johannes Zachhuber However much interest theological views of creation may have garnered in the context of scientific theory about the origin

More information

The Other Half of Hegel s Halfwayness: A response to Dr. Morelli s Meeting Hegel Halfway. Ben Suriano

The Other Half of Hegel s Halfwayness: A response to Dr. Morelli s Meeting Hegel Halfway. Ben Suriano 1 The Other Half of Hegel s Halfwayness: A response to Dr. Morelli s Meeting Hegel Halfway Ben Suriano I enjoyed reading Dr. Morelli s essay and found that it helpfully clarifies and elaborates Lonergan

More information

From the ELCA s Draft Social Statement on Women and Justice

From the ELCA s Draft Social Statement on Women and Justice From the ELCA s Draft Social Statement on Women and Justice NOTE: This document includes only the Core Convictions, Analysis of Patriarchy and Sexism, Resources for Resisting Patriarchy and Sexism, and

More information

PART FOUR: CATHOLIC HERMENEUTICS

PART FOUR: CATHOLIC HERMENEUTICS PART FOUR: CATHOLIC HERMENEUTICS 367 368 INTRODUCTION TO PART FOUR The term Catholic hermeneutics refers to the understanding of Christianity within Roman Catholicism. It differs from the theory and practice

More information

A CONCEPTUAL ANALYSIS OF SECULARISM AND ITS LEGITIMACY IN THE CONSTITUTIONAL DEMOCRATIC STATE

A CONCEPTUAL ANALYSIS OF SECULARISM AND ITS LEGITIMACY IN THE CONSTITUTIONAL DEMOCRATIC STATE A CONCEPTUAL ANALYSIS OF SECULARISM AND ITS LEGITIMACY IN THE CONSTITUTIONAL DEMOCRATIC STATE Adil Usturali 2015 POLICY BRIEF SERIES OVERVIEW The last few decades witnessed the rise of religion in public

More information

- We might, now, wonder whether the resulting concept of justification is sufficiently strong. According to BonJour, apparent rational insight is

- We might, now, wonder whether the resulting concept of justification is sufficiently strong. According to BonJour, apparent rational insight is BonJour I PHIL410 BonJour s Moderate Rationalism - BonJour develops and defends a moderate form of Rationalism. - Rationalism, generally (as used here), is the view according to which the primary tool

More information

Affirmative Judgments: The Sabbath of Deconstruction

Affirmative Judgments: The Sabbath of Deconstruction University of Nebraska - Lincoln DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln Faculty Publications -- Department of English English, Department of 2010 Affirmative Judgments: The Sabbath of Deconstruction

More information

In Search of a Political Ethics of Intersubjectivity: Between Hannah Arendt, Emmanuel Levinas and the Judaic

In Search of a Political Ethics of Intersubjectivity: Between Hannah Arendt, Emmanuel Levinas and the Judaic Ausgabe 1, Band 4 Mai 2008 In Search of a Political Ethics of Intersubjectivity: Between Hannah Arendt, Emmanuel Levinas and the Judaic Anna Topolski My dissertation explores the possibility of an approach

More information

Legal and Religious Dimension of Morality in Christian Literature

Legal and Religious Dimension of Morality in Christian Literature Legal and Religious Dimension of Morality in Christian Literature Abstract Dragoş Radulescu Lecturer, PhD., Dragoş Marian Rădulescu, Dimitrie Cantemir Christian University Email: dmradulescu@yahoo.com

More information

To be able to define human nature and psychological egoism. To explain how our views of human nature influence our relationships with other

To be able to define human nature and psychological egoism. To explain how our views of human nature influence our relationships with other Velasquez, Philosophy TRACK 1: CHAPTER REVIEW CHAPTER 2: Human Nature 2.1: Why Does Your View of Human Nature Matter? Learning objectives: To be able to define human nature and psychological egoism To

More information

Class #13 - The Consciousness Theory of the Self Locke, The Prince and the Cobbler Reid, Of Mr. Locke's Account of Our Personal Identity

Class #13 - The Consciousness Theory of the Self Locke, The Prince and the Cobbler Reid, Of Mr. Locke's Account of Our Personal Identity Philosophy 110W: Introduction to Philosophy Spring 2012 Hamilton College Russell Marcus Class #13 - The Consciousness Theory of the Self Locke, The Prince and the Cobbler Reid, Of Mr. Locke's Account of

