CONCEPT OF WILLING IN WITTGENSTEIN S PHILOSOPHICAL INVESTIGATIONS

Similar documents
Wittgenstein and Moore s Paradox

"Can We Have a Word in Private?": Wittgenstein on the Impossibility of Private Languages

Ludwig Wittgenstein: Philosophical Investigations

A Philosophical Critique of Cognitive Psychology s Definition of the Person

1/13. Locke on Power

Chapter 5: Freedom and Determinism

Wittgenstein says in Philosophical Investigations I33 that

The Metaphysical Status of Tractarian Objects 1

Death and Immortality (by D Z Phillips) Introductory Remarks

Hence, you and your choices are a product of God's creation Psychological State. Stephen E. Schmid

Overcoming Cartesian Intuitions: A Defense of Type-Physicalism

AGENT CAUSATION AND RESPONSIBILITY: A REPLY TO FLINT

Does Theism Imply Determinism? Questions about Hard Determinism. Objections to Hard Determinism, I. Objections to Hard Determinism, II

Wittgenstein on The Realm of Ineffable

Hume's Functionalism About Mental Kinds

It is advisable to refer to the publisher s version if you intend to cite from the work.

Wittgenstein on forms of life: a short introduction

LOCKE STUDIES Vol ISSN: X

The Kripkenstein Paradox and the Private World. In his paper, Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Languages, Kripke expands upon a conclusion

Wittgenstein and the Skeptical Paradoxes

Wittgenstein on the Fallacy of the Argument from Pretence. Abstract

TRUTH IN WITTGENSTEIN, TRUTH IN LINDBECK

1/10. Descartes Laws of Nature

RULES, RIGHTS, AND PROMISES.

THE ROAD TO HELL by Alastair Norcross 1. Introduction: The Doctrine of the Double Effect.

POWERS, NECESSITY, AND DETERMINISM

This is a longer version of the review that appeared in Philosophical Quarterly Vol. 47 (1997)

AUSTIN AND WITTGENSTEIN ON "DOUBT" AND "KNOWLEDGE" imarquette University

What's the Point of Seeing Aspects?

Wittgenstein on the Impossibility of Private Language

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

out in his Three Dialogues and Principles of Human Knowledge, gives an argument specifically

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Many Minds are No Worse than One

MARK KAPLAN AND LAWRENCE SKLAR. Received 2 February, 1976) Surely an aim of science is the discovery of the truth. Truth may not be the

Moral Obligation. by Charles G. Finney

Stout s teleological theory of action

Qualia Ain't in the Head Review of Ten Problems of Consciousness: A Representational Theory of the Phenomenal Mind by Michael Tye

1/7. The Postulates of Empirical Thought

What is Wittgenstein s View of Knowledge? : An Analysis of the Context Dependency

Reading the Nichomachean Ethics

Meaning is Use and Wittgenstein s Treatment of Philosophical Problems

What God Could Have Made

Issue 4, Special Conference Proceedings Published by the Durham University Undergraduate Philosophy Society

Why I Am Not a Property Dualist By John R. Searle

Anscombe on 'Practical Knowledge'

Why Computers are not Intelligent: An Argument. Richard Oxenberg

Philosophical Writings Vol. 43 No.1 HOW NOT TO NATURALISE ACTION

Note: This is the penultimate draft of an article the final and definitive version of which is

UNITY OF KNOWLEDGE (IN TRANSDISCIPLINARY RESEARCH FOR SUSTAINABILITY) Vol. I - Philosophical Holism M.Esfeld

How Many Kinds of Reasons? (Pre-print November 2008) Introduction

The purpose of this paper is to introduce the problem of skepticism as the

THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE

Does the Skeptic Win? A Defense of Moore. I. Moorean Methodology. In A Proof of the External World, Moore argues as follows:

Final Paper. May 13, 2015

At the Frontiers of Reality

This is a collection of fourteen previously unpublished papers on the fit

Logic and Pragmatics: linear logic for inferential practice

To link to this article:

Primary and Secondary Qualities. John Locke s distinction between primary and secondary qualities of bodies has

My First Half-Century in the Iron Game

Reasons With Rationalism After All MICHAEL SMITH

A guide to Anscombe s Intention, 1-31

How to Investigate the Grammar of Aspect- Perception: A Question in Wittgensteinian Method

In essence, Swinburne's argument is as follows:

Kane is Not Able: A Reply to Vicens Self-Forming Actions and Conflicts of Intention

Philosophy Faculty Reading List and Course Outline PART II PAPER 09: WITTGENSTEIN READING LIST

Love One Another, As I Have Loved You

Chapter 18 David Hume: Theory of Knowledge

Wright on response-dependence and self-knowledge

Speaking My Mind: Expression and Self-Knowledge by Dorit Bar-On

Examining the nature of mind. Michael Daniels. A review of Understanding Consciousness by Max Velmans (Routledge, 2000).

