Schopenhauer, Husserl and the Invisibility of the Embodied Subject *

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Schopenhauer, Husserl and the Invisibility of the Embodied Subject *"

Transcription

1 Yaoping Zhu / Schopenhauer, Husserl and the Invisibility of the Embodied Subject META: RESEARCH IN HERMENEUTICS, PHENOMENOLOGY, AND PRACTICAL PHILOSOPHY VOL. X, NO. 2 / DECEMBER 2018: , ISSN , Schopenhauer, Husserl and the Invisibility of the Embodied Subject * Yaoping Zhu Soochow University Abstract For such refined idealists as Schopenhauer, Husserl and Wittgenstein, the correlation between the world and the subject must be recognized. Furthermore, the three commonly emphasize the distinction between the transcendental subject and the empirical subject as well as the distinction between the subject and object s mode of being. They all realized that the confusion of the transcendental subject and the empirical subject causes the paradox of that the subject as one part of the world is at the same time the a priori condition of the whole world. In the history of western Philosophy, Schopenhauer is the first to realize that the subject is no more than the invisible body, or the body playing the subject s role. Our body plays a role both as object and as subject. However, the fact does not mean that the body playing a role as a subject can be identified with the body playing a role as an object. As the subject, the body is the prerequisite of all the representations, but the body itself cannot simultaneously be represented by itself. If objects are always visible to me, then my body as a subject is invisible. Keywords: Schopenhauer, Husserl, Wittgenstein, the transcendental subject, invisibility, body Introduction For both Schopenhauer and Husserl, the correlation between the world and the subject must be recognized. Furthermore, the two commonly emphasize the distinction between the transcendental and the empirical subject as well as * The work on this paper has been supported by Chinese Government Scholarship no

2 META: Research in Hermeneutics, Phenomenology, and Practical Philosophy X (2) / 2018 the distinction between the subject and the object s mode of being. Both realize that the confusion of the transcendental subject and the empirical subject causes the paradox that the subject as one part of the world is at the same time the a priori condition of the whole world. On the one hand, the relation between the subject and the object is similar to the relation between the eye and its vision; on the other hand, the relation between the transcendental subject and the empirical subject is similar to the relation between the Seeing Eye and the seen eyes. In each of these relational pairs, the distinction between the former and the latter is that the latter is visible and the former is invisible. In the history of western Philosophy, Schopenhauer is the first to realize that the subject is no more than the invisible body or the body playing the subject s role. Our body plays a role both as object and as subject. However, before I grasp my body as an object that exists tangibly in time, in space and that is regulated by causality, I must comprehend my body directly as an invisible subject or ego. As the subject, the body is the prerequisite of all the representations, but the body itself cannot simultaneously be represented by itself. If objects are always visible to me, then my body as a subject is invisible. Inspired by Schopenhauer, Wittgenstein emphasizes that those eyes which appear in my field and can be seen by myself are not the same eyes that allow me to see. They are seen objects rather than seeing subjects. Analogously, as the metaphysical subject and the presupposed condition of the phenomenal world, I will not appear in that world. As the philosophical I, I am the limit of the world rather than an object in it. Similarly, Husserl strongly emphasized the invisibility of the subjectivistic body in his posthumously published manuscripts such as Ideas II (Husserl 1952) and To the Phenomenology of Intersubjectivity (Husserl 1973), etc. For him, the subjectivistic body and the objectivistic body are especially important to distinguish; otherwise, we enter into the paradox of our body as one part of the world while simultaneously the a priori condition of the whole world. 354

3 Yaoping Zhu / Schopenhauer, Husserl and the Invisibility of the Embodied Subject 1. Philosophy begins with the doubt and negation of the visible world s independence What is philosophy s starting point? With regard to the world in which we live, how does the philosophical attitude distinguish itself from the natural attitude? This is a question that almost every philosopher must answer. As the first philosopher who consciously calls upon the rational examination to our social and personal life, Socrates regards To know yourself as his own motto, and treats having recognized the ignorance of myself as the most significant distinction between himself as a philosopher and ordinary people. To him, this phrase means, in part, that he is the only one who realizes that the knowledge he has about the visible world is not genuine knowledge. Plato expounds on his master s doctrine most impressively in his famous cave metaphor : people in everyday life possess only illusory knowledge about things in the visible world, not truth about the ideal world. Unfortunately, almost none of them realize this fact in their entire lives, just as the bound prisoners never realize that what they see on the cave wall is nothing but a shadow of real things. As we have just seen, Socrates and Plato regard the doubt and the negation of ordinary people s natural views as the starting point of the philosophical wisdom. Analogously, Descartes treats the universal doubt of all kinds of beliefs people acquire in their everyday lives as the first step in philosophical meditation. This is the truth he tries to express through his famous formulation, I think, therefore I am. It is the insight that nothing is more reliable in this whole world than the ego or consciousness. An ego can doubt the existence of anything in the world but itself, because the ego s existence is an indispensable precondition of its activity of doubting. Its doubting activity is exactly the most obvious evidence of its existence. Descartes s philosophy has overthrown the following prejudice: in everyday life, I tend to think that is absolutely real which I see with my own eyes, hear with my own ears or touch with my own hands. However, in fact, these things are much less real than my action of seeing, hearing or touching or the I 355

4 META: Research in Hermeneutics, Phenomenology, and Practical Philosophy X (2) / 2018 who sees, hears or touches. As Descartes himself explained in the end of the Second Meditation: Surely my awareness of my own self is not merely much truer and more certain than my awareness of the wax but also much more distinct and evident. For if I judge that the wax exists from the fact that I see it, clearly this same fact entails much more evidently that I myself also exist. It is possible that what I see is not really the wax; it is possible that I do not even have eyes with which to see anything. However, when I see, or think I see (I am not here distinguishing the two), it is simply not possible that I who am now thinking am not something. By the same token, if I judge that the wax exists from the fact that I touch it, the same result follows, namely, that I exist. If I judge that it exists from the fact that I imagine it, or for any other reason, exactly the same thing follows. And the result that I have grasped in the case of the wax may be applied to everything else located outside me. (Descartes 1996, 22) In short, my seeing and touching of the wax, or I as the subject of such activities as seeing and touching, is more certain and evident than the wax. Generally, my experience or consciousness of things is more certain than the things experienced. Consciousness or thought is the only thing that cannot be doubted. Kant s Copernican revolution of philosophy also starts with the overturn of the common sense, i.e., the following prejudice about the relation between the subject and the object: cognitive objects and their forms of existence such as time, space and causality are independent of subjects, who are negatively affected by them to acquire the knowledges about them, just as Locke s theory of tabula rasa has taught us. In contrast, for Kant, objects must conform to my form of knowing to become my cognitive objects. In other words, although objects exist within the forms of time, space and causality for me, this fact does not mean that objects as things-in-themselves exist in those forms. Rather, the idea of time, space and causality in my mind causes me to believe that they exist within those forms, just as the earth s rotation rather than sun s rotation around the earth produces the appearance of the sun s rise and fall. The essential meaning of Kant s revolution lies in the fact that we must rid ourselves of the view that the visible objects are independent of the subject s consciousness of them and regard them as dependent on an invisible subject. The world 356

5 Yaoping Zhu / Schopenhauer, Husserl and the Invisibility of the Embodied Subject and objects in it are treated as appearances or representations that are given through the consciousness of the knower or subject rather the things-in-themselves, which are independent of the consciousness of ego or subject. Thus, Schopenhauer can understand the Kant s philosophy as the world is my representation. On the one hand, the objects in the visible world become appearances depending on an ego or a consciousness, rather than as independent things; on the other hand, in a striking contrast, the ego or consciousness becomes the supreme Substance, requiring nothing but itself to exist. Just as Feuerbach has noted, Kant and Fichte s transcendental idealism treats consciousness and ego as God. All things exist through the ego or consciousness, which takes the God s place and becomes the absolute reality, the measure of existence and the indispensable precondition. The supreme ego or consciousness of Kant and Fichte is the prelude of Hegel s absolute spirit. Hegel s philosophy purports to regard the thought abstracted from the human being as the sacred, absolute essence, as God. Compared to such a God, sensible individual things that are taken by common sense to be true and real become the most senseless and fleeting illusions. Only the universal or everlasting essence grasped by reflection or abstract thinking are the truth. In Hegel s own words: The universal does not exist externally to the outward eye as a universal. The kind as kind cannot be perceived: the laws of the celestial motions are not written on the sky. The universal is neither seen nor heard, its existence is only for the mind. (Hegel 1975, 35) In one word, the invisible universal that our thinking grasps is much more true and real than the individual grasped by the senses. Philosophy s task is to lead us from visible things to an Absolute by which all else is brought into being. This Absolute is an object of the mind and thought rather than the senses. For Hegel, the negation of all of sensible things in our eyes vision is the starting point of every kind of philosophy. As an outstanding historian of philosophy, Hegel has much more precise insight into the boundary between philosophy and non- 357

