STILL NO REDUNDANT PROPERTIES: REPLY TO WIELENBERG

Similar documents
ARE THE MORAL FIXED POINTS CONCEPTUAL TRUTHS?

WHY THERE REALLY ARE NO IRREDUCIBLY NORMATIVE PROPERTIES

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW

Perception and Mind-Dependence: Lecture 2

A Rational Solution to the Problem of Moral Error Theory? Benjamin Scott Harrison

HYBRID NON-NATURALISM DOES NOT MEET THE SUPERVENIENCE CHALLENGE. David Faraci

THE MORAL FIXED POINTS: REPLY TO CUNEO AND SHAFER-LANDAU

SIMON BOSTOCK Internal Properties and Property Realism

Generic truth and mixed conjunctions: some alternatives

SWINBURNE ON THE EUTHYPHRO DILEMMA. CAN SUPERVENIENCE SAVE HIM?

Explanatory Indispensability and Deliberative Indispensability: Against Enoch s Analogy Alex Worsnip University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill

HAVE WE REASON TO DO AS RATIONALITY REQUIRES? A COMMENT ON RAZ

Shafer-Landau's defense against Blackburn's supervenience argument

THE UNBELIEVABLE TRUTH ABOUT MORALITY

From Necessary Truth to Necessary Existence

Truth At a World for Modal Propositions

SCHROEDER ON THE WRONG KIND OF

NON-COGNITIVISM AND THE PROBLEM OF MORAL-BASED EPISTEMIC REASONS: A SYMPATHETIC REPLY TO CIAN DORR

Review of Erik J. Wielenberg: Robust Ethics: The Metaphysics and Epistemology of Godless Normative Realism

ARMSTRONGIAN PARTICULARS WITH NECESSARY PROPERTIES *

5 A Modal Version of the

Non-naturalism and Normative Necessities

A Solution to the Gettier Problem Keota Fields. the three traditional conditions for knowledge, have been discussed extensively in the

Self-Evidence and A Priori Moral Knowledge

POWERS, NECESSITY, AND DETERMINISM

THINKING ANIMALS AND EPISTEMOLOGY

There might be nothing: the subtraction argument improved

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

Bart Streumer, Unbelievable Errors, Oxford: Oxford University Press, ISBN

Comments on Truth at A World for Modal Propositions

Philosophical Issues, vol. 8 (1997), pp

(Some More) Vagueness

On Some Alleged Consequences Of The Hartle-Hawking Cosmology. In [3], Quentin Smith claims that the Hartle-Hawking cosmology is inconsistent with

Understanding Truth Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002

Externalism and a priori knowledge of the world: Why privileged access is not the issue Maria Lasonen-Aarnio

Armstrongian Particulars with Necessary Properties

e grounding argument against non-reductive moral realism

Non-naturalism and Normative Necessities

Informalizing Formal Logic

Introduction to Cognitivism; Motivational Externalism; Naturalist Cognitivism

Can logical consequence be deflated?

ON PROMOTING THE DEAD CERTAIN: A REPLY TO BEHRENDS, DIPAOLO AND SHARADIN

SMITH ON TRUTHMAKERS 1. Dominic Gregory. I. Introduction

Against the Vagueness Argument TUOMAS E. TAHKO ABSTRACT

Broad on Theological Arguments. I. The Ontological Argument

WHY WE REALLY CANNOT BELIEVE THE ERROR THEORY

Stang (p. 34) deliberately treats non-actuality and nonexistence as equivalent.

Rule-Following and the Ontology of the Mind Abstract The problem of rule-following

WHAT DOES KRIPKE MEAN BY A PRIORI?

Postmodal Metaphysics

PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE AND META-ETHICS

PLEASESURE, DESIRE AND OPPOSITENESS

The Puzzle of Pure Moral Motivation

SOME RADICAL CONSEQUENCES OF GEACH'S LOGICAL THEORIES

Humean Supervenience: Lewis (1986, Introduction) 7 October 2010: J. Butterfield

THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE

Supervenience Arguments and Normative Non-naturalism

Ramsey s belief > action > truth theory.

