Merely Mechanistic Laws : Causal Mechanism and Kant s Antinomy of the Teleological Power of Judgment. Thomas Teufel

Similar documents
Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy

Kant on Biology and the Experience of Life

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel s Idealism

Kant On The A Priority of Space: A Critique Arjun Sawhney - The University of Toronto pp. 4-7

THE STUDY OF UNKNOWN AND UNKNOWABILITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY

Tuukka Kaidesoja Précis of Naturalizing Critical Realist Social Ontology

To appear in The Journal of Philosophy.

Comments on Ontological Anti-Realism

1/12. The A Paralogisms

Is there a good epistemological argument against platonism? DAVID LIGGINS

Sidgwick on Practical Reason

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

Freedom as Morality. UWM Digital Commons. University of Wisconsin Milwaukee. Hao Liang University of Wisconsin-Milwaukee. Theses and Dissertations

From Transcendental Logic to Transcendental Deduction

Kantian Humility and Ontological Categories Sam Cowling University of Massachusetts, Amherst

Charles Hartshorne argues that Kant s criticisms of Anselm s ontological

1/10. The Fourth Paralogism and the Refutation of Idealism

Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics 1. By Tom Cumming

Stabilizing Kant s First and Second Critiques: Causality and Freedom

DEFEASIBLE A PRIORI JUSTIFICATION: A REPLY TO THUROW

Review of David J. Chalmers Constructing the World (OUP 2012) David Chalmers burst onto the philosophical scene in the mid-1990s with his work on

From the Categorical Imperative to the Moral Law

Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000)

Can Rationality Be Naturalistically Explained? Jeffrey Dunn. Abstract: Dan Chiappe and John Vervaeke (1997) conclude their article, Fodor,

A Freewheeling Defense of Kant s Resolution of the Third Antinomy

Reply to Lorne Falkenstein RAE LANGTON. Edinburgh University

1/5. The Critique of Theology

* Dalhousie Law School, LL.B. anticipated Interpretation and Legal Theory. Andrei Marmor Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992, 193 pp.

ALTERNATIVE SELF-DEFEAT ARGUMENTS: A REPLY TO MIZRAHI

A note on Bishop s analysis of the causal argument for physicalism.

Varieties of Apriority

1/9. The Second Analogy (1)

By submitting this essay, I attest that it is my own work, completed in accordance with University regulations. Minh Alexander Nguyen

This is a repository copy of Making Modal Distinctions: Kant on the possible, the actual, and the intuitive intellect..

The Coherence of Kant s Synthetic A Priori

DISCUSSION THE GUISE OF A REASON

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

Rethinking Knowledge: The Heuristic View

1/6. The Resolution of the Antinomies

proper construal of Davidson s principle of rationality will show the objection to be misguided. Andrew Wong Washington University, St.

Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible?

POWERS, NECESSITY, AND DETERMINISM

ABSTRACT of the Habilitation Thesis

The Groundwork, the Second Critique, Pure Practical Reason and Motivation

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

METHODISM AND HIGHER-LEVEL EPISTEMIC REQUIREMENTS Brendan Murday

It doesn t take long in reading the Critique before we are faced with interpretive challenges. Consider the very first sentence in the A edition:

Kant s Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysic of Morals

On Some Alleged Consequences Of The Hartle-Hawking Cosmology. In [3], Quentin Smith claims that the Hartle-Hawking cosmology is inconsistent with

How Successful Is Naturalism?

Is Kant's Account of Free Will Coherent?

Kant s Freedom and Transcendental Idealism

7AAN2039 Kant I: Critique of Pure Reason Syllabus Academic year 2015/16

Ayer and Quine on the a priori

FREEDOM AND THE SOURCE OF VALUE: KORSGAARD AND WOOD ON KANT S FORMULA OF HUMANITY CHRISTOPHER ARROYO

Under contract with Oxford University Press Karen Bennett Cornell University

Does Deduction really rest on a more secure epistemological footing than Induction?

Conditions of Fundamental Metaphysics: A critique of Jorge Gracia's proposal

The linguistic-cultural nature of scientific truth 1

Understanding How we Come to Experience Purposive. Behavior. Jacob Roundtree. Colby College Mayflower Hill, Waterville, ME USA

Received: 30 August 2007 / Accepted: 16 November 2007 / Published online: 28 December 2007 # Springer Science + Business Media B.V.

