Pascal is best known among philosophers for his wager in support of Christian

Similar documents
A Better Version of Pascal s Wager. Forthcoming in American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly. Michael Rota

175 Chapter CHAPTER 23: Probability

Betting on God: Pascal, Probability Theory and Theology. nevertheless made surprising contributions to the field of religious philosophy.

INTUITION AND CONSCIOUS REASONING

HUME, CAUSATION AND TWO ARGUMENTS CONCERNING GOD

Gandalf s Solution to the Newcomb Problem. Ralph Wedgwood

Bayesian Probability

Learning is a Risky Business. Wayne C. Myrvold Department of Philosophy The University of Western Ontario

Logic and Theism: Arguments For and Against Beliefs in God, by John Howard Sobel.

Gale on a Pragmatic Argument for Religious Belief

On Breaking the Spell of Irrationality (with treatment of Pascal s Wager) Selmer Bringsjord Are Humans Rational? 11/27/17 version 2 RPI

From Necessary Truth to Necessary Existence

Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible?

What God Could Have Made

KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST. Arnon Keren

Marcel Sarot Utrecht University Utrecht, The Netherlands NL-3508 TC. Introduction

Simplicity and Why the Universe Exists

some of the questions that Blaise Pascal and John Locke seek to address. The two great

Philosophy of Religion (PHIL11159)

Today s Lecture. Preliminary comments on the Problem of Evil J.L Mackie

There are various different versions of Newcomb s problem; but an intuitive presentation of the problem is very easy to give.

A Rejection of Skeptical Theism

The Prospective View of Obligation

Robert Nozick s seminal 1969 essay ( Newcomb s Problem and Two Principles

Does Deduction really rest on a more secure epistemological footing than Induction?

the negative reason existential fallacy

David E. Alexander and Daniel Johnson, eds. Calvinism and the Problem of Evil.

Evidential arguments from evil

Causing People to Exist and Saving People s Lives Jeff McMahan

CHRISTIANITY AND THE NATURE OF SCIENCE J.P. MORELAND

Bayesian Probability

1/5. The Critique of Theology

Philosophical Perspectives, 16, Language and Mind, 2002 THE AIM OF BELIEF 1. Ralph Wedgwood Merton College, Oxford

ABSTRACT: In this paper, I argue that Phenomenal Conservatism (PC) is not superior to

PHENOMENAL CONSERVATISM, JUSTIFICATION, AND SELF-DEFEAT

How to Write a Philosophy Paper

DENNETT ON THE BASIC ARGUMENT JOHN MARTIN FISCHER

SCHAFFER S DEMON NATHAN BALLANTYNE AND IAN EVANS

Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly *

Part 9: Pascal s Wager

THE MEANING OF OUGHT. Ralph Wedgwood. What does the word ought mean? Strictly speaking, this is an empirical question, about the

DEFEASIBLE A PRIORI JUSTIFICATION: A REPLY TO THUROW

Ramsey s belief > action > truth theory.

Think by Simon Blackburn. Chapter 5d God

In Epistemic Relativism, Mark Kalderon defends a view that has become

Inquiry, Knowledge, and Truth: Pragmatic Conceptions. Pragmatism is a philosophical position characterized by its specific mode of inquiry, and

Understanding Truth Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002

Christian Evidences. The Verification of Biblical Christianity, Part 2. CA312 LESSON 06 of 12

Ultimate Naturalistic Causal Explanations

The significance of faith proven by decision theory Pascal s wager game is correct and refutes atheism completely

Review of J.L. Schellenberg, Divine Hiddenness and Human Reason (Ithaca, NY: Cornell UP, 1993), i-x, 219 pages.

ALTERNATIVE SELF-DEFEAT ARGUMENTS: A REPLY TO MIZRAHI

Pascal s wager: tracking an intended reader in the structure of the argument 1

Reasons With Rationalism After All MICHAEL SMITH

Published in Analysis 61:1, January Rea on Universalism. Matthew McGrath

Philosophy of Religion 21: (1987).,, 9 Nijhoff Publishers, Dordrecht - Printed in the Nethenanas

WHY SHOULD ANYONE BELIEVE ANYTHING AT ALL?