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 4: Skepticism. Part 1: The Scope of Skepticism and Two Main Types of Skeptical Argument

Empty Names and Two-Valued Positive Free Logic

AN ACTUAL-SEQUENCE THEORY OF PROMOTION

finagling frege Mark Schroeder University of Southern California September 25, 2007

Faith and Philosophy, April (2006), DE SE KNOWLEDGE AND THE POSSIBILITY OF AN OMNISCIENT BEING Stephan Torre

To link to this article:

Smith s Incoherence Argument for Moral Rationalism

What God Could Have Made

Ayer s linguistic theory of the a priori

The Metaphysics of Perfect Beings, by Michael Almeida. New York: Routledge, Pp $105.00

ON THE GROUNDS OF NORMATIVITY STEPHANIE LEARY. A Dissertation submitted to the. Graduate School-New Brunswick

CHECKING THE NEIGHBORHOOD: A REPLY TO DIPAOLO AND BEHRENDS ON PROMOTION

Gunky time and indeterminate existence

Title II: The CAPE International Conferen Philosophy of Time )

In defence of the Simplicity Argument E. J. Lowe a a

Class #9 - The Attributive/Referential Distinction

On Searle on Human Rights, Again! J. Angelo Corlett, San Diego State University

DO NORMATIVE JUDGEMENTS AIM TO REPRESENT THE WORLD?

REASONS-RESPONSIVENESS AND TIME TRAVEL

Do Ordinary Objects Exist? No. * Trenton Merricks. Current Controversies in Metaphysics edited by Elizabeth Barnes. Routledge Press. Forthcoming.

Why there is no such thing as a motivating reason

Do Ordinary Objects Exist? No. * Trenton Merricks. Current Controversies in Metaphysics edited by Elizabeth Barnes. Routledge Press. Forthcoming.

Received: 30 August 2007 / Accepted: 16 November 2007 / Published online: 28 December 2007 # Springer Science + Business Media B.V.

DANCY ON ACTING FOR THE RIGHT REASON

Note: This is the penultimate draft of an article the final and definitive version of which is

Spinoza, the No Shared Attribute thesis, and the

Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible?

AGAINST THE BEING FOR ACCOUNT OF NORMATIVE CERTITUDE

Between the Actual and the Trivial World

Existentialism Entails Anti-Haecceitism DRAFT. Alvin Plantinga first brought the term existentialism into the currency of analytic

DEFEASIBLE A PRIORI JUSTIFICATION: A REPLY TO THUROW

British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 62 (2011), doi: /bjps/axr026

MORAL AND EPISTEMIC OPEN-QUESTION ARGUMENTS

The grounding argument against non-reductive moral realism

Hume s Law Violated? Rik Peels. The Journal of Value Inquiry ISSN J Value Inquiry DOI /s

On David Chalmers's The Conscious Mind

A Review of Neil Feit s Belief about the Self

Replies to Giuliano Torrengo, Dan Zeman and Vasilis Tsompanidis

HANDBOOK (New or substantially modified material appears in boxes.)

Intro to Ground. 1. The idea of ground. 2. Relata. are facts): F 1. More-or-less equivalent phrases (where F 1. and F 2. depends upon F 2 F 2

Epistemicism, Parasites and Vague Names * vagueness is based on an untenable metaphysics of content are unsuccessful. Burgess s arguments are

Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics 1. By Tom Cumming

Transcription:

DISCUSSION NOTE STILL NO REDUNDANT PROPERTIES: REPLY TO WIELENBERG BY CAMPBELL BROWN JOURNAL OF ETHICS & SOCIAL PHILOSOPHY DISCUSSION NOTE NOVEMBER 2012 URL: WWW.JESP.ORG COPYRIGHT CAMPBELL BROWN 2012

