Book reviews 493. San Diego State University. Religious Studies 44 (2008) doi: /s f 2008 Cambridge University Press

Similar documents
The Oxford Handbook of Epistemology

Kelly James Clark and Raymond VanArragon (eds.), Evidence and Religious Belief, Oxford UP, 2011, 240pp., $65.00 (hbk), ISBN

HUME, CAUSATION AND TWO ARGUMENTS CONCERNING GOD

Skepticism and Internalism

The Theory of Reality: A Critical & Philosophical Elaboration

Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Introduction

The Paradox of the stone and two concepts of omnipotence

Self-Evidence and A Priori Moral Knowledge

Beyond Virtue Epistemology 1

PHILOSOPHY 203: Introduction to Metaphysics and Epistemology, Fall Professor G. Rosen Hall (609)

The Philosophy of Religion

What God Could Have Made

PL-101: Introduction to Philosophy Fall of 2007, Juniata College Instructor: Xinli Wang

Pannenberg s Theology of Religions

Philosophy Courses-1

2014 THE BIBLIOGRAPHIA ISSN: Online First: 21 October 2014

Plantinga, Van Till, and McMullin. 1. What is the conflict Plantinga proposes to address in this essay? ( )

Philosophy Courses Fall 2011

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View

Course Text. Course Description. Course Objectives. StraighterLine Introduction to Philosophy

Atheism: A Christian Response

PH 501 Introduction to Philosophy of Religion

Table of x III. Modern Modal Ontological Arguments Norman Malcolm s argument Charles Hartshorne s argument A fly in the ointment? 86

Philosophy: The Quest For Truth PDF

From Transcendental Logic to Transcendental Deduction

PHILOSOPHY AND THEOLOGY

1 Hans Jonas, The Imperative of Responsibility: In Search of an Ethics for the Technological Age (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984), 1-10.

David E. Alexander and Daniel Johnson, eds. Calvinism and the Problem of Evil.

Luck, Rationality, and Explanation: A Reply to Elga s Lucky to Be Rational. Joshua Schechter. Brown University


Personal Identity and the Jehovah' s Witness View of the Resurrection

World Religions. These subject guidelines should be read in conjunction with the Introduction, Outline and Details all essays sections of this guide.

Philosophy of Religion 21: (1987).,, 9 Nijhoff Publishers, Dordrecht - Printed in the Nethenanas

RECENT WORK THE MINIMAL DEFINITION AND METHODOLOGY OF COMPARATIVE PHILOSOPHY: A REPORT FROM A CONFERENCE STEPHEN C. ANGLE

Review Tutorial (A Whirlwind Tour of Metaphysics, Epistemology and Philosophy of Religion)

Subject Overview Curriculum pathway

Systematic Theology Doctoral Seminar Christian Theology and Philosophical Analysis

Robert Kiely Office Hours: Tuesday 1-3, Wednesday 1-3, and by appointment

The Logical Problem of Evil and the Limited God Defense

Philosophy of Science. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

DAVID VANDER LAAN Curriculum Vitae

One of the central concerns in metaphysics is the nature of objects which

DESCARTES ONTOLOGICAL PROOF: AN INTERPRETATION AND DEFENSE

Epistemology. PH654 Bethel Seminary Winter To be able to better understand and evaluate the sources, methods, and limits of human knowing,

Warrant, Proper Function, and the Great Pumpkin Objection

POWERS, NECESSITY, AND DETERMINISM

Foreknowledge, evil, and compatibility arguments

Learning Ladder Philosophy and Ethics

PHILOSOPHY. Chair: Karánn Durland (Fall 2018) and Mark Hébert (Spring 2019) Emeritus: Roderick Stewart

Understanding and its Relation to Knowledge Christoph Baumberger, ETH Zurich & University of Zurich

THE SEMANTIC REALISM OF STROUD S RESPONSE TO AUSTIN S ARGUMENT AGAINST SCEPTICISM

A CRITIQUE OF THE FREE WILL DEFENSE. A Paper. Presented to. Dr. Douglas Blount. Southwestern Baptist Theological Seminary. In Partial Fulfillment

