Liberal Conservatism, Not Conservative Liberalism

Similar documents
Creighton University, Oct. 13, 2016 Midwest Area Workshop on Metaphysics, Oct. 14, 2016

Summary of Kant s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals

UNITED NATIONS EDUCATIONAL, SCIENTIFIC AND CULTURAL ORGANIZATION. Address by Mr Federico Mayor

Phil 114, Wednesday, April 11, 2012 Hegel, The Philosophy of Right 1 7, 10 12, 14 16, 22 23, 27 33, 135, 141

4 Liberty, Rationality, and Agency in Hobbes s Leviathan

A Review on What Is This Thing Called Ethics? by Christopher Bennett * ** 1

MILL ON LIBERTY. 1. Problem. Mill s On Liberty, one of the great classics of liberal political thought,

ETHICAL THEORIES. Review week 6 session 11. Ethics Ethical Theories Review. Socrates. Socrate s theory of virtue. Socrate s chain of injustices

J.J.ROUSSEAU ( ) Presented by: Thomas G.M. Associate professor, Pompei College Aikala.

WHY THE NAME OF THE UNIVERSITY IS VIVEKANANDA INTERNATIONAL UNIVERSITY?

The Catholic intellectual tradition, social justice, and the university: Sometimes, tolerance is not the answer

Freedom as Morality. UWM Digital Commons. University of Wisconsin Milwaukee. Hao Liang University of Wisconsin-Milwaukee. Theses and Dissertations

How to Live a More Authentic Life in Both Markets and Morals

STATEMENT OF EXPECTATION FOR GRAND CANYON UNIVERSITY FACULTY

Take Home Exam #2. PHI 1700: Global Ethics Prof. Lauren R. Alpert

Going beyond good and evil

LIBERTY: RETHINKING AN IMPERILED IDEAL. By Glenn Tinder. William B. Eerdmans Publishing Company Pp. xiv, 407. $ ISBN: X.

Philosophy Courses Fall 2016

IN his preface to Lyrical Ballads, William Wordsworth noted that,

The Other Half of Hegel s Halfwayness: A response to Dr. Morelli s Meeting Hegel Halfway. Ben Suriano

THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN SCIENCE, RELIGION AND ARISTOTELIAN THEOLOGY TODAY

ntroduction to Socialist Humanism: An International Symposium by Eri...

Fall 2016 Department of Philosophy Graduate Course Descriptions

denarius (a days wages)

Nietzsche s Philosophy as Background to an Examination of Tolkien s The Lord of the Rings

HEGEL (Historical, Dialectical Idealism)

NW: So does it differ from respect or is it just another way of saying respect?

The Role of Love in the Thought of Kant and Kierkegaard

Course Syllabus Political Philosophy PHIL 462, Spring, 2017

A Framework for the Good

I, for my part, have tried to bear in mind the very aims Dante set himself in writing this work, that is:

Bart Streumer, Unbelievable Errors, Oxford: Oxford University Press, ISBN

Aristotle s Doctrine of the Mean and the Circularity of Human Nature

Marx: Marx: Economic and Philosophical Manuscripts in Karl Marx: Selected Writings, L. Simon, ed. Indianapolis: Hackett.

SUMMARIES AND TEST QUESTIONS UNIT 6

EUROPEAN VALUES AND GEORGIA (IN THE LIGHT OF MERAB MAMARDASHVILI S VIEW)

Let us begin by first locating our fields in relation to other fields that study ethics. Consider the following taxonomy: Kinds of ethical inquiries

Introduction to Philosophy

ARE THERE DERIVATIVE NATURAL RIGHTS? By John Hasnas

GOD OR LABOR. Michael Bakunin

Ludwig Feuerbach The Essence of Christianity (excerpts) 1 PHIL101 Prof. Oakes updated: 10/23/13 9:10 AM. Section III: How do I know? Reading III.

Computer Ethics. Normative Ethics and Normative Argumentation. Viola Schiaffonati October 10 th 2017

TOP BOOKS TO READ IF YOU WANT TO STUDY PHILOSOPHY AT UNIVERSITY

Kant The Grounding of the Metaphysics of Morals (excerpts) 1 PHIL101 Prof. Oakes. Section IV: What is it worth? Reading IV.2.

