ON EFFICIENT CAUSALITY: METAPHYSICAL DISPUTATIONS 17,18, AND 19. By FRANCISCO SUAREZ. Translated By ALFRED J. FREDDOSO. New Haven:

Similar documents
THE ORDINATIO OF BLESSED JOHN DUNS SCOTUS. Book Two. First Distinction (page 16)

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy

Purple Haze: The Puzzle of Consciousness

xiv Truth Without Objectivity

Ibn Sina on Substances and Accidents

1/8. Leibniz on Force

270 Now that we have settled these issues, we should answer the first question [n.

Curriculum Vitae. Assistant Professor, Department of Philosophy, Syracuse University, August 2008

QUESTION 44. The Procession of Creatures from God, and the First Cause of All Beings

131 seventeenth-century news

1 Why should you care about metametaphysics?

Comments and notice of errors from readers are most welcome. Peter L.P. Simpson June, 2016

First Treatise <Chapter 1. On the Eternity of Things>

1/13. Locke on Power

On What There Is in Aquinas

PHILOSOPHY OF NATURE LET THOMAS AQUINAS TEACH IT. Joseph Kenny, O.P. St. Thomas Aquinas Priory Ibadan, Nigeria

WHAT ARISTOTLE TAUGHT

William Ockham on Universals

The Five Ways THOMAS AQUINAS ( ) Thomas Aquinas: The five Ways

Aquinas on the Beginning and End of Human Life

Cosmological arguments for the Existence of God Gerald Jones Dialogue Issue 26 April 2006

Comments on Leibniz and Pantheism by Robert Adams for The Twelfth Annual NYU Conference on Issues in Modern Philosophy: God

FOLLOWING CHRIST IN THE WORLD

On happiness in Locke s decision-ma Title being )

Warrant and accidentally true belief

Jonathan Edwards and Free Will

Hume Against Spinoza and Aristotle. Hume Studies Volume XVII, Number 2 (November, 1991) Frank J. Leavitt 208.

Under contract with Oxford University Press Karen Bennett Cornell University

1/6. The Second Analogy (2)

REVIEW. St. Thomas Aquinas. By RALPH MCINERNY. The University of Notre Dame Press 1982 (reprint of Twayne Publishers 1977). Pp $5.95.

Why to Get Rid of the Small Flitting Images: Descartes s Optics and Some Medieval Theories of Vision

Form, Substance, and Mechanism

Lecture 25 Hume on Causation

Aristotle and Aquinas

BOOK REVIEW: Gideon Yaffee, Manifest Activity: Thomas Reid s Theory of Action

Every simple idea has a simple impression, which resembles it; and every simple impression a correspondent idea

Unifying the Categorical Imperative* Marcus Arvan University of Tampa

A Framework for the Good

Fundamentals of Metaphysics

BOOK REVIEWS AND NOTICES

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View

Practical Rationality and Ethics. Basic Terms and Positions

AQUINAS S FOURTH WAY: FROM GRADATIONS OF BEING

The British Empiricism

Dr. Tuomas E. Tahko 12 January 2012

2017 Philosophy. Higher. Finalised Marking Instructions

PHIL 370: Medieval Philosophy [semester], Coastal Carolina University Class meeting times: [date, time, location]

DESCARTES ON THE OBJECTIVE REALITY OF MATERIALLY FALSE IDEAS

Francisco Suárez, S. J. DE SCIENTIA DEI FUTURORUM CONTINGENTIUM 1.8 1

Scholasticism I INTRODUCTION

Who or what is God?, asks John Hick (Hick 2009). A theist might answer: God is an infinite person, or at least an

Ayer s linguistic theory of the a priori

Humean Supervenience: Lewis (1986, Introduction) 7 October 2010: J. Butterfield

IN his paper, 'Does Tense Logic Rest Upon a Mistake?' (to appear

The Neo-Platonic Proof

A Complex Eternity. One of the central issues in the philosophy of religion is the relationship between

Anaximander. Book Review. Umberto Maionchi Carlo Rovelli Forthcoming, Dunod

Aristotle and the Soul

The Middle Path: A Case for the Philosophical Theologian. Leo Strauss roots the vitality of Western civilization in the ongoing conflict between

-- The search text of this PDF is generated from uncorrected OCR text.

Kant s Transcendental Idealism

What does it mean if we assume the world is in principle intelligible?