The normativity of content and the Frege point

Chapter 24. Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel: The Concepts of Being, Non-being and Becoming

Some Pragmatic Themes in Kant s Critique of Pure Reason

Idealism and the Harmony of Thought and Reality

Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly *

Orthodox truthmaker theory cannot be defended by cost/benefit analysis

Moral Argument. Jonathan Bennett. from: Mind 69 (1960), pp

BOOK REVIEWS. Duke University. The Philosophical Review, Vol. XCVII, No. 1 (January 1988)

NATURALISED JURISPRUDENCE

A Most Affecting View: Transcendental Affection as Causation De-Schematized. Chad Mohler

Epistemological Externalism and the Project of Traditional Epistemology. Contemporary philosophers still haven't come to terms with the project of

Huemer s Problem of Memory Knowledge

Important dates. PSY 3360 / CGS 3325 Historical Perspectives on Psychology Minds and Machines since David Hume ( )

Shafer-Landau's defense against Blackburn's supervenience argument

Logical Mistakes, Logical Aliens, and the Laws of Kant's Pure General Logic Chicago February 21 st 2018 Tyke Nunez

Nagel, Naturalism and Theism. Todd Moody. (Saint Joseph s University, Philadelphia)

1/9. The First Analogy

Chapter 5: Freedom and Determinism

Moral Relativism and Conceptual Analysis. David J. Chalmers

Elements of Mind (EM) has two themes, one major and one minor. The major theme is

In Kant s Conception of Humanity, Joshua Glasgow defends a traditional reading of

Self-Evidence and A Priori Moral Knowledge

Intro. The need for a philosophical vocabulary

Unifying the Categorical Imperative* Marcus Arvan University of Tampa

[JGRChJ 9 (2013) R28-R32] BOOK REVIEW

The Question of Metaphysics

Introductory Kant Seminar Lecture

What God Could Have Made

This handout follows the handout on The nature of the sceptic s challenge. You should read that handout first.

Ayer s linguistic theory of the a priori

1/8. The Third Analogy

Philosophy 125 Day 13: Overview

Philosophical Issues, vol. 8 (1997), pp

All philosophical debates not due to ignorance of base truths or our imperfect rationality are indeterminate.

No Dilemma for the Proponent of the Transcendental Argument: A Response to David Reiter

The Impossibility of Evil Qua Evil: Kantian Limitations on Human Immorality

Transcription:

Merely Mechanistic Laws : Causal Mechanism and Kant s Antinomy of the Teleological Power of Judgment Thomas Teufel Department of Philosophy, Baruch College, The City University of New York, One Bernard Baruch Way, New York, NY 10010, USA, thomas.teufel@baruch.cuny.edu Over the last 20 years, a consensus has emerged on the interpretation of Kant s Antinomy in the Dialectic of the Critique of the Teleological Power of Judgment. 1 At the heart of this consensus lies Peter McLaughlin s reading of the Antinomy, proposed in his 1989 Kants Kritik der Teleologischen Urteilskraft. 2 The core of McLaughlin s view has been endorsed by a broad range of commentators on Kant s third Critique (including Henry Allison, 3 John Zammito, 4 and Hannah Ginsborg 5 ) and has been questioned by critics only on tangential methodological grounds 6 culminating in John Zammito s 2006 verdict that McLaughlin s take on the Dialectic is the reigning wisdom 7 on this (the central) part of Kant s Teleology. A consensus, of course, need not be indicative of a convergence upon truth and in this case, I am afraid, it is not. In what follows I will say very little about McLaughlin s resolution of the Antinomy in terms of an alleged distinction between mechanism and causality. 8 While this is perhaps the best-known feature of McLaughlin s interpretation and one that harbors difficulties of its own it is McLaughlin s conception of the nature of the antinomical conflict (hence of just what tension needs resolving) that I am interested in 1 All translations from Kant s works follow (with occasional slight modifications) Guyer, Paul and Wood, Allen, eds.: The Cambridge Edition of the Works of Immanuel Kant [Cambridge Edition], 17 vols. Cambridge. 1995. 2 McLaughlin, Peter: Kants Kritik der Teleologischen Urteilskraft. Bonn. 1989. Idem: Kant s Critique of Teleology in Biological Explanation. Lewiston, NY. 1991. Idem: Newtonian Biology and Kant s Mechanistic Concept of Causality. In: Guyer, Paul (ed.): Kant s Critique of the Power of Judgment. Lanham, MD. 2003. 3 Allison, Henry: Kant s Antinomy of Teleological Judgment. In: Guyer, Paul (ed.): Kant s Critique of the Power of Judgment. Lanham, MD. 2003. 4 Zamitto, John: Teleology Then and Now: the Question of Kant s Relevance for Contemporary Controversies over Function in Biology. In: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 37.4. 2006, 759. 5 Ginsborg, Hannah: Two Kinds of Mechanical Inexplicability in Kant and Aristotle. In: Journal of the History of Philosophy 42.1. 2004, 35-7. 6 Guyer, Paul: Kant s System of Nature and Freedom. Oxford. 2005, 338n. 7 Zammito (2006) 759. 8 See McLaughlin (2003) 214-5. 1

