Systems in Legal and Moral Theory. Festschrift for Carlos E. Alchourrón and Eugenio Bulygin, Berlin, 1997.

Similar documents
A Realistic View on Law and Legal Cognition. Riccardo Guastini

Does law have to be effective in order for it to be valid?

Kelsen's Pure Theory of Law

Why Is Legal Reasoning Defeasible?

THE JUDICIAL TRUTH. Francesco Viola

Does Deduction really rest on a more secure epistemological footing than Induction?

Informalizing Formal Logic

Legal Interpretation without Truth

The Logical Structure of Legal Disagreements

Ramsey s belief > action > truth theory.

Legal positivism represents a view about the nature of law. It states that

THE SEMANTIC REALISM OF STROUD S RESPONSE TO AUSTIN S ARGUMENT AGAINST SCEPTICISM

Two conceptions of norms

THE RELATION BETWEEN THE GENERAL MAXIM OF CAUSALITY AND THE PRINCIPLE OF UNIFORMITY IN HUME S THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE

Skepticism and Internalism

CONVENTIONALISM AND NORMATIVITY

Some proposals for understanding narrow content

1 What is conceptual analysis and what is the problem?

AN EPISTEMIC PARADOX. Byron KALDIS

THE MEANING OF OUGHT. Ralph Wedgwood. What does the word ought mean? Strictly speaking, this is an empirical question, about the

Social Rules and Legal Theory

Introduction to Cognitivism; Motivational Externalism; Naturalist Cognitivism

Are There Reasons to Be Rational?

Verificationism. PHIL September 27, 2011

Lecture Notes Oliver Wendell Holmes and Jerome Frank, Legal Realism

Juan Alberto del Real Alcalá*

Ayer on the criterion of verifiability

* Dalhousie Law School, LL.B. anticipated Interpretation and Legal Theory. Andrei Marmor Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992, 193 pp.

Constructing the World, Lecture 4 Revisability and Conceptual Change: Carnap vs. Quine David Chalmers

Vol. II, No. 5, Reason, Truth and History, 127. LARS BERGSTRÖM

Chadwick Prize Winner: Christian Michel THE LIAR PARADOX OUTSIDE-IN

5: Preliminaries to the Argument

Faith and Philosophy, April (2006), DE SE KNOWLEDGE AND THE POSSIBILITY OF AN OMNISCIENT BEING Stephan Torre

NORMS, NORMS, AND NORMS: VALIDITY, EXISTENCE AND REFERENTS OF THE TERM NORM IN ALEXY, CONTE, AND GUASTINI*

THE CONCEPT OF OWNERSHIP by Lars Bergström

Wittgenstein on the Fallacy of the Argument from Pretence. Abstract

REPLY TO LUDLOW Thomas M. Crisp. Oxford Studies in Metaphysics 1 (2004): 37-46

McCOUBREY & WHITE S TEXTBOOK ON JURISPRUDENCE

Wright on response-dependence and self-knowledge

Lecture 3. I argued in the previous lecture for a relationist solution to Frege's puzzle, one which

WHY RELATIVISM IS NOT SELF-REFUTING IN ANY INTERESTING WAY

10. The aim of a theory of law is to reduce chaos and multiplicity to unity. legal theory is science and not volition. It is knowledge of what the

Is and Ought Distinction in Legal Philosophy

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

The Paradox of the stone and two concepts of omnipotence

Theories of propositions

Legal Positivism: the Separation and Identification theses are true.

ELEMENTS OF LOGIC. 1.1 What is Logic? Arguments and Propositions

Nagel, T. The View from Nowhere. New York: Oxford University Press, 1986.

Reply to Robert Koons

Figure 1 Figure 2 U S S. non-p P P

Part II: The Nature of Law and Natural Law

CESNUR The ordinary notion of place of worship

HART ON THE INTERNAL ASPECT OF RULES

Philosophy Of Science On The Moral Neutrality Of Scientific Acceptance

Conceptual Analysis meets Two Dogmas of Empiricism David Chalmers (RSSS, ANU) Handout for Australasian Association of Philosophy, July 4, 2006

POWERS, NECESSITY, AND DETERMINISM

Richard L. W. Clarke, Notes REASONING

xiv Truth Without Objectivity

Contextualism and the Epistemological Enterprise

Briefing Paper. Modern Jurisprudence Dworkin s Deadly Attack on Legal Positivism. November 2012

ON PROMOTING THE DEAD CERTAIN: A REPLY TO BEHRENDS, DIPAOLO AND SHARADIN

Criteria of Identity

On the hard problem of consciousness: Why is physics not enough?

