Deserving to Be Lucky: Reflections on the Role of Luck and Desert in Sports 1

Similar documents
Scanlon on Double Effect

Utilitarianism: For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), pp Reprinted in Moral Luck (CUP, 1981).

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

BELIEF POLICIES, by Paul Helm. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, Pp. xiii and 226. $54.95 (Cloth).

Handout 2: The Ethical Use of PEDs

Deontology, Rationality, and Agent-Centered Restrictions

KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST. Arnon Keren

POWERS, NECESSITY, AND DETERMINISM

No Love for Singer: The Inability of Preference Utilitarianism to Justify Partial Relationships

CONVENTIONALISM AND NORMATIVITY

Solving the Puzzle of Affirmative Action Jene Mappelerien

Can Rationality Be Naturalistically Explained? Jeffrey Dunn. Abstract: Dan Chiappe and John Vervaeke (1997) conclude their article, Fodor,

Chapter 3 PHILOSOPHICAL ETHICS AND BUSINESS CHAPTER OBJECTIVES. After exploring this chapter, you will be able to:

Moral requirements are still not rational requirements

DOES STRONG COMPATIBILISM SURVIVE FRANKFURT COUNTER-EXAMPLES?

OPEN Moral Luck Abstract:

Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly *

PROSPECTS FOR A JAMESIAN EXPRESSIVISM 1 JEFF KASSER

IS GOD "SIGNIFICANTLY FREE?''

2 FREE CHOICE The heretical thesis of Hobbes is the orthodox position today. So much is this the case that most of the contemporary literature

Writing Essays at Oxford

Philosophy 1100: Introduction to Ethics. Critical Thinking Lecture 2. Background Material for the Exercise on Inference Indicators

Responsibility and the Value of Choice

The Need for Metanormativity: A Response to Christmas

What Lurks Beneath the Integrity Objection. Bernard Williams s alienation and integrity arguments against consequentialism have

Knowledge and its Limits, by Timothy Williamson. Oxford: Oxford University Press, Pp. xi

Zdenko Kodelja HOW TO UNDERSTAND EQUITY IN HIGHER EDUCATION? (Draft)

Lucky to Know? the nature and extent of human knowledge and rational belief. We ordinarily take ourselves to

Ethics Handout 19 Bernard Williams, The Idea of Equality. A normative conclusion: Therefore we should treat men as equals.

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism

Précis of Democracy and Moral Conflict

Rawls, rationality, and responsibility: Why we should not treat our endowments as morally arbitrary

"Book Review: FRANKFURT, Harry G. On Inequality. Princeton and Oxford: Princeton University Press, 2015, 102 pp., $14.95 (hbk), ISBN

Florida State University Libraries

CRUCIAL TOPICS IN THE DEBATE ABOUT THE EXISTENCE OF EXTERNAL REASONS

Virtuous act, virtuous dispositions

The unity of the normative

Rawls s veil of ignorance excludes all knowledge of likelihoods regarding the social

THE CONCEPT OF OWNERSHIP by Lars Bergström

What God Could Have Made

SUMMARIES AND TEST QUESTIONS UNIT 6

Well-Being, Time, and Dementia. Jennifer Hawkins. University of Toronto

The Experience Machine and Mental State Theories of Wellbeing

Divine omniscience, timelessness, and the power to do otherwise

Section 1 of chapter 1 of The Moral Sense advances the thesis that we have a

NOTES ON WILLIAMSON: CHAPTER 11 ASSERTION Constitutive Rules

A Contractualist Reply

Luck, Rationality, and Explanation: A Reply to Elga s Lucky to Be Rational. Joshua Schechter. Brown University

the notion of modal personhood. I begin with a challenge to Kagan s assumptions about the metaphysics of identity and modality.

Reasons With Rationalism After All MICHAEL SMITH

On the alleged perversity of the evidential view of testimony

The Paradox of the stone and two concepts of omnipotence

Inquiry, Knowledge, and Truth: Pragmatic Conceptions. Pragmatism is a philosophical position characterized by its specific mode of inquiry, and

SUPPORT MATERIAL FOR 'DETERMINISM AND FREE WILL ' (UNIT 2 TOPIC 5)

In Defense of Culpable Ignorance

Are There Reasons to Be Rational?

What is the "Social" in "Social Coherence?" Commentary on Nelson Tebbe's Religious Freedom in an Egalitarian Age

Blame and Forfeiture. The central issue that a theory of punishment must address is why we are we permitted to

HUME AND HIS CRITICS: Reid and Kames

Future People, the Non- Identity Problem, and Person-Affecting Principles

Published in Analysis 61:1, January Rea on Universalism. Matthew McGrath

Final Paper. May 13, 2015

Comment on Martha Nussbaum s Purified Patriotism

Well-Being, Disability, and the Mere-Difference Thesis. Jennifer Hawkins Duke University

Actuaries Institute Podcast Transcript Ethics Beyond Human Behaviour

Compatibilist Objections to Prepunishment

LTJ 27 2 [Start of recorded material] Interviewer: From the University of Leicester in the United Kingdom. This is Glenn Fulcher with the very first

Andrea Westlund, in Selflessness and Responsibility for Self, argues

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

Bad Luck Once Again. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Vol. LXXVII No. 3, November 2008 Ó 2008 International Phenomenological Society

The form of relativism that says that whether an agent s actions are right or wrong depends on the moral principles accepted in her own society.