2014 THE BIBLIOGRAPHIA ISSN: Online First: 21 October 2014

Does the Third Man Argument refute the theory of forms?

NOT SO PROMISING AFTER ALL: EVALUATOR-RELATIVE TELEOLOGY AND COMMON-SENSE MORALITY

COSMOLOGICAL ARGUMENT: A PRAGMATIC DEFENSE

Kant and his Successors

Huemer s Clarkeanism

Scanlon on Double Effect

Copan, P. and P. Moser, eds., The Rationality of Theism, London: Routledge, 2003, pp.xi+292

DISCUSSION PRACTICAL POLITICS AND PHILOSOPHICAL INQUIRY: A NOTE

Is Epistemic Probability Pascalian?

Who Has the Burden of Proof? Must the Christian Provide Adequate Reasons for Christian Beliefs?

Jeffrey, Richard, Subjective Probability: The Real Thing, Cambridge University Press, 2004, 140 pp, $21.99 (pbk), ISBN

PLEASESURE, DESIRE AND OPPOSITENESS

Ayer s linguistic theory of the a priori

Ayer and Quine on the a priori

MEGILL S MULTIVERSE META-ARGUMENT. Klaas J. Kraay Ryerson University

Etchemendy, Tarski, and Logical Consequence 1 Jared Bates, University of Missouri Southwest Philosophy Review 15 (1999):

WEEK 4: APOLOGETICS AS PROOF

INTERPRETATION AND FIRST-PERSON AUTHORITY: DAVIDSON ON SELF-KNOWLEDGE. David Beisecker University of Nevada, Las Vegas

Explanatory Indispensability and Deliberative Indispensability: Against Enoch s Analogy Alex Worsnip University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill

The Logical Problem of Evil and the Limited God Defense

POWERS, NECESSITY, AND DETERMINISM

Causing People to Exist and Saving People s Lives

AN EPISTEMIC PARADOX. Byron KALDIS

IS GOD "SIGNIFICANTLY FREE?''

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism

Either God wants to abolish evil and cannot, or he can but does not want to, or he cannot and does not want to, or lastly he can and wants to.

Akrasia and Uncertainty

Moral Objectivism. RUSSELL CORNETT University of Calgary

Attraction, Description, and the Desire-Satisfaction Theory of Welfare

No Love for Singer: The Inability of Preference Utilitarianism to Justify Partial Relationships

G. A. Cohen, Finding Oneself in the Other, Michael Otsuka (ed.), Princeton University. Reviewed by Ralf M. Bader, Merton College, University of Oxford

Divine omniscience, timelessness, and the power to do otherwise

SAVING RELATIVISM FROM ITS SAVIOUR

PHILOSOPHY ESSAY ADVICE

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

The Will To Believe by William James

When is Faith Rational? 1. What is Faith?

5 A Modal Version of the

CAUSATION 1 THE BASICS OF CAUSATION

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

Is God Good By Definition?

A DEFINITION OF BELIEVING. R. G. Cronin

Transcription:

Midwest Studies in Philosophy, XXVI (2002) Pascal s Wagers 1 JEFF JORDAN Pascal is best known among philosophers for his wager in support of Christian belief. 2 Since Ian Hacking s classic article on the wager, three versions of the wager have been recognized within the concise paragraphs of the Pensées. 3 In what follows I argue that there is a fourth to be found there, a version that in many respects anticipates the argument of William James in his 1896 essay The Will to Believe. 4 This fourth wager argument, I contend, differs from the better-known three in that it has as a premise the proposition that theistic belief is more rewarding than non-belief in this life, whether God exists or not. As we will see, this proposition provides a way of circumventing the many-gods objection. From the four wagers found in Pascal s Pensées, I argue, one can salvage the resources for a version of the wager, Pascalian in nature, even if not in origin, immune to the many-gods objection. A brief comment on the apologetic role Pascal intended for the wagers played is our first task at hand. THE APOLOGETIC ROLE OF THE WAGERS While it is impossible to know the role in his projected apologetic work Pascal intended for his wagers, there are hints. Two prominent hints come early in frag- 1. I am grateful to several people who read and offered helpful comments: Steve Davis, Alan Hájek, J. J. MacIntosh, Joel Pust, Paul Saka, David Silver, and Doug Stalker. 2. Pensées, translated by Honor Levi (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1995), 153 6. In the Levi translation, the relevant passage is #680; in the Lafuma edition the passage is #343. All Pensées page citations are hereafter cited in the text and are to the Levi edition. Pensées numbered passages are cited with the Levi number first, then the Lafuma number. 3. The Logic of Pascal s Wager, American Philosophical Quarterly 9/2 (1972), 186 92. 4. The Will to Believe in The Will to Believe and Other Essays in Popular Philosophy (New York: Dover, 1956), 1 31. 213

214 Jeff Jordan ment #680. 5 The first is the sentence Let us now speak according to natural lights (153); and the second is the use of the indefinite article, If there is a God, he is infinitely beyond our comprehension (153). These sentences suggest that Pascal intended the wagers as arguments for the rationality of theistic belief, and not as arguments for the rationality of Christian belief. Theism is the proposition that there exists an all-powerful, all-knowing, morally perfect being. Judaism, Christianity, and Islam are all theistic religions. It is likely that Pascal had in mind a two-step apologetic strategy. The first step consists of arguments in support of theism generally, with the second step being arguments for Christianity in particular. As an ecumenical argument in support of theism, the wagers were designed to shown that theistic belief of some sort was rational, while appeals to fulfilled prophecy and to miracles were Pascal s favored arguments in support of Christianity. Many of the Pensées fragments consist of arguments either that Christianity is the true religion, or that it is superior to Judaism and Islam in significant respects (see #235 76/397 429, for instance). If this speculation is sound, then Pascal s apology was very much in line with the standard seventeenth and eighteenth century apologetic strategy: argue first that there is a god, and then identify which god it is that exists. This is the strategy adopted by Robert Boyle (1627 91) and by Bishop John Tillotson (1630 94), for instance, and by those, like William Paley (1734 1805), who employed the design argument to argue for a divine designer and then used the argument from miracles to identify that designer. 6 Earlier I mentioned that Pascal is known best for his wager in support of Christian belief. While that may be true, that recognition is misplaced if the argument of this section is correct. Pascal s wagers are arguments in support of theism generally, and not specifically for Christian theism. THREE WAGERS 7 About a third of the way into Pensées #680, a dialogue commences. Along with most commentators, I assume that Pascal formulates his wager arguments in response to questions and comments from an unnamed interlocutor. Prior to presenting his wager arguments, Pascal sets the stage with certain observations. The first is that neither the nature nor existence of God admits of rational proof: Reason cannot decide anything... Reason cannot make you 5. See Charles M. Natoli, The Role of the Wager in Pascal s Apologetics, New Scholasticism 57 (1983), 98 106. 6. On Boyle, see Final Causes of Natural Things (1688); on Tillotson, see The Wisdom of Being Religious Sermon I, Works of Tillotson, vol. I (London: J. F. Dove, 1820), pp. 317 89; and see Paley s A View of the Evidences of Christianity (1795), Part 3, chapter 8. 7. For more detail on the various versions of the wager, see, in addition to Hacking, Edward McClennen, Pascal s Wager and Finite Decision Theory in Gambling on God: Essays on Pascal s Wager (Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield, 1994), 115 37. And see Alan Hájek, The Illogic of Pascal s Wager, Proceedings of the 10th Logica International Symposium, Liblice, ed. T. Childers et al., 239 49.

