The Prospective View of Obligation

Similar documents
OBJECTIVISM AND PROSPECTIVISM ABOUT RIGHTNESS

A CONSEQUENTIALIST RESPONSE TO THE DEMANDINGNESS OBJECTION Nicholas R. Baker, Lee University THE DEMANDS OF ACT CONSEQUENTIALISM

THE CASE OF THE MINERS

Is Moral Obligation Objective or Subjective?

Objective consequentialism and the licensing dilemma

What To Do When You Don t Know What To Do. Fred Feldman. 1. A Puzzle in Ethics

Moral Obligation, Evidence, and Belief

Abstract: According to perspectivism about moral obligation, our obligations are affected by

A Contractualist Reply

WHEN is a moral theory self-defeating? I suggest the following.

Vol. II, No. 5, Reason, Truth and History, 127. LARS BERGSTRÖM

Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly *

OUGHT AND THE PERSPECTIVE OF THE AGENT

Philosophical Perspectives, 16, Language and Mind, 2002 THE AIM OF BELIEF 1. Ralph Wedgwood Merton College, Oxford

What Lurks Beneath the Integrity Objection. Bernard Williams s alienation and integrity arguments against consequentialism have

On Searle on Human Rights, Again! J. Angelo Corlett, San Diego State University

Scanlon on Double Effect

Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords

Akrasia and Uncertainty

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

Notes on Moore and Parker, Chapter 12: Moral, Legal and Aesthetic Reasoning

Bayesian Probability

TWO ACCOUNTS OF THE NORMATIVITY OF RATIONALITY

On the Concept of a Morally Relevant Harm

Zimmerman, Michael J. Supererogation and doing the nest one can. American Philosophical Quarterly 30(4), October 1993.

A lonelier contractualism A. J. Julius, UCLA, January

No Love for Singer: The Inability of Preference Utilitarianism to Justify Partial Relationships

Informational Models in Deontic Logic: A Comment on Ifs and Oughts by Kolodny and MacFarlane

The Need for Metanormativity: A Response to Christmas

SUNK COSTS. Robert Bass Department of Philosophy Coastal Carolina University Conway, SC

Justifying Rational Choice The Role of Success * Bruno Verbeek

Deontological Perspectivism: A Reply to Lockie Hamid Vahid, Institute for Research in Fundamental Sciences, Tehran

Accounting for Moral Conflicts

Zimmerman, Michael J. Subsidiary Obligation, Philosophical Studies, 50 (1986):

How should I live? I should do whatever brings about the most pleasure (or, at least, the most good)

Judith Jarvis Thomson s Normativity

Reasons With Rationalism After All MICHAEL SMITH

RESPONSE TO ADAM KOLBER S PUNISHMENT AND MORAL RISK

Lost in Transmission: Testimonial Justification and Practical Reason

Rawls s veil of ignorance excludes all knowledge of likelihoods regarding the social

A Case against Subjectivism: A Reply to Sobel

Rawls, rationality, and responsibility: Why we should not treat our endowments as morally arbitrary

GS SCORE ETHICS - A - Z. Notes

Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Introduction

CAN AN ACT-CONSEQUENTIALIST THEORY BE AGENT RELATIVE? Douglas W. Portmore

WORLD UTILITARIANISM AND ACTUALISM VS. POSSIBILISM

A solution to the problem of hijacked experience

Divine omniscience, timelessness, and the power to do otherwise

-- The search text of this PDF is generated from uncorrected OCR text.

NICHOLAS J.J. SMITH. Let s begin with the storage hypothesis, which is introduced as follows: 1

24.02 Moral Problems and the Good Life

A Review on What Is This Thing Called Ethics? by Christopher Bennett * ** 1

Dworkin on the Rufie of Recognition

Causing People to Exist and Saving People s Lives Jeff McMahan

Gandalf s Solution to the Newcomb Problem. Ralph Wedgwood

Buck-Passers Negative Thesis

THE MEANING OF OUGHT. Ralph Wedgwood. What does the word ought mean? Strictly speaking, this is an empirical question, about the

The fact that some action, A, is part of a valuable and eligible pattern of action, P, is a reason to perform A. 1

PARFIT'S MISTAKEN METAETHICS Michael Smith

Are There Reasons to Be Rational?