Rawlsian Values. Jimmy Rising

Equality, Fairness, and Responsibility in an Unequal World

A Framework for Thinking Ethically

The Principle of Sufficient Reason and Free Will

1. What is Philosophy?

Adam Smith and the Limits of Empiricism

In Kant s Conception of Humanity, Joshua Glasgow defends a traditional reading of

A New Argument Against Compatibilism

-- The search text of this PDF is generated from uncorrected OCR text.

HOW TO BE RESPONSIBLE FOR SOMETHING WITHOUT CAUSING IT* Carolina Sartorio University of Wisconsin-Madison

PRESS DEFINITION AND THE RELIGION ANALOGY

1/13. Locke on Power

New Aristotelianism, Routledge, 2012), in which he expanded upon

IN DEFENSE OF AN ANIMAL S RIGHT TO LIFE. Aaron Simmons. A Dissertation

Love and Duty. Philosophic Exchange. Julia Driver Washington University, St. Louis, Volume 44 Number 1 Volume 44 (2014)

David Ethics Bites is a series of interviews on applied ethics, produced in association with The Open University.

Philosophical Ethics. Distinctions and Categories

A Coherent and Comprehensible Interpretation of Saul Smilansky s Dualism

Attraction, Description, and the Desire-Satisfaction Theory of Welfare

The Critical Mind is A Questioning Mind

PHIL 202: IV:

EXERCISES, QUESTIONS, AND ACTIVITIES My Answers

Philosophical Perspectives, 16, Language and Mind, 2002 THE AIM OF BELIEF 1. Ralph Wedgwood Merton College, Oxford

Problems of Philosophy

moral absolutism agents moral responsibility

Positivism, Natural Law, and Disestablishment: Some Questions Raised by MacCormick's Moralistic Amoralism

Lecture Notes Wallace Matson, What Rawls Calls Justice (1978) Keith Burgess-Jackson 6 December 2016

factors in Bentham's hedonic calculus.

Reply to Brooke Alan Trisel James Tartaglia *

Transcription:

Journal of the Philosophy of Sport, 2007, 34, 13-25 2007 International Association for the Philosophy of Sport Deserving to Be Lucky: Reflections on the Role of Luck and Desert in Sports 1 Robert Simon Does luck spoil sport? For example, a tightly fought soccer game goes into the last few seconds tied. A player has a long but open shot on goal but his kick results in a poorly struck shot that is off line and too high. But as he kicks, the wind changes direction and an unexpected gust shifts his ball back on goal. Its erratic path allows it to escape the goalkeeper s desperate dive. The kick was not particularly skillful, but the wind gust led to victory. Did the better team win or was the game marred by luck, good for one team and bad for the other but deserved by neither? That luck spoils the sports contest, or at least tends to undermine its point, follows from what might be called the Skill Thesis. According to the Skill Thesis, competitive sports contests are tests of the competitors skills designed to determine which opponent is more skillful in the sport being played. If a contest is decided by luck, it has not determined which of the participants is most skillful and so the game is spoiled or, at the very least, has not determined which of the competitors has best met the test of competition. As Nicholas Dixon recently argued, unlucky losers... provide another category of failed athletic contests (4: p. 17). Some of my own remarks, such as the claim that competition in sports is supposed to be a test of the athletic ability of persons, also suggest such a view (10: p. 83). Does luck spoil the sports contest? If so, as Sigmund Loland has asked, should the possible influence of luck on sports, good and bad, be minimized (5: p. 88)? Concerns about the role of luck in sport, as Dixon has pointed out, reflect larger concerns about how luck should influence our moral evaluations concerns raised famously by Thomas Nagel in his paper Moral Luck (6). If A and B both drive while intoxicated, and A hits a pedestrian but B, who is just as intoxicated as A, does not injure anyone simply through pure luck, is B any less blameworthy than A? If we view even our character and our skills as unearned consequences of what Rawls has called the natural lottery, it remains unclear how much of our behavior is truly under our control and how much is attributable to the luck of the draw. Indeed, if one pushes the natural-lottery argument hard enough, it suggests that desert is not a fundamental moral notion and perhaps not applicable to the world of sport at all. If so, the athlete or team that plays best cannot deserve to win in any important sense, because the notion of desert has, at most, limited applicability to sport, and perhaps to all other areas of life, as well. So while the Skill Thesis may suggest that luck spoils the game, some versions of the lottery argument suggest that because of the luck of the initial draw of talents, skills, and abilities, overall The author <rsimon@hamilton.edu> is with the Dept. of Philosophy, Hamilton College, Clinton, NY 13323. 13