More information

Qué es la filosofía? What is philosophy? Philosophy

Qué es la filosofía? What is philosophy? Philosophy Philosophy PHILOSOPHY AS A WAY OF THINKING WHAT IS IT? WHO HAS IT? WHAT IS THE DIFFERENCE BETWEEN A WAY OF THINKING AND A DISCIPLINE? It is the propensity to seek out answers to the questions that we ask

More information

Comment on Martha Nussbaum s Purified Patriotism

Comment on Martha Nussbaum s Purified Patriotism Comment on Martha Nussbaum s Purified Patriotism Patriotism is generally thought to require a special attachment to the particular: to one s own country and to one s fellow citizens. It is therefore thought

More information

Cosmopolitan Theory and the Daily Pluralism of Life

Cosmopolitan Theory and the Daily Pluralism of Life Chapter 8 Cosmopolitan Theory and the Daily Pluralism of Life Tariq Ramadan D rawing on my own experience, I will try to connect the world of philosophy and academia with the world in which people live

More information

MODELS CLARIFIED: RESPONDING TO LANGDON GILKEY. by David E. Klemm and William H. Klink

MODELS CLARIFIED: RESPONDING TO LANGDON GILKEY. by David E. Klemm and William H. Klink MODELS CLARIFIED: RESPONDING TO LANGDON GILKEY by David E. Klemm and William H. Klink Abstract. We respond to concerns raised by Langdon Gilkey. The discussion addresses the nature of theological thinking

More information

Consciousness might be defined as the perceiver of mental phenomena. We might say that there are no differences between one perceiver and another, as

Consciousness might be defined as the perceiver of mental phenomena. We might say that there are no differences between one perceiver and another, as 2. DO THE VALUES THAT ARE CALLED HUMAN RIGHTS HAVE INDEPENDENT AND UNIVERSAL VALIDITY, OR ARE THEY HISTORICALLY AND CULTURALLY RELATIVE HUMAN INVENTIONS? Human rights significantly influence the fundamental

More information

ISSA Proceedings 2002 Dissociation And Its Relation To Theory Of Argument

ISSA Proceedings 2002 Dissociation And Its Relation To Theory Of Argument ISSA Proceedings 2002 Dissociation And Its Relation To Theory Of Argument 1. Introduction According to Chaim Perelman and Lucie Olbrechts-Tyteca (1969, 190), association and dissociation are the two schemes

More information

III Knowledge is true belief based on argument. Plato, Theaetetus, 201 c-d Is Justified True Belief Knowledge? Edmund Gettier

III Knowledge is true belief based on argument. Plato, Theaetetus, 201 c-d Is Justified True Belief Knowledge? Edmund Gettier III Knowledge is true belief based on argument. Plato, Theaetetus, 201 c-d Is Justified True Belief Knowledge? Edmund Gettier In Theaetetus Plato introduced the definition of knowledge which is often translated

More information

Freedom and servitude: the master and slave dialectic in Hegel's Phenomenology of Spirit

Freedom and servitude: the master and slave dialectic in Hegel's Phenomenology of Spirit Boston University OpenBU Theses & Dissertations http://open.bu.edu Boston University Theses & Dissertations 2014 Freedom and servitude: the master and slave dialectic in Hegel's Phenomenology of Spirit

More information

GCE. Religious Studies. Mark Scheme for June Advanced GCE Unit G585: Developments in Christian Theology. Oxford Cambridge and RSA Examinations

GCE. Religious Studies. Mark Scheme for June Advanced GCE Unit G585: Developments in Christian Theology. Oxford Cambridge and RSA Examinations GCE Religious Studies Advanced GCE Unit G585: Developments in Christian Theology Mark Scheme for June 2011 Oxford Cambridge and RSA Examinations OCR (Oxford Cambridge and RSA) is a leading UK awarding

More information

I. THE PHILOSOPHY OF DIALOGUE A. Philosophy in General

I. THE PHILOSOPHY OF DIALOGUE A. Philosophy in General 16 Martin Buber these dialogues are continuations of personal dialogues of long standing, like those with Hugo Bergmann and Eugen Rosenstock-Huessy; one is directly taken from a "trialogue" of correspondence