6 META: Research in Hermeneutics, Phenomenology, and Practical Philosophy X (2) / 2018 philosophy. He has an especially clear-minded head on the following point: philosophy must begin with the overthrow of the prejudice formed unconsciously in everyday life that the visible world and all it contains are independent. Just as Hegel emphasizes repeatedly in his Logic, philosophy distinguishes itself from ordinary consciousness by the fact that it sees the merely phenomenal character of what the latter supposes to have a self-subsistent being. (Hegel 1975, 188) In other words, philosophy treats the visible world and all it contains as decided by the other the ego or the absolute spirit. According to Hegel, this character of philosophy is manifested most vividly in Spinoza s philosophy. The significance or the greatness of Spinoza s theory lies in its abandonment of all particulars and its upholding of the unique substance. For Spinoza, God is the only substance that exists in itself and can be known through itself, while the world s particulars can exist and be known only through the substance, or God. Because Spinoza considers the world and all of its particulars as mere appearances, his philosophy is essentially an acosmism rather than an atheism or a Pantheism. (Hegel 1975, 215) For Hegel,Spinoza s suspicion and negation of the visible world and its things are the first step of all kinds of philosophy and the standard by which the philosophical attitude and natural attitude to the world can be distinguished. Therefore, thought must begin by placing itself at the standpoint of Spinozism ; to be a follower of Spinoza is the essential commencement of all philosophy. When man begins to philosophize, the soul must commence by bathing in this ether of the One Substance, in which whatever man has held as true disappears. This negation of whatever is particular, to which every philosopher must come, is the liberation of the mind and its absolute foundation. (Hegel 1996, ) 2. The negation of the pregivenness of the world by both Schopenhauer and Husserl as solipsists Even in his later years, Husserl still regarded the discovery of worldly phenomena s subjectivistic aspect as the most significant breakthrough of Logical investigations, as he noted in Crisis (Husserl 1970): 358

7 Yaoping Zhu / Schopenhauer, Husserl and the Invisibility of the Embodied Subject What is new in the Logical Investigations is found not at all in the merely ontological investigations, which had a one-sided influence contrary to the innermost sense of the work, but rather in the subjectively directed investigations (above all the fifth and sixth, in the second volume of 1901). (Husserl 1970, 234) For Husserl, the key to understanding his Phenomenology is to feel surprised by the correlation between the world and its subjective manners of givenness. On the one hand, the first significant step leading to Phenomenology is to feel shocked by the inherent correlation between the world and the world-consciousness; On the other hand, within our daily natural attitude, we are inclined to regard the world s pregivenness as reasonable and doubtless. People find it especially difficult to be free of the strongest and most universal, and at the same time most hidden, internal bond, namely, of the pregivenness of the world. (Husserl 1970,151) And this difficulty causes the following regrettable fact the correlation between world (the world of which we always speak) and its subjective manners of givenness never evoked philosophical wonder (that is, prior to the first breakthrough of transcendental phenomenology in the Logical Investigations), in spite of the fact that it had made itself felt even in pre-socratic philosophy and among the Sophists ( ) This correlation never aroused a philosophical interest of its own. (Husserl 1970, 165) In short, for Husserl,the visible world and all it contains are given as phenomena based on an invisible subject rather than as independent entities. The philosophical attitude distinguishes itself from the natural attitude by its realization of the correlation between the world and its subjective manner of givenness. Likewise, Schopenhauer also thinks that only people who enter into philosophical reflections can realized that the world is my representation, meaning that the visible world is given as representation or appearance, presupposing an I. This attitude is confirmed in his words at the beginning of his prominent masterpiece: The world is my representation : this is a truth valid to every living and knowing being, although man alone can bring it into reflective, abstract consciousness. If he really does so, philosophical discernment has dawned on him. It then becomes clear and certain to him that he does not know a sun and an earth, but only an eye that sees a sun, a hand that feels an earth; that the world around him is 359

8 META: Research in Hermeneutics, Phenomenology, and Practical Philosophy X (2) / 2018 there only as representation, in other words, only in reference to another thing, namely, that which represents, and this is himself. (Schopenhauer 1969, 3) Insofar as Schopenhauer regards the recognition that the world is my representation as the indication of the philosophical discernment, he is shocked by the inherent correlation between the world and the world-consciousness, even before Husserl. With regard to this fact, Husserl seems to have exaggerated the novelty of this breakthrough from Logical investigations. In an important note attached to the section 48 of Crisis, Husserl describes the course of his mind stretching over several decades: The first breakthrough of this universal a priori of correlation between experienced object and manners of givenness (which occurred during work on my Logical Investigations around 1898) affected me so deeply that my whole subsequent life-work has been dominated by the task of systematically elaborating on this a priori of correlation. (Husserl 1970, 166) However, clearly Schopenhauer had been affected deeply by the a priori correlation between the world and its subjective manners of givenness before Husserl. Maybe for this reason he quoted the following sentence of Jean-Jacques Rousseau before he began his own argument at the start of The World as Will and Representation: Quit thy childhood, my friend, and wake up. (Schopenhauer 1969, 2) The importance of quitting one s childhood or waking up lies in the fact that people find it difficult to realize that the visible world around them depends on themselves as those who represent. In other words, it is difficult for someone to wake up and quit the prejudice of the world s independence, an idea formed in childhood. The notion is similar to an idea Wittgenstein mentioned in his Tractatus: although the field of sight is dependent on the eye, but from nothing in the field of sight can it be concluded that it is seen from an eye. (Wittgenstein 2003, 123) In contrast, the field of sight and the objects in it appear to be independent of their manners of being given through the act of the eye s seeing. Analogously, within the natural attitude of daily life, people are inclined to think that the world is independent of the subject through which it is given. 360

9 Yaoping Zhu / Schopenhauer, Husserl and the Invisibility of the Embodied Subject The inherent correlation between the world and its subjective manners of givenness is difficult to recognize because the prejudice that the world exists in-itself is difficult to shed. People are always constrained by this prejudice, which takes root in childhood, a fact that explains why Husserl called people s prejudice of the world s pregivenness, the strongest and most universal, and at the same time most hidden, internal bond. (Husserl 1970, 151) Clearly, what Husserl calls the suspension of the natural attitude is essentially the same as what Schopenhauer calls quitting or jumping out of our childhood prejudice. Both of these states are preconditions to our recognition of the inherent correlation between the world and world-consciousness. In brief, as solipsists, both Husserl and Schopenhauer regard the negation of the world s pregivenness and the recognition of the inherent correlation between the world and its subjective manners of givenness as the first phase of philosophical discernment. 3. Moving toward the strictly carried out solipsism : from empirical idealism to transcendental idealism By suspending the natural attitude, the objective world becomes the subjective consciousness s correlate. However, for Husserl, the difficulty lies precisely here. On the one hand, the subjectivity, into which all objectivity, everything that exists at all, is resolved, can clearly be nothing other than the human consciousness; on the other hand, human consciousness itself is only a component part of the world. However, how can the human subjectivity as a component part of the world constitute the whole world? It seems as though that the subjective part of the world swallows up the whole world and thus itself too (Husserl 1970, 180), and nothing can be more absurd. While human subjectivity is a part of world, how could it play a simultaneous role as the world s condition? This problem is described as the paradox of human subjectivity. (Husserl 1970, 182) According to Husserl, this paradox originates from the confusion of the ultimately functioning-accomplishing subjects with the naively understood human being. In fact, the 361

10 META: Research in Hermeneutics, Phenomenology, and Practical Philosophy X (2) / 2018 transcendental subjects, i.e., those functioning in the constitution of the world (Husserl 1970,183) cannot be equated to human beings in the mundane world. After all, the suspension of the natural attitude or the epoche has turned the latter into phenomena. In Husserl s own words: ( ) in the epoche and in the pure focus upon the functioning egopole, and hence upon the concrete whole of life and of its intentional intermediary and final structures, it follows eo ipso that nothing human is to be found, neither soul nor psychic life nor real psychophysical human beings; all this belongs to the phenomenon, to the world as constituted pole. (Husserl 1970, 183) In short, the empirical self as a phenomenon in the constituted world should not be confused with the transcendental self as a subject who plays the role of constituting the world. Husserl s transcendental reduction mainly distinguishes the transcendental from the empirical consciousness. The transcendental reduction consists of the following two steps: first, the reduction of the world and the objects to the phenomena given by the consciousness; secondly, the reduction of the empirical to the transcendental consciousness. However, Husserl is not the first philosopher to confront the paradox of human subjectivity. In fact, Schopenhauer met a similar dilemma soon after he proffered his proposition, the world is my representation. As previously mentioned, for Schopenhauer, the world is entirely a representation; as such, it requires the knowing subject to support its existence, similar to how the field of sight requires the eye as its supporter. In his own words: Thus animals existed before men, fishes before land animals, plants before fishes, and the inorganic before that which is organic; consequently, the original mass had to go through a long series of changes before the first eye could be open. And yet the existence of this whole world remains forever dependent on that first eye that opened, were it even that of an insect. (Schopenhauer 1969, 30) However, the problem is, how can the eye of an insect as the result of a long chain of causes and effects and a component part of the world play as the substance on which the whole world is based simultaneously? As Schopenhauer himself writes: 362