Pascal s Wagers 215 choose one way or the other, reason cannot make you defend either of two choices (153). This should not be taken as asserting that evidence and argument are irrelevant to philosophical theology. Pascal did not think that. Certain kinds of arguments and evidence are irrelevant, while certain kinds are relevant. 8 Pascal clearly thought that his wager arguments were not only relevant but also rationally compelling. The wager presupposes a distinction between (A) a proposition being rational to believe, and (B) inducing a belief in that proposition being the rational thing to do. Although a particular proposition may lack sufficient evidential warrant, it could be, given the distinction between (A) and (B), that forming a belief in the proposition may be the rational thing, all things considered, to do. Pascal probably did not intend, nor should a Pascalian for that matter, to limit the dialectical force of the wager to pragmatic rationality only. The upshot of the wager, if sound, is that belief in God is the rational stance with all things considered. Let s distinguish between something being rationally compelling and something being plausible. An argument is rationally compelling if, upon grasping the argument, one would be irrational in failing to accept its conclusion. On the other hand, an argument is plausible if, upon grasping the argument, one would be reasonable or rational in accepting its conclusion, yet one would not be irrational in failing to accept it. Pascal believed that his wager made theistic belief rationally compelling. A second observation made by Pascal is that wagering about the existence of God is unavoidable,... you have to wager (154). Wagering is a forced decision to refuse to wager is tantamount to wagering against. A forced decision between alternatives occurs whenever deciding nothing is equivalent to one of the alternatives. We can understand wagering on God as taking steps to inculcate theistic belief. For those making a pro-wager, Pascal suggests a regimen of... taking holy water, having masses said... and imitating the faithful (156). Wagering against, then, is deciding not to take steps to bring about belief. It is not anachronistic to note the Jamesian similarities here: wagering about God arises because argument, evidence, and reason are inconclusive. Moreover, wagering is forced, and, clearly, the matter is momentous and involves, for most of Pascal s readers, living options. 9 Be that as it may, Hacking in his important 1972 paper The Logic of Pascal s Wager identifies three versions within the Pensées fragments. The first, which Hacking dubs the Argument from Dominance, is conveyed within the admonition to:... weigh up the gain and the loss by calling that heads that God exists... If you win, you win everything; if you lose, you lose nothing. Wager that he exists then, without hesitating. (154) 8. See, for instance, Daniel Foukes, Argument in Pascal s Pensées, History of Philosophy Quarterly 6/1 (1989), 57 68. 9. One significant difference between Pascal s wagers and James argument is that the latter is an argument for the permissibility of pro-belief, while the former argues for the rational obligation to believe.

216 Jeff Jordan Rational optimization requires adopting a particular alternative among several mutually exclusive and jointly exhaustive options, whenever doing so may render one better-off than by not doing so, and in no case could doing so render one worse-off. According to Pascal, theistic belief dominates. 10 Consider the following: God exists (God exists) 11 Believe 12 F1 F2 (Believe) F3 F4 In this matrix, there are two states of the world (possible ways that the world might be), one in which God exists and one in which God does not exist; and two acts (choices available to the agent), whether to bring about belief or not. Given that the outcomes associated with the acts have the following relations: F1 >> F3, and F2 is at least as good as F4, belief weakly dominates not believing. 13 Following Pascal, no great disvalue has been assigned to F3. Nowhere in #680 does Pascal suggest that non-belief results in hell, or an infinite disutility, if God exists. Represented schematically the argument from dominance proceeds: 1. For any person S, if one of the alternatives, a, available to S has an outcome better than the outcomes of the other available alternatives, and never an outcome worse than the others, S should choose a. And, 2. Believing in God is better than not believing if God exists, and is no worse if God does not exist. 14 Therefore, C. One should believe in God. This first wager is an example of a decision under uncertainty. Whenever one deliberates with knowledge of the outcomes but no knowledge of the probabilities associated with those outcomes, one faces a decision under uncertainty. On the other hand, if one deliberates armed with knowledge of both the outcomes and the probabilities associated with those outcomes, one faces a decision under risk. The transition to the second version of the wager is precipitated by the interlocutor s objection to the assumption that theistic wagering does not render one worse-off if God does not exist. In response Pascal introduces probability assignments to the discussion and, more importantly, the idea of an infinite utility: 10. As described, the first version of the wager is an argument from weak dominance. 11. Understanding God as the title for that individual, if any, who is omnipotent, omniscient, and morally perfect. 12. While it may be better to understand the acts as bringing about theistic belief, and remaining within non-belief, for convenience, I will formulate the acts as simply Believe and (Believe). 13. The expression X >> Y should be understood as X greatly exceeds Y. 14. Clearly enough, the acts in this case have no propensity to bring about the states.