3. Knowledge and Justification

Colin Ruloff, ed. Christian Philosophy of Religion: Essays in Honor of Stephen T. Davis

Mohammad Reza Vaez Shahrestani. University of Bonn

The Quest for Knowledge: A study of Descartes. Christopher Reynolds

UNCORRECTED PROOF GOD AND TIME. The University of Mississippi

Department of Philosophy. Module descriptions 2017/18. Level C (i.e. normally 1 st Yr.) Modules

Philosophy of Religion

Philosophy of Religion PHIL (CRN 22046) RELG (CRN 22047) Spring 2014 T 5:00-6:15 Kinard 205

Contemporary Philosophy of Religion

Teachur Philosophy Degree 2018

Philosophy 101: Introduction to Philosophy Section 4152 Online Course El Camino College Spring, 2017

A New Argument Against Compatibilism

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

Anna Marmodoro and Jonathan Hill (eds.), The Metaphysics of the Incarnation, Oxford University Press, 2011.

THE POSSIBILITY OF AN ALL-KNOWING GOD

PHL 170: The Idea of God Credits: 4 Instructor: David Scott Arnold, Ph.D.

Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords

Positions on the Theistic Arguments

Rethinking Knowledge: The Heuristic View

Qué es la filosofía? What is philosophy? Philosophy

THEOLOGICAL STUDIES. Objectives for Students. Systematic Theology. Theological Studies 1

Philosophy Courses-1

Molinism and divine prophecy of free actions

Common Sense: A Contemporary Defense By Noah Lemos Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. xvi

THE CHALLENGES FOR EARLY MODERN PHILOSOPHY: EDITORIAL INTRODUCTION 1. Steffen Ducheyne

PROSPECTS FOR A JAMESIAN EXPRESSIVISM 1 JEFF KASSER

PHILOSOPHY (PHIL) Philosophy (PHIL) 1. PHIL 56. Research Integrity. 1 Unit

Philosophy 305 Introduction to Philosophy of Religion Fall 2016 (also listed as CTI 310, RS 305) 42270; 33770; WAG 302 MWF 2-3

Pihlström, Sami Johannes.

FALL 2018 THEOLOGY TIER I

Plantinga, Pluralism and Justified Religious Belief

FACULTY OF ARTS B.A. Part II Examination,

Towards Richard Rorty s Critique on Transcendental Grounding of Human Rights by Dr. P.S. Sreevidya

The Divine Command Theory

Studies in Buddhist Philosophy by Mark Siderits (review)

Spinoza and Spinozism. By STUART HAMPSHIRE. (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2005.

The Philosophy of Religion

Buddhism s Engagement with the World. April 21-22, University of Utah

Is there a good epistemological argument against platonism? DAVID LIGGINS

1 FAITH AND REASON / HY3004

The Ontological Argument

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

Who or what is God?, asks John Hick (Hick 2009). A theist might answer: God is an infinite person, or at least an

Philosophy Courses Fall 2016

NEW YORK CITY COLLEGE OF TECHNOLOGY THE CITY UNIVERSITY OF NEW YORK DIVISION OF LIBERAL ARTS AND GENERAL EDUCATION DEPARTMENT OF SOCIAL SCIENCES

From the Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy

Rule-Following and the Ontology of the Mind Abstract The problem of rule-following

The Existence of God

Transcription:

