AGENT CAUSATION AND RESPONSIBILITY: A REPLY TO FLINT

Similar documents
Truth and Molinism * Trenton Merricks. Molinism: The Contemporary Debate edited by Ken Perszyk. Oxford University Press, 2011.

SUPER MARIO STRIKES BACK: ANOTHER MOLINIST REPLY TO WELTY S GUNSLINGERS ARGUMENT

Philosophy of Religion 21: (1987).,, 9 Nijhoff Publishers, Dordrecht - Printed in the Nethenanas

What God Could Have Made

AN ACTUAL-SEQUENCE THEORY OF PROMOTION

IS GOD "SIGNIFICANTLY FREE?''

David E. Alexander and Daniel Johnson, eds. Calvinism and the Problem of Evil.

Is Truth the Primary Epistemic Goal? Joseph Barnes

DENNETT ON THE BASIC ARGUMENT JOHN MARTIN FISCHER

Note: This is the penultimate draft of an article the final and definitive version of which is

Timothy O'Connor, Persons & Causes: The Metaphysics of Free Will. Oxford & New York: Oxford University Press, Pp. Xv and 135. $35.

Is Klein an infinitist about doxastic justification?

REASONS-RESPONSIVENESS AND TIME TRAVEL

Reflection on what was said about coercion above might suggest an alternative to PAP:

Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible?

Replies to Hasker and Zimmerman. Trenton Merricks. Molinism: The Contemporary Debate edited by Ken Perszyk. Oxford University Press, I.

Sosa on Safety and Epistemic Frankfurt Cases

A Posteriori Necessities by Saul Kripke (excerpted from Naming and Necessity, 1980)

THE CAMBRIDGE SOLUTION TO THE TIME OF A KILLING LAWRENCE B. LOMBARD

Philosophical Perspectives, 14, Action and Freedom, 2000 TRANSFER PRINCIPLES AND MORAL RESPONSIBILITY. Eleonore Stump Saint Louis University

Mind Association. Oxford University Press and Mind Association are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Mind.

THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE

12. A Theistic Argument against Platonism (and in Support of Truthmakers and Divine Simplicity)

To appear in J. Greco, ed., Philosophers and their Critics: Ernest Sosa, Oxford: Blackwell. Sosa on Abilities, Concepts and Externalism

Act individuation and basic acts

New Aristotelianism, Routledge, 2012), in which he expanded upon

COPLESTON: Quite so, but I regard the metaphysical argument as probative, but there we differ.

Divine omniscience, timelessness, and the power to do otherwise

Philosophical Issues, vol. 8 (1997), pp

In essence, Swinburne's argument is as follows:

DOES STRONG COMPATIBILISM SURVIVE FRANKFURT COUNTER-EXAMPLES?

INTRODUCTION. This week: Moore's response, Nozick's response, Reliablism's response, Externalism v. Internalism.

Time travel and the open future

Skepticism and Internalism

Cognitive Significance, Attitude Ascriptions, and Ways of Believing Propositions. David Braun. University of Rochester

THE PROBLEM WITH SOCIAL TRINITARIANISM: A REPLY TO WIERENGA

Skim the Article to Find its Conclusion and Get a Sense of its Structure

Small Stakes Give You the Blues: The Skeptical Costs of Pragmatic Encroachment

Freedom, Responsibility, and Frankfurt-style Cases

Lawrence Brian Lombard a a Wayne State University. To link to this article:

An Alternate Possibility for the Compatibility of Divine. Foreknowledge and Free Will. Alex Cavender. Ringstad Paper Junior/Senior Division

Causation and Freedom * over whether the mysterious relation of agent- causation is possible, the literature

The Mind Argument and Libertarianism

Scanlon on Double Effect

Kane is Not Able: A Reply to Vicens Self-Forming Actions and Conflicts of Intention

Could have done otherwise, action sentences and anaphora

Shieva Kleinschmidt [This is a draft I completed while at Rutgers. Please do not cite without permission.] Conditional Desires.

Foreknowledge and Freedom

WHY PLANTINGA FAILS TO RECONCILE DIVINE FOREKNOWLEDGE

Free Will Theodicies for Theological Determinists

Warrant and accidentally true belief

Free Acts and Chance: Why the Rollback Argument Fails Lara Buchak, UC Berkeley

AQUINAS S METAPHYSICS OF MODALITY: A REPLY TO LEFTOW

Resemblance Nominalism and counterparts

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Molinism and divine prophecy of free actions

BOOK REVIEW: Gideon Yaffee, Manifest Activity: Thomas Reid s Theory of Action

Wright on response-dependence and self-knowledge

THE SENSE OF FREEDOM 1. Dana K. Nelkin. I. Introduction. abandon even in the face of powerful arguments that this sense is illusory.

