Tuukka Kaidesoja Précis of Naturalizing Critical Realist Social Ontology

Similar documents
Dave Elder-Vass Of Babies and Bathwater. A Review of Tuukka Kaidesoja Naturalizing Critical Realist Social Ontology

Daniel Little Fallibilism and Ontology in Tuukka Kaidesoja s Critical Realist Social Ontology

NATURALISED JURISPRUDENCE

Rule-Following and the Ontology of the Mind Abstract The problem of rule-following

R. Keith Sawyer: Social Emergence. Societies as Complex Systems. Cambridge University Press

Intro. The need for a philosophical vocabulary

Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics 1. By Tom Cumming

Phil 1103 Review. Also: Scientific realism vs. anti-realism Can philosophers criticise science?

Introduction to Cognitivism; Motivational Externalism; Naturalist Cognitivism

New Aristotelianism, Routledge, 2012), in which he expanded upon

Chalmers, "Consciousness and Its Place in Nature"

Can Rationality Be Naturalistically Explained? Jeffrey Dunn. Abstract: Dan Chiappe and John Vervaeke (1997) conclude their article, Fodor,

Vol. II, No. 5, Reason, Truth and History, 127. LARS BERGSTRÖM

The Question of Metaphysics

PHILOSOPHY DEPARTMENT FALL SEMESTER 2009 COURSE OFFERINGS

POWERS, NECESSITY, AND DETERMINISM

On the Prospects of Confined and Catholic Physicalism. Andreas Hüttemann

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy

Naturalism vs. Conceptual Analysis. Marcin Miłkowski

Realism and instrumentalism

The stated objective of Gloria Origgi s paper Epistemic Injustice and Epistemic Trust is:

A New Argument Against Compatibilism

Shafer-Landau's defense against Blackburn's supervenience argument

Qualitative and quantitative inference to the best theory. reply to iikka Niiniluoto Kuipers, Theodorus

HABERMAS ON COMPATIBILISM AND ONTOLOGICAL MONISM Some problems

Centre for Public Policy Research Working Papers Series Paper No: 1. An Introduction to Critical Realism as a Meta-Theoretical Research Perspective

Van Fraassen: Arguments concerning scientific realism

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

Projection in Hume. P J E Kail. St. Peter s College, Oxford.

THEISM, EVOLUTIONARY EPISTEMOLOGY, AND TWO THEORIES OF TRUTH

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

Physicalism and Conceptual Analysis * Esa Díaz-León.

To appear in The Journal of Philosophy.

Aboutness and Justification

Realism and the success of science argument. Leplin:

There are two explanatory gaps. Dr Tom McClelland University of Glasgow

Argumentation and Positioning: Empirical insights and arguments for argumentation analysis

Rethinking Knowledge: The Heuristic View

Received: 30 August 2007 / Accepted: 16 November 2007 / Published online: 28 December 2007 # Springer Science + Business Media B.V.

Huemer s Clarkeanism

Van Fraassen: Arguments Concerning Scientific Realism

Elements of Mind (EM) has two themes, one major and one minor. The major theme is

Naturalism and is Opponents

PH 1000 Introduction to Philosophy, or PH 1001 Practical Reasoning

On Natural Kinds as Normatively Charged Epistemic Tools

BEYOND CONCEPTUAL DUALISM Ontology of Consciousness, Mental Causation, and Holism in John R. Searle s Philosophy of Mind

UC Berkeley UC Berkeley Previously Published Works

Philosophy of Science. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

How Not to Defend Metaphysical Realism (Southwestern Philosophical Review, Vol , 19-27)

Comments on Seumas Miller s review of Social Ontology: Collective Intentionality and Group agents in the Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews (April 20, 2

Phenomenal Knowledge, Dualism, and Dreams Jesse Butler, University of Central Arkansas

Review of David J. Chalmers Constructing the World (OUP 2012) David Chalmers burst onto the philosophical scene in the mid-1990s with his work on

ON CAUSAL AND CONSTRUCTIVE MODELLING OF BELIEF CHANGE

The Oxford Handbook of Epistemology

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 4: Skepticism. Part 1: The Scope of Skepticism and Two Main Types of Skeptical Argument