A Coherent and Comprehensible Interpretation of Saul Smilansky s Dualism

McCLOSKEY ON RATIONAL ENDS: The Dilemma of Intuitionism

Moral Reasons, Overridingness, and Supererogation*

Bombs and Coconuts, or Rational Irrationality

Moral Twin Earth: The Intuitive Argument. Terence Horgan and Mark Timmons have recently published a series of articles where they

Action in Special Contexts

Virtue Ethics without Character Traits

Epistemic Normativity for Naturalists

Democracy and epistemology: a reply to Talisse

NOT SO PROMISING AFTER ALL: EVALUATOR-RELATIVE TELEOLOGY AND COMMON-SENSE MORALITY

in Social Science Encyclopedia (Routledge, forthcoming, 2006). Consequentialism (Blackwell Publishers, forthcoming, 2006)

Correct Beliefs as to What One Believes: A Note

CONSEQUENTIALISM AND THE SELF OTHER ASYMMETRY

Future People, the Non- Identity Problem, and Person-Affecting Principles

Against Satisficing Consequentialism BEN BRADLEY. Syracuse University

Philosophical Ethics. Distinctions and Categories

Does the Skeptic Win? A Defense of Moore. I. Moorean Methodology. In A Proof of the External World, Moore argues as follows:

Why there is no such thing as a motivating reason

Sidgwick on Practical Reason

(A fully correct plan is again one that is not constrained by ignorance or uncertainty (pp ); which seems to be just the same as an ideal plan.

Interest-Relativity and Testimony Jeremy Fantl, University of Calgary

Responsibility and Normative Moral Theories

Is there a good epistemological argument against platonism? DAVID LIGGINS

Should We Assess the Basic Premises of an Argument for Truth or Acceptability?

Received: 30 August 2007 / Accepted: 16 November 2007 / Published online: 28 December 2007 # Springer Science + Business Media B.V.

POWERS, NECESSITY, AND DETERMINISM

How to Mistake a Trivial Fact About Probability For a. Substantive Fact About Justified Belief

Must Consequentialists Kill?

A SOLUTION TO FORRESTER'S PARADOX OF GENTLE MURDER*

* Dalhousie Law School, LL.B. anticipated Interpretation and Legal Theory. Andrei Marmor Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992, 193 pp.

Andrea Westlund, in Selflessness and Responsibility for Self, argues

Epistemic Consequentialism, Truth Fairies and Worse Fairies

BELIEF POLICIES, by Paul Helm. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, Pp. xiii and 226. $54.95 (Cloth).

ZAGZEBSKI ON RATIONALITY

Asymmetry and Self-Sacrifice

KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST. Arnon Keren

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View

Philosophical Review.

The ontology of human rights and obligations

The normativity of content and the Frege point

Transcription:

The Prospective View of Obligation Please do not cite or quote without permission. 8-17-09 In an important new work, Living with Uncertainty, Michael Zimmerman seeks to provide an account of the conditions for overall moral obligation. 1 In his account, overall moral obligation is the kind of moral obligation with which the morally conscientious person is primarily concerned. When confronting some moral choice a person may ask herself, out of conscientiousness, What ought I to do? In this question ought expresses overall moral obligation, and is a contrary to wrong. According to Zimmerman, conscientiousness precludes deliberately doing what one believes to be overall morally wrong, although it does not require deliberately doing, or trying to do, only what one believes to be overall morally right, since on occasion one may find oneself forced to act while lacking any belief about the overall moral status of one s act. 2 Noting that there has been philosophical disagreement about the correct account of this primary sense of moral obligation, Zimmerman distinguishes three prominent proposals: The Objective View (first formulation): An agent ought to perform an act if and only if it is the best option that he (or she) has. The Putatively-Right View: An agent ought to perform an act if and only if he believes that it is the best option that he has. 1