ALTERNATIVE POSSIBILITIES AND THE FREE WILL DEFENCE

Lost in Transmission: Testimonial Justification and Practical Reason

IN DEFENCE OF CLOSURE

A New Argument Against Compatibilism

CONCEPT OF WILLING IN WITTGENSTEIN S PHILOSOPHICAL INVESTIGATIONS

Counterfactuals and Causation: Transitivity

Philosophical Arguments

Leeway vs. Sourcehood Conceptions of Free Will (for the Routledge Companion to Free Will)

Chapter Six Compatibilism: Mele, Alfred E. (2006). Free Will and Luck. Oxford University Press: Oxford.

Kantian Humility and Ontological Categories Sam Cowling University of Massachusetts, Amherst

Journal of Cognition and Neuroethics

Agency Implies Weakness of Will

Chapter 5: Freedom and Determinism

Empty Names and Two-Valued Positive Free Logic

Prompt: Explain van Inwagen s consequence argument. Describe what you think is the best response

The Logical Problem of Evil and the Limited God Defense

Logic & Proofs. Chapter 3 Content. Sentential Logic Semantics. Contents: Studying this chapter will enable you to:

Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods

Pojman, Louis P. Introduction to Philosophy: Classical and Contemporary Readings. 3rd Ed. New York: Oxford University Press, 2004.

I will briefly summarize each of the 11 chapters and then offer a few critical comments.

CRITICAL STUDY FISCHER ON MORAL RESPONSIBILITY

Chapter 5: Freedom and Determinism

Compatibilism, Evil, and the Free-Will Defense

Am I free? Free will vs. determinism

Lana said the theme of the conference is really about understanding each other. When we write something, we take trouble to try to write it

A Rational Solution to the Problem of Moral Error Theory? Benjamin Scott Harrison

LESSON # 2. Do you think Eve should have listened to the snake, or listened to God?

What Is the Thingy Illusion and How Does It Mess Up Philosophy?

Is There Hope for Compatibilism?

Why Counterpart Theory and Four-Dimensionalism are Incompatible. Suppose that God creates ex nihilo a bronze statue of a

Harry Frankfurt Freedom of the Will and the Concept of a Person

From Necessary Truth to Necessary Existence

Promises, Social Acts, and Reid s First Argument for Moral Liberty

QUESTION TAGS

inertia Moral Philos Stud (2008) 140: DOI /s x Sartorio Carolina

>> THE NEXT CASE IS STATE OF FLORIDA VERSUS FLOYD. >> TAKE YOUR TIME. TAKE YOUR TIME. >> THANK YOU, YOUR HONOR. >> WHENEVER YOU'RE READY.

24.00: Problems of Philosophy Prof. Sally Haslanger November 16, 2005 Moral Relativism

PARFIT'S MISTAKEN METAETHICS Michael Smith

POWERS, NECESSITY, AND DETERMINISM

Fr. Copleston vs. Bertrand Russell: The Famous 1948 BBC Radio Debate on the Existence of God

Moral Twin Earth: The Intuitive Argument. Terence Horgan and Mark Timmons have recently published a series of articles where they

Transcription:

AGENT CAUSATION AND RESPONSIBILITY: A REPLY TO FLINT Michael Bergmann In an earlier paper I argued that if we help ourselves to Molinism, we can give a counterexample - one avoiding the usual difficulties - to the Principle of Alternate Possibilities: PAP. A person is morally responsible for performing a given act only if she could have acted otherwise. Thomas Flint has proposed three objections to my counterexample. In this paper I respond to each. In my "Molinist Frankfurt-Style Counterexamples and the Free Will Defense,"l I argued that if we help ourselves to Molinism, we can give a counterexample - one avoiding the usual difficulties - to the Principle of Alternate Possibilities: PAP. A person is morally responsible for performing a given act only if she could have acted otherwise. In his "On Behalf of the P AP-ists: A Reply to Bergmann,"2 Thomas Flint proposes three objections to my counterexample. In what follows, I respond to each. 1. Two Preliminary Matters Before considering Flint's three objections, it will be helpful if I begin by (i) explaining the way in which I use the term 'agent cause' (since it features so prominently in my counterexample and in my discussion of Flint's three objections) and (ii) briefly describing the counterexample I proposed. I use the term I agent cause' as follows: AC. X is the agent cause of e iff each of the following three conditions is satisfied: 1. X is a substance that had the power to bring about e 2. X exerted its power to bring about e 3. nothing distinct from X (not even X's character) caused X to exert its power to bring about e. FAITH AND PHILOSOPHY Vol. 20 No.2 April 2003 All rights reserved 229

