Gunky time and indeterminate existence

Similar documents
Aquinas' Third Way Modalized

The Problem with Complete States: Freedom, Chance and the Luck Argument

Sider, Hawley, Sider and the Vagueness Argument

5 A Modal Version of the

Against the Vagueness Argument TUOMAS E. TAHKO ABSTRACT

A Primer on Logic Part 1: Preliminaries and Vocabulary. Jason Zarri. 1. An Easy $10.00? a 3 c 2. (i) (ii) (iii) (iv)

On Finitism and the Beginning of the Universe: A Reply to Stephen Puryear. Citation Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 2016, v. 94 n. 3, p.

Material objects: composition & constitution

Vagueness in sparseness: a study in property ontology

From Necessary Truth to Necessary Existence

A Liar Paradox. Richard G. Heck, Jr. Brown University

STILL NO REDUNDANT PROPERTIES: REPLY TO WIELENBERG

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

Simplicity and Why the Universe Exists

The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel s Idealism

The cosmological argument (continued)

Counterparts and Compositional Nihilism: A Reply to A. J. Cotnoir

Final Paper. May 13, 2015

Ibn Sina on Substances and Accidents

Philosophy of Mathematics Nominalism

Published in Analysis 61:1, January Rea on Universalism. Matthew McGrath

POWERS, NECESSITY, AND DETERMINISM

By submitting this essay, I attest that it is my own work, completed in accordance with University regulations. Minh Alexander Nguyen

Why Counterpart Theory and Four-Dimensionalism are Incompatible. Suppose that God creates ex nihilo a bronze statue of a

PHILOSOPHY ESSAY ADVICE

Composition and Vagueness

Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000)

Benjamin Morison, On Location: Aristotle s Concept of Place, Oxford University Press, 2002, 202pp, $45.00, ISBN

Van Fraassen: Arguments Concerning Scientific Realism

Journal of Philosophy, Inc.

A Complex Eternity. One of the central issues in the philosophy of religion is the relationship between

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy

Merricks on the existence of human organisms

(Some More) Vagueness

Structuralism in the Philosophy of Mathematics

Figure 1 Figure 2 U S S. non-p P P

Framing the Debate over Persistence

Time travel and the open future

Mereological Ontological Arguments and Pantheism 1. which draw on the resources of mereology, i.e. the theory of the part-whole relation.

THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE

Creighton University, Oct. 13, 2016 Midwest Area Workshop on Metaphysics, Oct. 14, 2016

KAPLAN RIGIDITY, TIME, A ND MODALITY. Gilbert PLUMER

1/12. The A Paralogisms

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW

New Aristotelianism, Routledge, 2012), in which he expanded upon

USAGE STATEMENT & AGREEMENT. This document is the property of the author(s) and of

IS GOD "SIGNIFICANTLY FREE?''

Richard L. W. Clarke, Notes REASONING

BENEDIKT PAUL GÖCKE. Ruhr-Universität Bochum

What is the Nature of Logic? Judy Pelham Philosophy, York University, Canada July 16, 2013 Pan-Hellenic Logic Symposium Athens, Greece

In essence, Swinburne's argument is as follows:

Comments on Truth at A World for Modal Propositions

Names Introduced with the Help of Unsatisfied Sortal Predicates: Reply to Aranyosi

Putnam: Meaning and Reference

Between the Actual and the Trivial World

The argument from almost indiscernibles

UNCORRECTED PROOF GOD AND TIME. The University of Mississippi

Intro Viewed from a certain angle, philosophy is about what, if anything, we ought to believe.

Abstract Abstraction Abundant ontology Abundant theory of universals (or properties) Actualism A-features Agent causal libertarianism

Free will & divine foreknowledge

ANDREW E. STEINMANN S SEARCH FOR CHRONOLOGICAL GAPS IN GENESIS 5 AND 11: A REJOINDER

Dave Elder-Vass Of Babies and Bathwater. A Review of Tuukka Kaidesoja Naturalizing Critical Realist Social Ontology

ELEMENTS OF LOGIC. 1.1 What is Logic? Arguments and Propositions

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 4: Skepticism. Part 1: The Scope of Skepticism and Two Main Types of Skeptical Argument