Delusions and Other Irrational Beliefs Lisa Bortolotti OUP, Oxford, 2010

Skepticism and Internalism

Are There Philosophical Conflicts Between Science & Religion? (Participant's Guide)

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Realism, Approximate Truth, and Philosophical Method

The Philosophy of Physics. Physics versus Metaphysics

Department of Philosophy

2018 Philosophy of Management Conference Paper submission NORMATIVITY AND DESCRIPTION: BUSINESS ETHICS AS A MORAL SCIENCE

INESSENTIAL ARISTOTLE: POWERS WITHOUT ESSENCES

Rezensionen / Book reviews

Reflections on sociology's unspoken weakness: Bringing epistemology back in

Review of Constructive Empiricism: Epistemology and the Philosophy of Science

Kazuhisa Todayama (Graduate School of Information Science, Nagoya University, Japan)

Naturalized Epistemology. 1. What is naturalized Epistemology? Quine PY4613

Wittgenstein on The Realm of Ineffable

In Part I of the ETHICS, Spinoza presents his central

How Do We Know Anything about Mathematics? - A Defence of Platonism

Examining the nature of mind. Michael Daniels. A review of Understanding Consciousness by Max Velmans (Routledge, 2000).

The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel s Idealism

Nancey Murphy, Bodies and Souls, or Spirited Bodies? (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006). Pp. x Hbk, Pbk.

THE CHALLENGES FOR EARLY MODERN PHILOSOPHY: EDITORIAL INTRODUCTION 1. Steffen Ducheyne

Ayer and Quine on the a priori

Non-Naturalism and Naturalism in Mathematics, Morality, and Epistemology

SYSTEMATIC RESEARCH IN PHILOSOPHY. Contents

Are There Reasons to Be Rational?

Towards Richard Rorty s Critique on Transcendental Grounding of Human Rights by Dr. P.S. Sreevidya

Purple Haze: The Puzzle of Consciousness

Philosophical Ethics. Distinctions and Categories

Moral Twin Earth: The Intuitive Argument. Terence Horgan and Mark Timmons have recently published a series of articles where they

The Qualiafications (or Lack Thereof) of Epiphenomenal Qualia

In Defense of Pure Reason: A Rationalist Account of A Priori Justification, by Laurence BonJour. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,

Nature and its Classification

REASON AND PRACTICAL-REGRET. Nate Wahrenberger, College of William and Mary

Different kinds of naturalistic explanations of linguistic behaviour

Probability: A Philosophical Introduction Mind, Vol July 2006 Mind Association 2006

Kant and his Successors

Title II: The CAPE International Conferen Philosophy of Time )

1 Why should you care about metametaphysics?

Intentionality, Information and Consciousness: A Naturalistic Perspective

Intro to Ground. 1. The idea of ground. 2. Relata. are facts): F 1. More-or-less equivalent phrases (where F 1. and F 2. depends upon F 2 F 2

Psillos s Defense of Scientific Realism

The linguistic-cultural nature of scientific truth 1

Falsification or Confirmation: From Logic to Psychology

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

SWINBURNE ON SUBSTANCE DUALISM

Transcription:

Journal of Social Ontology 2015; 1(2): 321 326 Book Symposium Open Access Tuukka Kaidesoja Précis of Naturalizing Critical Realist Social Ontology DOI 10.1515/jso-2015-0016 Abstract: This paper introduces and contextualizes my book Naturalizing Critical Realist Social Ontology (London: Routledge, 2013). Keywords: Critical realism; Social ontology; Naturalist philosophy of social science; Causal power; Essentialism; Roy Bhaskar. Though most philosophers of science today consider themselves naturalists in some sense, there still are many social scientists and philosophers of social science who describe themselves as anti-naturalists (or non-naturalists), both in the ontological and the methodological sense. Anti-naturalists often reject naturalism because of the methodological monism and reductionist ontology that are sometimes regarded as essential components of any naturalist philosophy of science. Due to their assumed methodological monism and ontological reductionism, naturalist views are considered problematic since, according to anti-naturalist critics, they impede our understanding of the nature of social research, the humanities, and social ontology. One of the aims of my book, Naturalizing Critical Realist Social Ontology, is to show that while methodological monism and reductionist ontology are indeed problematic, they should not be seen as the defining features of naturalism. I take naturalism to be a philosophy of science that is continuous with the sciences and considers the human mind and social world to be embedded in the causal structure of reality. By contrast, methodological monism and reductionist ontology result from a failure to pay attention to the actual research practices and results of the cognitive and social sciences in the naturalist philosophy of science. In my book, I argue that empirical analysis of the current explanatory sciences does not support a view that the same scientific method is used in all empirical sciences. I also try to show that human agency, intentionality and normativity Tuukka Kaidesoja, Department of Social Research, University of Turku, Finland, e-mail: tuukka.kaidesoja@utu.fi 2015, Tuukka Kaidesoja, published by De Gruyter. This work is licensed under the Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 3.0 License.