230 Faith and Philosophy This is a slight modification of the typical Reidian understanding of agent causation, which, according to William Rowe, is just like the above except that it replaces 3 with: 3*. X had the power to refrain from bringing about e. 3 Rowe argues that 3* entails 3. 4 That seems plausible. And if it's true, then agent causation, as I understand it, seems to be weaker than the Reidian notion of agent causation insofar as my sort of agent causation seems to be entailed by the Reidian sort without entailing it. With this understanding of agent causation in mind, let's consider my proposed counterexample. There is an agent, Jones, of whom the following subjunctive conditional of agent causation is true: A. If from t* up until t Jones were in circumstances K and Demon didn't take away Jones's powers at t with respect to VI [a volition to pull the trigger of the gun in Jones's hand], then Jones would agentcause VI at t. There is also a powerful being, Demon, with knowledge of subjunctive conditionals of agent causation such as A (here's where the Molinist component comes in). In addition to having such knowledge, Demon also knows that Jones will be in circumstances K from t* up until t. Since Demon knows all this and wants Jones to agent-cause VI at t (Le., to pull the trigger, which will result in Smith's death), Demon is happy /lot to take away Jones's powers at t with respect to VI. However, the following counterfactual is true of Demon: C. If A were false, Demon would know it (long before t) and would take away Jones's powers at t with respect to VI. In fact, if A were false, not only would Demon take away Jones' powers at t with respect to VI, Demon would himself cause Jones to cause VI, thereby ensuring Smith's death. Finally, the antecedent of A is true (which, given the truth of A, implies that the consequent of A is true as well). I argued that in this example, Jones couldn't do otherwise than agent-cause VI even though Jones is responsible for Vl,5 II. Flint's First Objection Flint's first objection focuses on my claim that Jones is responsible for VI. To see exactly what his objection is targeting, it will be helpful to summarize the two points I made in defense of that claim. First, I noted that Jones would clearly be responsible for VI if he agent-caused VI when Demon wasn't present. This is because, if Jones agent-causes VI, the causal buck for VI stops with Jones. Second, I claimed that changing the case to include Demon (in the way described in my counterexample) won't change anything relevant since, in the Demon case, Jones does exactly what he does in the Demon-less case and "he does so with absolutely no

AGENT RESPONSIBILITY AND CAUSALITY 231 interference or influence from Demon".6 It is this second point that Flint's objection targets. For, says Flint, the fact that Jones's powers to do otherwise than agent-cause VI are removed when we add Demon to the situation "makes nonsense of the claim that there has been no interference or influence".7 Perhaps I didn't state that second point as carefully as I should have. I didn't intend to say that there was no way in which the addition of Demon to the situation affects Jones. Clearly it does. My point was just that the addition of Demon to the situation results in no interference with or influence on Jones's agent-causing of Vl.8 In both the Demon case and the Demon-less case, the causal buck for VI stops with Jones. That is sufficient for saying that Jones is responsible for VI. III. Flint's Second Objection Flint's second objection is that my counterexample forces us to credit Demon with causing Jones to agent-cause VI and that this is incoherent: Demon has set up a situation in which there's only one thing Jones can cause, and where he can't refrain from exercising his power to cause it. This surely seems like a situation in which Demon has caused Jones to exercise his power to agent-cause VI. And this even Bergmann would allow cannot be; his third condition of agent causation... implies that nothing distinct from Jones could cause Jones to agentcause anything. So Bergmann's counterexample may be incoherent even on his own account of agent causation. 9 This objection relies quite heavily on the point that, in my counterexample, Jones "can't refrain from exercising his power to cause [VI]". But does my counterexample really entail that Jones can't refrain from exercising his power to cause VI? In the first half of his paper, Flint develops an argument for the conclusion that my counterexample does, in fact, have that consequence. Let's take some time to consider whether that argument succeeds. According to Flint, there is a power I don't discuss in giving my counterexample, namely, the power to non intentionally refrain from agent-causing VI, where this is distinct from the power to intentionally refrain from agent-causing Vl. lo (To intentionally refrain from agent-causing VI involves agent-causing the relevant intention, something not involved in nonintentionally refraining from agent-causing VI.) Flint thinks that my counterexample entails that Jones lacks this power to nonintentionally refrain from agent-causing VI. For suppose that Jones had this power and exercised it. That is, suppose that: R. Jones refrains from agent-causing VI at t. Flint argues that R~_Cl1 (where C is the counterfactual, mentioned earlier, that is true of Demon in my counterexample). But that shows that if Jones has the power to nonintentionally refrain from agent-causing VI, then "Jones has a power the exercise of which counterfactually implies the falsity of C".'2 And that conflicts with something I say about my counterexam-