Still No Redundant Properties: Reply to Wielenberg I n previous work (Brown 2011), I proposed an argument for Ethical Naturalism, the view that there are no non-natural ethical properties. 1 A premise in my argument was the principle that no properties are redundant. (Below I call this principle NRP, short for No Redundant Properties. ) A property is redundant, in the relevant sense, if it does not enhance our ability to distinguish possibilities: Any possibilities that are distinguishable with this property are equally distinguishable without it. I showed that if ethical properties supervene on natural properties, then any non-natural ethical properties are in this way redundant. NRP implies, therefore, that ethical properties cannot supervene on natural properties unless they are natural properties. Erik J. Wielenberg has criticized my argument, and NRP in particular (Wielenberg 2011). Below I respond. Wielenberg begins by arguing directly against NRP. Here is his argument: Consider the following line of reasoning. Suppose that the God of traditional monotheism exists. This God exists in every possible world and is essentially omniscient (for any proposition p, if p is true, then p is known [and hence believed] by God) and essentially infallible (for any proposition p, if God believes that p, then p is true), which implies that necessarily, for any proposition p, p is true if and only if God believes p. Thus, for every pair of possible worlds w1 and w2 that are indistinguishable with respect to at least all properties except being believed by God, it is also the case that w1 and w2 are indistinguishable with respect to all properties. Consequently, the property of being believed by God is redundant in Brown s sense. By similar reasoning, the property of being true is also redundant. If there are no redundant properties, then at least one of these properties (being true or being believed by God) does not exist. Thus, [NRP] implies that the existence of the God of traditional monotheism is incompatible with there being some truths, from which it surely follows that this God does not exist. This argument seems too fast (Wielenberg 2011: 2 3). By this argument, in the last sentence, I assume that Wielenberg means this argument: There are no redundant properties; therefore, there is no God. I am unsure, however, what he means by saying that it is too fast. Normally, I would have thought, to call an argument too fast is just to say, in a colorful way, that it is invalid. The conclusion has been drawn prematurely the premises are not yet strong enough to rule out all possibilities in which the conclusion is false and thus the argument moves too hastily from premises to conclusion. 1 Strictly, my argument concerned descriptive properties. Here I switch to natural because this seems the more common terminology.

Were this Wielenberg s meaning, I would happily agree. As I show below, the argument is indeed invalid. However, I do not think this can be what he means. First, he seems to think the argument is valid: He says that the premise implies the conclusion. 2 More importantly, the invalidity of the argument would not in any way impugn the premise. Everyone knows that invalid arguments may have true premises. Yet it is the premise that is in dispute. 3 What Wielenberg wants to say, I think, is the following: Atheism the view that there is no God is controversial, and, since NRP entails atheism, it is no less controversial. The point is to highlight how strong a premise NRP is by revealing one of its contentious consequences. This objection is intelligible. If NRP did indeed imply atheism, then that would, I grant, be a mark against my argument, though not necessarily a decisive one. However, NRP does not imply atheism. To show this, it will be helpful to set out Wielenberg s argument more precisely. So far as I can tell, it goes like this: P1. If God exists, then the predicate true is necessarily coextensive with another predicate, believed by God. P2. If true is necessarily coextensive with another predicate, then any property denoted by true is redundant. P3. If true does not denote a property, then nothing is true. P4. Something is true. C. If God exists, there is at least one redundant property. This is valid. Premises (P3) and (P4) together imply that true denotes a property, and (P1) and (P2) imply that this property is redundant if God exists. However, (P2) and (P3) are dubious. Begin with (P2). As I explained in my earlier paper, what is true is this: If two predicates are necessarily coextensive, and they each denote distinct properties, then these properties are redundant (Brown 2011: 215-16). Wielenberg has overlooked two possibilities. One is that true and believed 2 He says that NRP implies that the existence of the God of traditional monotheism is incompatible with there being some truths, from which it surely follows that this God does not exist (Wielenberg 2011: 3). I assume that if P surely follows from Q, then Q implies P (and, of course, that implication is transitive). 3 Wielenberg gives another argument in a similar vein. He points out that NRP is incompatible with views in the philosophy of mind according to which there are phenomenal properties that supervene on but are distinct from physical properties; he offers Colin McGuinn s new mysterianism as an example (Wielenberg 2011: 3). Again he alleges that this somehow implicates NRP in reasoning that is too fast. I find this allegation equally obscure. 2