The Prospective View (fourth but not final formulation): An agent ought to perform an act if and only if it is the option that has the greatest expectable value for the agent. 3 Zimmerman argues that the Objective View and the Putatively-Right View are each subject to fatal problems, and that the Prospective View is the correct account of moral obligation. Although he proposes further and more complicated versions of the Prospective View, the differences between these and the view stated here are immaterial to our immediate purposes, so I shall confine myself to the version of the Prospective View articulated here. Zimmerman, of course, is not alone in advocating the Prospective View: it is an increasingly important contender in these debates, and has been adopted by a significant number of other theorists. 4 Zimmerman s special contribution to these debates is his innovative new positive argument in favor of the Prospective View. In this paper I examine Zimmerman s core argument in favor of the Prospective View, and make the case that this argument fails. I should note, however, that even if I am correct about this, and even if no other compelling argument in favor of the Prospective View is forthcoming, nonetheless the book itself contains a mass of interesting arguments on the topic of how morality ought to deal with agents lack of full and accurate information, and so is an extremely valuable new contribution to this literature. To understand Zimmerman s argument we need a bit more detail about how he understands the Prospective View. In his interpretation, the expectable value of an act for an agent is determined in part by the agent s epistemic probabilities for the various possible outcomes of the act. For an agent, the epistemic probability of an outcome is 2

the degree of belief that the agent would be warranted (or justified) in having concerning the occurrence of that outcome by the body of evidence that is available to her. 5 Zimmerman is broad-minded about the nature of the values of the outcomes; he intends his discussion to be relevant to what is morally obligatory across a wide range of substantive moral theories, including purely consequentialist ones, but also including purely or partly deontological theories. 6 However, he recognizes that agents often must choose an action when they are uncertain, not only about the possible outcomes of the action, but also about the possible values of those outcomes. Perhaps one option will result in the death of non-human animals, while another will result in the death of a human being. The agent may be morally uncertain about the relative values of these outcomes. Nonetheless she may be able to assign epistemic probabilities to these various possible values. Thus the fourth formulation of the Prospective View is phrased in terms of expectable value, which takes into account both the probabilities that various outcomes will occur and the probabilities about what the values of those outcomes might be. 7 Zimmerman s core argument for the Prospective View proceeds as follows. He describes a case whose unusual structure was originally introduced by Donald Regan and subsequently re-introduced by Frank Jackson. 8 Zimmerman s version of the case is as follows: Jill s case: Jill, a physician, has a patient, John, who is suffering from a minor but not trivial skin complaint. In order to treat him, she has three drugs from which to choose: A, B, and C. All the evidence at Jill s disposal indicates (in keeping with the facts) that giving John Drug B would cure him partially and giving no drug would render him permanently incurable. But her evidence indicates there is a 50% probability that Drug A would cure him completely and a similar probability that it would kill him. Her evidence indicates the same thing about Drug C. In actual fact, Drug A would cure him while Drug C would kill him. 9 3

The Objective View implies that Jill morally ought to give John Drug A, since it would completely cure him. Zimmerman argues that accepting this judgment is a mistake: as a conscientious person Jill would give John Drug B, since given her evidence it would be far too risky for Jill to give him either Drug A or Drug C, whereas giving him no drug at all would certainly leave him worse off than if she gave him Drug B. 10 Since conscientiousness precludes deliberately doing what one believes to be morally wrong, and Jill s choice of Drug B is the choice of a conscientious person despite the fact that she believes Drug B is guaranteed to be wrong according to the Objective View, it cannot be the case that giving Drug B is morally wrong. Zimmerman s conclusion is that we must reject the Objective View (which assesses Drug B as wrong) in favor of an account according to which Jill s giving Drug B is not morally wrong, but rather what she ought to do. The Prospective View provides just such an account, since (given reasonable values for the possible outcomes as shown in Figure 1) giving Drug A has the highest expectable value for Jill. Zimmerman concludes that the Prospective View is the correct account of the primary sense of moral obligation. 11 ACT POSSIBLE OUTCOME PROBABI- LITY EXPECTABLE ACTUAL A Complete cure 50 0.5 Death -100 0.5-25 50 B Partial cure 40 1 40 40 C D Complete cure 50 0.5-25 -100 Death -100 0.5 Permanent 0 1 0 0 illness Figure 1 12 4