If God brought about the Big Bang, did he do that before the Big Bang?

Moral requirements are still not rational requirements

Negative Facts. Negative Facts Kyle Spoor

How Subjective Fact Ties Language to Reality

William Carpenter and the Debate on Human Automatism in mid-victorian England

Gert, Heather J. Family Resemblances and Criteria, Synthese 105, no. 2, November, 1995,

Nigel Warburton Anthony Grayling, I wonder if you could say a little bit about personal identity as a philosophical problem.

1/12. The A Paralogisms

The Correspondence theory of truth Frank Hofmann

Empiricist Mentalist Semantics

Thomas Aquinas on the World s Duration. Summa Theologiae Ia Q46: The Beginning of the Duration of Created Things

IS GOD "SIGNIFICANTLY FREE?''

Wittgenstein s The First Person and Two-Dimensional Semantics

PHILOSOPHY 5340 EPISTEMOLOGY

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

prohibition, moral commitment and other normative matters. Although often described as a branch

Causing People to Exist and Saving People s Lives Jeff McMahan

1/8. Leibniz on Force

Chapter 6. Fate. (F) Fatalism is the belief that whatever happens is unavoidable. (55)

INTRODUCTION TO PESSO SYSTEM/PSYCHOMOTOR

THE MEANING OF OUGHT. Ralph Wedgwood. What does the word ought mean? Strictly speaking, this is an empirical question, about the

RAHNER AND DEMYTHOLOGIZATION 555

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology. Topic 6: Theories of Justification: Foundationalism versus Coherentism. Part 2: Susan Haack s Foundherentist Approach

Free Will: Do We Have It?

Free will and foreknowledge

PLEASESURE, DESIRE AND OPPOSITENESS

Class #3 - Meinong and Mill

Transcription:

42 Philosophy and Progress Philosophy and Progress: Vols. LVII-LVIII, January-June, July-December, 2015 ISSN 1607-2278 (Print), DOI : http://dx.doi.org/10.3329/pp.v57il-2.31203 CONCEPT OF WILLING IN WITTGENSTEIN S PHILOSOPHICAL INVESTIGATIONS Md. Abdul Muhit * In 611 to 632 and in Part II, section 8 of his Philosophical Investigations (1958), and very briefly in 97 of his Philosophical Grammar (1974) Wittgenstein talks about action and the will. His main idea behind these passages is the view that our mental vocabulary does not refer to any inner acts, states or processes. Our inner states or processes are not private objects that are known only to the person who has them. For Wittgenstein, to say that someone is in a given mental state is to say that he is in any of a large collection of publicly observable things. He supports this view by examining the workings of a representative selection of mental concepts, such * Professor, Department of Philosophy, University of Dhaka E-mail : mamuhit@hotmail.com as, understanding, deciding, believing, judging, expecting, intending, willing, etc. The present paper is an attempt to present a clear view of what Wittgenstein means by the concept of willing in his Philosophical Investigations. It seems very difficult to find a common conceptual framework within which the notion of willing in Wittgenstein s later philosophy can be captured. But it is clearly understood from various passages in Philosophical Investigations that Wittgenstein has tried to characterize willing in both positive and negative ways. In fact, there are certain passages from which we can spell out clearly that his negative characterization outweighs more than his positive characterization. By an analysis of his negative treatment of willing we will try to come out with a positive characterization of this concept in Wittgenstein s later philosophy. We will see that his philosophical arguments to show that willing is not a particular kind of act give some indication that his whole notion of it is compatible with the language of some kind of philosophical behaviorism. According to Wittgenstein, the notion of willing as a specific inner act is quite mythic: there is no inner mechanism which brings our actions about. Although he was not specific about it Wittgenstein here seems to be reacting (Hyman, 2014) against the empiricist view about willing as represented by the classic exposition of John Locke in his Essay Concerning Human Understanding (1979). Locke writes as follows: All our voluntary Motions are produced in us only by the free Action or Thought of our own Minds For example: My right Hand writes, whilst my left Hand is still: What causes rest in one, and motion in the other? Nothing but my Will, a Thought of my Mind. (Locke 1979, 4.10.19) Willing, Locke explains, is an act of the Mind, directing its thought to the production of any action, and thereby exerting its power to produce it (ibid.,