Pascal s Wagers 217 Since there is an equal chance of gain and loss, if you won only two lives instead of one, you could still put on a bet. But if there were three lives to win, you would have to play... and you would be unwise... not to chance your life to win three in a game where there is an equal chance of losing and winning. (154) While probability plays no part in the first argument, it has a prominent role in the second version of the wager, which Hacking calls the Argument from Expectation. Built upon the concept of maximizing expected utility, the argument from expectation assumes that the probability that God exists is one-half, and that the outcome of right belief if God exists is of infinite utility. 15 With these assumptions, theistic belief easily outdistances not believing, no matter what finite value is found in F2, F3, or F4: God exists (God exists) 1 / 2 1 / 2 Believe 0.5, 0.5, F2 EU = (Believe) 0.5, F3 0.5, F4 EU = finite value Put schematically: 3. For any person S, and alternatives, a and b, available to S, if a has a greater expected utility than does b, S should choose a. And, 4. Given that the existence of God is as likely as not, believing in God carries more expected utility than does not believing. Therefore, C. One should believe in God. Hacking asserts that the assumption of equal chance is monstrous. Perhaps it is. The beautiful thing about infinite utility, though, is that infinity multiplied by any finite value is still infinite. 16 The assumption that the existence of God is just as likely as not is needlessly extravagant, since, as long as the probability of the existence of God is judged to be greater than zero, believing will always carry an expected utility greater than that carried by non-belief. And this is true no matter the value or disvalue associated with the outcomes F2, F3, and F4. This observa- 15. One calculates the expected utility of an act j by (i) multiplying the benefits and probabilities of each outcome associated with j, (ii) subtracting any respective costs, and (iii) summing the totals from each associated outcome. Therefore, the expected utility of believing in God, given an infinite utility and 0.5 probabilities, is as follows: ( 1 / 2 ) + (F2 1 / 2 ) =. 16. Assuming, plausibly enough, that no sense can be made in this context of infinitesimal probabilities.

218 Jeff Jordan tion underlies the third version of the wager, what Hacking titles the Argument from Dominating Expectation, in which p represents a positive probability, with a range greater than zero and less than one-half: God exists, p (God exists), 1 - p Believe p, 1 - p, F2 EU = (Believe) p, F3 1 - p, F4 EU = finite value No matter how unlikely it is that God exists, as long as there is some positive non-zero probability that he does, believing is one s best bet: 5. For any person S, and alternatives, a and b, available to S, if a has a greater expected utility than does b, S should choose a. And, 6. Believing in God has a greater expected utility than does not believing. Therefore, C. One should believe in God. Because of its ingenious employment of infinite utility, the third version has become what most philosophers think of as Pascal s wager. It is the canonical version. Even so, the argument from dominating expectation is not Pascal s most formidable. PASCAL S FOURTH WAGER 17 The fourth version of the wager found in Pensées #680 resides in the concluding remarks that Pascal makes to his interlocutor: But what harm will come to you from taking this course? You will be faithful, honest, humble, grateful, doing good, a sincere and true friend. It is, of course, true; you will not take part in corrupt pleasure, in glory, in the pleasures of high living. But will you not have others? I tell you that you will win thereby in this life...(156). The fourth version brings us full circle, away from arguments under risk and back to an argument under uncertainty. This version remedies the defect that precluded the first argument from strict dominance. 17. Edward McClennen asserts that a fourth version of the wager employing only finite utilities and something like the principle of indifference is also contained in #680. See McClennen, Pascal s Wager and Finite Decision Theory, pp. 127 9.

