The Positive Argument for Constructive Empiricism and Inference to the Best

Similar documents
Van Fraassen: Arguments concerning scientific realism

Dispelling the Disjunction Objection to Explanatory Inference Kevin McCain and Ted Poston

Realism and the success of science argument. Leplin:

Van Fraassen: Arguments Concerning Scientific Realism

A Defense for Scientific Realism:

Review of Constructive Empiricism: Epistemology and the Philosophy of Science

How Successful Is Naturalism?

Van Fraassen s Appreciated Anti-Realism. Lane DesAutels. I. Introduction

Against the No-Miracle Response to Indispensability Arguments

The Illusion of Scientific Realism: An Argument for Scientific Soft Antirealism

CONSTRUCTIVE EMPIRICISM AND EPISTEMIC MODESTY: RESPONSE TO VAN FRAASSEN AND MONTON

Practical Inadequacy: Bas van Fraassen's Failures of Systematicity. Curtis Forbes

Kazuhisa Todayama (Graduate School of Information Science, Nagoya University, Japan)

Approximate Truth vs. Empirical Adequacy

THE HYPOTHETICAL-DEDUCTIVE METHOD OR THE INFERENCE TO THE BEST EXPLANATION: THE CASE OF THE THEORY OF EVOLUTION BY NATURAL SELECTION

Why Scientific Knowledge Is Still the Best. Moti Mizrahi, Florida Institute of Technology

Scientific realism and anti-realism

Are Scientific Theories True?

Psillos s Defense of Scientific Realism

The linguistic-cultural nature of scientific truth 1

Chapter One. Constructive Empiricism and the Case. Against Scientific Realism

Qualified Realism: From Constructive Empiricism to Metaphysical Realism.

A Modest Defense of Manifestationalism

We aim to cover in some detail a number of issues currently debated in the philosophy of natural and social science.

FINAL EXAM REVIEW SHEET. objectivity intersubjectivity ways the peer review system is supposed to improve objectivity

Should the Empiricist be a Constructive Empiricist? Marc Alspector-Kelly. Department of Philosophy. Western Michigan University

NATURALISED JURISPRUDENCE

Scientific Realism and Empiricism

145 Philosophy of Science

Explanatory Indispensability and Deliberative Indispensability: Against Enoch s Analogy Alex Worsnip University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill

Realism and Anti-Realism about Science A Pyrrhonian Stance

Empiricism. Otávio Bueno Department of Philosophy University of Miami Coral Gables, FL

Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000)

HPS 1653 / PHIL 1610 Revision Guide (all topics)

Historical Inductions, Unconceived Alternatives, and Unconceived Objections

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

ONE CANNOT BE JUST A LITTLE BIT REALIST: PUTNAM AND VAN FRAASSEN*

UNIVERSITY OF ALBERTA MATHEMATICS AS MAKE-BELIEVE: A CONSTRUCTIVE EMPIRICIST ACCOUNT SARAH HOFFMAN

An Empiricist Theory of Knowledge Bruce Aune

REVIEW THE DOOR TO SELLARS

Reconstructed Empiricism

Phil 1103 Review. Also: Scientific realism vs. anti-realism Can philosophers criticise science?

Experience and Foundationalism in Audi s The Architecture of Reason

Philosophy of Science. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

The Human Science Debate: Positivist, Anti-Positivist, and Postpositivist Inquiry. By Rebecca Joy Norlander. November 20, 2007

Quests of a Realist. Stathis Psillos, Scientific Realism: How Science Tracks Truth. London: Routledge, Pp. xxv PB.

BAS C. VAN FRAASSEN 1. AGAINST ANALYTIC METAPHYSICS

INTRODUCTION: EPISTEMIC COHERENTISM

Philosophy of Science PHIL 241, MW 12:00-1:15

SCIENTIFIC REALISM AND EPISTEMOLOGY

Tuomas E. Tahko (University of Helsinki)

Holtzman Spring Philosophy and the Integration of Knowledge

How Do We Know Anything about Mathematics? - A Defence of Platonism

CLASS #17: CHALLENGES TO POSITIVISM/BEHAVIORAL APPROACH

Huemer s Clarkeanism

Structural Realism or Modal Empiricism?

