On the Rationality of Metaphysical Commitments in Immature Science

Similar documents
Intro. The need for a philosophical vocabulary

The Human Science Debate: Positivist, Anti-Positivist, and Postpositivist Inquiry. By Rebecca Joy Norlander. November 20, 2007

[3.] Bertrand Russell. 1

Review of Who Rules in Science?, by James Robert Brown

Phil 1103 Review. Also: Scientific realism vs. anti-realism Can philosophers criticise science?

Wilhelm Dilthey and Rudolf Carnap on the Foundation of the Humanities. Christian Damböck Institute Vienna Circle University of Vienna

Hoong Juan Ru. St Joseph s Institution International. Candidate Number Date: April 25, Theory of Knowledge Essay

Kant and his Successors

Ayer on the criterion of verifiability

K.V. LAURIKAINEN EXTENDING THE LIMITS OF SCIENCE

Introduction The Science Wars in Perspective

Remarks on the philosophy of mathematics (1969) Paul Bernays

Religion and Science: The Emerging Relationship Part II

Tuukka Kaidesoja Précis of Naturalizing Critical Realist Social Ontology

PHI2391: Logical Empiricism I 8.0

Verificationism. PHIL September 27, 2011

Towards Richard Rorty s Critique on Transcendental Grounding of Human Rights by Dr. P.S. Sreevidya

Philosophy of Science. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

ABSTRACT of the Habilitation Thesis

E L O G O S ELECTRONIC JOURNAL FOR PHILOSOPHY/2008 ISSN Tracks in the Woods. F.A. Hayek s Philosophy of History.

Philosophy of Economics and Politics

Kazuhisa Todayama (Graduate School of Information Science, Nagoya University, Japan)

Daniel Little Fallibilism and Ontology in Tuukka Kaidesoja s Critical Realist Social Ontology

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism

SYSTEMATIC RESEARCH IN PHILOSOPHY. Contents

Qualitative and quantitative inference to the best theory. reply to iikka Niiniluoto Kuipers, Theodorus

Ontological Justification: From Appearance to Reality Anna-Sofia Maurin (PhD 2002)

Objectivism and Education: A Response to David Elkind s The Problem with Constructivism

Kant s Pragmatism. Tobias Henschen. This paper offers a definition of the term pragmatic, as it is used in Kant s Critique of Pure

The Illusion of Scientific Realism: An Argument for Scientific Soft Antirealism

Life, Automata and the Mind-Body Problem

Epistemology Naturalized

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy

Contents EMPIRICISM. Logical Atomism and the beginnings of pluralist empiricism. Recap: Russell s reductionism: from maths to physics

The Philosophical Review, Vol. 110, No. 3. (Jul., 2001), pp

Introductory Kant Seminar Lecture

PHILOSOPHY DEPARTMENT FALL SEMESTER 2009 COURSE OFFERINGS

AN IDEALISTIC PRAGMATISM

PHI 1700: Global Ethics

Carnap s notion of analyticity and the two wings of analytic philosophy. Christian Damböck Institute Vienna Circle

Review Tutorial (A Whirlwind Tour of Metaphysics, Epistemology and Philosophy of Religion)

Russell: On Denoting

Fr. Copleston vs. Bertrand Russell: The Famous 1948 BBC Radio Debate on the Existence of God

Inquiry, Knowledge, and Truth: Pragmatic Conceptions. Pragmatism is a philosophical position characterized by its specific mode of inquiry, and

Philosophy of Science PHIL 241, MW 12:00-1:15

THE HISTORIC ALLIANCE OF CHRISTIANITY AND SCIENCE

The Representation of Logical Form: A Dilemma

The Positive Argument for Constructive Empiricism and Inference to the Best

HUME, CAUSATION AND TWO ARGUMENTS CONCERNING GOD

FINAL EXAM REVIEW SHEET. objectivity intersubjectivity ways the peer review system is supposed to improve objectivity

Gestures in the Making

DO WE NEED A THEORY OF METAPHYSICAL COMPOSITION?