Of course, one alternative view of this situation is that Jill would do what is objectively obligatory by giving John Drug A, but given that she does not know A will cure him rather than kill him, she would do what is subjectively obligatory best in light of the non-normative properties she believes the acts to have by giving him Drug B. Zimmerman rejects this type of dual oughts answer because it delivers an equivocal answer to Jill s question of what she ought to do. She wants to know, in the unique sense of ought with which she as a conscientious person is concerned, what she ought to do. No guidance has been offered to her unless such a unique sense has been singled out. 13 Unlike the Dual Oughts View, the Prospective View offers her univocal advice on what to do give John Drug B and this act is precisely what we would all think is most reasonable for a person in Jill s position to choose. What drives Zimmerman s intuitions in Jill s case is the unusual feature that the wisest action is one that the agent can see in advance is guaranteed not to be best. Zimmerman says that a conscientious agent would never do what she believes to be wrong. Since Jill ought to give John Drug B, it follows that it cannot be wrong for her to give him B, despite the fact that she believes B is guaranteed to be less good than some other option. Zimmerman s solution is to introduce a new account of wrong the Prospective View -- according to which giving John Drug B is not wrong. There are various ways to challenge Zimmerman s core argument for the Prospective View. First, the dictum that the conscientious agent would never deliberately do what she believes to be overall morally wrong sounds persuasive, but is itself ambiguous. For example, it could mean the conscientious agent would never deliberately do what she believes to be overall objectively wrong, or it could mean the 5

conscientious agent would never deliberately do what she believes to be overall subjectively wrong. On both readings the dictum is intuitively plausible. However, we could take Jill s case to show that, surprisingly, the dictum on the first reading is false. If we reject the dictum because of Jill s case, Zimmerman s argument evaporates. But even if we want to retain the dictum, this is possible under the second reading. And the second reading is consistent with the Dual Oughts View which contemplates a system in which there are both objective and subjective oughts, the latter being the unique prescriptions that the agent ought to use in decision-making when she has no information indicating which act would be objectively right (even though she knows which act would be objectively wrong). This reading of the dictum would not support Zimmerman s Prospective View as the correct account of overall moral obligation. 14 A second problem with Zimmerman s account is that it flies in the face of a certain kind of continuity that arises in these cases. Zimmerman wants to say that a conscientious person would never deliberately do what she believes to be overall wrong. But he does not say in fact he denies that a conscientious person would never risk doing what she believes might be overall wrong. 15 For example, Jill s evidence could indicate that giving John Drug B is prospectively best in terms of what is actually valuable. It follows from the Prospective View that Jill ought to give John Drug B. But Jill s meta-ethical evidence could favor the truth of Objective View rather than the Prospective View. Thus, in giving him Drug B, she believes she runs a high risk of not fulfilling her obligation. 16 Suppose Jill s evidence indicates that there is a 0.998 chance that the Objective View is correct. Still, she ought to give John Drug B, even though she runs a 0.998 chance that in doing so she is doing what is overall wrong. Suppose her 6

evidence in favor of the Objective View is even stronger it supports a 0.9998 chance that in prescribing Drug B she is doing what is overall wrong. Still, she ought to prescribe Drug B. Suppose her evidence in favor of the Objective View is stronger yet it supports a 0.99998 chance that in prescribing Drug B she is doing what is overall wrong. Still, she ought to prescribe Drug B. One could go on like this indefinitely. What possible rationale could be offered for saying that a conscientious agent cannot have an obligation to perform an action which the agent justifiably believes to be morally wrong, but a conscientious agent can have an obligation to perform an action when the agent justifiably thinks there is (merely!) a 0.99998 chance that it is morally wrong? Zimmerman s entire argument depends on drawing a line between these two cases, but it is difficult to see what theoretical reason could justify insisting on such a distinction. 17 And if we can t justify such a distinction, there seems no reason to accept the dictum that forms the lynchpin for Zimmerman s argument. Instead we could accept the Dual Oughts View, which implies that Jill ought subjectively to prescribe Drug B, even though her evidence makes it certain that doing so will be objectively wrong. Indeed, once we ve realized there are cases with this structure, this is exactly what we are inclined to think about them. The third and worst problem is that it is possible to show that Zimmerman s Prospective View is subject to the very same issue that he invokes to reject the Objective View and show the Prospective View is correct. Consider this. The abstract structure of the Jill s case is as follows. Moral Standard I (the Objective View) requires a great deal of information to apply, while Moral Standard II (the Prospective View), which is responsive to the same values as Moral Standard I, requires less information to apply. 7