Pascal s Wagers 219 God exists (God exists) Believe F2 (Believe) F3 F4 Like its predecessors, the fourth version implies that the benefits of belief vastly exceed those of non-belief if God exists; but, unlike the others, the fourth implies that F2 > F4. No matter what, belief is one s best bet. Belief strictly dominates nonbelief. Let s call this version of the wager the Argument from Strict Dominance : 7. For any person S, if among the alternatives available to S, the outcomes of one alternative, a, are better in every state than those of the other available alternatives, and the states are causally independent of the available actions, S should choose a. And, 8. Believing in God is better than not believing whether God exists or not. Therefore, C. One should believe in God. Premise (8) is true only if one gains simply by believing. Pascal apparently thought that this was obvious. Sincere theistic belief results, he thought, in virtuous living and virtuous living is more rewarding than vicious living. The response of Pascal s interlocutor, we might plausibly imagine, would be that Pascal has made an illicit assumption: why think that virtuous living requires theism? And even if virtuous living requires theism, why think that being morally better is tantamount to being better-off all things considered? Now whether virtue is its own reward only in a theistic context or not, the relevant point is whether theistic belief provides more benefit than not believing, even if God does not exist. If it does, then this is an important point when considering the many-gods objection. THE MANY-GODS OBJECTION Like the canonical version, the fourth version seems vulnerable to what is known as the many-gods objection. Notice that in all four Pascalian arguments the wager consists of a 2 2 matrix: there are two acts available to the agent, with only two possible states of the world. From Pascal s day to the present, critics have been quick to point out that Pascal s partitioning of the possible states of the world overlooks the obvious what if some deity other than God exists? What if a deity exists, something like Michael Martin s perverse master deity that harbors animus toward theism, such that s/he rewards nonbelief? 18 In effect, the many-gods 18. Michael Martin, Atheism: A Philosophical Justification (Philadelphia: Temple University Press, 1990), pp. 232 4.

220 Jeff Jordan objection asserts that Pascal s 2 2 matrix is flawed because the states it employs are not jointly exhaustive of the possibilities. 19 G N D Believe in G F1 F2 F3 Believe in Neither F4 F5 F6 Believe in D F7 F8 F9 With D representing the existence of a non-standard deity, a deviant deity, and N representing the world with no deity of any sort (call this state naturalism ), theistic belief no longer strictly dominates. 20 With infinite utility residing in both column G and D, and, with the values of F3, F4, and F7, presumably the same, even weak dominance seems lost to theism. 21 Just as the many-gods objection is thought by many to be the bane of the third version, one might think it is fatal to the fourth version of the wager as well. And so it is. The possibility of an infinite reward presented to nontheists defeats any theistic claim to dominance, weak or strict. Still all is not lost for the Pascalian. With (8) in hand, the Pascalian could salvage from the ruins of the fourth version a wager that circumvents the many-gods objection. Given that the lower two cells of the D column equal the upper cell of the G column, and that F3 = F4 = F7, the Pascalian could employ the N column as a principled way to adjudicate between believing theistically or not. That is, whether one believes theistically, or believes in a deviant deity, or refrains from believing in any deity at all, one is exposed to the same kind of risk (F3 or F4 or F7). The worst outcomes of theistic belief, of deviant belief, and of naturalistic belief are on par. Moreover, whether 19. The number of critics invoking the many-gods objection is legion. Among their number are Paul Saka, Pascal s Wager and the Many-Gods Objection, Religious Studies 37 (2001), 321 41; Graham Priest, Logic: A Very Short Introduction (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000), 94 8; William Gustason, Pascal s Wager and Competing Faiths, International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 44 (1998), 31 9; Richard Gale, On the Nature and Existence of God (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1991), 349 51; Antony Flew, Is Pascal s Wager the Only Safe Bet? God, Freedom and Immortality (Buffalo, NY: Prometheus, 1984), 61 8; Michael Martin, Pascal s Wager as an Argument for Not Believing in God, Religious Studies 19 (1983), 57 64; J. L. Mackie, The Miracle of Theism (Oxford: Clarendon, 1982), 203; Peter Dalton, Pascal s Wager: The Second Argument, Southern Journal of Religion 13 (1975), 31 46; Merle Turner, Deciding for God The Bayesian Support of Pascal s Wager Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 29/1 (1968), 84 90; and James Cargile, Pascal s Wager, Philosophy 41 (1966), 250 7. 20. By non-standard deity, I mean the gerrymandered fictions of philosophers. 21. As before, I exclude infinite disutilities.