14 Simon outcomes in sports ultimately are more the result of luck than we might think. If so, the significance of claims of athletic desert and merit is greatly reduced, assuming they are not expelled from the playing field altogether. On the contrary, I first want to support and further develop the view, also advanced by Sigmund Loland (5: esp. pp. 87 92), that luck may not always undermine the good sports contest in the way suggested previously, and in some of its manifestations, may even be compatible with the Skill Thesis. 2 It all depends on the kind of luck involved. Indeed, in some cases, it may be plausible to say the athlete in question deserved to be lucky. Second, I want to question whether plausible versions of the lottery argument do eliminate or significantly reduce the significance of desert claims in sports and athletics. While I realize that my arguments need fuller development, I hope to at least ask enough questions to suggest that the role of luck in sports raises issues that may be both complex and interesting and warrant further exploration within the discipline. Does Luck Spoil the Game? Tiger Woods and the 2005 Masters What I believe will stand as one of the most famous shots ever hit in the history of golf was pulled off by Tiger Woods in the final round of the 2005 Masters Tournament. Woods, in position to win the tournament, had hit his tee shot over the par three 16th green into a position from which it looked nearly impossible to recover in two shots for a needed par. He was in thick grass behind a severely sloped green, with the hole cut down the slope only a few feet from the pond guarding the side of the green. To even get close to the hole, Woods would have to hit his shot high on the left, away from the hole, and judge the speed of the severe slope perfectly. If he hit the shot too hard, it might roll into the water, which would surely cost him the tournament. But if he tried too hard to avoid the water and left his putt above the hole, he would have an extremely difficult downhill putt to save par with the same water hazard still lurking behind the hole. Unbelievably, his shot rolled into the hole on its very last turn, giving him a score of one under par for the hole and allowing him to eventually win the event in a play-off against Chris DiMarco. I suggest that there is an important sense in which Woods s shot was lucky and also an important sense in which, if he did not actually deserve to be lucky, the luck in question actually enhances the sports contest in a way compatible with the Skill Thesis and so is morally dissimilar to the fluky gust of wind in the earlier soccer example. That Tiger Woods hit a superb shot was not lucky. For now, however, let us assume that it was lucky that the ball actually went in the hole. Woods might hit a much higher percentage of shots in that situation that would end up near the hole or roll just by it than any average player and a slightly higher percentage than most highly skilled players when placed under the sort of pressure he was under at the time. Still, even Tiger Woods might have to hit shots for hours, perhaps days, before he might actually hole another shot from that position, even in a practice session with no competitive pressure. It is plausible to think that while it was not lucky that he hit a good shot, perhaps a shot few if any other players could have pulled off in that situation, he was lucky that the shot went in.

Deserving to Be Lucky 15 Assuming that it was lucky that Woods holed the shot, there is a sense in which he deserved to be lucky, or if that is too paradoxical a way of putting it, his good luck does not undermine the Skill Thesis. The reason for this is suggested by famous golfer Gary Player s claim, The more I practice the luckier I get. Because Woods (and perhaps only Woods) has the skills to hit a high percentage of shots that have a chance to go in, he is able to give himself a better chance to be lucky than anyone else. So, when he does get the luck, he deserves it more than other players. Or, perhaps better, part of the explanation of why he was lucky is his level of skill. Accordingly, his luck does not undermine the Skill Thesis, but, on the contrary, his skill is what enables him to be lucky more often than others. But is this really a case of luck? Why not just say that the shot reflected Woods s skill. Although it was improbable, it was not lucky. Luck was not involved, only ability. Such a view may even have been expressed by Tiger s competitor, Chris DiMarco, who when reflecting on the shot told an interviewer, Believe it or not, when he made that shot I was ready for it.... When Tiger made it, it was sure unexpected but there you ve got to say, OK, you re playing Tiger Woods and he s going to do things like that. 3 On this view, my example is flawed because it confuses improbability of success with luck. Thus, it is improbable that a pitcher will throw a no-hitter in a Major League Baseball game, but if the pitcher succeeds, it is at least largely through skill, not luck. This last remark has several implications, however. First, the use of the expression largely through skill suggests that many sports achievements involve an element of luck. Even in a no-hitter, opposing batters often make solid contact only to see their line drives go right at a waiting fielder. Woods himself frequently has said that there is an element of luck in any tournament win. It seems that achievements in sport usually reflect varying degrees of skill and luck. If so, most contests involve an element of luck: Luck admits of degrees. The pitcher had a bit of luck in that all three of the opponents solid hits went directly to a fielder, but, otherwise, the no-hitter was the result of skill. In another game, however, luck can play a larger role, as when one baseball team continually hits weak bloopers that just happen to fall between the fielders. In any case, the thesis that luck does not always ruin or even negatively affect the game and that some luck can be, in a sense, deserved does not rest entirely on the Woods example. Perhaps what that example does show, however, is that the line between luck and skill cannot always be easily drawn and that many sports actions may reflect varying elements of both. Given that, we can distinguish between strong and weak amendments to the Skill Thesis. According to the strong version, elite athletes can deserve to be lucky in that their skill level is such that they give themselves the best chance for good luck to strike a far better chance than most other competitors. According to the weak version, although it may not be warranted to talk of deserving to be lucky, at least sometimes a lucky play can be compatible with the Skill Thesis since the kind of luck in question is not a fluke. Rather, it results from skilled athletes giving themselves the best chance for a fortunate outcome. To make this point more plausible, consider a different version of our original example where a fluky gust of wind determines the outcome of a soccer game. Suppose again that the game is played on an exceedingly windy day, which makes