More information

The Paradox of the stone and two concepts of omnipotence

The Paradox of the stone and two concepts of omnipotence Filo Sofija Nr 30 (2015/3), s. 239-246 ISSN 1642-3267 Jacek Wojtysiak John Paul II Catholic University of Lublin The Paradox of the stone and two concepts of omnipotence Introduction The history of science

More information

Robert Kiely Office Hours: Monday 4:15 6:00; Wednesday 1-3; Thursday 2-3

Robert Kiely Office Hours: Monday 4:15 6:00; Wednesday 1-3; Thursday 2-3 A History of Philosophy: Nature, Certainty, and the Self Fall, 2014 Robert Kiely oldstuff@imsa.edu Office Hours: Monday 4:15 6:00; Wednesday 1-3; Thursday 2-3 Description How do we know what we know? Epistemology,

More information

Transsexual(s and) Becoming

Transsexual(s and) Becoming Transsexual(s and) Becoming A Theological Analysis by Carrie Elizabeth Delmore Harry Benjamin created the term transsexuality in the first half of the twentieth century to describe the phenomenon of people

More information

Ludwig Feuerbach The Essence of Christianity (excerpts) 1 PHIL101 Prof. Oakes updated: 10/23/13 9:10 AM. Section III: How do I know? Reading III.

Ludwig Feuerbach The Essence of Christianity (excerpts) 1 PHIL101 Prof. Oakes updated: 10/23/13 9:10 AM. Section III: How do I know? Reading III. Ludwig Feuerbach The Essence of Christianity (excerpts) 1 PHIL101 Prof. Oakes updated: 10/23/13 9:10 AM Section III: How do I know? Reading III.6 The German philosopher, Ludwig Feuerbach, develops a humanist

More information

Death and Discourse: An Inquiry into Meaning and Disruption James R. Goebel California State University, Fullerton

Death and Discourse: An Inquiry into Meaning and Disruption James R. Goebel California State University, Fullerton Death and Discourse: An Inquiry into Meaning and Disruption James R. Goebel California State University, Fullerton Abstract: In Being and Nothingness, Jean-Paul Sartre vehemently argues that we must assume

More information

My Notes. Saturday, February 16, :42 AM

My Notes. Saturday, February 16, :42 AM Genesis 1-3 + TOB Page 1 My Notes Saturday, February 16, 2008 10:42 AM Opening Prayer Introduction stuff The book is $5.50 We are done with the books Read 1 Peter 3:15-16a Genesis - General Two accounts

More information

It doesn t take long in reading the Critique before we are faced with interpretive challenges. Consider the very first sentence in the A edition:

It doesn t take long in reading the Critique before we are faced with interpretive challenges. Consider the very first sentence in the A edition: The Preface(s) to the Critique of Pure Reason It doesn t take long in reading the Critique before we are faced with interpretive challenges. Consider the very first sentence in the A edition: Human reason

More information

1/12. The A Paralogisms

1/12. The A Paralogisms 1/12 The A Paralogisms The character of the Paralogisms is described early in the chapter. Kant describes them as being syllogisms which contain no empirical premises and states that in them we conclude

More information

DALLAS BAPTIST UNIVERSITY THE ILLOGIC OF FAITH: FEAR AND TREMBLING IN LIGHT OF MODERNISM SUBMITTED TO THE GENTLE READER FOR SPRING CONFERENCE

DALLAS BAPTIST UNIVERSITY THE ILLOGIC OF FAITH: FEAR AND TREMBLING IN LIGHT OF MODERNISM SUBMITTED TO THE GENTLE READER FOR SPRING CONFERENCE DALLAS BAPTIST UNIVERSITY THE ILLOGIC OF FAITH: FEAR AND TREMBLING IN LIGHT OF MODERNISM SUBMITTED TO THE GENTLE READER FOR SPRING CONFERENCE BY MARK BOONE DALLAS, TEXAS APRIL 3, 2004 I. Introduction Soren