322 Tuukka Kaidesoja can be understood in naturalist ontological terms once we pay attention to the actual research practices of the cognitive and social sciences (rather than speculate about what a complete neuroscience that does not yet exist might be able to explain in purely physicalist terms in some distant future). Indeed, I suggest that the best explanatory practices in these sciences include an assumption that micro-reductive explanations of the systemic (or emergent) properties of cognitive and social systems in terms of their underlying mechanisms do not explain these properties away. What I think is relatively novel in my arguments in this context is that I reject methodological monism and reductionist ontologies (e.g., eliminative materialism and reductionist physicalism), not because they are naturalistic (or scienceoriented), but because they are not naturalistic enough meaning that they are not compatible with the best explanatory practices and developments in the empirical sciences. The meaning of the term sciences is here construed in a broad sense that encompasses the research practices both in the natural sciences and in the behavioral and social sciences. Accordingly, the book contributes to the ongoing discussion on the proper scope of the naturalist philosophy of science. It does this by defending a naturalist program of social ontology that aims to do justice to the best explanatory practices and results of the behavioral and social sciences, and to the relevant parts of the natural sciences. One of the reasons why this task is important is that many recent developments in studies on the cognitive evolution of humans, social neuroscience, and other cognitive sciences support an ontological view that humans are social and cultural beings by nature, even though the conceptualization of culture and social life in these sciences is often relatively underdeveloped from the viewpoint of the social sciences. Although I think that these developments should be taken into account in the social sciences, it is also my view that, in contrast to what appears to be the view by many philosophers engaged in debates on social ontology, a naturalist social ontology cannot be plausibly developed without paying serious attention to the ontological assumptions and presuppositions of the epistemically successful research practices and theories in the social sciences. Furthermore, unlike some methodological monists, I do not want to restrict my attention to those explanatory practices in the social sciences that use experimental and/or statistical methods that seek to imitate experimentation as far as possible. Though practices of this kind form an important part of the social sciences and cannot be ignored in naturalist social ontology, it should be noted that their ontological assumptions and presuppositions often include remarkable (and sometimes misleading) simplifications and idealizations. This is the reason why I think that ontological studies on these experimentally-oriented practices should be complemented with ontological analysis on the ethnographic and