16 Simon it nearly impossible for all but the most skilled players to control shots from anywhere but short range. This time, however, our shooter is one of the elite players and, in fact, can control her shots better than anyone else on the field. This time she shoots from some distance from the goal, and although her shot looks like it will miss, she was the only player in the game who could even have come close from that distance. Suddenly, however, the wind gusts, diverting the shot past the now out-of-position goalkeeper and into the net for the winning shot. Didn t this shooter deserve to be lucky since it was only through skill that she was able to place the ball in a position where luck could take effect? In fact, she was the only one on the field who could have done so. Or, if you find the idea of deserving to be lucky too paradoxical, shouldn t you at least concede that her shot did not spoil the game? In fact, as the weaker amendment suggests, isn t the victory compatible with the Skill Thesis? Even though the outcome was decided in part by luck, an unexpected wind gust, it was the shooter s skill that put her in position for luck to strike. (Surely this case differs from the one in which a poorly struck shot is pushed into the net by an unexpected gust of wind. In this sort of case, the game was won because of a fluke. This contrasts with the case in which the athlete s skill created the opportunity for luck to strike.) Even if the argument as made so far is granted, however, we can question whether the role of luck ought to be minimized in sport. Here it is important to distinguish what I would call a fluke, having nothing to do with the skill of the athlete, from what I have suggested is deserved luck or what might be called positional luck (since it arises from the skill of putting oneself in a position to be lucky). 4 The case for eliminatism, the view that the role of luck in sport should be eliminated or at least minimized, surely is strongest when applied to flukes since, by definition, they do not arise from the skills of the athletes and hence appear to violate the Skill Thesis. Even here, however, the case for eliminatism is far from self-evident. For one thing, the possibility of a fluke s determining an outcome of a contest introduces an element of uncertainty that can make the game more exciting for spectators and participants alike. Moreover, it may promote a desirable degree of humility among even the most successful athletes and create an appreciation for the often arbitrary contingencies that can affect human life. Finally, even flukes can be regarded as compatible with a broad interpretation of the Skill Thesis. Even if a contest is decided by a fluke, that does not reflect in any way the skill of the players in that event. How the athletes react to it in future contests may indicate how well they meet the test set by competitive sport. Is the loser destroyed by a fluky loss in a crucial contest, or can he or she overcome bad fortune and rise to new heights in the future? Do the beneficiaries of flukes become overconfident, and as a result do they lose to supposedly inferior opponents in the future? In other words, if we view the test of sport as extending beyond a specific contest to a series of contests, a season, or even a career, flukes can be part of the test of athletic competition. 5 Of course, such brief remarks are not determinative, but they at least suggest that eliminatism faces difficulties even when only flukes are at issue. The case for eliminatism is even weaker where positional luck is at issue. If the considerations advanced earlier have force, luck of this sort reflects the skill of the athlete and may even be deserved.

Deserving to Be Lucky 17 Consider a second issue. Is the degree to which positional or deserved luck should be tolerated, welcomed, or minimized relative to the sport being played? Should soccer games be held in enclosed arenas whenever possible to minimize the effects of weather? Should golf courses be designed to reward similar shots similarly or should the luck of the bounce be incorporated into course design, as in traditional Scottish link courses? That is, we might have choices in the way we situate or set up sports contests that allow greater or lesser roles for positional luck. As the sports relativist contends, the degree to which restrictions are desirable may vary from sport to sport. It might be plausibly argued, for example, that in short timed events, such as a 100-yard dash, we should want to virtually eliminate luck from affecting the contest since, or so it might be argued, there is virtually no way competitors can react to its influence in the brief time in which the event transpires. 6 Although I cannot discuss this sort of sports relativism extensively here and would not reject it out of hand, the previous arguments suggest that positional luck (and perhaps even flukes) may play a desirable role in virtually all athletic contests. In addition to the suspense added to contests for spectators and participants, luck can often also add to the nature of the test faced by athletes, even in events such as sprints in track or swimming. Thus, suppose in a sprint event at an intercollegiate swim meet, three swimmers, A, B, and C, are the top contenders to win. Swimmer A unfortunately starts falsely (and as a result is disqualified). B is momentarily distracted by A s false start, but C maintains concentration and wins by a small margin. In a sense, A s false start was luck from the perspective of B and C, who are not responsible for it. Be that as it may, C, by maintaining concentration more fully than B, met the test constituted by the event and in this sense deserved to win even though C might not have won if B had maintained concentration to a similar extent. So, against both eliminatism and strong versions of sports relativism, positional luck can play a role compatible with the Skill Thesis even in events such as sprints where the claims of sports relativism might have seemed to have their clearest application. 7 I conclude, then, that luck does not always spoil a good sports contest and does not always show that the best athletes failed to win. As Loland puts it, Where luck follows skill, there is no serious threat to... meritocratic distribution of advantage (5: p. 88). Rather, the abilities of skilled athletes created the potential for luck to work in their favor, and so on the stronger version of my thesis, they did deserve to be lucky. At the very least (on the weaker version), they met the challenge of the contest better than their opponents. In such cases, luck does not spoil the game but can even enhance it and make us appreciate the skills of the successful players even more than otherwise. 8 The Place of Desert in Sport The idea that some athletes deserve to be lucky presupposes that desert can play a role in competitive sport. We speak of some competitors deserving to win, or not deserving to lose, or of superior athletes deserving the MVP award. We compare the merits of top players and think that normally the most meritorious player deserves the most recognition. But is this kind of talk, or at least much of it,