More information

Response to The Problem of the Question About Animal Ethics by Michal Piekarski

Response to The Problem of the Question About Animal Ethics by Michal Piekarski J Agric Environ Ethics DOI 10.1007/s10806-016-9627-6 REVIEW PAPER Response to The Problem of the Question About Animal Ethics by Michal Piekarski Mark Coeckelbergh 1 David J. Gunkel 2 Accepted: 4 July

More information

Being Human Prepared by Gerald Gleeson

Being Human Prepared by Gerald Gleeson Being Human Prepared by Gerald Gleeson A Reflection Paper commissioned by the Australian Catholic Bishops Conference Committee for Doctrine and Morals Chapter 1. Created and Evolved Each and every human

More information

THE FALL OF MAN. June 25, Abstract. The problems generated by a literal reading of Genesis, chapter 3

THE FALL OF MAN. June 25, Abstract. The problems generated by a literal reading of Genesis, chapter 3 THE FALL OF MAN Charles C. Munroe III FCPE Email: ccmunroeiii@msn.com June 25, 2018 Abstract The problems generated by a literal reading of Genesis, chapter 3 The Genesis story of Adam and Eve, if taken

More information

Response to Gregory Floyd s Where Does Hermeneutics Lead? Brad Elliott Stone, Loyola Marymount University ACPA 2017

Response to Gregory Floyd s Where Does Hermeneutics Lead? Brad Elliott Stone, Loyola Marymount University ACPA 2017 Response to Gregory Floyd s Where Does Hermeneutics Lead? Brad Elliott Stone, Loyola Marymount University ACPA 2017 In his paper, Floyd offers a comparative presentation of hermeneutics as found in Heidegger

More information

Quaerens Deum: The Liberty Undergraduate Journal for Philosophy of Religion

Quaerens Deum: The Liberty Undergraduate Journal for Philosophy of Religion Quaerens Deum: The Liberty Undergraduate Journal for Philosophy of Religion Volume 1 Issue 1 Volume 1, Issue 1 (Spring 2015) Article 4 April 2015 Infinity and Beyond James M. Derflinger II Liberty University,

More information

Richard L. W. Clarke, Notes REASONING

Richard L. W. Clarke, Notes REASONING 1 REASONING Reasoning is, broadly speaking, the cognitive process of establishing reasons to justify beliefs, conclusions, actions or feelings. It also refers, more specifically, to the act or process

More information

1/9. Leibniz on Descartes Principles

1/9. Leibniz on Descartes Principles 1/9 Leibniz on Descartes Principles In 1692, or nearly fifty years after the first publication of Descartes Principles of Philosophy, Leibniz wrote his reflections on them indicating the points in which

More information

AN OUTLINE OF CRITICAL THINKING

AN OUTLINE OF CRITICAL THINKING AN OUTLINE OF CRITICAL THINKING LEVELS OF INQUIRY 1. Information: correct understanding of basic information. 2. Understanding basic ideas: correct understanding of the basic meaning of key ideas. 3. Probing:

More information

The Development of Laws of Formal Logic of Aristotle

The Development of Laws of Formal Logic of Aristotle This paper is dedicated to my unforgettable friend Boris Isaevich Lamdon. The Development of Laws of Formal Logic of Aristotle The essence of formal logic The aim of every science is to discover the laws

More information

The Middle Path: A Case for the Philosophical Theologian. Leo Strauss roots the vitality of Western civilization in the ongoing conflict between

The Middle Path: A Case for the Philosophical Theologian. Leo Strauss roots the vitality of Western civilization in the ongoing conflict between Lee Anne Detzel PHI 8338 Revised: November 1, 2004 The Middle Path: A Case for the Philosophical Theologian Leo Strauss roots the vitality of Western civilization in the ongoing conflict between philosophy

More information

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg 1 In Search of the Ontological Argument Richard Oxenberg Abstract We can attend to the logic of Anselm's ontological argument, and amuse ourselves for a few hours unraveling its convoluted word-play, or

More information

Thought is Being or Thought and Being? Feuerbach and his Criticism of Hegel's Absolute Idealism by Martin Jenkins