by God denote the same property. 4 The other is that only true denotes a property; believed by God does not. Wielenberg seems to assume that if the property of being true were removed, our ability to distinguish possibilities would not be diminished, because we would still have the property of being believed by God, and anything distinguishable by the former property would be equally distinguishable by the latter. But this is not so if either (a) there is no such property as being believed by God, or (b) there is such a property but it is identical to being true. The other questionable premise, (P3), seems to assume a general principle that I explicitly rejected in my paper namely, that there can be things which satisfy a given predicate only if there s a corresponding property which those things instantiate (Brown 2011: 214). As a counterexample to this principle, I gave the predicate non-self-instantiating. 5 Moreover, the view that truth is not a property is already held by some philosophers who endorse a deflationary theory of truth. 6 These philosophers do not deny that there are truths. I do not insist that NRP is entirely innocuous. Any premise strong enough to imply Ethical Naturalism is bound to be contentious. But it is important to be clear on just how strong NRP is, and Wielenberg has significantly overstated its strength. Wielenberg also challenges the rationale I gave for NRP. This rationale appeals to ontological parsimony. Redundant properties, I argued, are unnecessary; we do not need to posit them, and therefore we should not posit them. Wielenberg s criticism, however, seems to misunderstand my argument. He says: Brown s rationale for [NRP] is adequate only if the only good reason to believe that a particular property is instantiated is that the instantiation of that property would serve to distinguish possibilities (Wielenberg 2011: 3). But this, I think, is false. I need not deny that there may be reasons to believe in redundant properties. I do say that we should not believe in such properties, but that is a different claim. If I told you, for example, that you should not eat poisonous food, I would not thereby imply that the only reason you can have to eat food is that it is non-poisonous. Wielenberg suggests that one reason we have for believing in non-natural ethical properties, despite their redundancy, is that certain events seem to instantiate such properties 4 That Wielenberg overlooked this possibility is a little surprising. The question of whether distinct properties can be necessarily coextensive has received much attention in the relevant literature. See, e.g., Jackson (1998: 125-28), Shafer-Landau (2003: 90-92), Streumer (2008: 541-45) and Brown (2011: 215-16). 5 Here is another counterexample. Many philosophers including, perhaps, Kant deny that existence is a property: There is no such property as the property of existing. But they do not thereby believe that nothing exists. 6 See, e.g., Ayer (2001/1936: 87). 3

(Wielenberg 2011: 4). I am quite willing to grant that this is such a reason. Still, I maintain, we should not believe in such properties; the reason is outweighed. I do claim that we have no need to posit redundant properties. Wielenberg s example might be intended as a counterexample to this claim. According to him, perhaps, we need to posit non-natural ethical properties in order to explain why it appears to us that certain events have such properties. But this seems simply false surely we can explain these appearances in other ways, without committing to the existence of such properties. 7 Similarly, we do not need to posit ghosts in order to explain why some people feel that they can sense the presence of dead relatives. In order to undermine my case for NRP, Wielenberg needs to show not merely that we may have reasons to posit redundant properties but that we need to do so. I do not think he has done this. 8 University of Edinburgh Department of Philosophy campbell.brown@ed.ac.uk 7 Cf. Harman (1977, ch. 1). 8 Thanks to Matthew Chrisman, Michael Ridge and an anonymous reviewer for helpful comments on this paper. 4

References Ayer, A. J. (2001/1936) Language, Truth and Logic, London: Penguin Classics. Brown, C. (2011) A New and Improved Supervenience Argument for Ethical Descriptivism, in R. Shafer-Landau, ed., Oxford Studies in Metaethics, Vol. 6, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 205-18. Harman, G. (1977) The Nature of Morality: An Introduction to Ethics, Oxford: Oxford University Press. Jackson, F. (1998) From Metaphysics to Ethics: A Defence of Conceptual Analysis, Oxford: Oxford University Press. Shafer-Landau, R. (2003) Moral Realism: A Defence, Oxford: Oxford University Press. Streumer, B. (2008) Are There Irreducibly Normative Properties? Australasian Journal of Philosophy 86: 537-61. Wielenberg, E. J. (2011) The Failure of Brown s New Supervenience Argument, Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy. 5