18 Simon based on a mistaken presupposition? To paraphrase the title of a recent article that appeared in this journal, where is the desert when the best man wins? (2) Of particular interest, to me at least, is skepticism about the role of desert in sport arising from the kinds of concerns raised by John Rawls in A Theory of Justice. These arise from what has been called the natural lottery, that is, the initial distribution of genetic endowments and favorable environmental circumstances into which the individual is born. Since these factors were not under the person s control, he or she can claim no credit for them or for the benefits that arise largely as a result of their influence. More strictly, as George Sher has formulated the argument, if one individual has a competitive advantage over another due to differences in initial circumstances that were under the control of neither, the favored individual can claim no credit for the successes that flow from that undeserved head start (8: pp. 362 364). Many of us would reply that in athletics it is not our initial innate talent that determines athletic success but what we do with it how hard we work to develop it, our choice of strategies, our commitment to training, and the like. Rawls responds, however, that the assertion that a man deserves the superior character that enables him to make the effort to cultivate his abilities is equally problematic: for his character depends in large part upon fortunate family and social circumstances for which he can claim no credit (7: p. 104). It is unclear, however, how such remarks of Rawls are to be taken. I doubt that they express an overall commitment to some form of hard determinism or incompatibilism. After all, Rawls s focus in A Theory of Justice is on assessing the fairness or unfairness of structural inequalities in the basic structure of societies, not on defending a metaphysical approach to free will. If so, the natural-lottery argument is best understood as an appeal to our considered judgment that in a system where initial advantages are unfairly distributed, the claims of the successful that they deserve to be on top should at best be taken with a large grain of salt. Perhaps even in such an unfair system, someone can deserve praise for individual moral choices for example, for helping someone in trouble but large-scale economic success and failure averaged over a large population are often or generally the result of unearned initial circumstances for which we can take no credit. Whether or not this was Rawls s view, David Carr recently has criticized attributions of desert in competitive sport on the grounds that outcomes in athletics reflect and frequently are best explained by unearned initial distributions of talents and abilities for which the competitors can take no credit. Carr s article is interesting and important, not only because of its analytic acuity but also because it draws out the apparent implications for desert from some apparently simple and plausible assumptions. Carr himself denies that he is a hard determinist or that he rejects all applications of the concept of personal responsibility. Rather, Carr acknowledges that some qualities, let us call them moral qualities, are under the athlete s control. He specifically mentions courage and self-control and presumably would allow other qualities such as dedication, commitment, integrity, and the capacity to maintain composure and focus in the face of difficulty, as well. However, Carr suggests that not only innate athletic ability but also such qualities as the ability to see and take advantage of strategic opportunities (strategic intelligence) or the ability to benefit

Deserving to Be Lucky 19 from repetitive training, drills, and exercises reflect initial endowments and so are undeserved. As Carr says of strategic intelligence, there is no reason assuming such intelligence to be the usual mixture of training and native wit to give him or her any special credit for it (2: p. 6). Do such arguments, based on our lack of responsibility for our initial endowments of skills and abilities, undermine the legitimacy of most attributions of desert in sport? In a sense, is athletic success largely the result of the luck of the initial draw? Are claims that a particular athlete or team deserved to win or deserved the award (or deserved to lose) always or almost always inapplicable or illegitimate? I suggest not. Any theory that seeks to undermine claims of desert based on the morally arbitrary initial distribution of natural and social assets without falling into a version of hard determinism or total rejection of personal responsibility needs to distinguish, as Carr attempts to, between characteristics that are and are not under an individual s control. However, it is far from clear how this is to be done in a satisfactory way. For example, is there a sharp distinction between self-control, which Carr regards as a moral property for whose exercise we are responsible, and a broad understanding of strategic intelligence, thought of as the ability to best use one s other assets as the competitive situation of the sports contest dictates? On the contrary, it would seem that the ability to control one s emotions is itself an important component of strategic intelligence. Moreover, self-control is the kind of trait that may well be influenced at least as much by one s genetic endowment or early childhood education as the development of strategic intelligence itself. Rather than simply assuming that one ability, the ability to keep one s cool under pressure, is entirely our responsibility, and the other, the ability to recognize and take advantage of strategic possibilities, is entirely out of our control, a more flexible interactive model seems at least as plausible. Moral qualities such as selfcontrol, mental toughness, and ability (or even the courage) to see the situation as it is and not as the athlete would like it to be are all components of strategic intelligence. Doesn t the capacity (or meta-ability) of top athletes to use their other abilities intelligently seem on the face of it to be as much under their control as what Carr has called moral qualities such as courage, dedication, or integrity? Of course, the natural lottery may play some role in influencing how each of these characteristics develops. But, assuming that we reject hard determinism, it would seem that the most the critic of desert is entitled to conclude is that we do not deserve total credit for our achievements in athletics, rather than that we do not deserve any credit for them. Surely, some of the credit for Tiger Woods s fabulous shot in the 2005 Masters goes to his father Earl for his enormous influence on Woods s development. But Woods s control under pressure, his ability to focus, and the dedication and practice that enabled him to hone his skills and develop his innate talent surely are at least partly to his credit, as well. At the very least, we have not been shown a plausible place to draw the line between those moral qualities, allegedly under the athlete s control, and strategic capacities, allegedly the result of the natural lottery or the luck of the draw. This point is reinforced by George Sher s observation that in any complex activity or practice, there are multiple combinations of talents, skills, and capacities