Who or what is God?, asks John Hick (Hick 2009). A theist might answer: God is an infinite person, or at least an

The Resurrection of Material Beings: Recomposition, Compaction and Miracles

Dr. Tuomas E. Tahko 12 January 2012

2. Refutations can be stronger or weaker.

Empty Names and Two-Valued Positive Free Logic

Explanatory Indispensability and Deliberative Indispensability: Against Enoch s Analogy Alex Worsnip University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill

Philosophy Epistemology Topic 5 The Justification of Induction 1. Hume s Skeptical Challenge to Induction

Stephen Mumford Metaphysics: A Very Short Introduction Oxford University Press, Oxford ISBN: $ pages.

C. Exam #1 comments on difficult spots; if you have questions about this, please let me know. D. Discussion of extra credit opportunities

One of the central concerns in metaphysics is the nature of objects which

A note on Bishop s analysis of the causal argument for physicalism.

VI. CEITICAL NOTICES.

Presentism, persistence and trans-temporal dependence

1. Introduction Formal deductive logic Overview

Do Ordinary Objects Exist? No. * Trenton Merricks. Current Controversies in Metaphysics edited by Elizabeth Barnes. Routledge Press. Forthcoming.

Do Ordinary Objects Exist? No. * Trenton Merricks. Current Controversies in Metaphysics edited by Elizabeth Barnes. Routledge Press. Forthcoming.

Definite Descriptions and the Argument from Inference

Deflationary Nominalism s Commitment to Meinongianism

A Generalization of Hume s Thesis

Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg

The Relationship between the Truth Value of Premises and the Truth Value of Conclusions in Deductive Arguments

Situations in Which Disjunctive Syllogism Can Lead from True Premises to a False Conclusion

Does the Skeptic Win? A Defense of Moore. I. Moorean Methodology. In A Proof of the External World, Moore argues as follows:

The Appeal to Reason. Introductory Logic pt. 1

No Physical Particles for a Dispositional Monist? Baptiste Le Bihan Université de Rennes 1. Draft (Forthcoming in Philosophical Papers)

The Rejection of Skepticism

MINIMAL TRUTHMAKERS DONNCHADH O CONAILL AND TUOMAS E. TAHKO

There might be nothing: the subtraction argument improved

Forces and causes in Kant s early pre-critical writings

Anti-Metaphysicalism, Necessity, and Temporal Ontology 1

Fictionalism, Theft, and the Story of Mathematics. 1. Introduction. Philosophia Mathematica (III) 17 (2009),

Lecture 4: Transcendental idealism and transcendental arguments

A note on science and essentialism

Divine omniscience, timelessness, and the power to do otherwise

Anti-Metaphysicalism, Necessity, and Temporal Ontology 1

Transcription:

Gunky time and indeterminate existence Giuseppe Spolaore Università degli Studi di Padova Department of Philosophy, Sociology, Education and Applied Psychology Padova, Veneto Italy giuseppe.spolaore@gmail.com Article info CDD: 115 Received: 15.03.2017; Accepted: 15.03.2017 DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.1590/0100-6045.2017.v40n1.gs Keywords Event of coming to be Instant Time atom Continuum Indeterminate existence ABSTRACT The paper criticizes an argument recently presented by Ross Cameron. The argument purports to show that, if time is gunky (that is, if there are no time atoms), and if changes in existence are underwritten by events of coming to be, then there are cases of indeterminate existence. The putative reason is that, if time is gunky, then events of coming to be cannot be instantaneous, and hence, changes in existence must be gradual, non-clear-cut. The paper argues that this argument conflates two different readings of event of coming to be. Under one reading, the argument is unsound. Under the other, the argument is valid only if a further, nontrivial premise is added, which concerns the relation between time atoms, instants, and instantaneous events. The aim of this paper is to criticize an argument presented in a recent book by Ross Cameron (2015). The aim might seem modest the argument is put forth in a somewhat casual and tentative way in the book, but the reasons why the argument fails have general interest. Here are the premises of the argument: (1) Time is gunky (viz., any temporal interval has proper parts); (2) Changes in existence are underwritten by Aristotelian events of coming to be ;