SWINBURNE ON SUBSTANCE DUALISM

Phil 435: Philosophy of Language. P. F. Strawson: On Referring

part one MACROSTRUCTURE Cambridge University Press X - A Theory of Argument Mark Vorobej Excerpt More information

PHILOSOPHICAL PROBLEMS & THE ANALYSIS OF LANGUAGE

Semantic Values? Alex Byrne, MIT

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

History of Modern Philosophy Fall nd Paper Assignment Due: 11/8/2019

-- The search text of this PDF is generated from uncorrected OCR text.

Against the Contingent A Priori

Principles of Legal Interpretation. Mark Greenberg, UCLA. In the large literature on legal interpretation, we find intelligent argument and

Cognitivism about imperatives

A Liar Paradox. Richard G. Heck, Jr. Brown University

VAGUENESS. Francis Jeffry Pelletier and István Berkeley Department of Philosophy University of Alberta Edmonton, Alberta, Canada

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW

356 THE MONIST all Cretans were liars. It can be put more simply in the form: if a man makes the statement I am lying, is he lying or not? If he is, t

Skepticism is True. Abraham Meidan

THE LARGER LOGICAL PICTURE

Quine: Quantifiers and Propositional Attitudes

PHL271 Handout 2: Hobbes on Law and Political Authority. Many philosophers of law treat Hobbes as the grandfather of legal positivism.

Aristotle on the Principle of Contradiction :

Moral requirements are still not rational requirements

Can logical consequence be deflated?

WHY WE REALLY CANNOT BELIEVE THE ERROR THEORY

On Legal and Moral Defeasibility

Let s Bite the Bullet on Deontological Epistemic Justification: A Response to Robert Lockie 1 Rik Peels, Vrije Universiteit Amsterdam.

Carritt, E. F. Anthony Skelton

Williams on Supervaluationism and Logical Revisionism

Naturalized Epistemology. 1. What is naturalized Epistemology? Quine PY4613

Kelsen s Legal Monism and the Future of the European Constitution

Scientific Progress, Verisimilitude, and Evidence

Moral Argument. Jonathan Bennett. from: Mind 69 (1960), pp

10 CERTAINTY G.E. MOORE: SELECTED WRITINGS

Is phenomenal character out there in the world?

Naturalist Cognitivism: The Open Question Argument; Subjectivism

LEGAL STUDIES RESEARCH PAPER SERIES

Transcription:

Riccardo Guastini A Sceptical View on Legal Interpretation 1. Scepticism Defined By scepticism in the province of legal interpretation theories I mean the thesis according to which interpretive statements are neither true nor false. An interpretive statement is a meaning-ascribing sentence, i.e., a sentence to the effect that a legal (e.g., constitutional, statutory, etc.) text T means M or, in a slightly different formulation, that a legal provision P expresses a certain rule R 1. This sceptical thesis does not suppose any particular theory of meaning 2. It is merely the conclusion of the following simple argument. (i) Jurists and judges actually disagree about the meanings of most statutory and constitutional sentences. In other words, most legal provisions are in fact interpreted, at least diachronically, in different ways. (ii) Ab esse ad posse valet consequentia. Therefore most legal provisions are liable to different and competing interpretations. (iii) Nevertheless, no truth-criterion is available for meaning-ascribing sentences at least, nobody was able to identify and defend a convincing criterion. E.g., the theses according to which the truth-criterion of interpretive statements is either the common usage of language or the intention of lawgiving authorities which in fact seem to suggest such criteria are but normative theories of legal interpretation. (iv) As a consequence, any interpretive decision i.e., any act of interpretation accomplished by subjects, such as judges, who apply the law supposes a choice between competing possibilities 3. This amounts to saying that interpreta- 1 Cf. R. Guastini, Interpretive Statements, in E. Garzón Valdés et al. (eds.), Normative Systems in Legal and Moral Theory. Festschrift for Carlos E. Alchourrón and Eugenio Bulygin, Berlin, 1997. 2 The thesis only assumes that words (viz., sentences) have no objective or proper meaning independent of use and understanding. 3 Interpretation accomplished by law-applying organs must not be confused with cognitive interpretation, as accomplished by legal scientists, which consists not in choosing a definite meaning, but in listing in a descriptive mood the various possible meanings of the legal text at issue. Analisi e diritto 2005, a cura di P. Comanducci e R. Guastini