20 Simon that can contribute to success (8: pp. 370 373). In athletics, one player may have more innate ability than others, but her competitors may have different combinations of characteristics, such as the capacity to exert greater effort or the patience and courage to develop new techniques even if the learning process may involve temporary setbacks. These qualities may allow them to overcome their initial disadvantage in native talent. Accordingly, if we acknowledge that some of the factors contributing to athletic success are under the athlete s control and that these include higher order capacities grouped under the umbrella concept of strategic capabilities, athletic performance is not simply the result of the natural lottery and is often the sort of activity for which participants can claim at least partial credit (or take at least partial blame). Of particular interest in this context is the point made by my colleague at Hamilton College, sociologist Dan Chambliss, in his award winning book, Champions: The Making of Olympic Swimmers. In his book, Chambliss describes his experiences as an observer at the Mission Viejo swim club during the selection of swimmers for the American team in the 1984 Olympic Games (3). During his study, Chambliss attended virtually all team practices and meetings and had full access to athletes and coaches. His special interest was to advance a theory as to why some athletes made the Olympic team and others did not. In a chapter titled The Mundanity of Excellence, Chambliss argued that differences in natural ability do relatively little to explain who made the cut and who did not. Indeed, past a certain surprisingly minimal point, adding time to workouts had little if any effect. Rather, he found that such factors as not cutting corners in practice (for example, using perfect form in making turns rather than being sloppy), changing techniques, and favorable attitudes toward practice (i.e., regarding practice not as a chore but as one of the centers of the athlete s social life) all played major roles. Chambliss s work suggests that the kinds of factors most clearly affected by the natural lottery or the luck of the draw, such as innate ability and innate character traits, play only a partial role in affecting athletic outcome. Other factors including psychological and moral ones that are likely to be under the athlete s control, such as the willingness to treat each practice as if it were an actual contest, play a significant role, as well. 9 So far, I have argued that there is no clear line distinguishing the characteristics that are most affected by the natural lottery or luck of the draw, such as innate ability and those that Carr admits are under the athletes control, such as moral qualities. I also have suggested that strategic capacities should be regarded as at least partly in the latter group and, along with the kinds of factors studied by Chambliss, may affect athletic success at least as much as innate abilities and capacities. This point is reinforced by Sher s argument about plural paths to success, which also suggests that it is how one uses one s gifts, and not the mere possession of them, that is crucial. Of course, some may reject the whole distinction between what is under our control and what is not, perhaps because they think such a distinction applies to the world only if causal determinism is false, and they believe causal determinism is true. What I have argued is that if the distinction does make sense, which Carr explicitly allows and which I believe Rawls might have acknowledged, as well, there is room for merit-based claims of desert in competitive athletics.

Deserving to Be Lucky 21 Let me also suggest, although briefly, that a conceptual framework that allows for claims of desert based on our responsibility for some of our actions may have a moral rather than a metaphysical base and so be defensible regardless of the truth of determinism. That is, the distinction between what is and is not under our control may be justified by what might be called its moral function rather than its metaphysical basis or appropriateness. An analogy with the law of torts may be useful here. Torts is that area of law where it is determined who should bear the costs of an injury. For example, should it be the injured person (as when I hit my thumb with a hammer) or another agent (as when you carelessly swing your hammer, not noticing my thumb is in the way). One approach to determining who should bear the cost is to find the real cause of the injury. If the real or true cause is my action, I am responsible and should bear the cost, but if the real cause is your action, you are responsible and should bear the cost. A problem with this approach is that it may not be a simple matter of fact which contributing factor is the real cause. Were you to blame for not checking that my thumb was out of the way before you swung your hammer, or should I have taken more care in keeping my thumb to myself once I saw you were carrying a hammer? The issue seems to be a moral one, not one of simple causation. 10 Thus, on a second approach, we can think of torts as the attempt to distribute the costs of injury fairly. On this view, it is more akin to a moral than a metaphysical enterprise. Thus, if a golfer is struck by another player s errant shot, who should bear the costs of the injury? Courts have ruled that as long as players take due care to warn others of mishit shots, usually by calling out a warning, they normally are not responsible for injuries caused by their wild slices or hooks. Rather, there are certain risks inherent in golf, and golfers are regarded as voluntarily assuming them when entering the course. Right or wrong, this seems like a moral argument about assuming responsibility for one s actions. On this view, the law of torts is moral, not metaphysical. A similar approach can be applied to desert claims in sports. One traditional line of argument that reflects this approach attempts to reconcile determinism with responsibility and personal desert by relying on utilitarianism. For example, rewarding merit (and in some cases penalizing substandard behavior) may create incentives for acting in desirable ways and so improve the general welfare. However, even many of those favorably disposed to some forms of utilitarianism find such an approach unsatisfactory, since it at most seems to show that it is useful to treat people as responsible agents, not that it also is fair or just to do so. A second nonutilitarian approach may be more successful in providing an ethical basis for desert claims. This approach ties the practice of acknowledging our deserts to the Rawlsian primary good of self-respect. Thus, it is noteworthy that in A Theory of Justice, Rawls rests his argument for the principle of equal opportunity, which in his theory takes priority over other aspects of his difference principle, to self-respect. For example, he argues that If some places were not open on a basis fair to all, those kept out would be right in feeling unjustly treated even though they benefited from the greater efforts of those who were allowed to hold them.... They would be justified in their complaint... because they were debarred from experiencing the realization of self which comes from a skillful and devoted exercise of social duties. (7: p. 84)