11 Yaoping Zhu / Schopenhauer, Husserl and the Invisibility of the Embodied Subject Thus, we see, on the one hand, the existence of the whole world necessarily dependent on the first knowing being, however imperfect it be; on the other hand, this first knowing animal just as necessarily wholly dependent on a long chain of causes and effects which has preceded it, and in which it itself appears as a small link. These two contradictory views, to each of which we are led with equal necessity, might certainly be called as antinomy in our faculty of knowledge. (Schopenhauer 1969, 30) In my view, Schopenhauer here speaks of as the antinomy of the faculty of knowledge, which is exactly what Husserl called the paradox of human subjectivity. According to Schopenhauer, this antinomy results from the neglecting of the distinction between the subject and object s modes of being. While the object lies within the forms of space, time and causality, the subject the knower never the known does not; on the contrary, it is always presupposed by those forms themselves. (Schopenhauer 1969,5) In fact, insofar as it is taken to be a subject, the first knowing being lies outside of the causal chain. On the other hand, when it is taken as the result of a long causal chain, the first knowing animal is no longer a subject but an object. For Schopenhauer, Kant s chief merits is that he suggests the following theory: although the object lies within the form of time, space and causality, these forms are the subject s mode of knowing rather than the mode of the thing-in-itself, so they can be found and fully known, starting from the subject, even without the knowledge of the object itself. (Schopenhauer 1969, 5) To use Kant s language, time, space and causality do not belong to the thingin-itself, but only to its appearance or phenomenon, of which they are the form. (Schopenhauer 1969, 30) On the other hand, although the form of space, time and causality as forms of knowing reside a priori in our consciousness, the subject itself doesn t exist in the form of time, space and causality. In other words, as the seeing subject, the first eye that opened does not appear in its own field of sight and does not lie in the forms of time, space and causality. Conversely, when the first eye is treated as the result of the biological evolution, or as existing in the form of time, space and causality, then it becomes the seen object rather than the seeing subject. To sum up, the relation of the object and the subject is similar to that of the field of sight 363

12 META: Research in Hermeneutics, Phenomenology, and Practical Philosophy X (2) / 2018 and the eye, in which the former presupposes the latter; the two do not coexist. As the supporter of the represented world, the one who represents never appears in that world; In contrast, the one who represents always lies outside of that world. Thus the above mentioned antinomy of the faculty of knowledge is removed by the following rule: the subject that plays the role of the whole world s supporter cannot be regarded simultaneously as a component part of that world. Clearly, Wittgenstein was once deeply impressed by Schopenhauer s doctrine, just as we can see in such sentences in his Tractatus as: where in the world is a metaphysical subject to be noted? You say that this case is altogether like that of the eye and the field of sight. But you do not really see the eye. (Wittgenstein 2003, 123) In other words, my eye as the precondition or supporter of my field of sight can see anything but itself; conversely, those eyes which appear in my field and can be seen by myself are not the same eyes that allow me to see. They are seen objects rather than seeing subjects. As the result, to prevent the paradox of the eye in the field of sight plays as the supporter of that field outside of that field, the seeing eye should be distinguished from the seen eyes, such as other people s eyes or my own eyes seen through a mirror. Analogously, as the metaphysical subject and the presupposed condition of the phenomenal world, I will not appear in that world. As the philosophical I, I am the limit of the world rather than an object in it. In Wittgenstein s own words, The philosophical I is not the man, not the human body or the human soul of which psychology treats, but the metaphysical subject, the limit not a part of the world. (Wittgenstein 2003, 121) In one word, the philosophical I shouldn t be confused with the concrete I which exists as the unity of the human s body and soul. At this point, Wittgenstein is clearly consisted with Schopenhauer and Husserl. For Wittgenstein, the subtle relation between the eye and its vision or that between an I and its world means, In fact, what solipsism means, is quite correct, only, it cannot be said, but it shows itself. (Wittgenstein 2003, 121) The reason that what solipsism means cannot be said lies in the following two facts: first, the relation between the subject and the object 364

13 Yaoping Zhu / Schopenhauer, Husserl and the Invisibility of the Embodied Subject cannot be regard as the relation between two parts of a world that is constituted by the subject; Second, as a picture of the world, language can be used to describe the objects in the phenomenal world and their relations, but cannot be used to describe the relation of the world with its presupposed subject. Nevertheless, when most of the solipsists take the I as the basis of the whole world, they are inclined to regard I as an object among other objects in the world. For Wittgenstein, such a view neglects the boundary between the I and I s world and is not the point of a pure and rigorous solipsism. In the solipsism strictly carried out, the I shrinks to an extentionless point and there remains one reality coordinated with it, and such kind of solipsism coincides with pure realism. (Wittgenstein 2003, 123) In my view, Wittgenstein s distinction between these two forms of solipsism has a similar motivation and function with the Husserl s distinction between transcendental and empirical idealism. 4. Schopenhauer s exposition of the body s double functions and the subject s corporeality For Schopenhauer, the world is the subject s representation, and a subject always exists as an embodied individual. To regard the world as a representation means to regard the sun as the sun seen through my eyes, to regard the earth as the earth touched by my hands, etc. In other words, the subject s knowledge of the world as representation is given entirely through the medium of a body. (Schopenhauer 1969, 99) In Schopenhauer s view, the peculiarity of my body lies mainly in its double essences and functions, which means that it is not only an object but also a subject. The distinction between my body and all kinds of other objects lies in the fact that the former appears as will in our consciousness. For example, my body appears as the appetite or sexual desire in my consciousness. In other words, will gives us information about what the body is, not only as representation, but as something over and above this, and hence what it is in itself. (Schopenhauer 1969, 103) According to Schopenhauer, by recognizing the body s double status, we attain the insight that the world is not only 365

14 META: Research in Hermeneutics, Phenomenology, and Practical Philosophy X (2) / 2018 will s representation, but also its manifestation. In fact, if the investigator himself were nothing more than the purely knowing subject (a winged cherub without a body) (Schopenhauer 1969, 99), then it would be impossible for him to understand what the world is in itself besides the mere representation of the knowing subject. On the one hand, as a subject, my body is the precondition of my representation of the whole world; on the other hand, as an object, my body exists in time, space and necessity, like other objects. Furthermore, before I know my body as an object, I grasp it directly as a subject, i.e., as will. As a subject, which knows everything but is never known, the body is the condition of the form of time, space and causality, and consequently is the condition of knowing any other things that exist as representations in the forms of time, space and causality. Although the body plays a role as both an object and a subject, the two roles cannot be identified with one another. Before I grasp my body as an object which exits tangibly in time, in space and that is regulated by causality, I has comprehended my body directly as an invisible subject or ego. As a subject, the body is the prerequisite of all representations but the body itself cannot simultaneously be represented by itself. If objects are always visible to me, then my body as a subject is invisible. For Schopenhauer, this truth is exactly what the following beautiful passage from the Sacred Upanishad tries to tell us: That which sees everything can t be seen; that which hears everything can t be heard; that which perceives everything can t be perceived; that which knows everything can t be known. It is nothing but that which sees, hears, perceives and knows everything. (Schopenhauer 1889, 166) Schopenhauer once talked about the fate of his own philosophy as follows: In short, professional philosophers do not care to learn from me, nor do they even see how much they might learn from me: that is, all that their children and their children s children will learn from me. (Schopenhauer 1889, 166) The prophecy has unfortunately come true. Schopenhauer is the first one in the western history of philosophy to credit the 366