140 tion is not an act of knowledge but rather an «act of will» 4, which always implies discretion. (v) Hence the language of interpreters is not descriptive in character. Interpretive statements are not constative sentences: they lack truth value, i.e., they are not capable of truth or falsity 5. Indeed, they do not describe the one and only supposedly pre-existing meaning; rather, they ascribe meaning. 2. Variety of Interpretive Controversies The statement to the effect that most legal provisions are liable to different and competing interpretations should not be taken to imply that most legal provisions are (strictly speaking) ambiguous, i.e., that they can be interpreted either as expressing a certain rule or as expressing another. Of course ambiguity (semantic and syntactic) is an important source of interpretive perplexities and controversies 6, but it is probably not the main one after all, genuine ambiguity is rather unusual. Other kinds of controversies deserve to be mentioned e.g., the following ones. (a) Sometimes interpreters agree that a certain legal provision P expresses a certain rule R1, but they disagree as to whether P also expresses the rule R2. (b) Sometimes interpreters agree that a certain legal provision P expresses a rule R1, but they disagree as to whether R1 also entails the rule R2. (c) Sometimes interpreters agree that a certain legal provision P expresses a rule R1, but they disagree as to whether R1 is defeasible i.e., subject to implicit and unspecified exceptions 7. Almost all legal sentences can give rise to interpretive questions of the mentioned kinds. 3. Sources of Interpretive Controversies Interpretive controversies are often supposed to spring from certain objective properties (such as ambiguity, vagueness, indeterminacy, etc.) of lawgivers lan- 4 H. Kelsen, Introduction to the Problems of Legal Theory (1934), translated and ed. by B. Litschewski and S. L. Paulson, Oxford, 1992, 82. 5 The obvious reference is to J. L. Austin, How to Do Things with Words, Oxford, 1962. 6 This is especially true of ambiguity affecting whole sentences and stemming (not from their formulation, but) from their context. 7 On the concept of defeasibility cf. C. E. Alchourrón, On Law and Logic, in Ratio Juris, 1996.

141 guage 8. This, however, gives an overly simplified picture of how legal communication actually works. The variety of interpretations of one and the same legal text stems mainly from two others factors (which are absent from everyday communication): first, the variety of commonly accepted interpretive techniques; second, dogmatics, i.e., the variety of juristic doctrines. Different interpretive methods such as analogy, distinguishing, argument a contrariis, and so on lead to conflicting interpretive results. Juristic doctrines such as the doctrine of parliamentary government, the doctrine of the rule of law, the doctrine of torts, the doctrine of contracts, etc. are logically independent of interpretation (being construed by jurists prior to interpretation and independently of the interpretation of any specified legal text) but nevertheless influence interpretation, either by turning it in a particular direction or by excluding certain interpretive choices. 4. Interpretation and Law Creation Distinguished In a sense, interpretation is the very source of legal rules, since «it is only words that the legislature utters», and legal texts «do not interpret themselves» 9. I mean that law-giving authorities issue not meanings (rules), but just sentences, whose normative meaning contents i.e., the expressed rules are to be detected by means of interpretation 10. This is not to say that legal sentences have no meaning at all before interpretation. Scepticism claims only that, prior to interpretation legal sentences have no definite meaning, since they are liable to different interpretations. Nevertheless, interpretation is to be distinguished from the creation of new rules. A legal sentence typically admits of a number of interpretations but it does not admit any interpretation whatsoever. Following Kelsen, one may say that each legal sentence provides interpreters with a framework of possible meanings 11. Such a framework depends on the rules of the language at stake, the methods of interpretation commonly accepted, juristic doctrines, precedents, etc. It may happen, however, that a particular interpreter (e.g., a judge) breaks out of the framework, and ascribes to a legal sentence a new meaning which is not included in the framework. Such an ascription of meaning is not a suitable move in the game of interpretation strictly understood it amounts to the creation of a new rule. 8 Cf. e.g. A. Ross, On Law and Justice, London, 1958, 111 ff. 9 J. C. Gray, The Nature and Sources of the Law, second edition from the author s notes, by R. Gray, New York, 1948, 170, 125. 10 G. Tarello, L interpretazione della legge, Milano, 1980. 11 H. Kelsen, Introduction to the Problems of Legal Theory, 80 f.