Department of Philosophy

Van Fraassen: Arguments Concerning Scientific Realism

UNITY OF KNOWLEDGE (IN TRANSDISCIPLINARY RESEARCH FOR SUSTAINABILITY) Vol. I - Philosophical Holism M.Esfeld

Gilbert. Margaret. Scientists Are People Too: Comment on Andersen. Social Epistemology Review and Reply Collective 6, no. 5 (2017):

The Philosophy of Physics. Physics versus Metaphysics

Class #3 - Meinong and Mill

Under contract with Oxford University Press Karen Bennett Cornell University

Philosophy and Methods of the Social Sciences

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Lectures and laboratories activities on the nature of Physics and concepts and models in optic: 1. Scientific sentences

THE TACIT AND THE EXPLICIT A reply to José A. Noguera, Jesús Zamora-Bonilla, and Antonio Gaitán-Torres

Theories of propositions

UNIVERSITY OF WISCONSIN-MADISON Department of History. Semester I,

Philosophy 125 Day 1: Overview

145 Philosophy of Science

Perspectival Methods in Metaphysics

Wolfgang Spohn Fachbereich Philosophie Universität Konstanz D Konstanz

Deontological Perspectivism: A Reply to Lockie Hamid Vahid, Institute for Research in Fundamental Sciences, Tehran

Moral Objectivism. RUSSELL CORNETT University of Calgary

The Question of Metaphysics

Chapter Six. Aristotle s Theory of Causation and the Ideas of Potentiality and Actuality

THE REFUTATION OF PHENOMENALISM

The Quest for Knowledge: A study of Descartes. Christopher Reynolds

PL-101: Introduction to Philosophy Fall of 2007, Juniata College Instructor: Xinli Wang

Development of Thought. The word "philosophy" comes from the Ancient Greek philosophia, which

How Do We Know Anything about Mathematics? - A Defence of Platonism

Chapter 31. Logical Positivism and the Scientific Conception of Philosophy

THE STUDY OF UNKNOWN AND UNKNOWABILITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY

FIL 4600/10/20: KANT S CRITIQUE AND CRITICAL METAPHYSICS

A Scientific Realism-Based Probabilistic Approach to Popper's Problem of Confirmation

A Logical Approach to Metametaphysics

A Quick Review of the Scientific Method Transcript

Radical Centrism & the Redemption of Secular Philosophy

Examining the nature of mind. Michael Daniels. A review of Understanding Consciousness by Max Velmans (Routledge, 2000).

Why I Am Not a Property Dualist By John R. Searle

POWERS, NECESSITY, AND DETERMINISM

Chapter 18 David Hume: Theory of Knowledge

PH 1000 Introduction to Philosophy, or PH 1001 Practical Reasoning

Rorty on Language and Social Practices

Epistemic Contextualism as a Theory of Primary Speaker Meaning

The Sea-Fight Tomorrow by Aristotle

The linguistic-cultural nature of scientific truth 1

Tuesday, September 2, Idealism

14 Hegel and analytic philosophy

AN OUTLINE OF CRITICAL THINKING

SYLLABUS. Business and Social Sciences Department: History/Philosophy

BERKELEY, REALISM, AND DUALISM: REPLY TO HOCUTT S GEORGE BERKELEY RESURRECTED: A COMMENTARY ON BAUM S ONTOLOGY FOR BEHAVIOR ANALYSIS

Theories of the mind have been celebrating their new-found freedom to study

Transcription:

On the Rationality of Metaphysical Commitments in Immature Science ALEXANDER KLEIN, CORNELL UNIVERSITY Kuhn famously claimed that like jigsaw puzzles, paradigms include rules that limit both the nature of acceptable solutions and the steps by which they are to be obtained (Kuhn 1962/1996, 38). Some such rules are quasi-metaphysical in the sense that they are premised on ontological assumptions about the most basic constituents of reality (Kuhn 1962/1996, 41). For instance, after about 1630 many natural scientists accepted the view that the universe was composed of minute corpuscles, and they accepted as a guiding rule of inquiry that natural phenomena should be explained in terms of the size, shape, motion, and interaction of these elementary entities. But such metaphysical commitments (and the rules they issue) are difficult to justify rationally. After all, the commitments are presuppositions of normal-scientific inquiry and so cannot themselves be established by normal science. How, if at all, can such metaphysical commitments be justified? One potential answer can be drawn from Michael Friedman s recent work. He holds that philosophy has historically operated as a meta-framework for deliberation about presuppositional elements of normal science. For instance, to make coordinating principles in relativity theory intelligible to those working inside rival frameworks, Einstein drew on a philosophical debate about absolute versus relative motion, a debate stretching back to the seventeenth century (Friedman 2001, 101-106). Perhaps a paradigm s metaphysical commitments can also be justified or at least made intelligible to those outside the paradigm through such philosophical (i.e., meta-scientific) deliberation. Friedman s account can help make sense of metaphysical commitments in mature sciences (e.g., 20 th century physics). But I will argue that his account is less useful for analyzing the dynamics of immature sciences. Young sciences are often hatched out of philosophy through a kind of disciplinary mitosis. In the struggle to draw a stable boundary between philosophy and the young science, the science s

metaphysical commitments are often designed not to draw on, but rather strenuously to avoid making contact with philosophical discussion. Or so I shall argue. Specifically, my aim is to show how metaphysical commitments can emerge during the mitotic phase (as I call it) of scientific development. I will show how such commitments can indeed be rational even though their justification comes from neither normal-scientific demonstration nor meta-scientific, philosophical deliberation. They can be rational to the extent that they stand to help establish a stable boundary between philosophy and the emerging science. To support my position, I offer a case study of empirical psychology s emergence from philosophy in the late 19 th century. I focus on William James s Principles of Psychology, the field s first blockbuster textbook to be written in English. Among the more controversial aspects of that book was the way it defined psychology s proper object, the mental state. 1 The definition was controversial precisely for the forthright way that it incorporated metaphysical assumptions about the mind. 2 James argued that at the outset of inquiry, psychologists must assume certain data uncritically. They must assume the existence of (1) thoughts and feelings inside (2) a physical world in time and space with which they coexist and which (3) they know (James 1890/1981, 6-7). He then claimed that those thoughts and feelings the psychologist studies i.e., mental states must be construed as having five basic properties that the scientist is to decline to be responsible for explaining (James 1892/1983, 271). For instance, the first basic property of the mental state is that every thought tends to be part of a personal consciousness (James 1890/1981, 220). I argue that each of these basic properties is metaphysically loaded in a special sense that becomes clear only when we place James s work into an appropriate historical context. 1 This was a technical phrase for James; see (James 1890/1981, 6, 186; James 1892/1983, 275). He used thought, feeling, and mental state interchangeably. 2 Three reviews that attacked the notion that psychology must begin with metaphysical assumptions or at any rate, with James s particular metaphysical assumptions were (Fullerton 1894; Ladd 1892; Peirce 1891).