232 Faith and Philosophy pie, namely, that C would be true of Demon no matter which of his powers Jones exercisedy From this Flint concludes that my counterexample entails that Demon takes away Jones's power to nonintentionally refrain from agent-causing VI. That's why Flint says that, in my counterexample, Jones can't refrain from exercising his power to cause Vl. The reason I didn't mention this power to nonintentionally refrain from agent-causing VI is that it isn't an active power that Jones can exercise. '4 Instead, it is the potential for something to happen to Jones. Some might call it a passive power - something that can be activated (by something distinct from Jones); but it isn't something that can be exercised by Jones. In fact, I don't even want to say it is a passive power to nonintentionally refrain from agent-causing VI. The term 'refrain' has connotations of being intentional. I prefer to think of it as Jones's potential to nonintentionally fail to agent-cause VI. Now suppose that I grant (as I do) that Jones has this potential to nonintentionally fail to agent-cause VI. Can Flint's argument (that R ---...-C) be used to show that I'm in trouble? No. For now our question isn't "What would happen if Jones were to exercise his power to nonintentionally refrain from agent-causing VI?" Instead, the question is "What would happen if Jones's potential to nonintentionally fail to agent-cause VI were activated?" In other words, the question is "What would happen if R*: Jones nonintentionally fails to agent-cause VI at t were true?" Thus, in order to show that I'm in trouble when I allow that Jones has the potential to nonintentionally fail to agent-cause VI, Flint must argue that R* ---...-C But once we replace R in Flint's argument with R*, we can see where it goes wrong. As Flint makes clear when he lays out the argument, it depends for its success on the validity of the following line of reasoning: Jones could exercise his power to refrain only if Demon has not taken away that power. And if Demon didn't take away that power, then obviously he didn't take away all of Jones's powers. So (ii) R ---... GI [where GI is the claim that Demon didn't take away all ofjones's powers at t with respect to VI].15 Thus, unless R ---... GI, Flint's argument fails to show that R ---... -C And since our focus is R* rather than R, we may conclude that, unless R* ---... Gl, Flint's argument can't be used to show that R* ---... -C And the fact is that R* does not counterfactually imply GI. To see why, consider once again the following counterfactual which is true of Demon in my counterexample: C If A were false, Demon would know it (long before t) and would take away Jones's powers at t with respect to VI. When I said (in stating the consequent of C) that Demon would take away (all of) Jones's powers at t with respect to VI, I was speaking of all of the

AGENT RESPONSIBILITY AND CAUSALITY 233 active powers with respect to VI that Jones can exercise. I was not speaking of the potentialities Jones has with respect to VI - the things that can happen to him with respect to VI. This was made evident in my description of the example when I said that Demon would take away all of Jones's powers at t with respect to VI and that Demon himself would cause Jones to cause VI at t. 16 For since, in that counterfactual scenario, Demon caused Jones to cause VI at t, it is obvious that Jones still had the potential to be caused to cause VI despite the fact that all his powers with respect to VI had been taken away. So clearly I wasn't suggesting that Demon was taking away all of Jones's potentialities with respect to VI; it was active powers with respect to VI that I had in mind. Once we see this, it is easy to see that R* doesn't counterfactually imply GI (where GI is understood to be speaking of active powers). For the fact that Jones has the potential to nonintentionally fail to agent-cause VI doesn't counterfactually imply that Jones is left with some active powers with respect to VI that he can exercise. Once we see that R* doesn't counterfactually imply GI, we can (as I noted earlier) conclude that Flint's argument can't be used to show that R* --- -CO And from that we may conclude that it can't be used to show that my counterexample is inconsistent with the claim that Jones has the potential to nonintentionally fail to agent-cause VI. Now all of this is, of course, directly relevant to Flint's second objection. For as we noted earlier, this objection relied on Flint's claim that, in my counterexample, Jones can't refrain from exercising his power to cause VI. If refraining from exercising the power to cause VI can include such things as nonintentionally failing to agent-cause VI, then Flint has failed to establish that claim. If, on the other hand, it can't include such things, then we can note that even if Jones can't refrain from exercising his power to cause VI, he can nonintentionally fail to agent-cause VI. Either way the objection fails. For Flint wanted to suggest that, in my counterexample, Jones was forced to agent-cause VI. He created this impression by arguing that, according to my counterexample, Jones couldn't even nonintentionally fail to agent-cause VI. But as we have seen, his argument does not establish that conclusion. 17 IV. Flint's Third Objection Let's look briefly at the third and last of Flint's three objections. According to this objection, my counterexample is incoherent if one understands agent causation in the way Thomas Reid and most agency theorists understand it (vyhere clause 3 from my definition of agent causation is replaced with 3*), rather than in the way I understand it. 1S The problem, says Flint, is that my example entails that Jones agent-causes VI even though he lacks the power to refrain from causing VI. And yet, if we insist upon clause 3* instead of merely clause 3, then agent-causing VI requires the power to refrain from causing VI. So, says Flint, on the Reidian account of agentcausation, my example is incoherent. I have two responses. First, it is difficult to see why this observation (even if correct) would cause any problem for me. When I described my counterexample, I made it clear that I was thinking of agent causation as