142 5. Hard and Soft Scepticism The soft form of scepticism defended in this paper 12 is not to be confused with what I shall call hard scepticism. According to hard scepticism, in the game of legal interpretation anything goes : interpreters, namely supreme courts judges, can ascribe to any legal text any meaning whatsoever, making it impossible to distinguish between genuine interpretation (i.e., the choice of one definite meaning within a framework of admissible meanings) and the creation of new rules 13. Prima facie, hard scepticism seems to be supported by a thesis of Kelsen s, viz., the thesis according to which, in most legal systems, positive law attaches legal effects to any interpretive decision whatsoever that may happen to be enacted by a law-applying organ. In other words, positive law does not distinguish between interpretive decisions falling within the framework of admissible meanings and interpretive decisions falling outside such a framework 14 : all interpretive decisions of law-applying organs have the same legal consequences, viz., they create individual norms in force. Kelsen s thesis is quite correct. However, it is immaterial to the theory of legal interpretation. Kelsen here provides nothing more than a description of positive law. Perhaps all interpretations are, in a sense, equivalent from the point of view of positive law, but they are not equivalent from the standpoint of the theory of legal interpretation, which investigates interpretation as such, not the positive rules which govern the legal effects of interpretive decisions. Kelsen s thesis in no way denies the distinction between interpretive decisions within and outside the framework; and that distinction is of utmost significance for the analysis of actual interpretative practices. 6. Text-oriented and Fact-oriented Interpretation Two kinds of interpretation should be sharply distinguished. (i) Text-oriented, or in abstracto, interpretation amounts to ascribing meaning to a legal text i.e., deciding which rules such a text expresses without attention to any particular case 15. Text-oriented interpretation resembles translation: it consists in giving the interpreted text a new formulation, i.e., translating the lawgivers language into the language of the interpreter. Accordingly, 12 Supra, 4. 13 M. Troper, La théorie du droit, le droit, l État, Paris, 2001, 69 ff. 14 H. Kelsen, Théorie pure du droit (1960), traduction par Ch. Eisenmann, Paris, 1962, 453 ff. 15 Rules attach legal consequences (obligations, rights, sanctions, etc.) to classes of cases.

143 its result is a new text purportedly synonymous with the original one. (ii) Fact-oriented, or in concreto, interpretation, in turn, amounts to subsuming an individual case under a rule, i.e., to deciding whether or not an individual case falls within the scope of a given rule (belongs to the class of cases subject to the rule). Its output, in continental jurists language, is the legal qualification of the facts of the case. Text-oriented interpretation is interpretation in the strict sense. Fact-oriented interpretation simply amounts to the application of law. Text-oriented interpretation affects the major premiss of a judicial syllogism, while fact-oriented interpretation affects the minor premiss 16. 7. Scepticism vs. Open Texture Theory Nowadays, the most influential theory of legal interpretation assumes that the main problems of interpretation depend on the open texture of language. Any legal provision has a core of settled meaning side by side with an area of penumbra or so the theory runs. Accordingly, two classes of cases can be distinguished: easy cases (which fall within the core) and hard cases (which fall within the penumbra). Law-applying organs have no interpretive discretion in clear or easy cases, where a right answer is provided directly by the law, while any interpretive decision is discretional when a hard or borderline case is at hand 17. In easy cases interpretive statements are true or false; only in hard cases are they not. This view is correct as far as fact-oriented interpretation i.e., the application of rules to individual cases is concerned. Fact-oriented interpretation, however, aims at determining the scope of rules. Therefore it presupposes the previous identification of the rules at issue. In other words, it presupposes text-oriented interpretation. But the main problems of interpretation do not pertain to the application of previously identified rules. Rather they pertain primarily to the identification of rules themselves, i.e., to the process of extracting rules (meaning contents) from legal sentences 18. The open texture theory completely disregards the problems of text-oriented interpretation. 16 Cf. M. Troper, La théorie du droit, le droit, l État, 106 ff. 17 Cf. e. g. H. L. A. Hart, The Concept of Law, Oxford, 1961, 124 ff.; N. MacCormick, Legal Reasoning and Legal Theory, Oxford, 1978, 195 ff.; C. Luzzati, La vaghezza delle norme. Un analisi del linguaggio giuridico, Milano, 1990; G. R. Carrió, Notas sobre derecho y lenguaje, 4th ed., Buenos Aires, 1994, 49 ff.; J. J. Moreso, La indeterminación del derecho y la interpretación de la Constitución, Madrid, 1997, 108 ff.; E. Diciotti, Interpretazione della legge e discorso razionale, Torino, 1999, 367 ff.; T. Endicott, Vagueness in Law, Oxoford, 2000. 18 Supra, 2.

144 The open texture theory therefore gives a seriously misleading picture of legal interpretation, since interpretive discretion relates almost entirely to textoriented interpretation, rather than to subsumption. As far as text-oriented interpretation is concerned no right answer exists, since various answers, i.e., alternative interpretations, are always available, and, from a purely descriptive point of view, no one of them can be deemed right.