Pascal s Wagers 221 one believes theistically, or believes in a deviant deity, or refrains from believing in any deity at all, one enjoys eligibility for the same kind of reward ( = = ). The best outcomes, that is, of theistic belief, of deviant belief, and of naturalistic belief are on par. The Pascalian claim of (8), however, is important. If (8) is well supported, then there is reason to believe that F2 > F5. Is (8) well supported? Does theistic belief provide more benefit than not believing, even if God does not exist? To answer this, let s adopt something like Bentham s model of utility by stipulating that theistic belief provides more benefit than not believing, even if God does not exist (a better this-world outcome), if, on average, believing theistically ranks higher than not believing theistically in at least one of two categories, and is never lower than not believing in either of the two: (i) happiness, and (ii) longevity. To get a handle on the matter, let s assume that happiness correlates with greater life satisfaction. What do the studies show? With regard to (i), one researcher asserts extensive studies have found the presence of religious beliefs and attitudes to be the best predictors of life satisfaction and a sense of well-being. 22 A study from the University of Minnesota of 3,300 parents of twins found a small but statistically significant correlation (.07) between religious commitment and happiness. 23 More generally, a recent analysis of 100 studies, which examined the association of religious belief and life satisfaction, found that 80% of the studies reported at least one significant positive correlation between the variables. 24 This analysis grouped studies as being either statistically significant in one direction, or in the other direction, or having no statistical significance at all, and then counted votes. But in the absence of any study that incorporates sample size and magnitude of effect, as well as vote counting, one can remain unmoved by the research with regard to (i). The effect, if any, of theistic belief on longevity has been an object of study for over a century. In 1872 Francis Galton, a cousin of Darwin, conducted a retrospective study of the life span of royalty, compared with others of similar economic status. 25 Galton hypothesized that royalty have their length of life prayed for more often than do their economic peers, and yet he found no noticeable increase in royal longevity. Galton s study has not, however, survived the test of time. A much more recent (2000) and sophisticated meta-analysis of 29 independent studies, involving data from 125,000 subjects, found that religious involvement had a significant and substantial association with increased survival. 26 In particular, frequent religious attendance (once a week or more) is associated with 22. Quoted in Ralph W. Hood, Jr., Bernard Spilka, Bruce Hunsberger, and Richard Gorsuch, The Psychology of Religion (New York: Guilford Press, 1996, 2nd ed.), 384. 23. David Lykken, Happiness (New York: St. Martin s Press, 1999), 18 19. 24. Harold Koenig, Michael McCullough, and David Larson, Handbook of Religion and Health (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001), 117, 215 ff. 25. Francis Galton, Statistical Enquires into the Efficacy of Prayer, The Fortnightly Review 12 (August, 1872), 125 35. 26. Koenig, McCullough, and Larson, Handbook of Religion and Health, 328 30. For a detailed discussion of the meta-analysis, see M. E. Cullough, W. T. Hoyt, D. Larsen, H. G. Koenig, and C. E. Thoresen, Religious Involvement and Mortality: A Meta-analytic Review, Health Psychology 19 (2000), 211 22.