15 Yaoping Zhu / Schopenhauer, Husserl and the Invisibility of the Embodied Subject body with supreme status, he even called the theory of the identification of body and will as the highest philosophical truth. However, only after more than one hundred years is his insight recognized as truth by such philosophers as Husserl, Merleau-Ponty, etc. 5. Husserl s phenomenological interpretation of the embodied subject s invisibility The problem of the body was not a major topic of works Husserl published during his lifetime. Rather, his elucidations of the body s double statues of the body and the invisibility of the embodied subject mainly appeared in his posthumously published manuscripts such as Ideas II (Husserl 1952), To the phenomenology of intersubjectivity (Husserl 1973), etc. According to Husserl s opinion, the body s duality is primarily reflected in the fact that the body is originally constituted in a double way. On the one hand, as a physical thing, the body has its extension, in which are included its real properties, its color, smoothness, hardness, warmth, and whatever other material qualities of that kind there are (Husserl 1952, 145); on the other hand, the body senses ; that is to say, the body can have the experience of specifically Bodily occurrences of the type we call sensings. (Husserl 1952, 146) Husserl takes the following common fact as an example to explain his point: My hand is lying on the table. I experience the table as something solid, cold, and smooth. Moving my hand over the table, I get an experience of it and its thingly determinations. At the same time, I can at any moment pay attention to my hand and find on it touchsensations, sensations of smoothness and coldness, etc. (Husserl 1952, 146) Those sensations occur on my hand and Husserl calls them localized sensations, but they are the properties of the Body as the organ of an ego or a subject rather than the properties of the body as a physical thing. Husserl takes the case of the touching of my left hand with the right hand as another example to emphasize his point: Touching my left hand, ( ) I do not just sense, but I perceive and have appearances of a soft, smooth hand ( ) But when I touch the 367

16 META: Research in Hermeneutics, Phenomenology, and Practical Philosophy X (2) / 2018 left hand I also find in it, too, series of touch-sensations, which are localized in it, though these are not constitutive of properties (such as roughness or smoothness of the hand, of this physical thing). If I speak of physical thing, left hand, then I am abstracting from these sensations. ( ) If I do include them, then it is not that the physical thing is now richer, but instead it becomes Body. It senses. (Husserl 1952, 145) In other words, my left hand can not only be perceived as a physical object; it can also play a role as a subject to perceive other objects including my right hand. In later case, it functions as the embodied ego or subject rather than a physical object. Generally, the Body s properties such as size, shape, color and temperature,etc. are its physical properties. On this occasion, it is viewed as a spatio-thingly object (Körper) rather than as an experiencing subject (Leib). (Moran 2013, 293) Thus, Husserl emphasizes the importance of distinguishing between the experiencing Body and the experienced body. The former is given through unthematized pre-reflective body-consciousness, while the latter is given through the thematized consciousness of body obtained through an act of objectivation. (Zahavi 1994, 69) Only the Body that functions as an experiencing subject is the Body in an authentic sense and in this sense, the Body is an essential precondition of the perception of any object, including the Body itself. In Husserl s own words,... in all experience of spatio-thingly objects, the Body is involved as the perceptual organ of the experiencing subject. (Husserl 1952, 144) As an experiencing subject, my unthematized Bodyconsciousness accompanies and makes possible every spatial experience, including the experience of my body viewed as a spatial thing. In conclusion, before I perceived my body as an object, I have grasped it as the experiencing subject as I can, as the organ of will; as such a subject, my body does not possess natural properties related to gender, height, weight, complexion, age, etc. My body possesses those properties only when it is viewed as an object. While my body is visible as an object, it is invisible as a subject. The corporeality of an ego or a subject cannot be viewed as a counterevidence of its invisibility. The reason why the body which plays the role of a subject cannot be looked upon as an object simultaneously lies 368

17 Yaoping Zhu / Schopenhauer, Husserl and the Invisibility of the Embodied Subject on that it is the precondition of the constitution of an object. In the example of my vision, my eyes which function as the subject of seeing cannot be regarded as the seen objects simultaneously, because they are the precondition of the vision of all other things. Including those visible parts of my own body, all of visible things can be presented to me from various distances and perspectives. On the contrary, the distance between the invisible parts of my body and me is always zero. In other words, the invisible parts of my body is always here and never over there. When I see spatial object it necessarily stands over and against my bodily standpoint; it can only be there, as opposed to my lived-body which can only be here. (Alweiss 2012, 138) In Husserl s own words, Every external perception brings with it its current spatial present and within it, the absolute zero-point of all spatial orientation. The latter is located in the very lived-body of the perceiver ( ) The zeropoint is itself nothing visible ( ) Thus, miraculously a perceptual object that we call one s own lived-body is distinctive in such a way that with each perception of an object, whatever it may be, the livedbody is always there and always co-constituted. And this object is entirely unique by virtue of the fact that it always bears within it the zero-point, the absolute Here, in relation to which every other object is a There. (Husserl 2001, 584) In brief, my lived-body is the absolute zero point of all experience. Farness, nearness, left and right make sense in relation to my lived-body. I cannot be anywhere else but here_ I can never be there because thereness is possible only in relation to my absolute standpoint. (Alweiss 2012, 139) According to Husserl s understanding, the embodied subject s invisibility causes people to tend to take the ego or subject as a spiritual substance that exists independent of the body. I see with my unseen eyes, that is to say, I am not conscious of my seeing eyes but of my eye s seeing. It seems as though I am a Specter or ghost that can see everything in the world without the naked eye. Analogously, I can touch something with my hand and become conscious of touching something without being conscious of the touching hand, and it seems as though I am a spiritual entity that can touch something without hands. (Husserl 1973, 229) Nevertheless, such a spiritual entity is essentially nothing but the invisible body. 369

18 META: Research in Hermeneutics, Phenomenology, and Practical Philosophy X (2) / 2018 In the final analysis, this mistake is caused by that we neglect the following fact: the body is both an object and a subject; as a subject, the body is incorporeal and invisible. I can be conscious of seeing something without seeing my own eyes and be conscious of touching something without touching my own hands. However, this does not mean that I am a spiritual substance that exists independent of my body. It merely means that, before I seize my eyes and hands as objects, I already grasp them as subjects of seeing or touching. My body is at first the perceiving subject rather than the perceived object. Enlightened by Husserl s phenomenology of body, Merleau-Ponty bases his entire phenomenological project on an account of bodily intentionality (Carman 1999, 205). For him, if the essence of the so-called transcendental subject is no more than the invisible body, then the sensing body itself rather than the pure consciousness should be taken as the starting point of our philosophical meditation. At this point, he tries to distinguish his own philosophy from Husserl s transcendental idealism and assimilate Heidegger s theory of being-in-theworld. In spite of that, he agrees with Husserl on the invisibility of the embodied subject: I observe external objects with my body, I handle them, examine them, walk around them, but my body itself is a thing which I do not observe: in order to be able to do so, I should need the use of a second body which itself would be unobservable. (Merleau-Ponty 1962, 104) He thus concludes, In so far as it sees or touches the world, my body can therefore be neither seen nor touched. What prevents its ever being an object, ever being completely constituted is that it is that by which there are objects. It is neither tangible nor visible in so far as it is that which sees and touches. (Merleau-Ponty 1962, 105) In another word, if we confuse the body playing a role as a subject with the one playing a role as an object, then we will be faced with the paradox of that the subject as one part of the world is at the same time the a priori condition of the whole world. So far as an owner of such an insight is concerned, Merleau-Ponty is completely consistent with Husserl, Schopenhauer and Wittgenstein. 370

19 Yaoping Zhu / Schopenhauer, Husserl and the Invisibility of the Embodied Subject REFERENCES Alweiss, Lilian. 2012, The truth of Solipsism. In Heidegger- Jahrbuch 6. Heidegger und Husserl, Herausgegeben von Rudolf Bernet, Alfred Denker und Holger Zaborowski, Freiburg: Verlag Karl Alber. Carman, Taylor The Body in Husserl and Merleau- Ponty. Philosophical Topics 27(2): Descartes, René Meditations on First Philosophy. Translated by John Cottingham. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Hegel, G. W. F The Science of Logic (The First Part of the Encyclopaedia of the Philosophical Sciences in Outline). Oxford: Oxford University Press Hegel s Lectures on the History of Philosophy. New Jersey: Humanities Press. Husserl; Edmund Ideen zu einer reinen Phänomenologie und Phänomenologischen Philosophie II. The Hague, Netherlands: Martinus Nijhoff The Crisis of European Sciences and Transcendental Phenomenology. Evanston: Northwestern University Press Zur Phänomenologie der Intersubjektivität. I/II/III. The Hague, Netherlands: Martinus Nijhoff Analyses Concerning Passive and Active Synthesis. Translated by Anthony J. Steinbock. Dorercht/Boston/London: Kluwer Academic Publishers. Merleau-Ponty; Maurice Phenomenology of Perception, Translated by Colin Smith. London: Routledge & Degan Paul. Moran, Dermot: 2013, The Phenomenology of Embodiment: Interwining and Reflexivity. In The Phenomenology of Embodied Subjectivity, edited by Rasmus Thybo Jensen and Dermot Moran, Switzerland: Springer International Publishing. 371