I. Scientific Realism: Introduction

POWERS, NECESSITY, AND DETERMINISM

ON CAUSAL AND CONSTRUCTIVE MODELLING OF BELIEF CHANGE

Theoretical Virtues in Science

Scientific Progress, Verisimilitude, and Evidence

What is a counterexample?

In Defense of Mathematical Inferentialism

Analogy and Pursuitworthiness

Metametaphysics. New Essays on the Foundations of Ontology* Oxford University Press, 2009

Chapter 18 David Hume: Theory of Knowledge

REALISM/ANTI-REALISM

The stated objective of Gloria Origgi s paper Epistemic Injustice and Epistemic Trust is:

PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE PHIL 145, FALL 2017

UNIVERSITY OF ALBERTA MATHEMATICS AS MAKE-BELIEVE: A CONSTRUCTIVE EMPIRICIST ACCOUNT SARAH HOFFMAN

HPS 1653 / PHIL 1610 Introduction to the Philosophy of Science

The Theory/Experiment Interface of the Observation of Black Holes

From the Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy

UNITY OF KNOWLEDGE (IN TRANSDISCIPLINARY RESEARCH FOR SUSTAINABILITY) Vol. I - Philosophical Holism M.Esfeld

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

Self-Evidence and A Priori Moral Knowledge

REVIEW: James R. Brown, The Laboratory of the Mind

PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR ARTICLE

Issue 4, Special Conference Proceedings Published by the Durham University Undergraduate Philosophy Society

Subject and Object in Scientific Realism. Howard Sankey. University of Melbourne. 1. Introduction: Subject and Object

PHENOMENAL CONSERVATISM, JUSTIFICATION, AND SELF-DEFEAT

Introductory Kant Seminar Lecture

CONTRASTIVE EMPIRICISM AND INDISPENSABILITY

ABSTRACT: In this paper, I argue that Phenomenal Conservatism (PC) is not superior to

The Best Explanation: A Defense of Scientific Realism

The Uniformity Principle vs. the Disuniformity Principle

Paley s Inductive Inference to Design

Stance relativism: empiricism versus metaphysics

Realism and instrumentalism

THE ROLE OF COHERENCE OF EVIDENCE IN THE NON- DYNAMIC MODEL OF CONFIRMATION TOMOJI SHOGENJI

Review of Erik J. Wielenberg: Robust Ethics: The Metaphysics and Epistemology of Godless Normative Realism

Mizrahi, Moti. In Defense of Weak Scientism: A Reply to Brown. Social Epistemology Review and Reply Collective 6, no. 11 (2017): 9-22.

Philosophy and Methods of the Social Sciences

Stance relativism: empiricism versus metaphysics

Rethinking Knowledge: The Heuristic View

Introduction to Cognitivism; Motivational Externalism; Naturalist Cognitivism

Reason and Explanation: A Defense of Explanatory Coherentism. BY TED POSTON (Basingstoke,

Kitcher, Correspondence, and Success

Naturalism, Science and the Supernatural

Transcription:

The Positive Argument for Constructive Empiricism and Inference to the Best Explanation Moti Mizrahi Florida Institute of Technology motimizra@gmail.com Abstract: In this paper, I argue that the positive argument for Constructive Empiricism (CE), according to which CE makes better sense of science, and of scientific activity, than realism does (van Fraassen 1980, 73), is an Inference to the Best Explanation (IBE). But constructive empiricists are critical of IBE, and thus they have to be critical of their own positive argument for CE. If my argument is sound, then constructive empiricists are in the awkward position of having to reject their own positive argument for CE by their own lights. Keywords: Constructive Empiricism; Inference to the Best Explanation; Positive Argument; Scientific Realism According to Bas van Fraassen (1980, 73), the positive argument for Constructive Empiricism (CE), is that it makes better sense of science, and of scientific activity, than realism does and does so without inflationary metaphysics. Although van Fraassen would not characterize it as such, this positive argument for CE looks like an Inference to the Best Explanation (IBE), for in IBE, a hypothesis is accepted on the basis of a judgment that it best explains the available evidence (Psillos 2007, 442). And a good explanation makes sense out of that which it is intended to explain (Sinnott-Armstrong and Fogelin 2015, 198; emphasis added). In van Fraassen s positive argument, CE is said to be supported by the premise that it makes better 1

sense of, or provides a better explanation for, scientific activity than Scientific Realism (SR) does. In other words, the phenomenon to be explained is scientific activity and the two competing hypotheses are CE and SR. Both CE and SR are supposed to explain scientific activity. Van Fraassen claims that CE makes better sense of, or provides a better explanation for, scientific activity than SR does, and he even makes an appeal to simplicity or parsimony when he says that CE makes better sense of, or provides a better explanation for, scientific activity than SR without inflationary metaphysics (van Fraassen 1980, 73). If this is correct, then van Fraassen s positive argument for CE is an IBE that runs as follows (see Psillos 2007 on the structure of IBE): (1) Scientists theorize about unobservables and then test their hypotheses by observation and experimentation (= scientific activity). (2) The best explanation for scientific activity is CE. (3) No hypothesis (e.g., SR) explains scientific activity as well as CE does. (4) Therefore, CE is (probably) true. It is important to note that IBEs like the one outlined above are not uniquely scientific arguments. Rather, IBEs are used in both scientific and non-scientific contexts, which is why it would do constructive empiricists no good to protest that van Fraassen s use of the phrase makes better sense of should not to be equated with explains. For, as Walton (2005, 51) puts it, An explanation is successful if it communicates understanding of a sort needed to enable the questioner to make sense of the thing questioned (emphasis added). Accordingly, an argument can still be an IBE even if the explanation it purports to support is not a scientific one, strictly speaking. As McCain and Poston (2017, 1) put it: 2

Explanatory reasoning is quite common. Not only are rigorous inferences to the best explanation (IBE) used pervasively in the sciences, explanatory reasoning is virtually ubiquitous in everyday life. It is not a stretch to say that we implement explanatory reasoning in a way that is so routine and automatic that it easily goes unnoticed [Douven 2017]. Perhaps for this reason, the fact that van Fraassen s positive argument for CE is an IBE went unnoticed, but it is an IBE nonetheless. Given that a good explanation makes sense out of that which it is intended to explain (Sinnott-Armstrong and Fogelin 2015, 198), and CE is said to make better sense of science, and of scientific activity, than realism does (van Fraassen 1980, 73), i.e., CE is supposed to make sense out of or explain scientific activity, it follows that CE is said to provide a better explanation of scientific activity than SR does. In other words, van Fraassen s positive argument for CE is an IBE. The problem, of course, is that van Fraassen (and constructive empiricists in general) is critical of IBE. Van Fraassen (1980, 143) argues against IBE as follows: [IBE] is a rule that selects the best among the historically given hypotheses. We can watch no contest of the theories we have so painfully struggled to formulate, with those no one has proposed. So our selection may well be the best of a bad lot (emphasis added). This is van Fraassen's well-known argument from a bad lot against IBE. (Cf. Schupbach 2014.) According to van Fraassen, whenever we infer that one hypothesis is better than alternative hypotheses on explanatory grounds, we could simply be selecting the best hypothesis among several bad ones (i.e., hypotheses that are not even close to the truth). The reason for this is that, for constructive empiricists, explanatory considerations, such as simplicity and explanatory scope, are not truth-conducive. As van Fraassen (1980, 87) puts it: 3