Concept of Willing in Wittgenstein s Philosophical Investigations 43 44 Philosophy and Progress 2.21.28). Willing is its proper name; but Locke concedes that it is hard to find the right words to describe it. At one point, he describes it as a thought or preference of the mind ordering, or, as it were, commanding the doing or not doing such or such a particular action (ibid., 2.21.5). But he admits that the words preferring, ordering, and commanding do not capture the phenomenon precisely. He concludes that since willing is a very simple act, whosoever desires to understand what it is, will better find it by reflecting on his own mind, and observing what it does, when it wills, than by any variety of articulate sounds whatever (ibid., 2.21.30). In other words, one should not try to define the act of will: one should simply discover it by introspection. Contra Locke, Wittgenstein argues that willing is not the name of an action; neither is it the name of a voluntary action. According to him, willing is not a causal mark of the voluntary. If willing were some kind of causal bringing about, then it too could be brought about. But the philosophical idea of willing excludes that possibility; it makes no sense to speak of willing willing. ( 613) As if the willing of willing were a preparatory act of willing. However, I can bring about situations in which I have to will something. But that is not to will willing. Wittgenstein writes: In the sense in which I can ever bring anything about (such as stomach-ache through over-eating), I can also bring about an act of willing, In this sense I bring about the act of willing to swim by jumping into the water. Doubtless I was trying to say: I can't will willing; that is, it makes no sense to speak of willing willing. "Willing" is not the name of an action; and so not the name of any voluntary action either. And my use of a wrong expression came from our wanting to think of willing as an immediate non-causal bringing about. ( 613) From the last sentence of the above quotation it immediately follows that, for Wittgenstein, willing is not also some kind of special, non-causal bringing about. Here Wittgenstein suggests that there is an underlying picture which suggests the notion of a non-causal bringing about. A misleading analogy lies at the root of this idea; the causal nexus seems to be established by a mechanism connecting two parts of a machine. The connection may be broken if the mechanism is disturbed. (We think only of disturbances to which a mechanism is normally subject, not, say, of cogwheels suddenly going soft, or passing through one another, and so on.) ( 613) Willing, then, as we might picture it, is like part of the action mechanism, though it is not a physical item in the mechanism. So, it is a bringing about but not in the same sense as a causal mechanism. This is the reason of Wittgenstein speaking of the idea a non- causal bringing about. But this seems to be a mystification. What is left of the analogy between voluntary bringing about and the causal mechanism if the notion of connecting parts of the mechanism is not present? Willing, for Wittgenstein, comes to be thought of as a mover which is not itself moved. He puts it in 618: One imagines the willing subject here as something without any mass (without any inertia); as a motor which has no inertia in itself to overcome. And so it is only mover, not moved. That is: One can say "I will, but my body does not obey me" but not: "My will does not obey me." (Augustine.) Wittgenstein also denies that willing is an experience. In his Notebooks 1914-1916, he first mentions this point: The act of will is not an experience. (p. 89, dated 9.11.16) In experience, Wittgenstein insists, something is given to us, something happens, or something is perceived. But in willing, a thing does not happen to us, rather we do something. The will cannot be a phenomenon, for every phenomenon only happens,