20 META: Research in Hermeneutics, Phenomenology, and Practical Philosophy X (2) / 2018 Schopenhauer; Arthur The World as Will and Representation. Translated by E.F.J. Payne. New York: Dover Publications, Inc Two Essays. London: George Bell and sons. Wittgenstein, Ludwig Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus. Translated by C.K.Ogden. New York: Barnes & Noble Books. Zahavi, Dan Husserl s Phenomenology of the Body. Études Phénoménologiques 19: Yaoping Zhu is professor at Soochow University and specializes in German Classical Philosophy and European Continental Philosophy, especially in Husserl and Heidegger s Phenomenology. His recent publications include Heidegger s Ontological Transformation of Husserl s Phenomenology (Soochow University Press, 2015) and other related articles. Address: Yaoping Zhu Department of Philosophy, Soochow University 199 Ren ai Road, Suzhou Jiangsu Province, P.R. China. zhuyaoping19@sina.com 372

Phenomenology: a historical perspective. The purpose of this session is to explain the historical context in which

Phenomenology: a historical perspective. The purpose of this session is to explain the historical context in which 1 Phenomenology: a historical perspective The purpose of this session is to explain the historical context in which phenomenology arises as a philosophy in the twentieth century. Etymology is the study

More information

A HOLISTIC VIEW ON KNOWLEDGE AND VALUES

A HOLISTIC VIEW ON KNOWLEDGE AND VALUES A HOLISTIC VIEW ON KNOWLEDGE AND VALUES CHANHYU LEE Emory University It seems somewhat obscure that there is a concrete connection between epistemology and ethics; a study of knowledge and a study of moral

More information

THE CRISIS OF THE SCmNCES AS EXPRESSION OF THE RADICAL LIFE-CRISIS OF EUROPEAN HUMANITY

THE CRISIS OF THE SCmNCES AS EXPRESSION OF THE RADICAL LIFE-CRISIS OF EUROPEAN HUMANITY Contents Translator's Introduction / xv PART I THE CRISIS OF THE SCmNCES AS EXPRESSION OF THE RADICAL LIFE-CRISIS OF EUROPEAN HUMANITY I. Is there, in view of their constant successes, really a crisis

More information

Kant and his Successors

Kant and his Successors Kant and his Successors G. J. Mattey Winter, 2011 / Philosophy 151 The Sorry State of Metaphysics Kant s Critique of Pure Reason (1781) was an attempt to put metaphysics on a scientific basis. Metaphysics

More information

Edmund Husserl s Transcendental Phenomenology by Wendell Allan A. Marinay

Edmund Husserl s Transcendental Phenomenology by Wendell Allan A. Marinay Edmund Husserl s Transcendental Phenomenology by Wendell Allan A. Marinay We remember Edmund Husserl as a philosopher who had a great influence on known phenomenologists like Max Scheler, Edith Stein,

More information

1/10. The Fourth Paralogism and the Refutation of Idealism

1/10. The Fourth Paralogism and the Refutation of Idealism 1/10 The Fourth Paralogism and the Refutation of Idealism The Fourth Paralogism is quite different from the three that preceded it because, although it is treated as a part of rational psychology, it main

More information

THE STUDY OF UNKNOWN AND UNKNOWABILITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY

THE STUDY OF UNKNOWN AND UNKNOWABILITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY THE STUDY OF UNKNOWN AND UNKNOWABILITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY Subhankari Pati Research Scholar Pondicherry University, Pondicherry The present aim of this paper is to highlights the shortcomings in Kant

More information

LEIBNITZ. Monadology

LEIBNITZ. Monadology LEIBNITZ Explain and discuss Leibnitz s Theory of Monads. Discuss Leibnitz s Theory of Monads. How are the Monads related to each other? What does Leibnitz understand by monad? Explain his theory of monadology.

More information

Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus (abridged version) Ludwig Wittgenstein

Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus (abridged version) Ludwig Wittgenstein Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus (abridged version) Ludwig Wittgenstein PREFACE This book will perhaps only be understood by those who have themselves already thought the thoughts which are expressed in

More information

The CopernicanRevolution

The CopernicanRevolution Immanuel Kant: The Copernican Revolution The CopernicanRevolution Immanuel Kant (1724-1804) The Critique of Pure Reason (1781) is Kant s best known work. In this monumental work, he begins a Copernican-like

More information

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras Module - 21 Lecture - 21 Kant Forms of sensibility Categories

More information

1/12. The A Paralogisms

1/12. The A Paralogisms 1/12 The A Paralogisms The character of the Paralogisms is described early in the chapter. Kant describes them as being syllogisms which contain no empirical premises and states that in them we conclude

More information

1/5. The Critique of Theology

1/5. The Critique of Theology 1/5 The Critique of Theology The argument of the Transcendental Dialectic has demonstrated that there is no science of rational psychology and that the province of any rational cosmology is strictly limited.

More information

The British Empiricism

The British Empiricism The British Empiricism Locke, Berkeley and Hume copyleft: nicolazuin.2018 nowxhere.wordpress.com The terrible heritage of Descartes: Skepticism, Empiricism, Rationalism The problem originates from the

More information

PHILOSOPHY IAS MAINS: QUESTIONS TREND ANALYSIS

PHILOSOPHY IAS MAINS: QUESTIONS TREND ANALYSIS VISION IAS www.visionias.wordpress.com www.visionias.cfsites.org www.visioniasonline.com Under the Guidance of Ajay Kumar Singh ( B.Tech. IIT Roorkee, Director & Founder : Vision IAS ) PHILOSOPHY IAS MAINS:

More information

Important dates. PSY 3360 / CGS 3325 Historical Perspectives on Psychology Minds and Machines since David Hume ( )

Important dates. PSY 3360 / CGS 3325 Historical Perspectives on Psychology Minds and Machines since David Hume ( ) PSY 3360 / CGS 3325 Historical Perspectives on Psychology Minds and Machines since 1600 Dr. Peter Assmann Spring 2018 Important dates Feb 14 Term paper draft due Upload paper to E-Learning https://elearning.utdallas.edu

More information

24.01 Classics of Western Philosophy

24.01 Classics of Western Philosophy 1 Plan: Kant Lecture #2: How are pure mathematics and pure natural science possible? 1. Review: Problem of Metaphysics 2. Kantian Commitments 3. Pure Mathematics 4. Transcendental Idealism 5. Pure Natural

More information

Contents EMPIRICISM. Logical Atomism and the beginnings of pluralist empiricism. Recap: Russell s reductionism: from maths to physics

Contents EMPIRICISM. Logical Atomism and the beginnings of pluralist empiricism. Recap: Russell s reductionism: from maths to physics Contents EMPIRICISM PHIL3072, ANU, 2015 Jason Grossman http://empiricism.xeny.net lecture 9: 22 September Recap Bertrand Russell: reductionism in physics Common sense is self-refuting Acquaintance versus

More information

1.0 OBJECTIVES. Contents. 1.0 Objectives

1.0 OBJECTIVES. Contents. 1.0 Objectives UNIT 1 Contents 1.0 Objectives PHENOMENOLOGY Phenomenology 1.1 Introducing Phenomenology 1.2 The Story of Phenomenology 1.3 The Method of Phenomenology 1.4 Intentionality of Consciousness 1.5 The Meaning

More information

Kant Lecture 4 Review Synthetic a priori knowledge

Kant Lecture 4 Review Synthetic a priori knowledge Kant Lecture 4 Review Synthetic a priori knowledge Statements involving necessity or strict universality could never be known on the basis of sense experience, and are thus known (if known at all) a priori.

More information

Examining the nature of mind. Michael Daniels. A review of Understanding Consciousness by Max Velmans (Routledge, 2000).

Examining the nature of mind. Michael Daniels. A review of Understanding Consciousness by Max Velmans (Routledge, 2000). Examining the nature of mind Michael Daniels A review of Understanding Consciousness by Max Velmans (Routledge, 2000). Max Velmans is Reader in Psychology at Goldsmiths College, University of London. Over

More information

Thought is Being or Thought and Being? Feuerbach and his Criticism of Hegel's Absolute Idealism by Martin Jenkins

Thought is Being or Thought and Being? Feuerbach and his Criticism of Hegel's Absolute Idealism by Martin Jenkins Thought is Being or Thought and Being? Feuerbach and his Criticism of Hegel's Absolute Idealism by Martin Jenkins Although he was once an ardent follower of the Philosophy of GWF Hegel, Ludwig Feuerbach

More information

A Philosophical Critique of Cognitive Psychology s Definition of the Person

A Philosophical Critique of Cognitive Psychology s Definition of the Person A Philosophical Critique of Cognitive Psychology s Definition of the Person Rosa Turrisi Fuller The Pluralist, Volume 4, Number 1, Spring 2009, pp. 93-99 (Article) Published by University of Illinois Press

More information

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras Module - 20 Lecture - 20 Critical Philosophy: Kant s objectives

More information

Rationalism. A. He, like others at the time, was obsessed with questions of truth and doubt

Rationalism. A. He, like others at the time, was obsessed with questions of truth and doubt Rationalism I. Descartes (1596-1650) A. He, like others at the time, was obsessed with questions of truth and doubt 1. How could one be certain in the absence of religious guidance and trustworthy senses

More information

III Knowledge is true belief based on argument. Plato, Theaetetus, 201 c-d Is Justified True Belief Knowledge? Edmund Gettier

III Knowledge is true belief based on argument. Plato, Theaetetus, 201 c-d Is Justified True Belief Knowledge? Edmund Gettier III Knowledge is true belief based on argument. Plato, Theaetetus, 201 c-d Is Justified True Belief Knowledge? Edmund Gettier In Theaetetus Plato introduced the definition of knowledge which is often translated

More information

To appear in The Journal of Philosophy.