When a theory is advocated, it is praised for many features other than empirical adequacy and strength: it is said to be mathematically elegant, simple, of great scope, complete in certain respects: also of wonderful use in unifying our account of hitherto disparate phenomena, and most of all, explanatory. Judgments of simplicity and explanatory power are the intuitive and natural vehicles of expressing our epistemic appraisal. What can an empiricist make of these other virtues which go so clearly beyond the ones he considers pre-eminent? (emphasis added) In other words, van Fraassen distinguishes between theoretical virtues that are epistemic or truthconductive and those that are merely pragmatic. For constructive empiricists, non-epistemic theoretical virtues, such as simplicity and explanatory scope, are merely pragmatic virtues, which are irrelevant to a theory s truth. Now the problem is clear: How can constructive empiricists be critical of IBE on the one hand and then use IBE to argue for CE on the other? Van Fraassen (1980, 73) argues that we should choose CE over SR, but our selection may well be the best of a bad lot (van Fraassen 1980, 143). Perhaps CE and SR make up a bad lot of explanations for scientific activity (see Mizrahi 2012 and 2014). Likewise, the fact that CE does not carry the metaphysical baggage that SR does is no reason to favor CE over SR, by the constructive empiricist s own lights, since parsimony, simplicity, elegance, and the like are not epistemic virtues but merely pragmatic virtues, which are not truth-conducive. If this is correct, then constructive empiricists cannot accept their own positive argument for CE, given that this positive argument is an instance of IBE, which is a form of inference that constructive empiricist reject as illegitimate. But perhaps there is a way out of this problem for constructive empiricists. They could argue that IBE is a legitimate form of inference in philosophy, but not in science. This move, 4

however, is rather ad hoc. First, as mentioned above, the structure of IBE is pretty much the same whether the explanation argued for is scientific or not. For instance, compare Psillos (2007, 442-443) analysis of IBE in formal, scientific contexts with Sinnott-Armstrong and Fogelin s (2015, 196) analysis of IBE in informal, non-scientific contexts. D is a collection of data (facts, observations). H explains D. No other hypothesis can explain D as well as H does. Therefore, H is (probably) true. (1) Observation: Your lock is broke, and your valuables are missing. (2) Explanation: The hypothesis that your house has been burglarized, combined with previously accepted facts and principles, provides a suitably strong explanation of observation 1. (3) Comparison: No other hypothesis provides an explanation nearly as good as that in 2. (4) Conclusion: Your house was burglarized. In both cases, the structure is that of an inference from observations and a comparison between competing hypotheses to the conclusion that one of those hypothesis best explains the observations, for To explain is to make sense of the observed facts (Watling 1964, 164). (See also Douven 2017.) Moreover, the criteria for selecting the best explanation among competing hypotheses are also shared between scientific and non-scientific IBEs. According to Sinnott- Armstrong and Fogelin (2015, 195), common standards for assessing explanations include explanatory power, falsifiability, and simplicity, whether those explanations are scientific or not. 5

Second, why think that IBE works in philosophy but not in science? After all, one of the main issues constructive empiricists have with IBE is that it is an inference from the observable to unobservable objects, events, and processes (van Fraassen 2001, 162), or from observable phenomena to unobservable theoretical entities. As Muller (2008, 143) puts it: [An inference] going from observable behavior to unobservable mental states, smacks too much of an Inference-to-the-Best-Explanation (IBE), which is a mode of inference that Van Fraassen is very critical about, in particular when it concerns an explanandum about observables only and an explanans which is also about unobservables (emphasis added). Indeed, Muller (2008, 143) cites the constructive empiricist s criticism of IBE as a reason to reject a premise in Maxwell s (2002) refutation of standard empiricism, of which CE is a version. Surely, however, IBEs in philosophy involve inferences from observable phenomena to unobservable theoretical entities as well. For example, the main argument for SR, known as the No-Miracles Argument, is an IBE according to which SR provides the best explanation of a robust phenomenon that stands in need of explanation, namely, the empirical success of the sciences (Sankey 2016, 35). This is an IBE from the observable success of science to the existence of the unobservable entities of the scientific theories that supposedly make this empirical success possible. For constructive empiricists, such IBEs from observable phenomena to the existence of unobservable theoretical entities are illegitimate. As van Fraassen puts the point with respect to sense-data: 6