Book reviews 493 While the new hermeneutics on multiplism found in the first chapter and a fresh comparative analysis of the issue of consciousness in the second chapter contextualize this study, the remaining chapters maintain this investigation within the parameters of Indian philosophical thought with a focus on the issues of liberation identified as the consequence of knowledge. This approach of reading Indian thought without reducing it to an appendage of Western philosophy or making it a branch of the history of philosophy is, I believe, the most appropriate method of approaching Indian philosophy. This wonderful text, programmatic in nature, paves the path for future studies in Indian philosophy, as many of the issues raised by Ram-Prasad require further investigation. STHANESHWAR TIMALSINA San Diego State University Religious Studies 44 (2008) doi:10.1017/s0034412508009700 f 2008 Cambridge University Press Linda Zagzebski Philosophy of Religion: An Historical Introduction (Oxford: Blackwell Publishing, 2007). Pp. ix+254. 50.00, $78.95 (Hbk); 16.99, $29.95 (Pbk). ISBN 9781405129220 (Hbk); 9781405118729 (Pbk). As an introduction to the philosophy of religion this book has four unique features: the first is that it is historical, but not chronological (viii). By this Linda Zagzebski means to draw attention to ancient, mediaeval, and modern sources and contributions to current debates. Were it chronological, she might have had chapters on ancient Greek, Hellenistic, early Christian, medieval Christian, early modern, and contemporary philosophy of religion. Instead, for many of the problems she examines, she traces their history to early sources, explains what motivated the thoughts and arguments, and then follows the history through classical versions of those arguments up to recent versions. A second unique feature is that she gives attention to the role of emotions in addressing many of the problems she examines. A third is that she draws on previously published views and arguments of hers (for example, her work on freedom and foreknowledge, on virtue epistemology, and on divine motivation theory). A fourth is that she incorporates and develops some of her current work on self-trust and religious diversity. In chapter 1 Zagzebski addresses three background issues. First, she describes what religion is, what philosophy is, and the early development of the philosophy of religion. Her account of religion: a complex human practice involving distinctive emotions, acts, beliefs which serve to express and foster a sense of the sacred (2). On her account, emotions seem to take primacy over acts (rituals, symbols, sacraments) and beliefs (both credal expressions and cognitive

494 Book reviews commitments). However, what typically have seemed to interest philosophers are beliefs and doctrines. On philosophy, she points out two obvious, important, but often neglected features of the rise of philosophy that are relevant to the philosophy of religion. The great minds of ancient India, Persia, China, Israel, were all religious thinkers but in Greece the great minds were philosophers. Also, Greek religion, unlike other ancient religions, was not concerned to answer ultimate questions about the origin of the universe and human fate (10); it was left to the Greek philosophers to address those questions. Second, she discusses the concept of God, and the origins and development of monotheism. Here she claims it is doubtful that philosophy of religion would exist were it not for the monotheistic religions (19). Third, she identifies potential conflicts and discomforts that can arise from the drive for truth motivated by philosophy and the drive for the sense of the sacred motivated by religion. She begins chapter 2 by proposing the audience-types (atheists, agnostics, or believers) to whom theistic arguments might be aimed. The classic formulations were constructed for the believer seeking understanding. Too often, it seems to me, philosophers evaluate theistic arguments abstracted from a sense of audience, perhaps making theistic arguments easy targets for unfair or simplified critiques. Attentive to their audience, Zagzebski then discusses teleological, cosmological, and ontological arguments both historical and contemporary versions. She concludes the chapter by examining various links among the arguments (Do all reduce to the ontological? Is there a cumulative case to be made?), wondering if an undue focus on theistic belief and argument tends to ignore the emotions. On her view of the structure of religious practice, beliefs are not more basic than emotions, and emotions may be paths to truth, especially truths that can be expressed inadequately or in a distorted fashion by ordinary beliefs (54). This view makes an appearance in almost every chapter. In chapter 3 she considers the merits and demerits of pragmatist and fideist approaches to justification of religious belief. Zagzebski points out that seventeenth-century Catholic theologians began using theistic arguments to try to convince atheist critics without, one should note, much success. Both sides accepted three assumptions about justification: (1) the justification for the practice of religion rests upon the justification of religious beliefs, (2) the justification of religious beliefs rests upon the justification of theism, (3) the justification of theism requires demonstration by argument whose premises are accessible to any normal, intelligent person, including the religious skeptic (56). Pragmatist and fideist approaches arose in response to these assumptions. Pascal rejected the first assumption, Kierkegaard the second, and Wittgenstein the third. In chapter 4, Zagzebski examines various issues that arise concerning the nature and character of God. She addresses whether or not the divine essence might be completely unavailable to our comprehension. She explores a handful of the puzzles that arise out of reasoned examination of the traditional attributes