ACTA PHILOSOPHICA, vol. 8 (1999), fasc. 1/recensioni

c:=} up over the question of a "Christian philosophy." Since it

Thomas Aquinas. Summa Theologiae la Translated, with Introduction and Commentary, by. Robert Pasnau

McKenzie Study Center, an Institute of Gutenberg College. Handout 5 The Bible and the History of Ideas Teacher: John A. Jack Crabtree.

Aquinas on Spiritual Change. In "Is an Aristotelian Philosophy of Mind Still Credible? (A draft)," Myles

Reading a Philosophy Text Philosophy 22 Fall, 2019

Summula philosophiae naturalis (Summary of Natural Philosophy)

Questions on Book III of the De anima 1

Descartes is commonly regarded as the origin of mind body dualism and

Henry of Ghent on Divine Illumination

The Philosophical Review, Vol. 110, No. 3. (Jul., 2001), pp

out in his Three Dialogues and Principles of Human Knowledge, gives an argument specifically

Aquinas' Third Way Modalized

THE PREPARATION OE A LAY APOSTLE

You will be assigned a primary source reading that will address the following question from a particular perspective. What is the meaning of life?

R. G. Collingwood, An Essay on Metaphysics, Clarendon Press, Oxford p : the term cause has at least three different senses:

Creighton University, Oct. 13, 2016 Midwest Area Workshop on Metaphysics, Oct. 14, 2016

The Summa Lamberti on the Properties of Terms

Reading Questions for Phil , Fall 2013 (Daniel)

Time 1867 words Principles of Philosophy God cosmological argument

Moral Obligation. by Charles G. Finney

POWERS, NECESSITY, AND DETERMINISM

Change in the Monad Martha Brandt Bolton March, It is well known that in the Aristotelian-scholastic metaphysics, the nature of a

Cartesian Rationalism

Philosophy of Nature, Philosophy of the Soul, Metaphysics

Metaphysical atomism and the attraction of materialism.

WHY IS GOD GOOD? EUTYPHRO, TIMAEUS AND THE DIVINE COMMAND THEORY

Dartmouth College THE DIVINE SIMPLICITY *

Thomas Aquinas on the World s Duration. Summa Theologiae Ia Q46: The Beginning of the Duration of Created Things

THE FREEDOM OF THE WILL By Immanuel Kant From Critique of Pure Reason (1781)

Primitive Thisness and Primitive Identity by Robert Merrihew Adams (1979)

On the Relation of Philosophy to the Theology Conference Seward 11/24/98

This handout follows the handout on The nature of the sceptic s challenge. You should read that handout first.

Robert Kiely Office Hours: Monday 4:15 6:00; Wednesday 1-3; Thursday 2-3

AN ACTUAL-SEQUENCE THEORY OF PROMOTION

Alexander of Hales, The Sum of Theology 1 (translated by Oleg Bychkov) Introduction, Question One On the discipline of theology

THOMISTIC STUDIES 2018 Modern Atheism

Disputation 20. On the First Efficient Cause and on His First Action, Which Is Creation

Transcription:

ON EFFICIENT CAUSALITY: METAPHYSICAL DISPUTATIONS 17,18, AND 19. By FRANCISCO SUAREZ. Translated By ALFRED J. FREDDOSO. New Haven: Yale University Press, 1994. Pp. xx, 428. A quick scan of the leading figures in Western Philosophy reveals that relatively few have made a name for themselves by defending intuitive, natural, and sensible positions. Aristotle is one, and perhaps Aquinas is another. Francisco Suarez, the sixteenth-century Spanish scholastic, would be a third. His invariable working procedure is to give copious consideration to the various ancient and medieval views, and then to find some sensible compromise position. But today Suarez can hardly claim to have a broad readership. Of his 54 Metaphysical Disputations (DM), only nine have now been published in English, while his other works remain almost entirely untranslated. This clear and accurate new translation aims to show readers what they have been missing. What is most immediately impressive about this long and dense volume is the light it shines on medieval and early modern thought. Suarez's copious references to earlier figures -- to Plato and other ancients, and to dozens of earlier scholastics -- makes his work valuable as an historical document. On the other hand, his wide readership in the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries makes him important for students of the early modern period. It is less clear, however, how much this volume has to offer on a strictly philosophical level. In his brief Introduction, Freddoso writes that DM 17-19 "constitute, as far as I know, the longest, most profound, and most thorough tract ever written on creaturely efficient causality from an Aristotelian