Précis of Naturalizing Critical Realist Social Ontology 323 historical studies of human cognition and social life in its naturally occurring settings (in contrast to artificially controlled or idealized environments). In this respect, my usage of the term naturalism is somewhat similar to that sometimes found in biology, where this label is earned by ecologists who observe and study plants and animals in the wild (i.e., in their natural ecological environment) rather than in controlled laboratory settings. These issues, regarding the need to incorporate the social sciences into a naturalist philosophy of science, form a part of the broader context of the book. The core argument of my book, however, is that critical realist social ontology should be naturalized. There are two reasons why I decided to focus on a critical realism that is based on, but not limited to, Roy Bhaskar s (e.g., 1978, 1979) early philosophy of science. Firstly, it is a relatively popular metatheory among social scientists, and it is perhaps the most well-known version of scientific realism in the social sciences. Secondly, even though it is commonly ignored in the naturalist philosophy of science, I think that critical realism provides a useful point of departure for developing a naturalized social ontology because it already contains a number of important naturalist ideas (as is recognized in the title of Bhaskar s second book, The Possibility of Naturalism). These ideas include an account of science in terms of research practices, a general model of mechanism-based causal explanation that is assumed to fit all special sciences despite the differences in their specific methods and objects of inquiry and a view that ontological arguments should begin with an analysis of scientific practices. In addition, critical realists argue for a realist (or generative) theory of causation in terms of causal powers and tendencies as well as for a non-reductionist social ontology that is based upon the concept of emergent causal power. This emergentist ontology seeks to take human agency, social structures and cultural meanings seriously. Despite the naturalist views it contains, a closer examination of critical realism nevertheless reveals that it also includes certain anti-naturalist ontological arguments and ideas, which are often intertwined with the naturalist ones in a complex manner. In the book, I analytically separate these two kinds of elements and show that the anti-naturalist ingredients in the social ontology of Bhaskar and his followers are sources of serious conceptual ambiguities and methodological problems. My argument then is that because of these ambiguities and problems, the anti-naturalist elements should be replaced by ontological concepts and views (which I outline in the book) that are internally consistent and more compatible with the naturalist position. The book also aims to show that this procedure allows critical realists to formulate ontological theories that are more in tune with many successful explanatory practices in the social sciences and with some of the most promising developments in the cognitive sciences.

324 Tuukka Kaidesoja More specifically, I argue that Kantian transcendental arguments, utilized by Bhaskar and many other critical realists, cannot be used to justify ontological doctrines without assuming some version of transcendental idealism (including historically and culturally relativized versions of this doctrine) that is incompatible both with ontological naturalism and scientific realism. It is then shown how the problems that pertain to the transcendental arguments of Bhaskar and his followers, such as the failure to provide detailed empirical justification for their premises as well as the allegedly transcendentally necessary status of their ontological conclusions can be avoided by reformulating these arguments as inferences to the best explanation. The aim of these naturalized ontological arguments is to develop fallible ontological theories that explain the epistemic success of our best practices of empirical research (described on the basis of an empirical analysis of them) and empirically well-confirmed explanatory theories better than the competing ontological views. Since arguments of this kind are also used in the empirical sciences, they are free from those a priori elements that vitiate Bhaskar s transcendental arguments. Accordingly, I deny that there has to be a specific metaphysical (or transcendental) grounding for social scientific research practices and emphasize that the epistemic status of social-ontological theories is exactly the same (i.e., more or less fallible) as that of the explanatory theories in the social sciences, even though the former are typically more abstract and general than the latter. In addition to transcendental arguments, the concepts of causal power and ontological emergence are among the key components of critical realism. Though I share some of their basic views pertaining to these concepts, I argue that both of these concepts are used ambiguously by Bhaskar and many other critical realists. For example, I demonstrate that there are sections in Bhaskar s (e.g., 1978, 1979) books where he tends to detach causal powers from concrete entities by interpreting the former as transcendentally real features of reality. In my reading, this commits him to the view that these transcendentally real powers are regarded as some kind of abstract universals and structures that are (or can be) instantiated by (or somehow participate in the generation of) concrete things which, in certain conditions (e.g., when their powers are triggered or exercised), may become the actual objects of our fallible perceptions or causal interventions. Even though he does not consistently advocate this view, it is shown that this kind of conception of causal powers is assumed, for example, in Bhaskar s (1979) property-dualist philosophy of mind as well as in his conception on social structures in terms of internally related social positions and roles. My worry is that this view introduces such causal properties to critical realist ontology that cannot be studied using any reliable empirical methods utilized in the explanatory sciences and, hence, it is not compatible with naturalism. By