Book reviews 495 of timelessness, perfect goodness, omnipotence, and omniscience. She considers various theories about what it means to say that God is a person (and the challenge of just what it is to say of any being that it is a person). In chapter 5, Zagzebski considers puzzles of fate, freedom, and foreknowledge which arise from consideration of divine timelessness and omniscience. She begins with a short history of the concept of fate in ancient Greek and Jewish thought, and identifies two concepts of a fated event: (a) where an event will happen no matter what anybody does beforehand (102); (b) where an event will happen, given the events that precede it, but it is not possible that those events do not occur (104). This seems like a distinction without a difference. However, she argues that on the former notion of fate, all causal paths lead to it, while on the latter only one (or a small number) of paths lead to it, but no paths that do not lead to it are possible paths (104). The latter sort of fate is compatible with free choice. Yet it is still a problem, as Zagzebski argues in the rest of the chapter: one s eternal destiny seems as much out of one s control whether one thinks matters are more like the former than the latter sort of fate. She examines the main solutions offered, historically, for theological fatalism. She concludes the chapter by considering a few recent arguments that seek to undermine acceptance of determinism. In chapter 6, she sorts out three distinct questions that an enquirer might have in mind when wondering about whether morality needs religion. Does morality need religion (1) to provide the goal of the moral life, (2) to provide the motive to be moral, (3) to provide morality with its foundation and justification (122)? Having sorted the questions this way, she can address the issues and avoid talking at cross-purposes all too common in popular discussions of whether morality needs religion. In chapter 7, Zagzebski addresses the problem of evil. She distinguishes the logical and the evidential problems of evil from the experiential problem, but does not divorce the two. She shows how sensitivity to the experiential problem can inform and guide construction of responses to the philosophical problems of evil. In chapter 8, she addresses four topics: whether or in what sense death is bad; respects in which various theories of personal identity impact what we could think about immortality; some arguments for life after death; and how a doctrine of the afterlife relates to the problem of evil. Regarding personal identity, Zagzebski proposes a modified Thomistic theory according to which each human is a form-matter composite, and the form (or soul) each individual has is a particular unique to that individual. My form (soul) can exist apart from my matter (body), but does so in a defective state since it needs my body (especially my sense organs) to have experience and acquire knowledge. Whatever collection of matter that my form informs is always my body. Thus a resurrected body, whatever matter composes it, would be my body so long as it is informed by my

496 Book reviews unique particular soul. Likely that body would look and act much like I do now, or did during my lifetime, just because it is informed by my soul. Pedagogically speaking, it seems to me a clearly expressed and accessible account for students. In chapter 9, The problem of religious diversity, she begins with a brief historical account, arguing that while diversity of religion has a very long history, its being a problem is quite young a post-enlightenment problem. She discusses and distinguishes various conceptions of exclusivism and inclusivism as they relate to religious diversity. She discusses and criticizes Hick s pluralist views. She develops some issues in epistemology and applies them to religious pluralism to address how one can maintain strong conviction about one s religious beliefs, emotions, and practices in the face of religious diversity. Here too, as in some other chapters, she places high value on emotions and their outputs. In particular, her newer work on self-trust is applied to considering how one can be justified in holding with conviction religious beliefs in the face of religious diversity. In chapter 10, the final chapter, Zagzebski addresses faith and reason issues. She clarifies that the alleged conflict between faith and reason is the potential conflict between sources of belief, more specifically between revelation and reason (where reason is broadly understood to include observation and inference). Such a conflict is not unique to religious believing, for often we consider conflicts between sources of belief: say between unaided observation and what physicists tell me about properties of tables, or between memory and testimony (when my sisters tell my children stories about me, which stories don t fit with my memory). In that regard, the conflict over sources of belief leads directly to concerns about the ethics of belief: believing rightly. She traces views on faith and reason from Philo of Alexandria to Hume. When she examines the ethics of belief, she shows how trust plays a central role in believing rightly, since so many of our beliefs are acquired by testimony, and to accept testimony requires trusting the testifier (while time, energy, or ability prevent us from evaluating the testifier). Believing rightly, on her view, is not so much the Cliffordian notion of sufficient evidence as it is of having intellectual virtues guide one s believing. I find her thoughts on religious diversity interesting but problematic. In several of the other chapters, Zagzebski draws, where appropriate, on her previously published views and arguments (for examples, her work on freedom and foreknowledge, on virtue epistemology, on divine motivation theory). It is in chapter 9 that she does more new philosophical work than in other chapters. It is for this reason that I focus my criticisms here. First, she gives the impression that the problem of religious diversity is a uniquely contemporary one. She says: Before the modern era in the West, the multiplicity of religions was not perceived as a problem for participation in a particular religion (190). Our time is not the first time in history when various diverse religions have existed side by side in cities and cultures, raising problems for the cities and cultures. For example, in China at different times there were