222 Jeff Jordan a 25% 33% reduction in the rate of dying during follow-up periods ranging from 5 to 28 years. The increased survival rate associated with religious involvement was found to hold independent of possible confounders like age, sex, race, education, and health status. Unlike studies that simply count votes, a meta-analysis incorporates sample size and magnitude effect. So even though this meta-analysis, like any social science statistical study, establishes a correlation and not causation, that is still reason to think that theism s this-world outcome is better than that of non-belief. In addition, there is no reason to think there is any deviant analogue of (8). We have no reason, that is, to think that belief in a deviant deity correlates with the kind of positive benefits that correlate with theistic belief. But this absence of evidence to think that belief in a deviant deity correlates with positive benefit, conjoined with the obvious opportunity costs associated with such a belief, is itself reason to think that F2 > F8. Indeed, no matter how we might expand the matrix in order to accommodate the exotica of possible divinity, we would have reason to believe that F2 exceeds any this-world outcome associated with the exotica. 27 So, given that F2 > F5 and that F2 > F8, even if the 2 2 matrix is abandoned in favor of an expanded one, a Pascalian beachhead is established: 9. For any person S making a forced decision under uncertainty, if one of the alternatives, a, available to S has an outcome as good as the best outcomes of the other available alternatives, b and c, and never an outcome worse than the worst outcomes of b and c, and, excluding the best outcomes and worse outcomes, has only outcomes better than the outcomes of b and c,s should choose a. And, 10. Theistic belief has an outcome better than the other available alternatives if naturalism obtains. Therefore, C. One should believe in God. Premise (9), which we might dub the Next Best Thing principle, is a cousin of the weak dominance principle. The same considerations that support the weak dominance principle also support the Next Best principle. If there is at least one state in which a particular alternative has an outcome better than that of the others and, moreover, that alternative has no outcome worse than the worst outcomes of the other alternatives, then that alternative weakly dominates. Decision-theoretic principles are guides to systematic deliberation, and the Next Best Thing principle advises that decisions should be made in much the same way as dominance principles. Given that the best outcomes and the worst outcomes are on par, one should choose an alternative, if any, whose outcomes are better than those of the other alternatives. One might object that by returning to a decision under uncertainty, one forgoes the distinctive Pascalian element featured in the canonical version: no matter how unlikely it is that God exists, the infinite payoff guarantees an infinite 27. Even though it is possible to imagine any number of deviant gods, any extension beyond a 3 3 matrix is logically redundant given that F2 exceeds the this world outcomes of the deviant deities, and given that the best cases and worse cases are on par.

Pascal s Wagers 223 expected utility. 28 But there are good reasons why a Pascalian would be well advised to forego the idea of infinite utility. 29 For one thing, as Anthony Duff has pointed out, deliberating with infinite utilities seems to result in an embarrassment of Pascalian riches. 30 Given a possible infinite utility and any positive non-zero probability, it looks as though any and every action carries an infinite expected utility. This fifth version of the wager saves the Pascalian the effort of trying to limit that embarrassment by returning to Pascal s first version of the wager. Another reason that the Pascalian would be well-advised to forego the infinite is that she can get her conclusion without relying on problematic decision-theoretic concepts. Most people, I suspect, have only naturalism and theism as live options, even if they admit the logical possibility of certain theological exotica, a calculation of expected utilities employing only finite utilities and probabilities, would likely conform to the ranking displayed in the fifth wager. 31 This fifth version of the wager, unlike its predecessors, is valid and is not obviously unsound: one can reasonably accept both premises. Perhaps the most interesting feature of it is that the contemporary evidence in support of (10), evidence not available to Pascal, provides the wager relief from the many-gods objection. With this fifth wager in hand, we might do no better than to invoke James again, Pascal s argument, instead of being powerless, then seems a regular clincher, and is the last stroke needed to make our faith...complete. 32 28. Such a complaint is found in J. J. MacIntosh, Is Pascal s Wager Self-Defeating? Sophia 39/2 (2000), 6 13. 29. For reasons why infinite utilities should be abandoned, see my Pascal s Wager Revisited, Religious Studies 34 (1998), 419 31. 30. Pascal s Wager and Infinite Utilities, Analysis 46 (1986), 107 9. 31. For an argument supporting this assertion, see my Pascal s Wager Revisited, 427 30. 32. James, op. cit., 11.