234 Faith and Philosophy entailing the satisfaction of clause 3, not clause 3*. Why is it a problem for me that my counterexample would be incoherent if understood in a way that I explicitly said it was not to be understood? Perhaps the suggestion is that I shouldn't be using the term' agent causation' in a non-reidian way. I disagree. I think that the account of agent causation I gave does a better job than Reid's account of capturing what at least some philosophers have in mind when thinking about agent causation. Second, I'm not sure that my counterexample would be incoherent even if agent causation were understood in the Reidian way. It all depends on how we are to understand: 3*. X had the power to refrain from bringing about e. Must X's power to refrain be thought of as an active power that X can exercise? If so, then my example would be incoherent given a Reidian account of agent causation. Or can the power to refrain from bringing about e be merely a passive power to have something happen to one? Can it, for example, be merely the potential to nonintentionally fail to agent-cause e? If so, then, in light of the remarks I made in response to Flint's second objection, I don't see why my example would be incoherent even given a Reidian account of agent causation.'9 Purdue University NOTES 1. Faith and Philosophy 19 (2002), 462-78. 2. Ibid., pp. 479-84. 3. See William Rowe, "The Metaphysics of Freedom: Reid's Theory of Agent Causation," American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly LXXIV (2000),427. 4. This is what his response to objection II on p. 430 of "The Metaphysics of Freedom" amounts to. 5. See section 2.2 of "Molinist Frankfurt-Style Counterexamples" where I layout this example in a little more detail. 6. "Molinist Frankfurt-Style Counterexamples,"p. 468. 7. "On Behalf of the P AP-ists," p. 482. 8. That's what I meant when I said "he does so with absolutely no interference or influence from Demon". 9. "On Behalf of the P AP-ists," p. 482 (emphasis is mine). 10. "On Behalf of the PAP-ists," p. 481. 11. I follow Flint in using the single-line arrow (~) to represent counterfactual implication. 12. "On Behalf of the P AP-ists," p. 482. 13. See premise 16 on p. 471 of my "Molinist Frankfurt-Style Counterexamples". 14. So I don't think it makes sense for Flint to ask, as he does, of this power "What would have happened if Jones were to exercise it?" (See his "On Behalf of the PAP-ists," p. 481.) 15. "On Behalf of the P AP-ists," p. 481. 16. In my original paper I said of Demon that "if he knows that Jones won't

AGENT RESPONSIBILITY AND CAUSALITY 235 agent-cause VI at t, he will intervene as follows: he will take away Jones's powers at t with respect to VI and will cause VI himself at t." (See "Molinist Frankfurt-Style Counterexamples," p. 467.) 17. It's worth noting here that weakly actualizing a state of affairs needn't involve causing it to obtain. Thus, even if one could show that the state of affairs Jones's agent-causing Vi were weakly actualized by Demon, that wouldn't be enough to show that Jones was forced to (or caused to) agent-cause VI. (To weakly actualize a state of affairs, S1, is to cause the actualization of a distinct state of affairs, S2, which is such that if it were actual, SI would be actual. For an explanation of why weakly actualizing a state of affairs needn't involve causing it to obtain, see Plantinga's Nature of Necessity (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1974), pp. 172-73.) 18. "On Behalf of the P AP-ists," pp. 482-83. 19. Thanks to Jeffrey Brower and William Rowe for comments on earlier drafts.