Book reviews 497 clearly identified Buddhist, Confucian, Taoist, Nestorian Christian, Manichean, and Muslim groups all recognized as different religions by the average person and by the government. These groups probably understood more or less about each other s religious beliefs depending on their extent of interaction. There were some conversions across lines; but they were generally rare (similar to our own day). Even though we may not know how those religiously diverse Chinese addressed the problems that the diversity posed, I think that the claims that we now live in a global community and now have to face a problem of religious diversity is culturally and historically myopic, coming out of European Christendom notions. Even America has been less mono-religious than people often assume. If there is a difference in America (or Europe) now, it might be that a century or two ago Americans and Europeans were aware of different people and their religions, people they traded with and interacted with in other ways, having religious views very different from theirs. Now, we have better understanding, seeing how those other religions make sense of the world for their adherents. We also see that many other religious communities function well and civilly together. Thus there is a heightened sensitivity to diversity. Second, she holds that in order for diversity of religions to become a problem, religion has to be seen just as a set of beliefs that one can choose over other sets of beliefs (190). Such, I say, is an impoverished notion of religion. Surely religious diversity was a problem at other times and in other places even when others did not reduce the religions to their doctrinal features. Surely then, as now, few people approach the diversity of religions as if in a supermarket having to make a decision; the vast majority then were and now are enculturated toward certain sets of belief or non-belief. Rather, the way I think she should be put is that in the modern West, we face a distinct sort of problem of religious diversity. Namely, when religion ceased to be seen as a complex human practice involving distinctive emotions, acts, beliefs which serve to express and foster a sense of the sacred (2), but instead come came to be seen as sets of beliefs an autonomous individual freely chooses and adopts or not and when particular religions are promoted as a set of beliefs to which one can convert, then diversity of religions becomes a distinct sort of problem. This is close to what Zagzebski is arguing, but not exactly. And the difference is important. It seems to me that one popular solution to the problem of religious diversity that arises out of the notion of religion as simply belief-sets is to remain Pyrrhoically sceptical to withhold assent to beliefs about religious matters. Withholding belief likely prevents you from ever being wrong. In some respects, refusing to have beliefs about important issues can exhibit a kind of intellectual shallowness. But there is another kind of shallowness. It is not hard to imagine us moderns, when challenged about our religion, to respond these are my beliefs, as if our beliefs are a private matter that have no public consequences. (I wish I could recall the distinct case, but I recall a politician being asked about her or his