here. In the first part of my paper, I sketch two competing ways in which the antinomical conflict can be construed: as concerning the problem of the occasional impossibility (or at least non-necessity), or as concerning the problem of the occasional insufficiency of mechanistic judging. In the second part, I argue that the reigning wisdom, in settling for the former interpretation, misconstrues (and, quite possibly, simply ignores) the pivotal detail that Kant is concerned with the explanatory prowess not of mechanistic laws but of merely mechanistic laws. Once we give this detail its proper due, we see that the reigning wisdom on Kant s Antinomy (hence, Dialectic) does not address Kant s Antinomy (hence, Dialectic). I. The Elements of the Antinomical Conflict As in each of Kant s three Critiques, a Dialectic is the part of the text in which Kant presents sets of equally natural and unavoidable 9 yet prima facie conflicting philosophical principles, whose conflict can only be resolved (that is to say, revealed as merely apparent) through the resources of the transcendental laws governing the respective Critique s domain. 10 Kant calls such an unavoidable yet transcendentally resolvable conflict an Antinomy. The antinomical conflict, which the transcendental resources of the third Critique are to help resolve in the Dialectic of the Critique of the Teleological Power of Judgment, is a conflict between two maxims concerning causal mechanism. The first of these maxims proclaims causal mechanism s unlimited explanatory sway, the second seeks to limit it. Three elements of this Antinomy, in particular, require our attention: first, Kant s notion of mechanism; second, the circumstance that the Antinomy is a conflict between maxims; third, the fact that the Antinomy concerns the explanatory sway not of mechanistic laws but of merely mechanistic laws. The fact that Kant frequently invokes causal mechanism in the third Critique (a topic mostly absent from the Critique of Pure Reason) reflects his recognition first 9 Allison, Henry: Kant s Transcendental Idealism. Yale. 2004, 308. 10 Kant argues in the introduction to the third Critique that the (reflecting) power of judgment does not have its own domain but only a territory (KU, AA 05: 177) over which it legislates. While this does affect the nature of the transcendental resources in question (specifically, it determines that the transcendental principle of purposiveness be a heautonomous, or procedural, principle in and through which judgment legislates to itself), it does not change the general logic by which the Antinomy finds a transcendental resolution. 2