Concept of Willing in Wittgenstein s Philosophical Investigations 45 is perceived by us, but is not something we do. In his Philosophical Grammar Wittgenstein substantiates this claim in the following way: The will can't be a phenomenon, for whatever phenomenon you take is something that simply happens, something we undergo, not something we do. The will isn't something I see happen, it's more like my being involved in my actions, my being my actions. Look at your arm and move it and you will experience this very vividly: "You aren't observing it moving itself, you aren't having an experience - not just an experience, anyway - you're doing something." You may tell yourself that you could also imagine exactly the same thing happening to your hand, but merely observed and not willed by you. But shut your eyes, and move your arm so that you have, among other things, a certain experience: now ask yourself whether you still can imagine that you were having the same experience but without willing it. ( 97, p. 144) For Wittgenstein, willing is not an instrument or device whereby we perform such voluntary actions as walking, talking or imagining. It is not like a brake one uses to stop a movement or a lever one uses to shift power from one to another pulley. When I raise my arm voluntarily I do not use any instrument to bring the movement about. My wish is not such an instrument. ( 614) If we try to think of willing as instrument and not agent, it tends to reappear in the guise of an agent. I ll walk, I might say, so, I d better will to bring my walking. So used, my willing will no longer serve to make the walking mine or even voluntary. That would be matter of my using willing, my doing that, and not a matter of its being willing that I happened to use. Willing is not, Wittgenstein remarks, any kind of wishing something. In Notebooks 1914-16, dated 4.1.1916 Wittgenstein remarked: Wishing is not acting. But willing is acting. (p. 46 Philosophy and Progress 88) To wish that something happen is to imply that this happening is not a voluntary action. When someone raises his or her arm, s/he does not wish that his or her arm might go up; any voluntary action, Wittgenstein says, excludes that wish. Thus, in 615 he remarks: Willing, if it is not to be a sort of wishing, must be the action itself. It cannot be allowed to stop anywhere short of the action. If it is the action, then it is so in the ordinary sense of the word; so it is speaking, writing, walking, lifting a thing, imagining something. But it is also trying, attempting, making an effort, to speak, to write, to lift a thing, to imagine something etc. What Wittgenstein means by the above remark is that if willing is just speaking, writing, walking, it can hardly be what makes instances of those actions voluntary. It may be pointed out here that Wittgenstein always argues against the idea of willing as mental states or mental acts, representing the deliberateness of voluntary actions, as something separate from the action itself. For him, willing is immanent in action itself; it neither evokes an action nor remain standing before action. In a certain way it is acting itself. In 621 Wittgenstein raises the question whether willing is the kinaesthetic sensation associated with voluntary activities. Let us not forget this: when 'I raise my arm', my arm goes up. And the problem arises: what is left over if I subtract the fact that my arm goes up from the fact that I raise my arm? ((Are the kinaesthetic sensations my willing?)) If willing is the kinaesthetic sensation, it might be among types of feelings associated with effort, trying, muscular movements, and the like. But Wittgenstein insists that when I raise my arm I do not usually try to raise it. ( 622) It is typically effortless. At all costs I will get to that house." But if there is no difficulty about it can I try at all costs to get to the house? ( 623)

Concept of Willing in Wittgenstein s Philosophical Investigations 47 48 Philosophy and Progress Wittgenstein here is reacting to William James view on willing (Hyman, 2014) as presented in The Principles of Psychology. James explains voluntary action by postulating sensations corresponding to each of the physical movements we are able to perform. James holds that I am aware of the movements of my limbs when I walk and of my lips when I speak because these movements produce characteristic kinaesthetic feelings in my mind; and he holds that my voluntary movements are caused by the images or ideas of kinaesthetic feelings stored in my memory. For example, when I raise my arm, the motion of my arm is caused by an idea of the feeling associated with this movement. No will-force over and above the idea needs to occur. Hence, according to James's view, the occurrence of the idea, pure and simple, is what is left over if I subtract the fact that my arm goes up from the fact that I raise my arm. Wittgenstein does not merely deny that voluntary movements are caused by memory images of kinaesthetic feelings: he rejects the very idea that kinaesthetic feelings advise me of the movement and position of my limbs. It is true, of course, that I can normally feel i.e. I am normally aware of how my limbs are disposed and how they are moving. But it does not follow that I am normally aware of feelings certain queer feelings in my muscles and joints, as Wittgenstein puts it in 624 which advise me of these things. And as a matter of fact, I am not normally aware of such feelings: I let my index finger make an easy pendulum movement of small amplitude. I either hardly feel it, or don't feel it at all. Perhaps a little in the tip of the finger, as a slight tension. (Not at all in the joint.) And this sensation advises me of the movement? for I can describe the movement exactly. (PI II, sec. VIII, p.185) So the reason why we imagine that kinaesthetic feelings advise me of the movement and position of my limbs may be that we are confusing being aware of something and being aware of sensations or sense-impressions caused by something. One may answer to the question How do you know that you have raised your arm? as I feel it. But for Wittgenstein, this answer is wrong, because it suggests that you recognize the special feeling, i.e., the kinaesthetic sensation, and can tell from recognizing them that their constant accompaniment, the raising of the arm, has occurred. The fact is that the certainty that you have raised your arm is itself a criterion of recognizing the feeling here. As Wittgenstein writes in 625: And are you certain that you recognize it right? You are certain that you have raised your arm; isn't this the criterion, the measure, of the recognition? In his Review of Wittgenstein s Philosophical Investigations (Mind, LXVIII, 1954) P. F. Strawson remarks that there are two things that Wittgenstein is not saying. He is not saying that one would have this certainty in the absence of any feeling, or in the presence of an unaccustomed feeling. It is no doubt because of the kinaesthetic sensations that I know; but it is not from them that I tell. Nor is he saying that I could never (say, if suitably stimulated) be mistaken about this. Here is a case where I know, but don t have a way of knowing, of telling. (p. 94) Wittgenstein reiterates the above claim that willing is not feeling in Part II of Philosophical Investigations in the following way. But after all, Wittgenstein imagines his interlocutor saying, you must feel it, otherwise you wouldn't know (without looking) how your finger was moving (p. 185). To this he replies: But knowing it only means: being able to describe it. I may be able to tell the direction from which a sound comes only because it affects one ear more strongly than the other, but I don't feel this in my ears; yet it has its effect: I know the direction from which the sound comes; for instance, I