To appear in The Journal of Philosophy. To appear in The Journal of Philosophy. Lucy Allais: Manifest Reality: Kant s Idealism and his Realism. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2015, pp. xi + 329. 40.00 (hb). ISBN: 9780198747130. Kant s doctrine

More information

Chapter 24. Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel: The Concepts of Being, Non-being and Becoming

Chapter 24. Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel: The Concepts of Being, Non-being and Becoming Chapter 24 Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel: The Concepts of Being, Non-being and Becoming Key Words: Romanticism, Geist, Spirit, absolute, immediacy, teleological causality, noumena, dialectical method,

More information

Freedom as Morality. UWM Digital Commons. University of Wisconsin Milwaukee. Hao Liang University of Wisconsin-Milwaukee. Theses and Dissertations

Freedom as Morality. UWM Digital Commons. University of Wisconsin Milwaukee. Hao Liang University of Wisconsin-Milwaukee. Theses and Dissertations University of Wisconsin Milwaukee UWM Digital Commons Theses and Dissertations May 2014 Freedom as Morality Hao Liang University of Wisconsin-Milwaukee Follow this and additional works at: http://dc.uwm.edu/etd

More information

Lecture 18: Rationalism

Lecture 18: Rationalism Lecture 18: Rationalism I. INTRODUCTION A. Introduction Descartes notion of innate ideas is consistent with rationalism Rationalism is a view appealing to reason as a source of knowledge or justification.

More information

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy Res Cogitans Volume 5 Issue 1 Article 20 6-4-2014 Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy Kevin Harriman Lewis & Clark College Follow this and additional works at: http://commons.pacificu.edu/rescogitans

More information

Heidegger Introduction

Heidegger Introduction Heidegger Introduction G. J. Mattey Spring, 2011 / Philosophy 151 Being and Time Being Published in 1927, under pressure Dedicated to Edmund Husserl Initially rejected as inadequate Now considered a seminal

More information

Wittgenstein on The Realm of Ineffable

Wittgenstein on The Realm of Ineffable Wittgenstein on The Realm of Ineffable by Manoranjan Mallick and Vikram S. Sirola Abstract The paper attempts to delve into the distinction Wittgenstein makes between factual discourse and moral thoughts.

More information

Kant s Copernican Revolution

Kant s Copernican Revolution Kant s Copernican Revolution While the thoughts are still fresh in my mind, let me try to pick up from where we left off in class today, and say a little bit more about Kant s claim that reason has insight

More information

Has Logical Positivism Eliminated Metaphysics?

Has Logical Positivism Eliminated Metaphysics? International Journal of Humanities and Social Science Invention ISSN (Online): 2319 7722, ISSN (Print): 2319 7714 Volume 3 Issue 11 ǁ November. 2014 ǁ PP.38-42 Has Logical Positivism Eliminated Metaphysics?

More information

Copyright 2000 Vk-Cic Vahe Karamian

Copyright 2000 Vk-Cic Vahe Karamian Kant In France and England, the Enlightenment theories were blueprints for reforms and revolutions political and economic changes came together with philosophical theory. In Germany, the Enlightenment

More information

Resolutio of Idealism into Atheism in Fichte

Resolutio of Idealism into Atheism in Fichte Maria Pia Mater Thomistic Week 2018 Resolutio of Idealism into Atheism in Fichte Introduction Cornelio Fabro s God in Exile, traces the progression of modern atheism from its roots in the cogito of Rene

More information

Introductory Kant Seminar Lecture

Introductory Kant Seminar Lecture Introductory Kant Seminar Lecture Intentionality It is not unusual to begin a discussion of Kant with a brief review of some history of philosophy. What is perhaps less usual is to start with a review

More information

Qué es la filosofía? What is philosophy? Philosophy

Qué es la filosofía? What is philosophy? Philosophy Philosophy PHILOSOPHY AS A WAY OF THINKING WHAT IS IT? WHO HAS IT? WHAT IS THE DIFFERENCE BETWEEN A WAY OF THINKING AND A DISCIPLINE? It is the propensity to seek out answers to the questions that we ask

More information

A. Aristotle D. Descartes B. Plato E. Hume

A. Aristotle D. Descartes B. Plato E. Hume A. Aristotle D. Kant B. Plato E. Mill C. Confucius 1....pleasure, and freedom from pain, are the only things desirable as ends. 2. Courage is not only the knowledge of the hopeful and the fearful, but

More information

Introduction to Philosophy PHL 221, York College Revised, Spring 2017

Introduction to Philosophy PHL 221, York College Revised, Spring 2017 Introduction to Philosophy PHL 221, York College Revised, Spring 2017 Beginnings of Philosophy: Overview of Course (1) The Origins of Philosophy and Relativism Knowledge Are you a self? Ethics: What is

More information

Contemporary Theology I: Hegel to Death of God Theologies

Contemporary Theology I: Hegel to Death of God Theologies Contemporary Theology I: Hegel to Death of God Theologies ST503 LESSON 19 of 24 John S. Feinberg, Ph.D. Experience: Professor of Biblical and Systematic Theology, Trinity Evangelical Divinity School. In

More information

FIRST STUDY. The Existential Dialectical Basic Assumption of Kierkegaard s Analysis of Despair

FIRST STUDY. The Existential Dialectical Basic Assumption of Kierkegaard s Analysis of Despair FIRST STUDY The Existential Dialectical Basic Assumption of Kierkegaard s Analysis of Despair I 1. In recent decades, our understanding of the philosophy of philosophers such as Kant or Hegel has been

More information

Divisibility, Logic, Radical Empiricism, and Metaphysics

Divisibility, Logic, Radical Empiricism, and Metaphysics Abstract: Divisibility, Logic, Radical Empiricism, and Metaphysics We will explore the problem of the manner in which the world may be divided into parts, and how this affects the application of logic.

More information

CONTENTS PREFACE

CONTENTS PREFACE CONTENTS PREFACE CHAPTER- I 1. INTRODUCTION 1.1 What is Man... 1-3 1.1.1. Concept of Man in Greek Philosophy... 3-4 1.1.2. Concept of Man in Modern Western Philosophy 1.1.3. Concept of Man in Contemporary

More information

1/6. The Second Analogy (2)

1/6. The Second Analogy (2) 1/6 The Second Analogy (2) Last time we looked at some of Kant s discussion of the Second Analogy, including the argument that is discussed most often as Kant s response to Hume s sceptical doubts concerning

More information

CONSTRUCTIVE ENGAGEMENT DIALOGUE SEARLE AND BUDDHISM ON THE NON-SELF SORAJ HONGLADAROM

CONSTRUCTIVE ENGAGEMENT DIALOGUE SEARLE AND BUDDHISM ON THE NON-SELF SORAJ HONGLADAROM Comparative Philosophy Volume 8, No. 1 (2017): 94-99 Open Access / ISSN 2151-6014 www.comparativephilosophy.org CONSTRUCTIVE ENGAGEMENT DIALOGUE SEARLE AND BUDDHISM ON THE NON-SELF SORAJ ABSTRACT: In this

More information

Chapter 25. Hegel s Absolute Idealism and the Phenomenology of Spirit

Chapter 25. Hegel s Absolute Idealism and the Phenomenology of Spirit Chapter 25 Hegel s Absolute Idealism and the Phenomenology of Spirit Key Words: Absolute idealism, contradictions, antinomies, Spirit, Absolute, absolute idealism, teleological causality, objective mind,

More information

Lecture 4: Transcendental idealism and transcendental arguments

Lecture 4: Transcendental idealism and transcendental arguments Lecture 4: Transcendental idealism and transcendental arguments Stroud s worry: - Transcendental arguments can t establish a necessary link between thought or experience and how the world is without a

More information

The Boundaries of Hegel s Criticism of Kant s Concept of the Noumenal

The Boundaries of Hegel s Criticism of Kant s Concept of the Noumenal Arthur Kok, Tilburg The Boundaries of Hegel s Criticism of Kant s Concept of the Noumenal Kant conceives of experience as the synthesis of understanding and intuition. Hegel argues that because Kant is

More information

CURRICULUM VITAE : Thomas Jack Lynch Teacher-Scholar Postdoctoral Fellow, Wake Forest University

CURRICULUM VITAE : Thomas Jack Lynch Teacher-Scholar Postdoctoral Fellow, Wake Forest University CURRICULUM VITAE STEVEN DELAY Wake Forest University Department of Philosophy Tribble Hall B306 stevendelay.com https://wfu.academia.edu/stevendelay delays@wfu.edu 336-758-2234 ACADEMIC APPOINTMENTS 2018-2019:

More information

Kant s Transcendental Idealism

Kant s Transcendental Idealism Kant s Transcendental Idealism Critique of Pure Reason Immanuel Kant Copernicus Kant s Copernican Revolution Rationalists: universality and necessity require synthetic a priori knowledge knowledge of the

More information

The Divine Nature. from Summa Theologiae (Part I, Questions 3-11) by Thomas Aquinas (~1265 AD) translated by Brian J.