498 Book reviews religious beliefs, and part of the response was along the lines but I won t let them guide my public decisions.) Religious beliefs for us moderns are like novelties we collect, put on a shelf, and show our friends to entertain them after dinner. So suppose that in order to avoid intellectual lassitude, we hold with some conviction various religious beliefs which inform and are informed by emotions in such a way as to guide our actions. That, in itself, will not motivate for us a problem of religious diversity. It arises when we are confronted with people we care about who conscientiously, with conviction and integrated into a seemingly coherent practice have religious beliefs, emotions, and actions, but ones much different from ours. Now we have a problem to be addressed. And on that problem, I think that Zagzebski s thoughts about the role of self-trust are helpful and interesting. Third, it seems to me that she should have addressed this problem by arguing that such a view of religion, reduced to doctrinal content, is woefully impoverished in addition to being just plain wrong. That is to say, she should have drawn upon her resources from the book s first chapter. On an impoverished view of religion, the contemporary problem of religious diversity arises. Namely, faced with religion as a choice, one now has to reflect upon the grounds of choice and deliberate about whether this or that religion is the right one (or to be current, right for me). And when multiple religions have competing doctrines about the nature of the deity, or proper practices, or the summum bonum, or how to acquire the summum bonum, one is now confronted with a distinct problem of religious diversity. Instead of thinking that it is unusual people who are thousands of miles away who have unusual religious views, we find our neighbours, friendly and apparently quite normal, holding very different religious beliefs from our own. And we can begin to wonder what makes our religious beliefs special or superior? Should I consider myself epistemically privileged? Or am I epistemically biased or myopic? However, I claim, this is a problem that can be avoided with a less impoverished notion of what religion is, the richer notion she identified at the beginning of the book. That richer notion may lead to some problems of religious diversity, but I think Zagzebski s explorations of the role of self-trust, toward the end of chapter 9, can be developed to address those problems. As a textbook: (A) I am not confident that this could serve as the sole textbook for a philosophy of religion course. Most teachers of philosophy of religion want students working over the primary texts. Zagzebski refers to the primary sources, and provides limited quotes from them. The book could serve as a supplement to the primary readings. (B) I m not sure this could be used in a beginners course. But two of my friends who teach introductory philosophy of religion have told me that they are considering it. (C) Still, I think it can be a good book for teachers, especially those who have developed their interests in philosophy of religion out of philosophical interests in epistemology or metaphysics or mind. (D) For those who have developed their interests in philosophy of religion from an historical

Book reviews 499 perspective, the book is a thoughtful and philosophically interesting reminder of some of those matters. (E) It is well suited for teachers of philosophy of religion, graduate students, and strongly interested amateurs (including divinity school students and faculty, and ministers). ERIC SNIDER Bethel University Religious Studies 44 (2008) doi:10.1017/s0034412508009712 f 2008 Cambridge University Press Peter van Inwagen and Dean Zimmerman (eds) Persons: Human and Divine (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2007). Pp.ix+380. 60.00 (Hbk). ISBN 9780199277516. Peter van Inwagen and Dean Zimmerman have edited a fine collection of fifteen essays at the intersection of the philosophy of God and the philosophy of mind, dedicated to the late Philip L. Quinn. The work as a whole provides some reason for thinking that philosophical reflection on God and human nature should be intertwined. Alvin Plantinga and several other contributors employ arguments based on their Christian theism for certain tenets in philosophy of mind and Brian Leftow draws on some models of personal identity in philosophy of mind to shed light on a Trinitarian concept of God. The contributors differ substantially in their metaphysics (idealism, dualism, and physicalism are each represented), but they have close to a consensus when it comes to accepting theism. In the introduction Zimmerman addresses theologians who may be put off by the analytic methodology of most contributors. Under the heading What analytic philosophy is, was, and wasn t, Zimmerman challenges the assumption that the analytic river is still patrolled by theologian-eating sharks (7). He reports that the waters are much safer, at this point, and under the heading The need for cooperation, Zimmerman urges theologians and philosophers to work on joint projects. This call for co-operation is (in my view) laudatory, though the book itself does not contain work by theologians (unless one is counting philosophical theologians) and the analytic style of, say, John Hawthorne s meticulous, formal reconstruction of Descartes view of attributes is more in keeping with a logic or mathematics journal than current theological literature. Zimmerman devotes a significant part of the introduction to the status of mind body dualism. I shall follow his lead and begin with a survey of how Persons addresses the debate over dualism and its chief rivals. Zimmerman is one among a growing number of philosophers who think that dualism still belongs on the table of live options in philosophy of mind (13). He