Concept of Willing in Wittgenstein s Philosophical Investigations 49 50 Philosophy and Progress look in that direction. (Ibid.) Wittgenstein s point is that whatever physiological mechanism enables me to know where a sound is coming from, there is no need to postulate a sensation corresponding to the direction. Similarly, whatever mechanism enables me to know how my finger is moving, there is no need to postulate a kinaesthetic sensation corresponding to the movement of my finger either. Pain, Wittgenstein points out, provides another analogy. I know that the itch is in my toe, but not because the itch has a toeish quality about it. And memory, he adds, provides yet another. I know I had toast for breakfast, but not because a feeling of pastness is associated with my thought of eating toast. As he writes: It is the same with the idea that it must be some feature of our pain that advises us of the whereabouts of the pain in the body, and some feature of our memory image that tells us the time to which it belongs. (Ibid.) Finally, Wittgenstein considers the idea that willing to raise my arm is deciding to raise it: Examine the following description of a voluntary action: I form the decision to pull the bell at 5 o'clock, and when it strikes 5, my arm makes this movement. Is that the correct description, and not this one: and when it strikes 5, I raise my arm? One would like to supplement the first description: and see! my arm goes up when it strikes 5. And this and see! is precisely what doesn't belong here. I do not say See, my arm is going up! when I raise it. ( 627) What Wittgenstein is saying here, in effect, is that if willing is deciding, the so-called act it is supposed to cause cannot be an act at all: it can only be a phenomenon I observe. Finally, we may ask: What is left over if I subtract the fact that my arm goes up from the fact that I raise my arm? Wittgenstein s reply is that what is left over is just what characterizes voluntary movements. The difference between my raising my arm and my arm simply going up in the air does not consist in the presence of the former case an interior act of will. What commonly characterizes voluntary movements is the knowledge of what one is doing, absence of surprise as to what is happening, and foreknowledge of one s voluntary movements. Thus Wittgenstein remarks in 628: Voluntary movement is marked by the absence of surprise. And in 629: When people talk about the possibility of foreknowledge of the future they always forget the fact of the prediction of one's own voluntary movements. References 1. Gustafson, D. (1984). Wittgenstein and a Causal View of Intentional Action. Philosophical Investigations, 7(3). 2. Hyman, John. (2014). Action and The Will. In Oskari Kuusela and Marie McGinn, (eds.) The Oxford Handbook of Wittgenstein (pp. 451-472). Oxford: Oxford University Press. 3. James, William. (1950). The Principles of Psychology, Vol. 2, New York: Dover. 4. Locke, John. (1979). Essay Concerning Human Understanding. Oxford: Oxford University Press. 5. Pitcher, G. (ed.), (1966). Wittgenstein. New York: Anchor Books. 6. Wittgenstein, Ludwig. (1958). Philosophical Investigations. Trans. by G. E. M. Anscombe, 2 nd ed., Oxford: Blackwell Publishers, 1958 7. ----------. (1961). Notebooks 1914-1916. Edited by G. H. von Wright and G. E. M. Anscombe, translated by G. E. M. Anscombe, New York: Harper and Row Publishers. 8. ----------. (1974). Philosophical Grammar. edited by Rush Rhees, translated by Anthony Kenny, Oxford: Basil Blackwell.