Such events as experiences, and such entities as sense-data, when they are not already understood in the framework of observable phenomena ordinarily recognized, are theoretical entities (van Fraassen 1980, 72). Indeed, the positive argument for CE itself is an IBE from observable phenomena to unobservable theoretical entities. After all, according to van Fraassen (1980, 12), CE is the view that Science aims to give us theories that are empirically adequate; and acceptance of a theory involves as belief only that it is empirically adequate (emphasis added), and to accept a theory is (for us) to believe that it is empirically adequate that what the theory says about what is observable (by us) is true (van Fraassen 1980, 18; emphasis added). Beliefs, and thus acceptance, which is defined by van Fraassen in terms of belief, are mental states or events (Evnine 1991, 7; see also Schwitzgebel 2015). As the constructive empiricist, Muller (2008, 133), explicitly acknowledges, Acceptance is [...] taken to be the dispositional mental state guiding our behaviour (emphasis added). But mental states or events are theoretical entities, i.e., they are unobservable (Muller 2008, 143). Therefore, the positive argument for CE is an IBE from observable phenomena, namely, scientific activity, to unobservable theoretical entities, namely, mental states or events, such as belief and acceptance. As Van Dyck (2007, 23) puts it: The distinction between acceptance and belief can be put to good use in making sense of scientific practice. Hence, constructive empiricism is an attractive position, which makes better sense of science, and of scientific activity, than realism does (1980: 73) (emphasis in original). In fact, like sense-data, mental states or events are the worst kind of unobservable theoretical entities, by the constructive empiricist s own lights, because they are the theoretical entities of an armchair psychology that cannot even rightfully claim to be scientific (van Fraassen 1980, 7

72). Insofar as he is sure that sense-data do not exist (van Fraassen 1980, 72), van Fraassen should also be sure that mental states or events do not exist. And yet, mental states or events, such as beliefs, which are entities postulated by folk psychology (Schwitzgebel 2015), are key theoretical posits of CE. By their own lights, then, constructive empiricists should reject the positive argument for CE as an inference that smacks too much of an [IBE] (Muller 2008, 143) because it is an inference from observable behavior, which is scientific activity as far as the positive argument for CE is concerned, to unobservable mental states (Muller 2008, 143), which are belief and acceptance as far as the positive argument for CE is concerned. This is also the reason why van Fraassen s voluntarist epistemology cannot provide a way out of this problem for constructive empiricists. On van Fraassen s voluntarist epistemology (1989, 171-173; 2000, 277; 2002, 92), one is rationally entitled to believe anything that one is not compelled to disbelieve. In other words, for van Fraassen (1989, 157), one can rationally believe anything that does not sabotage its own possibility of vindication (1985, 248). Accordingly, constructive empiricists might wish to appeal to van Fraassen s voluntarist epistemology in order to argue that the conclusion of positive argument for CE is merely that we are rationally entitled to believe CE over SR, not that CE is probably true because it is a better explanation for scientific activity than SR is. This move, however, is ineffective in resolving the tension between the positive argument for CE being an IBE from the observable phenomenon of scientific activity to unobservable theoretical entities like mental states or events and the constructive empiricist s critique of IBE. For even van Fraassen s voluntarist epistemology itself is couched in terms of unobservable theoretical entities, namely, the mental states or events of rational belief and disbelief. As such, appealing to van Fraassen s voluntarist 8