22 Simon However, if a realization of self comes from a skillful and devoted exercise of social duties, isn t that because we take pride in our performance or at least view it as something for which we are responsible? It is not viewed merely as something that happens to us but something we do. My suggestion is that taking this responsibility perspective is justifiable not primarily, or at least not only, because it reflects debatable metaphysical presuppositions but rather because it promotes self-respect and assigns due weight to what might be regarded as the central characteristics of personhood. That is, if individuals are to be treated as persons such that it is appropriate for them to find fulfillment and satisfaction through their actions, characteristics we regard as central to their personhood, such as character and choices, must be attributed to the person. Thus, our voluntary actions reflect our status as persons and are not events that merely happen to us. The practice of assigning deserts according to merit is an important way of assigning weight to those central characteristics of personhood and so is justifiable by reference to the ethical importance of that assignment. 11 As competitors in sport, we react to the choices and strategies of others, decide which of our skills to develop and how to do so, and employ the various forms of strategic intelligence. Thus, if Rawls s point is correct, sports, or at least certain instances of sporting activity, are paradigmatic activities in which we express the core qualities of personhood and find fulfillment through doing so. We may wonder, at this point, whether sport plays a unique or at least special role in allowing for the expression of our personhood and in promoting self-respect. This question needs to be explored more fully than I am able to do at present, but perhaps the following brief comments might suggest lines of inquiry that warrant further examination. While I doubt that any claim of uniqueness can be justified, a more plausible claim is that competitive sport, when carried out within an appropriate moral framework, does have certain features that enable it to play a special role regarding self-respect. These features have been emphasized in much of the literature on the ethics of sport but, when conjoined, constitute a highly plausible basis for assigning sport a special role in this area. In particular, a well-designed sport provides a complex variety of challenges to participants that call on them to make intelligent choices about strategies, about the intentions of opponents, about how to react to moves made by the opposition, and about which skills to develop and exercise in particular contexts. Accordingly, when we freely enter sporting competition with due regard for meeting its internal goals (meeting the challenges of the sport), we are called on to express deep features of our character as persons while reacting to other competitors who also exercise similar traits of personhood and who facilitate our own development by contributing to the sporting challenges we face. 12 My own suggestion for developing such a line of argument further would be to explore its relation to Peter Strawson s influential distinction between the participant perspective, in which reactive attitudes such as gratitude presuppose an internal perspective of the person, and the objective attitude, which does not. 13 While I hope such a suggestion proves fruitful, the major argument made here is that desert-based claims of merit should be recognized in sport because the practice of doing so is crucial to such goods as self-respect, fulfillment, and mutual acknowledgment of our status as persons. As Claudia Card suggests, the recognition of one s deserts is... important to one s self-respect, even to one s

Deserving to Be Lucky 23 personal integrity and identity, just as recognition of oneself as politically the equal of one s peers (also) is important to one s self-respect (1: p. 188). But is this to misunderstand Rawls s suggestion about self-fulfillment? Perhaps Rawls s point is not that we should take pride in our achievements, which may be largely due to the luck of the draw in the natural lottery, but that carrying out socially useful tasks and exercising skills is something from which humans gain respect and that they find fulfilling. Thus, I find it fulfilling to be a good adviser to students and gain respect from the fact that I am doing something useful, without taking pride in my activity, thinking I deserve some special reward for it. Perhaps the respect and fulfillment come from contributing to a greater good or doing something useful rather than pride in one s merit. And of course, one might argue, sport does not contribute to a greater good in the same way as medicine, science, teaching, and other forms of useful work. However, it is hard to see why we would gain self-respect or self-fulfillment from an activity that did not reflect back on our core personal qualities; it might be appropriate to be glad that we are contributing to a greater good, but to get fulfillment and respect from the skillful exercise of our talent (rather than merely from some activity we just happen to be engaged in), which is what Rawls refers to in his own discussion, requires us to view our relevant behavior as our own acts, which in turn opens us to the possibility of receiving credit or blame for them. If so, the recognition of merit in sport may be appropriate not just because it recognizes that some areas of our life may be under our control (which hard determinism denies) but also because at its best sport constitutes a practice in which we recognize ourselves as persons and treat others in ways that generate self-respect, fulfillment, and mutual acknowledgment of our common personhood. It might also be objected that this line of argument does not show that we actually deserve anything in sport but only that there is a moral case for treating us as if we have legitimate claims of desert. That is, just as utilitarianism shows at most that it is useful to recognize claims of desert (as incentives or disincentives), so the present argument only shows that it is fair or just to give some weight to desert claims. Neither argument, however, shows that we actually deserve anything. 14 This sort of objection has considerable force, but perhaps it begs the question by assuming that the real basis of desert must be metaphysical (free will?) rather than moral. That is, if the practice of assigning weight to claims of desert has a moral basis all the way down, then we do sometimes deserve certain responses to our performances, just as certain distributions are fair if they satisfy the appropriate criteria of fairness. If this line of response is correct, or even on the right track, when we say, for example, that Tiger Woods deserved to win the 2005 Masters, we are making a moral claim that stands or falls on the worth of the moral arguments supporting it and those supporting the overall practice of acknowledging desert, within which it falls. Concluding Comment I have argued here, or perhaps better have presented sketches of how a more fully worked out argument might go, for two conclusions. First, following a line of thought suggested by Sigmund Loland (5: particularly pp. 87 92), I have maintained