The agent is in circumstances in which she does not have enough information to identify which act is obligatory according to Moral Standard I, but she does have enough information to identify which act is obligatory according to Moral Standard II. She also has enough information to ascertain that the obligatory act according to Moral Standard II is wrong according to Moral Standard I. Nonetheless, we agree that she ought (in some sense) to do what Moral Standard II recommends. If we accept Zimmerman s dictum that a conscientious agent would never perform an act she believes to be wrong, we must reject Moral Standard I. We can replicate this structure with the Prospective View serving as Moral Standard I. Zimmerman himself recognizes that it requires a fair amount of information to apply the Prospective View, and that sometimes the agent cannot discover what it requires. 18 Thus there will be occasions when agents are unable to discover what the Prospective View requires, and will need guidance from still another standard that is responsive to the same values but that requires less information. One often recommended example of such a standard is what is sometimes called the Minimax View, according to which an agent ought to perform an act if and only if the option minimizes the maximum possible loss of value. Following Zimmerman, we can stipulate that this view, like the Prospective View, depends on what the agent would be epistemically justified in believing about the possible outcomes of her options. Now consider the following case. Harry s case: Harry, a physician, has a patient, Renee, with a moderately serious neurologically-based tremor. Harry has three choices: he can prescribe Treatment E (doing nothing), F, or G. Harry knows the possible outcomes of these various courses of treatment. Some of these outcomes concern the cure for Renee s tremor, while others concern loss of the use of a limb. If Harry prescribes no 8

treatment, Renee s tremor might spontaneously disappear, or continue as is, or she might suffer the loss of the use of her right foot. Harry has no way to estimate the probabilities of the various possible outcomes of the treatments, or what their possible interactions with the possible cure are. However, his senior colleague has reliably informed Harry that Treatment E would not maximize expectable value, and Harry believes this. Harry s choices can be represented by the following matrix. ACT POSSIBLE OUTCOME E F G PROB- ABILITY Cure 10? No cure -10? Lose use of right foot -20? Not lose use of right foot 0? Cure 10? No cure -10? Lose use of left hand -30? Not lose use of left hand 0? Cure 10? No cure -10? Lose use of right hand -40? Not lose use of right hand 0? MAXIMIZE EXPECTABLE? WORST POSSIBLE No -30? -40? -50 Figure 2 Because Harry has no evidence regarding the probabilities of the various possible outcomes, he has no evidence supporting any figure for the expectable value of any act, although he does have excellent evidence, namely his senior colleague s statement, that not treating Renee (Treatment E) would fail to maximize expectable value. 19 Thus we have a situation, quite parallel to Jill s case, in which the agent lacks sufficient information to apply Standard I (the Prospective View) but has enough information to apply related Standard II (the Minimax View). And it seems perfectly credible that a conscientious agent in this case ought to do what Standard II recommends Treatment E even though his evidence shows that Treatment E is wrong according to 9

Standard I. 20 Since, according to Zimmerman, a conscientious agent would avoid doing what he believes to be overall morally wrong, Zimmerman s logic entails that the Prospective View is not the correct account of what is overall morally wrong. Thus, by replicating Zimmerman s argument for rejecting the Objective View in favor of the Prospective View, we have found an equally compelling argument that the Prospective View should be rejected in favor of the Minimax View. On this logic, the Minimax View emerges as the unique correct account of obligation the kind of obligation that a conscientious agent ought to follow as his primary overall moral obligation. But this is clearly a wild conclusion. The Minimax View may well give the agent the best advice about what it is wise to do when his information is too highly impoverished for application of the Prospective View, but we should not conclude that it is the primary and unique account of obligation. 21 This is especially true since one can imagine replicating this argument yet again for some fourth account of obligation that is responsive to the same values but requires even less information than the Minimax View. This shows that Zimmerman s Prospective View can be hoist on its own petard the chief positive argument favoring its adoption can be redeployed to show that it should not be adopted after all. Having seen three progressively more serious problems with Zimmerman s core argument in favor of the Prospective View, we can fairly conclude that this argument fails to establish the Prospective View as the primary and unique account of obligation. Holly M. Smith Rutgers University 10