epistemology does not change the fact that the positive argument for CE is an IBE from observable phenomena (i.e., scientific activity) to unobservable theoretical entities (i.e., mental states or events), which is an inference that constructive empiricists have to be critical of by their own lights. To sum up, I have argued that the positive argument for CE, according to which CE makes better sense of science, and of scientific activity, than realism does (van Fraassen 1980, 73), is an IBE. But constructive empiricists are critical of IBE, and thus they have to be critical of their own positive argument for CE. If my argument is sound, then constructive empiricists remain in the awkward position of having to reject their own positive argument for CE by their own lights. If CE is to be a credible antirealist alternative to SR, as Monton and Mohler (2017) claim it is, constructive empiricists must resolve this tension. Acknowledgments I am grateful to an anonymous reviewer of the Journal for General Philosophy of Science for helpful comments on an earlier draft and to editor, Helmut Pulte. References Douven, Igor. (2017). Abduction. In E. N. Zalta (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2017 Edition). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2017/entries/abduction/. Evnine, Simone. (1991). Donald Davidson. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press. 9

Maxwell, Nicholas. (2002). The Need for a Revolution in the Philosophy of Science. Journal for General Philosophy of Science 33 (2): 381-408. McCain, Kevin and Poston, Ted. (2017). Best Explanations: An Introduction. In K. McCain and T. Poston (eds.), Best Explanations: New Essays on Inference to the Best Explanation (1-6). Oxford: Oxford University Press. Mizrahi, Moti (2012). Why the ultimate argument for scientific realism ultimately fails. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 43 (1):132-138. Mizrahi, Moti (2014). Constructive Empiricism: Normative or Descriptive? International Journal of Philosophical Studies 22 (4):604-616. Monton, Bradley and Mohler, Chad. (2017). Constructive Empiricism. In E. N. Zalta (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2017 Edition). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2017/entries/constructive-empiricism/. Muller, F. A. (2008). In Defence of Constructive Empiricism: Maxwell's Master Argument and Aberrant Theories. Journal for General Philosophy of Science 39 (1): 131-156. Psillos, Stathis (2007). The Fine Structure of Inference to the Best Explanation. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 74 (2): 441-448. 10

Sankey, Howard. (2016). Scientific Realism and the Rationality of Science. New York: Routledge. Schupbach, Jonah N. (2014). Is the Bad Lot Objection Just Misguided? Erkenntnis 79 (1): 55-64. Schwitzgebel, Eric. (2015). Belief. In E. N. Zalta (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2015 Edition). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2015/entries/belief/. Sinnott-Armstrong, Walter and Fogelin, Robert. (2015). Understanding Arguments. Ninth Edition. Stamford, CT: Cengage Learning. Van Dyck, Maarten. (2007). Constructive Empiricism and the Argument from Underdetermination. In Bradley Monton (ed.), Images of Empiricism: Essays on Science and Stances, with a Reply from Bas C. van Fraassen (11-31). New York: Oxford University Press. van Fraassen, B. C. (1980). The Scientific Image. Oxford: Clarendon Press. van Fraassen, B. C. (1985). Empiricism in the Philosophy of Science. In P. M. Churchland & C. A. Hooker (Eds.), Images of Science: Essays on Realism and Empiricism, with a Reply from Bas C. van Fraassen (245-308). Chicago: The University of Chicago Press. van Fraassen, B. C. (1989). Laws and Symmetry. Oxford: Clarendon Press. 11

van Fraassen, B. C. (2000). The False Hopes of Traditional Epistemology. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 60 (2): 253-280. van Fraassen, B. C. (2001). Constructive Empiricism Now. Philosophical Studies 106 (1/2): 151-170. van Fraassen, B. C. (2002). The Empirical Stance. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press. Walton, Douglas. (2005). Abductive Reasoning. Tuscaloosa: The University of Alabama Press. Watling, John. (1964). Review of Foresight and Understanding by Stephen Toulmin. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 15 (58): 164-166. 12