24 Simon that luck does not always spoil an athletic contest but can often enhance our appreciation for the skills of top performers who, in a sense, can deserve to be lucky. 15 Second, I have suggested that attempts to expunge the idea of desert (and claims of merit based on it) from sports by appeal to natural-lottery-type arguments should be viewed skeptically. If this second line of argument has force, it reinforces the conviction that sports, while lacking the instrumental value of activities such as education and medicine, have a value of their own. In them, we express our nature as persons when we freely attempt to meet challenges for their own sake and exercise deep human capacities in doing so. While excessive pride in achievement is a vice and modesty a virtue, the influence of luck on individual athletic contests and, on a broader scale, through the natural lottery does not rule out the role of merit and desert in sport. 16 Although many factors may influence the outcome of athletic contests, and desert is seldom the whole story (hence, modesty is appropriate after success in sport), desert need not be entirely absent, either. Sometimes, the best competitors deserve the trophy. Notes 1. This address was given as the Warren P. Fraleigh Distinguished Scholar Lecture for the International Association for the Philosophy of Sport, Niagara Falls, Canada, September 2006. I am grateful for the many acute questions from the audience during discussion, as well as from a referee for this journal, and regret that I am unable to examine all of them here. I am also grateful to Hamilton College for a faculty fellowship that helped support work on this essay. 2. Loland, like myself, thinks that the influence of luck does not always spoil a sports contest and can sometimes enhance it, and hence the influence of luck should not be eliminated but optimized (5: p. 91). However, while Loland acknowledges that luck sometimes can follow skill, I believe I draw a tighter connection between the exercise of skill and ensuing luck than he might wish to acknowledge and do not know if he would endorse the strong version of my thesis, namely, that a skilled athlete can deserve to be lucky. 3. Chris DiMarco quoted in All the Right Stuff, Golf Magazine. Vol. 48, No. 4 (April 2006), p. 87. 4. The expression positional luck was suggested by a referee for this journal. 5. On this point, see also Loland s discussion (5: pp. 100 102). 6. In discussion after the Fraleigh Lecture, Gunnar Breivik suggested that luck does and perhaps should play varying degrees in different sports, and I am grateful to him, and to a referee for this journal, for calling such a view to my attention. For further consideration of this issue, see Loland s discussion (5: particularly pp. 87 92). 7. The idea for this example emerged from a suggestion by former Hamilton College swim coach David Thompson, although he himself had some doubt as to whether the false start was a genuine instance of luck. 8. Nicholas Rescher has distinguished luck from fortune. On Rescher s distinction, you are lucky if you win the lottery but are fortunate if you will gain a large inheritance from wealthy relatives. Luck is a matter of having something good or bad happen that lies outside the horizon of effective forseeability.... You are fortunate if something good happens to you or for you in the natural course of things (6: p. 28). On this view, Woods s shot in the 2005 Masters was lucky, but it was not luck that Tiger Woods has become a great golfer, although it surely is fortunate for him (and for golf fans) that he has done so.

Deserving to Be Lucky 25 9. I myself think Chambliss may assign too low a role to natural ability (after all, the athletes he studied may have been preselected at least partly on the basis of such ability), but even if that is right, he still can be correct in arguing that other factors also play a significant role in affecting athletic success. 10. Such a view is suggested, for example, by William Prosser when he writes that the real basis of negligence is... behavior which should be recognized as involving unreasonable danger to others (italics my own), William Prosser, Negligence from his The Law of Torts, 4th ed. (West Publishing Company, 1971), reprinted in John Arthur and William Shaw, eds., Readings in the Philosophy of Law (NJ: Pearson, Prentice-Hall, 2006) p. 409, and by Jules L. Coleman s and Jeffrie G. Murphy s discussions of assigning the cost of automobile accidents, particularly in their Philosophy of Law (Boulder, CO: Westview Press, 1990), pp. 149 161. 11. I have argued more fully for this point elsewhere. (See 9: pp. 224 241). 12. A referee for this journal raised the intriguing question of whether the exercise of either chemically or genetically enhanced skills and talents would have a similar tie to self-respect. 13. See Peter Strawson, Freedom and Resentment, in G. Watson, ed. Free Will. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1982, 59 80. 14. I owe this point both to my colleague Richard Werner and to Jeffrey Frye, who raised it during discussion at the Fraleigh lecture. I would not have appreciated its force without their criticism. 15. As Steven Mumford pointed out at the Fraleigh lecture, an element of luck may make the contest more interesting to spectators by generating uncertainty, perhaps by enhancing the chances of an upset. See also Loland (5: p. 91) for a similar point. 16. Thus, whether desert should be the dominant factor in distributing rewards and punishment in any endeavor or social practice may depend on our evaluation of the overall fairness of the practice. My claim is not that desert should or should always be the only or even the dominant principle of distribution, even in sports, but rather that it is among the principles that need to be counted and given weight. References 1. Card, Claudia. Individual Entitlements in Justice as Fairness In Victoria Davion and Clark Wolf (Eds.). The Idea of a Political Liberalism. Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield, 2000, 176-189. 2. Carr, David. Where s the Merit if the Best Man Wins? Journal of the Philosophy of Sport, XXVI, 1999, 1-9. 3. Chambliss, Dan. Champions: The Making of Olympic Swimmers. New York: Harper Collins, 1988. 4. Dixon, Nicholas. On Winning and Athletic Superiority. Journal of the Philosophy of Sport, XXVI, 1999, 10-26. 5. Loland, Sigmund. Fair Play in Sport: A Moral Norm System. New York: Routledge, 2002. 6. Nagel, Thomas. Moral Luck in Nagel s Mortal Questions. New York: Cambridge University Press, 1991. 7. Rawls, John. A Theory of Justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1971. 8. Sher, George. Effort, Ability, and Personal Desert Philosophy and Public Affairs, 8(4), 1979, 361-376. 9. Simon, Robert L. An Indirect Defense of the Merit Principle The Philosophical Forum, X(2 4), 1978-79, 224-240. 10. Simon, Robert L. Fair Play. Boulder, CO: Westview Press, 2004.