Précis of Naturalizing Critical Realist Social Ontology 325 means of a detailed comparison of their views, I further argue that this transcendental realist interpretation of causal powers is clearly incompatible with Rom Harré and Edward Madden s (1975) account of causal powers in terms of powerful particulars. This is because Harré and Madden consistently ascribe causal powers and potentials to concrete entities (in contrast to abstract universals or conceptual abstractions). My suggestion is also that, unlike abstract social structures, concrete and organized social systems such as particular schools, factories, political parties, governments, and transnational corporations can be plausibly conceived of as such powerful particulars that may possess empirically tractable (though not necessarily perceivable) emergent causal powers. Accordingly, in contrast to Bhaskar s relatively ambiguous account of the concept of emergent power, I restrict this concept to non-aggregative dispositional properties of concrete entities. Another problem in the concept of causal power in critical realism is that it is connected to the essence-based notion of natural kind both in Bhaskar s early works and in Harré and Madden s book. For example, Bhaskar (1978, p. 171) claims that there is the necessity implicit in the concept of a thing s real essence, i.e., those properties and powers, which are most basic in an explanatory sense, without which it would not be the kind of thing it is, i.e., which constitute its identity or fix its membership in its kind. I argue, by contrast, that we should disconnect the concepts of causal power and essence-based natural kind because the latter does not fit, for example, the current understanding of biological species in evolutionary biology, nor does it do justice to those psychological and social kinds that can be considered interactive (or looping) kinds in Ian Hacking s (1999) sense. It is further suggested that Richard Boyd s (e.g., 1991) Homeostatic Property Cluster theory of kinds appears to provide useful ideas for the ontological analysis of the non-essence-based kinds studied in the sciences. The general conclusion of my book is that the original formulation of critical realism contains these and some other unresolved ambiguities and problems, which result from the attempt to combine naturalist and anti-naturalist ontological views that do not fit together. I further point out that these tensions have practical consequences as to how critical realism is utilized as a meta-theory in empirical social research since, at the methodological level, critical realism appears to give rise to an unjustified bias towards abstract theorizing and the favoring of interpretative methods over the post-positivist uses of statistical methods and theoretical modeling in explanatory social research. The message of my book is that, despite of the fact that Bhaskar and other critical realists should be credited for developing compelling critiques of the Humean regularity theory of causality (including the positivist research practices in the social sciences that are based on it) and extreme forms of social constructionism (including

326 Tuukka Kaidesoja hermeneutical anti-naturalism), critical realism has not yet fully realized its potential as an underlabourer to the social sciences due to the problematic antinaturalist elements it contains. Although I have so far mostly concentrated on describing my critical assessment of the original critical realism, the book also elaborates a naturalized version of critical realist social ontology. The latter includes a non-transcendental-realist and non-essentialist concept of causal power that reconnects causal powers to what Harré and Madden (1975) call powerful particulars without assuming that these particulars should have real essences that fix their memberships in essence-based natural kinds. Furthermore, I combine the understanding of causality in terms of powers with an ontology of concrete social systems that selectively and critically draws on recent realist and naturalist philosophy of science, including Mario Bunge s (e.g., 1998, 2003) systemic social ontology and William Wimsatt s (e.g., 2007) notion of ontological emergence in terms of failure of aggregativity. Ontologies of human agency, cognition and culture are in turn expounded by examining the assumptions and implications of the perspectives of embodied, situated and distributed cognition that are in certain respects incompatible with Bhaskar s philosophy of mind and social ontology. Finally, I demonstrate the fruitfulness of the basic ideas of Bunge s systemic social ontology by using them to clarify the ontological assumptions related to some of the basic concepts of social theory. Nevertheless, I readily admit that I was only able to sketch a naturalized critical realism in broad outline. Although I regard the sketch as highly promising, I admit that it needs more work. Bibliography Bhaskar, Roy (1978[1975]): A Realist Theory of Science. 2nd edition. Sussex: The Harvester Press. Bhaskar, Roy (1979): The Possibility of Naturalism: A Philosophical Critique of the Contemporary Human Sciences. Brighton: The Harvester Press. Boyd, Richard (1991): Realism, Anti-Foundationalism and the Enthusiasm for Natural Kinds. In: Philosophical Studies 61, p. 127 148. Bunge, Mario (1998): Social Science under Debate: A Philosophical Perspective. Toronto: University of Toronto Press. Bunge, Mario (2003): Emergence and Convergence: Qualitative Novelty and the Unity of Knowledge. Toronto: University of Toronto Press. Hacking, Ian (1999): The Social Construction of What? Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press. Harré, Rom and Edward Madden (1975): Causal Powers: A Theory of Natural Necessity. Oxford: Basil Blackwell. Wimsatt, William C. (2007): Re-Engineering Philosophy for Limited Beings: Piecewise Approximations to Reality. Cambridge MA & London: Harvard University Press.