1 Michael Zimmerman, Living with Uncertainty (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2008). 2 Ibid., pp. 2, 35. 3 Ibid., pp. 2, 5, 39. Zimmerman himself labels what I have called the Putatively-Right View the Subjective View. His label runs counter to what I regard as more common usage, which reserves the term subjectively right to refer to the action that is best in light of the agent s beliefs about its non-normative properties. This alternate terminology would suggest Putatively-Right View for Zimmerman s second view, which prescribes the act that the agent believes to be the best option. That is, it prescribes this action in light of the agent s beliefs about its normative properties. (Zimmerman is hardly alone in this usage, however. See, for example, Judith Jarvis Thomson, The Realm of Rights (Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press, 1990), pp. 172-173.) It is puzzling that Zimmerman does not explicitly recognize and discuss subjective rightness as I am interpreting it. In any event, since I want to make use of the more standard notion of subjective rightness, I have re-labeled Zimmerman s second view to avoid confusion. 4 For examples, see Jonathan Bennett, The Act Itself (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1995), Chapter 3; Richard Brandt, Ethical Theory (Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall, Inc., 1959), p. 365; Allan Gibbard, Wise Choices, Apt Feelings (Cambridge, Massachusetts; Harvard University Press, 1990), p. 42; Shelly Kagan, The Limits of Morality (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1989), p. 1; Graham Oddie and Peter Menzies, An Objectivist s Guide to Subjective Value, Ethics 102 (April 1992): 512 533; T.M. Scanlon, Moral Dimensions (Cambridge, Massachusetts; Harvard University Press, 2008), p. 47; and Michael Hooker, Ideal Code, Real World (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2000), Section 3.1, in which he advocates a Prospective View version of rule utilitarianism. Note that these theorists have adopted various interpretations of the Prospective View that do not in every case mirror the particular version Zimmerman advocates. 5 Zimmerman, pp. 19, 34, 35. 6 Ibid., pp. 3-5. 7 Ibid., pp. 38-39. 8 Donald Regan, Utilitarianism and Co-operation (Oxford; Clarendon Press, 1980), and Frank Jackson, Decision-theoretic Consequentialism and the Nearest and Dearest Objection, Ethics 101: 461 82. 9 Zimmerman, pp. 17-18. 10 Ibid., pp. 18-19. 11 At this point in the text Zimmerman merely says this argument tend[s] to confirm the Prospective View (p. 20). His overall argument in its favor includes arguments showing the other Views are incorrect, as well as additional arguments showing that the Prospective View can handle well or at least acceptably a variety of other cases and issues. However, it is clear that he regards Jill s case as the lynchpin of his argument against the objective view and in favor of the Prospective View (p. 57). 12 The value and probability figures are from Zimmerman, ibid., pp. 19-20. As he points out, the recommendation to give John Drug B is consistent with a wide range of plausible (or even fuzzy) values and probabilities for the possible outcomes (p. 34). 13 Zimmerman, ibid., pp. 6 7; 27. 14 Zimmerman rejects the tenability of any view that accommodates more than one ought. On the one hand, he finds that it strains credulity to recognize a distinct sense of ought for every plausible proposed account of moral obligation, such as the three he describes. But more importantly, he claims that an agent such as Jill needs a univocal answer to her question What ought I to do? If some advisor gives her an answer that recognizes two oughts (such as You ought objectively to prescribe Drug A, but you ought subjectively to prescribe Drug B ) you have not provided her with any help, since she wants to know the unique ought that she should follow, since she can follow only one (ibid., pp. 6 7). But this dismisses the Dual Oughts View that I have described too rapidly. According to it, from Jill s point of view as a decision-maker, the Subjective Ought is the only one she should follow in making her decision. If her beliefs entail that a certain act is objectively obligatory, then the Subjective View should stipulate that that act is subjectively obligatory. There can be no known conflict, from Jill s point of view, between what she subjectively ought to do and what she objectively ought to do, even though she recognizes that an omniscient observer might see that what she subjectively ought to do would be different from what she 11