82 Giuseppe Spolaore and here is the conclusion: (C) There must be cases of indeterminate existence. It is useful to break Cameron s reasoning into two parts. This is the first one: [Consider arbitrary object A and] suppose A exists, but didn t always exist. By (2) there must have been an event of A s coming to be. Given (1), this event was not instantaneous. No event is instantaneous, because there are no instants: there are only extended temporal regions, and hence every event occupies some extended temporal region. In that case, there can be no instantaneous transition from A s not existing to its existing: instead, there had to be an extended process during which A came to be. (184 185) In a nutshell, if time is gunky, then there are no instants, and so: (IC) No event of coming to be is instantaneous. Any thing comes into existence through an extended process. The second part of the reasoning leads from intermediate conclusion (IC) to (C): Now what should we say about the status of A during this event? Not that it exists [ ] for then it would have already come to be. But not that it doesn t exist, either, [ ] for there is a difference concerning A s being from before it started coming to be and now when it is coming to be. So we should say [ ] that while A is coming to be, its ontological status is indeterminate: A exists is neither determinately true (as it will be once it has come to be), but nor is it determinately false (as it was before it started to come to be) it is indeterminate whether it is true or false. (185) For our purposes, it is useful to focus on a key assumption Cameron makes in this part, namely: (3) There is a difference in A s being from before and after the time at which the event of A s coming to be begins; that is, the beginning of the event of A s coming to be marks a difference in the ontological status of A.

Gunky time and indeterminate existence 83 So much for a general presentation of Cameron s argument. Now let us see what is wrong with it. Consider an expression like event of A s coming to be. As a matter of fact, we can use it in at least two different ways: (I) we can use it to denote an accomplishment (see Vendler 1957), that is, a temporally extended activity with a culmination. The accomplishment of A s coming to be is an event that leads from a state at which A does not exist to a state at which A exists, generally by playing a distinctive causal role in the transition. Standard examples of accomplishments of coming to be are the building of a house and the assembling of a composite artefact from scattered parts. Actually, Aristotle s own examples in his Physics, I, are precisely of this kind; (II) we can use it in a more abstract fashion, to indicate a transition from a state at which A does not exists to a state at which A exists. 1 So understood, events of coming to be need not play any causal role at all. Now, as we shall see, the impression that Cameron s argument is valid rests on equivocation. Depending on what reading of the event of A s coming to be is chosen, different steps in the reasoning become valid, but there is no single reading that validates the whole argument. More precisely, reading (I) makes the first part of Cameron s argument valid (albeit in a somewhat vacuous way) and the second invalid, and indeed very weak. As for reading (II), the situation is precisely reversed: the second part of the argument is (somewhat vacuously) valid and the first invalid, and philosophically unconvincing. Let us consider cases (I) and (II) in turn. (I) Let us assume that an event of A s coming to be is an accomplishment that culminates in A s existence. If so, intermediate conclusion (IC) is obviously true, for all accomplishments are temporally extended. However, as we have seen, the step from (IC) to (C) crucially involves assumption (3), 1 Transitions of coming to be, so understood, are close to what Vendler (1957) calls achievements, that is, events that have a culmination but, unlike accomplishments, have no inner telic complexity (standard examples: reaching the summit, winning the game, dying). However, I prefer not to use the word achievements here, for achievements are generally thought to be instantaneous events, and to insist on this feature would beg the question against Cameron s intermediate conclusion (IC).

84 Giuseppe Spolaore that is, the view that an event of A s coming to be marks a difference concerning A s being from its very beginning. Unfortunately, this assumption need not be true under reading (I). Consider, for instance, a standard accomplishment of coming to be like the building of a house. It appears that, when the building begins, the house is firmly out of existence, exactly as it was before. Of course, one might insist that exist is vague, and that, at some point during the construction, the house is neither (determinately) in existence nor out of it. However, this view right or wrong as it may be makes the premise that time is gunky irrelevant to the argument. If exist is vague, we can reach conclusion (C) anyway, regardless of whether time is gunky. And if exist is not vague, and so there is no intermediate state between existence and nonexistence, the natural conclusion is that A begins to exist right at the end of the event of A s coming to be, and that it never existed before. Maybe Cameron s argument aims at showing that if time is gunky then exists must be vague, so that there can be no neat transition between existence and nonexistence? This leads us to the second understanding of event of A s coming to be. (II) If event of A s coming to be is taken to denote a transition between a state at which A exists (let us call it A exists ) to a state at which A does not exist ( A does not exist ), then (IC) boils down to: (IC2) The transition from A does not exist to A exists cannot be neat. However, (IC2) does not follow from (1) (3). To see why, suppose that the timeline is gunky and there exist intervals of time Black and White such that: Black completely precedes White (Black < White in symbols), and Black and White are adjacent (no interval T is such that Black < T < White). Now assume that object A never exists during Black and always exists during White (see Figure 1). If so, the transition from A exists to A does not exist is neat, and in no sense an extended process.