expressed in the 1786 Metaphysical Foundations of Natural Science 11 and again in the Introduction to the Critique of the Power of Judgment 12 that critical philosophy must distinguish between transcendental and metaphysical forms of its principles. Kant explains that transcendental principles determine their objects only through ontological predicates (pure concepts of the understanding) (KU, AA 05: 181), while their metaphysical reformulations presuppose empirical concepts. Kant s primary example of this is the causal principle. Kant notes that the transcendental causal principle (that every event has a cause, i.e., the category of causality) presupposes the ontological concept of a changeable substance[] (KU, AA 05: 181). Because of the principle s consequent high level of abstraction, it is compatible with metaphysical interpretations of causal change (e.g., hylozoistic or monist) that are inconsistent with the specifically Newtonian conception of causality Kant ultimately sought to justify in the Critique of Pure Reason. The critical justification of that conception, Kant recognized in the Foundations, would have to be the justification of a causal principle that made metaphysical presuppositions. In particular, it would have to be the critical justification of a causal principle that made use of the empirical concept of a body (as a moveable thing in space) (KU, AA 05: 181). Presupposing this concept, a causal principle fully consistent with the Newtonian understanding of causal change follows entirely a priori (ibid.), namely, that change in a movable thing in space must have an external cause (ibid., my emphasis). It follows that, the critical justification of the Newtonian view of causal change amounts to the critical justification of the metaphysical causal principle that every material event has an external cause. 13 Since this metaphysical causal principle presupposes the materiality of the causal relata and since it emphasizes the consequent externality of the causal relation, it is closely related to the science of mechanics 14 and, in that sense, a principle of causal mechanism. The topic of causal mechanism looms large in the Critique of the Teleological Power of Judgment, not because Kant there revisits the issue of its transcendental 11 See, e.g., MAN, AA 04: 546. 12 See KU, AA 05: 181. 13 See Westphal, Kenneth R.: Kant s Transcendental Proof of Realism. Cambridge. 2004, 128f., 157ff., 171. 14 See Allison (2003) 221. 3

justification (he attempts that justification in the Foundations), 15 but because (assuming causal mechanism to be transcendentally well-grounded) Kant discusses the puzzling possibility of an empirical irregularity testing mechanism s clockwork efficiency. He detects this possibility in a recalcitrant tribe of moveable thing in space: organisms. In order to understand the nature of Kant s interest in organisms, the next important thing to note is that the Antinomy is a conflict between maxims (i.e., between merely subjective principles of action). Unlike other such conflicts in Kant s oeuvre, this one is, then, not a conflict between competing metaphysical visions of an ultimate reality. Instead, it is a conflict between competing epistemic principles guiding empirical investigation, or regulative principles for research (KU, AA 05: 387). Accordingly, Kant is interested in organisms as presenting the occasion for an antinomical conflict between principles of judgment. If to say that the conflicting principles are principles of judgment is to highlight their status as subjective rather than objective principles, this is not to suggest, however, that these regulative principles are wholly optional. If the maxims were optional, then no unavoidable conflict could arise between them. What creates the conflict here is, specifically, that the first of the maxims is supposedly an a priori constraint on our judging of natural origins, whose unlimited reign the second, empirically based maxim, denies. The first maxim is this: All generation of material things and their forms must be judged as possible in accordance with merely mechanistic laws. (KU, AA 05: 387). Reformulated in terms of the metaphysical causal principle, it is the maxim that: All generation of material things and their forms must be judged as possible in accordance with laws governing the interactions of movable bodies in space. Kant explains the nonoptional nature of the maxim s prescription by noting that the maxim is provided to [the power of judgment] a priori by the understanding (KU, AA 05: 386). Now, the idea of a principle that is supposed to be both an epistemic heuristic for the power of judgment and, at the same time, a priori and necessary, certainly seems rather odd. The mystery does not run very deep, however. The principle of mechanistic judging is a mere maxim for the power of judgment because there simply is no a priori necessity to dictate that intellects like ours must investigate questions of natural origin or of the generation of 15 See Westphal (2004) ch. 6. 4

material things. However, if we choose to employ our power of judgment in the service of investigating questions of natural origin, then the maxim demands our answers must be mechanistic answers. The competing second maxim is a denial of this mechanistic imperative. It proclaims that: Some products of material nature cannot be judged as possible in accordance with merely mechanistic laws (KU, AA 05: 387). Kant notes that this maxim is occasioned by particular experiences (KU, AA 05: 386). And he adds to the maxim the parenthetical remark that judging them [the products of nature in question] requires an entirely different law of causality, namely that of final causes (KU, AA 05: 387). Accordingly, by denying the mechanistic imperative on the basis of contravening experience the second maxim seeks to make room for final causality and teleology. It is important to note that the Antinomy thus does not address, positively, what sort of causality final causality is, nor what it is about some products of material nature (ibid.) that might trigger their teleological demand on us. Instead, the Antinomy narrowly addresses the question whether there is any room, among explanatory approaches to natural phenomena, for explanations that are not mechanistic. But this way of putting what is at issue in the Antinomy is not yet free from ambiguity. The question raised by the second maxim s denial of an explanatory strategy based on mechanism can be construed in two different ways. It can either be construed as the question whether non-mechanistic explanations are sometimes required in addition to mechanistic explanations (where the latter are, however, also necessary). On this construal, what is being denied by the second maxim is mechanism s sufficiency for explaining certain natural phenomena. Or it can be construed as the question whether non-mechanistic explanations are sometimes required as opposed to mechanistic explanations (where the latter are in principle unavailable). On this construal, what is being denied by the second maxim is mechanism s necessity for explaining the phenomena in question on the ground that a mechanistic explanation of genuinely nonmechanistic phenomena is impossible. Which of these challenges we take the Antinomy to address determines what sort of resolution the Antinomy admits of. If non-mechanistic explanations were sometimes required in addition to mechanism, then this requirement cannot rest on empirical 5