Thought is Being or Thought and Being? Feuerbach and his Criticism of Hegel's Absolute Idealism by Martin Jenkins Thought is Being or Thought and Being? Feuerbach and his Criticism of Hegel's Absolute Idealism by Martin Jenkins Although he was once an ardent follower of the Philosophy of GWF Hegel, Ludwig Feuerbach

More information

Broad on Theological Arguments. I. The Ontological Argument

Broad on Theological Arguments. I. The Ontological Argument Broad on God Broad on Theological Arguments I. The Ontological Argument Sample Ontological Argument: Suppose that God is the most perfect or most excellent being. Consider two things: (1)An entity that

More information

Final Paper. May 13, 2015

Final Paper. May 13, 2015 24.221 Final Paper May 13, 2015 Determinism states the following: given the state of the universe at time t 0, denoted S 0, and the conjunction of the laws of nature, L, the state of the universe S at

More information

Beauvoir s Politics of Ambiguity Dr. Christine Daigle, Philosophy Department, Brock University

Beauvoir s Politics of Ambiguity Dr. Christine Daigle, Philosophy Department, Brock University Beauvoir s Politics of Ambiguity Dr. Christine Daigle, Philosophy Department, Brock University In this paper 1, I will argue that Simone de Beauvoir s The Second Sex (1949) can be read as a paradigm work

More information

Lonergan on General Transcendent Knowledge. In General Transcendent Knowledge, Chapter 19 of Insight, Lonergan does several things:

Lonergan on General Transcendent Knowledge. In General Transcendent Knowledge, Chapter 19 of Insight, Lonergan does several things: Lonergan on General Transcendent Knowledge In General Transcendent Knowledge, Chapter 19 of Insight, Lonergan does several things: 1-3--He provides a radical reinterpretation of the meaning of transcendence

More information

SOME CONSEQUENCES OF MICHAEL THOMSON S LIFE AND ACTION FOR SOCIAL PHILOSOPHY SUPPLEMENTARY VOLUME LIFE AND ACTION IN ETHICS AND POLITICS ITALO TESTA

SOME CONSEQUENCES OF MICHAEL THOMSON S LIFE AND ACTION FOR SOCIAL PHILOSOPHY SUPPLEMENTARY VOLUME LIFE AND ACTION IN ETHICS AND POLITICS ITALO TESTA SUPPLEMENTARY VOLUME LIFE AND ACTION IN ETHICS AND POLITICS SOME CONSEQUENCES OF MICHAEL THOMSON S LIFE AND ACTION FOR SOCIAL PHILOSOPHY BY ITALO TESTA 2015 Philosophy and Public Issues (New Series), Supplementary

More information

Let Us Make Man in Our Image, In Our Likeness

Let Us Make Man in Our Image, In Our Likeness Let Us Make Man in Our Image, In Our Likeness 1: 24-31 DIG: What happened on the sixth day of creation? How does the sixth day fill the third day? What two actions are taken on this day? What are the three

More information

Going beyond good and evil

Going beyond good and evil Going beyond good and evil ORIGINS AND OPPOSITES Nietzsche criticizes past philosophers for constructing a metaphysics of transcendence the idea of a true or real world, which transcends this world of

More information

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism? Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism? Author: Terence Rajivan Edward, University of Manchester. Abstract. In the sixth chapter of The View from Nowhere, Thomas Nagel attempts to identify a form of idealism.

More information

Aristotle on the Principle of Contradiction :

Aristotle on the Principle of Contradiction : Aristotle on the Principle of Contradiction : Book Gamma of the Metaphysics Robert L. Latta Having argued that there is a science which studies being as being, Aristotle goes on to inquire, at the beginning

More information

In Part I of the ETHICS, Spinoza presents his central

In Part I of the ETHICS, Spinoza presents his central TWO PROBLEMS WITH SPINOZA S ARGUMENT FOR SUBSTANCE MONISM LAURA ANGELINA DELGADO * In Part I of the ETHICS, Spinoza presents his central metaphysical thesis that there is only one substance in the universe.

More information

William Meehan Essay on Spinoza s psychology.

William Meehan Essay on Spinoza s psychology. William Meehan wmeehan@wi.edu Essay on Spinoza s psychology. Baruch (Benedictus) Spinoza is best known in the history of psychology for his theory of the emotions and for being the first modern thinker

More information