Gunky time and indeterminate existence 85 A does not exist A exists Figure 1. If Cameron s argument is sound, the assumption that A never exists on Black and always exists on White is inconsistent with (1), for (1) entails that no such neat transition can take place. However this is false: there exists a consistent, atomless mereological theory that allows for adjacent intervals (see Hellmann and Shapiro 2013; it is worth noting that this work is explicitly based on Aristotle s atomless conception of the continuum see also Hellmann and Shapiro 2015 for a historical survey of the atomless conception). Plausibly, under reading (II), the argument from (1) (2) to (IC) is not only deductively invalid but also philosophically unconvincing, in the sense that, if one subscribes to (1) (2), then one is very likely to reject (IC). After all, those philosophers who deny the existence of atomic temporal parts are generally driven, like Aristotle, by the will to avoid Eleatic qualms about the instant of change. On the face of it, it is unlikely that they subscribe to (IC), that is, that they are prepared to replace the non-existent instant of change (understood as a time atom) with a full interval of change. In their eyes, this move would only reinstall Zeno s conclusion that between any two incompatible states in time must lie some middle men, which postpone change and eventually make it impossible. An atomless conception of time does not entail that instants do not exists, but only that they are not atomic parts of the timeline. (For instance, following Hellman and Shapiro s (2013) treatment of points, we might identify instants with Cauchy sequences of intervals, but there are many alternative possibilities see again Hellmann and Shapiro 2015 for a survey.) Thus, there is no inconsistency in claiming that there exists an instant the instant of change that lies between Black and White, and denying that there are time atoms. Correspondingly, there is no inconsistency in admitting that there are instantaneous events and denying that any event exists, which only occupies a time atom. There is a telling analogy here between events (qua transitions) and borders. When we say that the border between, e.g., a black and a white area is neat, we need not (and generally do not) mean that the

86 Giuseppe Spolaore border occupies a region of space that is one space atom wide. And this is especially so if we think that space atoms do not even exist! Within an atomless conception of space, it is natural to think of neat borders as entities that supervene on certain spatial features of extended areas, not to deny their existence. Analogously, instantaneous events need not be conceived as events that fully occupy an atomic part of the timeline. To summarize, event of A s coming to be can receive two readings, which I have indicated as (I) and (II). Under reading (I), an event of A s coming to be is an extended activity that culminates in the existence of A. However, an event of A s coming to be, so conceived, need not mark a difference in the ontological status of A from its very beginning, against premise (3). Under reading (II), an event of A s coming to be is a transition between a state at which A does not exist and a state at which A exists. Under this reading, Cameron s argument is valid only if some further premise is assumed to be true. As a matter of fact, Cameron presupposes a specific conception of instants, according to which they are atomic temporal parts of the timeline (and, as a consequence, instantaneous events are events that fully occupy atomic temporal parts of the timeline). For all that has been said so far, this conception may very well be true. However, as I have argued, it is not forced upon us. Moreover, it is unlikely that one finds it very appealing if one believes, in accordance with premise (2), that atomic temporal parts do not even exist. References CAMERON, R. The Moving Spotlight. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2015. HELLMAN, G. and SHAPIRO, S. The classical continuum without points. Review of Symbolic Logic, 6 (3): 488 512, 2013. HELLMAN, G. and Shapiro, S. Frege meets Aristotle: Points as abstracts. Philosophia Mathematica, 25 (1): 73 90, 2015. VENDLER, Z. Verbs and times. Philosophical Review, 66 (2): 143 160, 1957.