The Divine Nature. from Summa Theologiae (Part I, Questions 3-11) by Thomas Aquinas (~1265 AD) translated by Brian J. The Divine Nature from Summa Theologiae (Part I, Questions 3-11) by Thomas Aquinas (~1265 AD) translated by Brian J. Shanley (2006) Question 3. Divine Simplicity Once it is grasped that something exists,

More information

Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics 1. By Tom Cumming

Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics 1. By Tom Cumming Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics 1 By Tom Cumming Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics represents Martin Heidegger's first attempt at an interpretation of Kant's Critique of Pure Reason (1781). This

More information

The Theory of Reality: A Critical & Philosophical Elaboration

The Theory of Reality: A Critical & Philosophical Elaboration 55 The Theory of Reality: A Critical & Philosophical Elaboration Anup Kumar Department of Philosophy Jagannath University Email: anupkumarjnup@gmail.com Abstract Reality is a concept of things which really

More information

GROUP A WESTERN PHILOSOPHY (40 marks)

GROUP A WESTERN PHILOSOPHY (40 marks) GROUP A WESTERN PHILOSOPHY (40 marks) Chapter 1 CONCEPT OF PHILOSOPHY (4 marks allotted) MCQ 1X2 = 2 SAQ -- 1X2 = 2 (a) Nature of Philosophy: The word Philosophy is originated from two Greek words Philos

More information

Heidegger's What is Metaphysics?

Heidegger's What is Metaphysics? Heidegger's What is Metaphysics? Heidegger's 1929 inaugural address at Freiburg University begins by posing the question 'what is metaphysics?' only to then immediately declare that it will 'forgo' a discussion

More information

Philosophy of Mathematics Kant

Philosophy of Mathematics Kant Philosophy of Mathematics Kant Owen Griffiths oeg21@cam.ac.uk St John s College, Cambridge 20/10/15 Immanuel Kant Born in 1724 in Königsberg, Prussia. Enrolled at the University of Königsberg in 1740 and

More information

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras Module - 22 Lecture - 22 Kant The idea of Reason Soul, God

More information

DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA, RIVERSIDE. Graduate course and seminars for Fall Quarter

DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA, RIVERSIDE. Graduate course and seminars for Fall Quarter DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA, RIVERSIDE Graduate course and seminars for 2012-13 Fall Quarter PHIL 275, Andrews Reath First Year Proseminar in Value Theory [Tuesday, 3-6 PM] The seminar

More information

Arkady Nedel. RAS Institute of Philosophy Tibetan Culture and Information Center in Moscow. First International Conference Buddhism and Phenomenology

Arkady Nedel. RAS Institute of Philosophy Tibetan Culture and Information Center in Moscow. First International Conference Buddhism and Phenomenology Information about the Conference: http://eng.iph.ras.ru/7_8_11_2016.htm RAS Institute of Philosophy Tibetan Culture and Information Center in Moscow First International Conference Buddhism and Phenomenology

More information

MEDITATIONS ON THE FIRST PHILOSOPHY: THE ONTOLOGICAL ARGUMENT

MEDITATIONS ON THE FIRST PHILOSOPHY: THE ONTOLOGICAL ARGUMENT MEDITATIONS ON THE FIRST PHILOSOPHY: THE ONTOLOGICAL ARGUMENT René Descartes Introduction, Donald M. Borchert DESCARTES WAS BORN IN FRANCE in 1596 and died in Sweden in 1650. His formal education from

More information

Phil 114, Wednesday, April 11, 2012 Hegel, The Philosophy of Right 1 7, 10 12, 14 16, 22 23, 27 33, 135, 141

Phil 114, Wednesday, April 11, 2012 Hegel, The Philosophy of Right 1 7, 10 12, 14 16, 22 23, 27 33, 135, 141 Phil 114, Wednesday, April 11, 2012 Hegel, The Philosophy of Right 1 7, 10 12, 14 16, 22 23, 27 33, 135, 141 Dialectic: For Hegel, dialectic is a process governed by a principle of development, i.e., Reason

More information

Projection in Hume. P J E Kail. St. Peter s College, Oxford.

Projection in Hume. P J E Kail. St. Peter s College, Oxford. Projection in Hume P J E Kail St. Peter s College, Oxford Peter.kail@spc.ox.ac.uk A while ago now (2007) I published my Projection and Realism in Hume s Philosophy (Oxford University Press henceforth abbreviated

More information

George Berkeley. The Principles of Human Knowledge. Review

George Berkeley. The Principles of Human Knowledge. Review George Berkeley The Principles of Human Knowledge Review To be is to be perceived Obvious to the Mind all those bodies which compose the earth have no subsistence without a mind, their being is to be perceived

More information

Philosophy Catalog. REQUIREMENTS FOR A MAJOR IN PHILOSOPHY: 9 courses (36 credits)

Philosophy Catalog. REQUIREMENTS FOR A MAJOR IN PHILOSOPHY: 9 courses (36 credits) Philosophy MAJOR, MINOR ASSOCIATE PROFESSORS: James Patrick, Michael VISITING ASSISTANT PROFESSOR: Charles The Hollins University philosophy major undertakes 1) to instruct students in the history of philosophy,

More information

For example brain science can tell what is happening in one s brain when one is falling in love

For example brain science can tell what is happening in one s brain when one is falling in love Summary Husserl always characterized his phenomenology as the only method for the strict grounding of science. Therefore phenomenology has often been criticized as an obsession with the system of absolutely

More information

Absolute Totality, Causality, and Quantum: The Problem of Metaphysics in the Critique of Pure Reason

Absolute Totality, Causality, and Quantum: The Problem of Metaphysics in the Critique of Pure Reason International Journal of Humanities Social Sciences and Education (IJHSSE) Volume 4, Issue 4, April 2017, PP 72-81 ISSN 2349-0373 (Print) & ISSN 2349-0381 (Online) http://dx.doi.org/10.20431/2349-0381.0404008

More information

Freedom and servitude: the master and slave dialectic in Hegel's Phenomenology of Spirit

Freedom and servitude: the master and slave dialectic in Hegel's Phenomenology of Spirit Boston University OpenBU Theses & Dissertations http://open.bu.edu Boston University Theses & Dissertations 2014 Freedom and servitude: the master and slave dialectic in Hegel's Phenomenology of Spirit

More information

THE MIND-BODY PROBLEM

THE MIND-BODY PROBLEM Jayadev Sahoo Dept. of Philosophy Pondicherry University Kalapet-605014 THE MIND-BODY PROBLEM Introduction The problem of the mind and body relationship occupies a pivotal position in the philosophy of

More information

The Representation of Logical Form: A Dilemma

The Representation of Logical Form: A Dilemma The Representation of Logical Form: A Dilemma Benjamin Ferguson 1 Introduction Throughout the Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus and especially in the 2.17 s and 4.1 s Wittgenstein asserts that propositions

More information

From Transcendental Logic to Transcendental Deduction

From Transcendental Logic to Transcendental Deduction From Transcendental Logic to Transcendental Deduction Let me see if I can say a few things to re-cap our first discussion of the Transcendental Logic, and help you get a foothold for what follows. Kant

More information

1. I live. On Possibility of Dis/Ability in Husserl s Phenomenology. Contents. Introduction 2016/12/16. Introduction

1. I live. On Possibility of Dis/Ability in Husserl s Phenomenology. Contents. Introduction 2016/12/16. Introduction PEACE VII Conference Phenomenology of Dis/Ability 16-18. December Tokyo University Komaba Campus On Possibility of Dis/Ability in Husserl s Phenomenology Shinji HAMAUZU (Osaka University, Clinical Philosophy)

More information

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras Module - 28 Lecture - 28 Linguistic turn in British philosophy

More information

Absolute Totality, Causality, and Quantum: The Problem of Metaphysics in the Critique of Pure Reason. Kazuhiko Yamamoto, Kyushu University, Japan

Absolute Totality, Causality, and Quantum: The Problem of Metaphysics in the Critique of Pure Reason. Kazuhiko Yamamoto, Kyushu University, Japan Absolute Totality, Causality, and Quantum: The Problem of Metaphysics in the Critique of Pure Reason Kazuhiko Yamamoto, Kyushu University, Japan The Asian Conference on Ethics, Religion & Philosophy 2017

More information

Response to The Problem of the Question About Animal Ethics by Michal Piekarski

Response to The Problem of the Question About Animal Ethics by Michal Piekarski J Agric Environ Ethics DOI 10.1007/s10806-016-9627-6 REVIEW PAPER Response to The Problem of the Question About Animal Ethics by Michal Piekarski Mark Coeckelbergh 1 David J. Gunkel 2 Accepted: 4 July

More information

Philosophy of Consciousness

Philosophy of Consciousness Philosophy of Consciousness Direct Knowledge of Consciousness Lecture Reading Material for Topic Two of the Free University of Brighton Philosophy Degree Written by John Thornton Honorary Reader (Sussex

More information

The Copernican Shift and Theory of Knowledge in Immanuel Kant and Edmund Husserl.