Neo-Kantian idealists like Edward Caird, Francis Herbert Bradley, and especially Thomas Hill Green had developed pointed criticisms of psychology during the 1870s and 80s. They argued that minds are not appropriate objects of scientific investigation. 3 They especially rejected the notion that a would-be science of mind could provide any results relevant to philosophy. 4 These critics often argued that there were certain, basic features of the mind that were intractable to scientific investigation. They portrayed this alleged intractability as evidence that there was something flawed about the very idea of a natural science of mind. I show that those five features James chose as basic properties of the mental state are metaphysically loaded in the following sense, then. They are metaphysical in that they identify mental properties that were hotly contested in the fight between idealists and mental scientists; 5 and they are loaded in the sense that the scientist is to decline to be responsible for explaining them. James consigns the job of explaining such basic features of the mind to philosophy. Thus, James s basic definition of the mental state contains metaphysical presuppositions about the mind; Kuhn s claim that sciences contain metaphysical presuppositions squares with the results of our case study. But the presuppositions are rational to adopt, I argue, because they stand to help divide labor between philosophy and the emerging science of psychology. They accomplish this task by specifying which specific questions are to be the province of philosophy and which 3 Bradley was more moderate, arguing that psychology could be a science, though like other sciences, it could provide only an incomplete account of its subject matter. Green, Caird, and their ally Andrew Seth Pringle-Patteson categorically rejected psychology on the grounds that the mind is just not the sort of thing that can be studied using empirical methods. Recently, Fred Wilson has contrasted Bradley s more nuanced position to that of Green and Pringle-Pattison, correctly noting that the point of idealism for Green was to establish that a natural science of human being is impossible, in (Wilson 1999, 10). Also see (Wilson 1998, 9). 4 In the next generation, leading British philosophers like Russell would take their cue from the anti-psychologism not just of Frege, but perhaps as importantly of idealists like Green and Bradley (see Griffin 1996; Keen 1971) who participated in the debate I discuss in the paper. Note that the British debate is a counterpart to the better-known, German arguments over psychology s scientific status. On the German debates, see (Kusch 1995). 5 Prominent mental scientists who participated in this debate included James, Alexander Bain, and a host of allies who often published in the British journal Mind.

the province of psychology. If I am right, notice that these presuppositions are not rational because they can be justified through any theoretical argument (whether intra- or extra-paradigmatic). They are rational in the manner of an ingenious invention. The compliment I am paying James is much like the compliment one might pay an engineer who figures out how to build a better bicycle. For instance, in the 1890s bicycles began being mass produced with pneumatic tires an invention (by John Boyd Dunlop) that made for greater traction and a smoother ride. Dunlop s new design was rational not because it revealed some fundamental truth about nature. It was rational because it provided an ingenious solution to problems inherent in older bicycle designs. Similarly, I want to claim that James s metaphysical postulates were rational in that they were an ingenious invention for solving a design problem how to structure intellectual communities so as to quell the incessant squabbling between philosophers and early empirical psychologists. In other words, James s metaphysical postulates provided the emerging science of mind with, as it were, greater traction and a smoother ride. Works Cited Friedman, Michael (2001), Dynamics of Reason. Stanford, CA: CSLI Publications. Fullerton, George Stuart (1894), "The Psychological Standpoint," Psychological Review 1 (2):113-133. Griffin, Nicholas (1996), "Bradley's Contribution to the Development of Logic," in James Bradley (ed.) Philosophy after F.H. Bradley, Bristol: Thoemmes, 195-230. James, William (1890/1981), The Principles of Psychology. Edited by Frederick H. Burkhardt, Fredson Bowers and Ignas K. Skrupskelis, The Works of William James. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. (1892/1983), "A Plea for Psychology as a 'Natural Science'," in Frederick H. Burkhardt, Fredson Bowers and Ignas K. Skrupskelis (eds.), Essays in Psychology, Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 270-277. Keen, C. N. (1971), "The Interaction of Russell and Bradley," Russell: The Journal of the Bertrand Russell Archives 3:7-11. Kuhn, Thomas S. (1962/1996), The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Kusch, Martin (1995), Psychologism: A Case Study in the Sociology of Philosophical Knowledge. London: Routledge.

Ladd, George Trumbull (1892), "Psychology as So-Called "Natural Science"," The Philosophical Review 1 (1):24-53. Peirce, Charles S. (1891), "James's Psychology--I," Nation 53:15. Wilson, Fred (1998), "Bradley's Critique of Associationism," Bradley Studies: The Journal of the Bradley Society 4:5-60. (1999), "The Significance for Psychology of Bradley's Humean View of the Self," Bradley Studies: The Journal of the Bradley Society 5 (1):5-44.