perspective" (xvii). Those that make it through DM 17 and 18 with strength enough to begin DM 19 will indeed be rewarded. Here Suarez takes up freedom and necessity, and he offers a detailed and sophisticated analysis of human action. But DM 17 and 18 (which are almost entirely independent of DM 19) seem far less interesting. Here Suarez offer a general account of efficient causality, but it is often difficult to see how his Aristotelian perspective sheds light on modern questions about causality. Still, perhaps this Aristotelian perspective can be valuable without shedding light on modern (i.e., Humean) problems about causality -- indeed, perhaps it can be valuable precisely because it offers a different perspective. Freddoso thinks so: "in presenting this translation... I hope to contribute to the current resuscitation of Aristotelian metaphysics" (xvi). So what does an Aristotelian theory of causality look like? As one might expect, Suarez gives separate treatment to the four kinds of Aristotelian causes. The present volume is devoted to efficient causality, which is of course the variety that corresponds most closely to our modern idea of a cause. In DM 17 Suarez clarifies a great deal of standard scholastic terminology, explaining what efficient causes are, and then the different types of efficient causes, including per se vs. per accidens causes, principal vs. instrumental causes, and univocal vs. equivocal causes. As readers with an interest in the medieval period will immediately see, this whole discussion is extremely valuable as a guide to earlier usage. Readers with no special interest in the terminology will likely be less impressed.

DM 18 is much more ambitious. It begins by asking "whether created things really effect anything" (37), a question that leads Suarez to reject occasionalism. Then, over the next 200+ pages, Suarez takes up a detailed metaphysical analysis of how one thing can be the efficient cause of another. Here the reader looking for a promising theory of causation faces considerable impediments, because almost the entire account presupposes an Aristotelian metaphysics that is not readily transferrable into modern lines of thought. Suarez argues, among other things, that form and not matter will always be the principle of causality (51); that accidents can be instrumental causes in the production of a substance (62) but that the substantial form will be the principal principle involved in such causation (52); that among accidents only qualities are per se principles of acting (117). Are these interesting claims? It is certainly not immediately evident that they are; on the other hand it would be foolish to dismiss them as uninteresting relics. Evaluating these issues would be a major task. This is a task that Freddoso has already taken up, not just with this translation but in a series of published articles. Yet even in this splendid translation Suarez often seems to be moving in a closed theoretical circle. One senses his philosophical skill, but often feels frustrated in trying to connect his concerns with our concerns. Even when the debate shifts to a more concrete level, and examples are offered, the gulf still remains. The examples he considers (e.g., in discussing the possibility of action at a distance, how magnets work (209), and why the bottom

of a kettle is cooler than the boiling water above it (203)) will be of interest to historians of science, but don't advance the philosophical debate as we now define it. It is clear, in contrast, that DM 19 deserves a broad philosophic audience. Suarez's basic position is that "freedom exists formally in the will and not in the intellect" (337). This gets explained and defended in terms of a sophisticated action theory. Like all the appetitive faculties, an act of will is "an intrinsic and spontaneous tendency or inclination toward the object" (340). This means that desires and inclinations are not commanded or chosen by will, but simply are will's commands and choices. Only such inclinations count as intrinsically voluntary. Other human actions, including intellection, are extrinsically voluntary, and therefore cannot be formally free. In all of this Suarez attempts to follows Aquinian lines, but he seems at crucial points to make concessions to the voluntarism of earlier figures like Olivi and Scotus. Thus Suarez maintains that it is probable, though not certain, that will can choose either of two objects even when intellect has judged one of the two to be better (356). And he later holds that even at the instant at which a choice is made, the will must be both capable of choosing the act and capable of not choosing it. To explain how this can be true even at that instant at which the choice is made, he distinguishes between temporal instants and instants of nature (380). Freddoso is medieval philosophy's best and most prolific translator. Here, as in his earlier works, the English is both

clear and faithful to the original. The translation is literal enough to satisfy philosophers, but not so ploddingly literal as to wear down the reader. Frequent footnotes help make sense of obscure references and tangled arguments. In comparing forty pages of the translation with the original Latin I was unable to find a single significant mistake, omission, or even questionable rendering. Some minor complaints: Freddoso's practice is to leave Suarez's sources as they stand in the Latin. As a result, readers must either recognize on their own names like Henry, Gabriel, Durandus, the Master, Hervaeus, etc., or discover on their own that full names and dates are provided in the index (although there Durandus [of St. Pourçain] is wrongly identified as William Durandus). Also, Freddoso includes without comment the paragraph titles of the standard 1866 edition, which suggests that these are Suarez's own headings. That assumption strikes me as dubious. Robert Pasnau, St. Joseph's University