objectively ought to do. Of course Regan style cases show that there can be circumstances in which an agent s beliefs indicate an action is objectively wrong but subjectively right. Working out the details of such a Dual Oughts View is the labor for another occasion. 15 Ibid., p. 59. 16 Ibid., p. 59. 17 This is especially pressing, given that Zimmerman himself concedes that lottery paradox problems provide difficulties for attempts to define knowledge in terms of justificational probabilities (pp. 36-37). 18 Zimmerman, ibid., pp. 70, 71, 173. In correspondence Zimmerman states that he remains unsure whether or not it could be impossible for an agent to discover what is prospectively best. Given his definition of prospectively best, it seems transparent to me that some agents will not have the time, information, or cognitive skills necessary to ascertain what is prospectively best for them on a given occasion. 19 To make these assignments intuitive, one can think of the senior colleague as having evidence that (in the case of Treatments E and F only) that the probabilities for Treatments E and F are as follows: ACT E F POSSIBLE OUTCOME PROB- ABILITY Cure 10 0.2 No cure -10 0.8 Lose use of right foot -20 0.9 Not lose use of R foot 0 0.1 Cure 10 0.9 No cure -10 0.1 Lose use of left hand -30.01 Not lose use of L hand 0 0.9 EXPECTABLE MAXIMIZE EXPECTABLE? WORST POSSIBLE -24 No -30 5? -40 Figure 3 Thus the expectable value of Treatment E is - 24, while the expectable value of Treatment G is 5. Treatment E fails to maximize expectable value. For some reason Harry s senior colleague does not convey these probability estimates to Harry, and Harry is unable to obtain them from the colleague or by himself. It might be claimed that Harry should use the principle of insufficient reason, and assign equal probabilities to each of the possible outcomes of each treatment. However, there are grave problems with the principle of insufficient reason, a principal one being that it is indeterminate what the correct partition of possible outcomes should be (Are there only two potential outcomes regarding the cure, and two potential outcomes for the new disability? Might there be a partial cure? Might there be a partial loss of the use of the limb? If so, how finely does one partition the partial cures and partial losses?) And even if the principle of insufficient reason is correct, not every agent has time to calculate expectable values by using it. 20 Zimmerman denies that there is any correct answer to the person who asks What ought I to do when I don t know what is prospectively best? except the simple answer You ought to do whatever is prospectively best, whether you know what that is or not. He defends this admittedly unhelpful answer by saying that the reason for rejecting the Objective View in favor of the Prospective View is not to find a helpful response to the question What ought I to do when I don t know what is actually best? Rather, the move was dictated by the recognition that [Jill s original case] shows quite clearly that it is not in general the case that one ought, in the sense that expresses overall moral obligation, to do what is actually best (Zimmerman, p. 71). But this mis-states the case. The only reason to invoke the Prospective View in Jill s case is to deal with the fact that she does not have enough evidence to determine what she ought to do according to the Objective View. The Prospective View only becomes plausible precisely because it can be 12

used for decision guidance in cases where the agent cannot use the Objective View. If Jill or agents in general -- were omniscient, we would have no reason to invoke the Prospective View. It is worth pointing out, however, that there is happy coincidence between the Objective View and the Prospective View that partially obscures this point. When an agent has sufficient information to apply both the Prospective View and the Objective View to evaluate all her options, the two views will agree both on what act is obligatory and what acts are wrong. It is only when the agent s information is not sufficient to identify the right act according to the Objective View (even though it may be sufficient to identify an action as wrong) that she needs to turn to the Prospective View. No such happy coincidence obtains between the Prospective View and the Minimax View when the agent has sufficient information to apply both, since the Minimax View does not utilize the information about probabilities needed by the Prospective View. 21 Of course some theorists might advocate that some alternative account, such as the Satisficing View, or the Minimax Regret View, as better than the Minimax View for these circumstances. This is immaterial to the argument in the text. 13