grounds (for, ex hypothesi, on those grounds mechanism holds without fail). Their requirement can, then, only rest on either psychological or transcendental grounds. The resolution of the Antinomy would, accordingly, have to be either deflationist or transcendental idealist. Conversely, if non-mechanistic explanations were sometimes required as opposed to mechanistic explanations, then this requirement would have to rest on empirical grounds (since the presumed failure of mechanism can only be established by actual experience of non-mechanistic forms of causality). 16 The resolution of the Antinomy would, accordingly, have to appeal to teleological realist considerations. 17 Which of these Antinomies is Kant s? Hence, what exactly is being denied by the second maxim s denial of an explanatory strategy based on mechanistic laws: the sufficiency or the possibility (or at least the necessity) of mechanistic explanations of certain natural phenomena? The answer to this question depends almost entirely on the significance of Kant s carefully placed adverb merely in the maxims. We thus need to sharpen our focus. For, the first maxim pointedly asserts and the second maxim equally pointedly denies that all generation of material things must be judged in accordance with merely [bloß] mechanistic laws (KU, AA 05: 387). The pertinent thing to ask of the Antinomy, accordingly, is this: what is being denied by the second maxim s denial of an explanatory strategy based on merely mechanistic laws? The answer to this question is complicated by the fact that there is a potential slide in Kant s merely from the laudatory to the derogatory. 18 And it is only a mild exaggeration to say that everything in Kant s Teleology hangs on which rhetorical posture we see him adopt here. The slide in question is one from an emphasis on essentiality to an emphasis on triviality. It is the sort of shift in perspective that would greet us if we awoke to a world in which Kant s Critique of Mere Reason was a classic of Western philosophy. Thus, the answer to our question ( what is being denied by the second maxim s denial of an explanatory strategy based on merely mechanistic laws? ) rides on 16 Once a phenomenon is confirmed as a genuinely non-mechanistic phenomenon, a mechanistic explanation of it is then, ipso facto, impossible. 17 This is indeed the direction in which McLaughlin takes things, when he argues that a form of causality that is not mechanistic but that, nevertheless, is governed by the (metaphysical) causal principle is both ontologically and experientially possible. See McLaughlin, Peter (1989) 138f., 156f. See idem: What Functions Explain. Cambridge. 2001, 27, 173. 18 Cf., Melville, Stephen: Notes on the Reemergence of Allegory. In: Seams: Art as Philosophical Context. Amsterdam. 1996, 153ff. 6