The Copernican Shift and Theory of Knowledge in Immanuel Kant and Edmund Husserl. The Copernican Shift and Theory of Knowledge in Immanuel Kant and Edmund Husserl. Matthew O Neill. BA in Politics & International Studies and Philosophy, Murdoch University, 2012. This thesis is presented

More information

This handout follows the handout on The nature of the sceptic s challenge. You should read that handout first.

This handout follows the handout on The nature of the sceptic s challenge. You should read that handout first. Michael Lacewing Three responses to scepticism This handout follows the handout on The nature of the sceptic s challenge. You should read that handout first. MITIGATED SCEPTICISM The term mitigated scepticism

More information

Appendix 1: An aphoristic summary of Ontological Investigations.

Appendix 1: An aphoristic summary of Ontological Investigations. Appendix 1: An aphoristic summary of Ontological Investigations. This appendix is a translation of a paper written for the Swedish journal Ord&Bild (2/1986). It contains a summary of my views in Ontological

More information

Descartes and Schopenhauer on Voluntary Movement:

Descartes and Schopenhauer on Voluntary Movement: Descartes and Schopenhauer on Voluntary Movement: Why My Arm Is Lifted When I Will Lift It? Katsunori MATSUDA (Received on October 2, 2014) The purpose of this paper In the ordinary literature on modern

More information

Hegel's Circular Epistemology in the Phenomenology of Spirit and the Science of Logic

Hegel's Circular Epistemology in the Phenomenology of Spirit and the Science of Logic Duquesne University Duquesne Scholarship Collection Electronic Theses and Dissertations Spring 2013 Hegel's Circular Epistemology in the Phenomenology of Spirit and the Science of Logic Sila Ozkara Follow

More information

Jacob Martin Rump, PhD Symposium: Contemporary Work in Phenomenology Boston Phenomenology Circle Boston University, 1 April 2016

Jacob Martin Rump, PhD Symposium: Contemporary Work in Phenomenology Boston Phenomenology Circle Boston University, 1 April 2016 Comments on George Heffernan s Keynote The Question of a Meaningful Life as a Limit Problem of Phenomenology and on Husserliana 42 (Grenzprobleme der Phänomenologie) Jacob Martin Rump, PhD Symposium: Contemporary

More information

Saul Kripke, Naming and Necessity

Saul Kripke, Naming and Necessity 24.09x Minds and Machines Saul Kripke, Naming and Necessity Excerpt from Saul Kripke, Naming and Necessity (Harvard, 1980). Identity theorists have been concerned with several distinct types of identifications:

More information

Sophia Perennis. by Frithjof Schuon

Sophia Perennis. by Frithjof Schuon Sophia Perennis by Frithjof Schuon Source: Studies in Comparative Religion, Vol. 13, Nos. 3 & 4. (Summer-Autumn, 1979). World Wisdom, Inc. www.studiesincomparativereligion.com PHILOSOPHIA PERENNIS is generally

More information

Thursday, November 30, 17. Hegel s Idealism

Thursday, November 30, 17. Hegel s Idealism Hegel s Idealism G. W. F. Hegel Hegel Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel (1770-1831) was perhaps the last great philosophical system builder. His distinctively dynamic form of idealism set the stage for other

More information

On the epistemological status of mathematical objects in Plato s philosophical system

On the epistemological status of mathematical objects in Plato s philosophical system On the epistemological status of mathematical objects in Plato s philosophical system Floris T. van Vugt University College Utrecht University, The Netherlands October 22, 2003 Abstract The main question

More information

The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel s Idealism

The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel s Idealism The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel s Idealism What is a great mistake? Nietzsche once said that a great error is worth more than a multitude of trivial truths. A truly great mistake

More information

THE FREEDOM OF THE WILL By Immanuel Kant From Critique of Pure Reason (1781)

THE FREEDOM OF THE WILL By Immanuel Kant From Critique of Pure Reason (1781) THE FREEDOM OF THE WILL By Immanuel Kant From Critique of Pure Reason (1781) From: A447/B475 A451/B479 Freedom independence of the laws of nature is certainly a deliverance from restraint, but it is also

More information

Perceiving Abstract Objects

Perceiving Abstract Objects Perceiving Abstract Objects Inheriting Ohmori Shōzō's Philosophy of Perception Takashi Iida 1 1 Department of Philosophy, College of Humanities and Sciences, Nihon University 1. Introduction This paper

More information

What one needs to know to prepare for'spinoza's method is to be found in the treatise, On the Improvement

What one needs to know to prepare for'spinoza's method is to be found in the treatise, On the Improvement SPINOZA'S METHOD Donald Mangum The primary aim of this paper will be to provide the reader of Spinoza with a certain approach to the Ethics. The approach is designed to prevent what I believe to be certain

More information

A Philosophical Study of Nonmetaphysical Approach towards Human Existence

A Philosophical Study of Nonmetaphysical Approach towards Human Existence Hinthada University Research Journal, Vo. 1, No.1, 2009 147 A Philosophical Study of Nonmetaphysical Approach towards Human Existence Tun Pa May Abstract This paper is an attempt to prove why the meaning

More information

Summary of Kant s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals

Summary of Kant s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals Summary of Kant s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals Version 1.1 Richard Baron 2 October 2016 1 Contents 1 Introduction 3 1.1 Availability and licence............ 3 2 Definitions of key terms 4 3

More information

Hegel. G. J. Mattey. Winter, 2008 / Philosophy 151

Hegel. G. J. Mattey. Winter, 2008 / Philosophy 151 Hegel G. J. Mattey Winter, 2008 / Philosophy 151 Philosophy and its History Hegel was the first modern philosopher to have taken the history of philosophy to be central to own philosophy. Aristotle had

More information

SPINOZA, SUBSTANCE, AND SUBJECTIVITY IN HEGEL S LECTURES ON THE PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION

SPINOZA, SUBSTANCE, AND SUBJECTIVITY IN HEGEL S LECTURES ON THE PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION SPINOZA, SUBSTANCE, AND SUBJECTIVITY IN HEGEL S LECTURES ON THE PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION Anna Madelyn Hennessey, University of California Santa Barbara T his essay will assess Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel

More information

Realism and its competitors. Scepticism, idealism, phenomenalism

Realism and its competitors. Scepticism, idealism, phenomenalism Realism and its competitors Scepticism, idealism, phenomenalism Perceptual Subjectivism Bonjour gives the term perceptual subjectivism to the conclusion of the argument from illusion. Perceptual subjectivism

More information

Tuesday, November 11, Hegel s Idealism

Tuesday, November 11, Hegel s Idealism Hegel s Idealism G. W. F. Hegel Hegel Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel (1770-1831) was perhaps the last great philosophical system builder. His distinctively dynamic form of idealism set the stage for other

More information

1/9. The Second Analogy (1)

1/9. The Second Analogy (1) 1/9 The Second Analogy (1) This week we are turning to one of the most famous, if also longest, arguments in the Critique. This argument is both sufficiently and the interpretation of it sufficiently disputed

More information

UNIVERSITY OF CALICUT QUESTION BANK

UNIVERSITY OF CALICUT QUESTION BANK UNIVERSITY OF CALICUT SCHOOL OF DISTANCE EDUCATION B.A PHILOSOPHY (2011 ADMISSION ONWARDS) VI SEMESTER CORE COURSE MODERN WESTERN PHILOSOPHY QUESTION BANK Unit-1: Spirit of Modern Philosophy 1. Who among

More information

Descartes, Husserl, and Derrida on Cogito

Descartes, Husserl, and Derrida on Cogito Descartes, Husserl, and Derrida on Cogito Conf. Dr. Sorin SABOU Director, Research Center for Baptist Historical and Theological Studies Baptist Theological Institute of Bucharest Instructor of Biblical

More information