whether Kant uses merely in an applauding sense, evoking ideas of unmixed purity, or in a disparaging sense, playing on ideas of limitation and impotence. If the first, then to deny that certain products of nature can be judged in accordance with merely mechanistic laws (KU, AA 05: 387, my emphasis) would place the emphasis on the adverb and hence on the exclusive use of the laws in question. This would suggest that mechanistic laws are fully called for in judging those products but that they alone (somehow) fail to do the explanatory trick. Pure mechanism is insufficient an admixture of further explanatory principles is needed. If the second, then to deny that certain products of nature can be judged in accordance with merely mechanistic laws (ibid., my emphasis) would place the emphasis on the adjective and hence on the mechanistic nature of the laws in question. Mechanism would stand indicted as providing no basis for judging phenomena whose exalted characteristics lie so patently beyond its humble reach. With mechanistic explanations of these non-mechanistic characteristics thus impossible, an altogether different form of explanation is necessary. II. The Nature of the Antinomical Conflict Peter McLaughlin (and the reigning wisdom on the Dialectic) understands the antinomical conflict in the Dialectic in the second sense. As McLaughlin puts it, Kant s antinomical conflict is one between the global necessity and the local impossibility of the mechanistic manner of explanation. 19 Treating Kant s second maxim as advocating that local impossibility, McLaughlin evidently does not think that Kant inserts the adverb merely into the maxim s denial of an explanatory strategy based on mechanistic laws in order to challenge the sufficiency, in local cases, of mechanism s reign. Given the dialectic of merely discussed in Part I, this means that McLaughlin either takes the qualifier merely in its derogatory sense 20 or, else, that he ignores it altogether. I myself will ignore the latter, uncharitable interpretation and argue, only, that it would be a serious mistake to think that Kant uses the adverb merely in the second maxim in a derogatory sense. Three considerations make this clear. First, Kant was, of 19 McLaughlin (1989) 152, my emphasis. 20 This sense is evident, also, in the interpretation of Henry Allison, one of whose emendations (Allison, 2003, 233, n.1) of Werner Pluhar s translation is to render Kant s bloß as the trivializing simply (ibid., 224) in Kant s subsequent formulation of the first maxim. It is in this formulation that Allison finally takes the maxim to be properly construed (ibid.). 7

course, an ardent, lifelong Newtonian. It is simply implausible that, just in order to accommodate teleology, he would preface talk of mechanistic laws with intentionally belittling qualifiers. Kant did not take Sir Isaac for a joke. Second, even if Kant s intent in the second maxim was to propose limits on the reign of mechanism, it makes no strategic sense that he should employ intentionally belittling qualifiers already in the first maxim whose purpose would have to be to present mechanism unfettered by the sought-for limits. But we need not rely on intuitions about the strength of Kant s Newtonianism or the finer points of argumentative strategy. For, third, and most importantly, Kant is fully explicit about what is not being denied by his second maxim, noting that it is also not thereby said that those forms [in nature] would not be possible in accordance with the mechanism of nature (KU, AA 05: 388, my emphasis). Since that is, however, exactly what would be said, had Kant intended the merely as a swipe at mechanistic laws (or omitted it altogether), it follows (given the dialectic of merely discussed in Part I), that Kant must be using merely in the applauding sense discussed. Anticipating just the sort of reading that has now, despite his best efforts, become exegetical orthodoxy, Kant thus explicitly seeks to forestall interpretations according to which his second maxim advocates the possibility of objects that cannot be judged mechanistically. Kant could not be more clear: even if we reflect on certain forms of nature teleologically, reflection in accordance with the first maxim is not thereby suspended (KU, AA 05: 388, my emphasis). To be sure, Kant does go on to say that one can press mechanistic explanations only as far as one can (ibid.). But, since teleological reflection does not entail the suspension of mechanistic reflection, an inability to press mechanistic explanations further can only mark the sort of contingent inexplicability that any investigation of natural phenomena is sooner or later bound to encounter. It cannot mark the phenomenon at hand as of the genuinely non-mechanistic sort that would make a mechanistic explanation of it impossible. What does this mean for the nature of the antinomical conflict in the Teleology? Just this: if Kant s second maxim does not deny the possibility of a mechanistic explanation of objects whose judging nonetheless also requires an entirely different law of causality, then the second maxim is simply not in conflict with the requirement that 8

we judge all products of nature (including the ones that call for alternative forms of explanation) in accordance with mechanistic laws. The first maxim demands that every judging of natural origins must be a mechanistic judging; the second maxim leaves this unopposed, conceding that every judging of natural origins may indeed be a mechanistic judging. The universal necessity of mechanistic judging, therefore, is simply not contested in Kant s Antinomy. The second maxim is in conflict only with the requirement that we always judge in accordance with mechanistic laws alone. Kant s Antinomy in the Critique of the Teleological Power of Judgment can, then, be presented as follows. Given that our judgments of natural origins must always be mechanistic, those judgments must then either i. always be only mechanistic (Thesis), or ii. not always be only mechanistic (Antithesis). 9