QUESTION 44. The Procession of Creatures from God, and the First Cause of All Beings

James V. Schall characteristically introduces. Unserious Docility. Thomas P. Harmon

Environmental Ethics. Espen Gamlund, PhD Associate Professor of Philosophy University of Bergen

Qué es la filosofía? What is philosophy? Philosophy

Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly *

Virtue Ethics. Chapter 7 ETCI Barbara MacKinnon Ethics and Contemporary Issues Professor Douglas Olena

The view that all of our actions are done in self-interest is called psychological egoism.

Robot como esclavos modernos

Korsgaard and Non-Sentient Life ABSTRACT

Introduction to Philosophy: The Big Picture

Computer Ethics. Normative Ethics Ethical Theories. Viola Schiaffonati October 4 th 2018

Philosophical Review.

Contents Introduction...1 The Goodness Ethic...1 Method...3 The Nature of the Good...4 Goodness as Virtue and Intention...6 Revision History...

Making Decisions on Behalf of Others: Who or What Do I Select as a Guide? A Dilemma: - My boss. - The shareholders. - Other stakeholders

Duty and Categorical Rules. Immanuel Kant Introduction to Ethics, PHIL 118 Professor Douglas Olena

Psychological G-d. Psychic Redemption

What Lurks Beneath the Integrity Objection. Bernard Williams s alienation and integrity arguments against consequentialism have

BLEEDING HEARTS AND BLOODY MINDS REASON IN ACTION IN ALTRUISTIC BENEVOLENCE. Howard Adelman

The Conflict Between Authority and Autonomy from Robert Wolff, In Defense of Anarchism (1970)

Kant s Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysic of Morals

The philosophy of human rights II: justifying HR. HUMR 5131 Fall 2017 Jakob Elster

factors in Bentham's hedonic calculus.

FIRST STUDY. The Existential Dialectical Basic Assumption of Kierkegaard s Analysis of Despair

Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Introduction

GS SCORE ETHICS - A - Z. Notes

Virtue Ethics. What kind of person do you want to grow up to be? Virtue Ethics (VE): The Basic Idea

Health Care Decisions For the Common Good

... it is important to understand, not intellectually but

1 The Philosophic Principles of Rational Being

THE MENO by Plato Written in approximately 380 B.C.

Affirmative Dialectics: from Logic to Anthropology

THE EIGHT KEY QUESTIONS HANDBOOK

CONTENTS PREFACE

First Treatise <Chapter 1. On the Eternity of Things>

The Stoics. The Stoics

Reading Questions for Phil , Fall 2016 (Daniel)

Noonan, Harold (2010) The thinking animal problem and personal pronoun revisionism. Analysis, 70 (1). pp ISSN

Tuesday, September 2, Idealism

POLS 3000 INTRODUCTION TO POLITICAL THEORY

Identities and Reasons (Comment on T.M. Scanlon s Ideas of Identity and their Normative. Status ) John Skorupski

Dalai Lama: Behind Our Anxiety, the Fear of Being Unneeded

Psychological Egoism, Hedonism and Ethical Egoism

Unconditional Love Transforms

Interfaith Dialogue as a New Approach in Islamic Education

Evaluating actions The principle of utility Strengths Criticisms Act vs. rule

J.f. Stephen s On Fraternity And Mill s Universal Love 1

ETHICAL POSITIONS STATEMENT

Character. character. Developing a life that makes a difference. Character is power. testimony. theology

Rawlsian Values. Jimmy Rising

Section 1 of chapter 1 of The Moral Sense advances the thesis that we have a

Chapter 3 PHILOSOPHICAL ETHICS AND BUSINESS CHAPTER OBJECTIVES. After exploring this chapter, you will be able to:

The Advantages of a Catholic University

In the name of Allah, the Beneficent and Merciful S/5/100 report 1/12/1982 [December 1, 1982] Towards a worldwide strategy for Islamic policy (Points

Principle Approach Education

SOCIOLOGICAL THEORY (Michaelmas 2017) Dr Michael Biggs

EXERCISES, QUESTIONS, AND ACTIVITIES My Answers

Transcription:

Peter Augustine Lawler Liberal Conservatism, Not Conservative Liberalism The Meaning of Conservatism, Revised 3rd edition by Roger Scruton St. Augustine s Press, 2002. In the end, we must face the fact that it is impossible to be a pure conservative, just as it is impossible to be a pure liberal. In explaining the meaning of conservatism, Roger Scruton does not try to claim that any human being can be only a conservative. Instead, he shows that the clash between liberals and conservatives is really one between perspectives. The liberal perspective is first person, and the conservative perspective is third person, and all modern human beings look at the world from both points of view. The problem, according to Scruton, is that we selfish modern individuals refuse to give the thirdperson view its due, despite the fact that it is perfectly natural, and just, for us to do so. I am a liberal insofar as I view everything from the standpoint of my desires as a free individual. I approach everything in the world as if it exists for my sake. All social and political institutions not to mention other human beings I judge according to how they help me maximize my autonomy and secure the unlimited satisfaction of my desires. This first-person perspective lies at the foundation of Milton Friedman s libertarian vision of the spontaneous order arising in market exchanges; it lies at the foundation of Karl Marx s vision of the unlimited personal choice that human beings will enjoy under communism. Such a liberal view dominates everywhere in our political and intellectual worlds today: government and every other human institution even the family is understood as resulting from the free choice (the social contract) of autonomous individuals. And for Scruton, this liberalism is above all an American myth, because America is the Lockean society par excellence. It is fashionable today to say that liberalism has been discredited or is now exhausted, but Scruton helps us see that this is far from true. The Lockean progress that aims to reconstruct all of human life in accordance with libertarian principles continues to accelerate. In advanced, post-industrial societies today, the average man and especially the average intellectual spends more of his life in the first-person perspective than ever. (Though it is important to add, as a gentle corrective to Scruton s English chauvinism, that the church-going Peter Augustine Lawler is Dana Professor of Government at Berry College in Georgia and author, most recently, of Aliens in America: The Strange Truth about Our Souls (ISI Books, 2002). 58 THE INTERCOLLEGIATE REVIEW Fall 2003/Spring 2004

and baby-begetting Americans spend considerably less time in such solipsism than do typical Europeans. The American myth, truth to tell, has gone global, while Locke, not to mention John Stuart Mill, were, after all, Englishmen.) Responsible liberals today may join with Scruton in acknowledging that extreme libertarianism is self-destructive, because the free individual, despite his shameful ingratitude, nonetheless depends upon social institutions that cannot really be understood to exist for him. The recent experience of Europe shows us that people who begin to fall exclusively into the first-person perspective stop procreating. Their selfish individualism which is oriented, first of all, to self-preservation turns against the requirements of self-preservation. Their unnatural lack of concern for family, community, country, and species will turn out, in the long run, to be contrary to their own self-interest: Who will support the current young and perpetually adolescent Europeans in their old age? Who will defend them against their enemies? So in America today, responsible liberals who are usually called neoconservatives see that liberalism depends on human beings who are somewhat child-centered, patriotic, and religious. These responsible liberals praise these non-individualistic human propensities in an effort to shore up liberalism. One of their slogans is conservative sociology with liberal politics. The neoconservatives recognize that the politics of free and rational individuals depends upon a pre-political social world that is far from free and rational as a whole. In their prudence, responsible liberals often think of themselves as Aristotelians. They want to limit Lockean first-personalization, and they usually contend that they have on their side not only the social capital of tradition but human nature itself. But as Scruton shows, the problem remains that these responsible liberals are themselves, in the end, first-person thinkers. In our sophisticated or very self-conscious world, even an Aristotelian approach presents a problem. True, Aristotle was pro-family but he subordinated unselfconscious and necessity-driven family life to the free political life of friends and citizens. In the world of the polis, such an understanding might produce a virtuous ethic of noble self-sacrifice, but that is not our world. In our world, citizenship entails devotion to an essentially Lockean or individualistic political regime. The Aristotelian assertion that man is a political animal too readily comes to mean merely that our political principles reign in splendid sovereignty over all social, familial, and religious attachments. Our national greatness too easily becomes our relentless capacity to Lockeanize the world. In their resistance to what is unnatural or disoriented in modern individualism, neoconservatives tend to rely too much on sociology and sociobiology rather than relying on what is distinctive in human nature. They lack a genuinely conservative political science, as well as a genuinely conservative theology and metaphysics. Neoconservatives are really conservative liberals, and we have to wonder how tenable their position is over the long run. Part of the problem the neoconservatives face is that they hope to defend what appears to be a contradiction verging on an oxymoron. As the French political philosopher Pierre Manent has observed, modern human beings really want to be human individuals. We want the benefits of free individuality, but we also want to be embedded beings living in a world rich in humanly satisfying moral contents. We want Lockean freedom including Lockean technology and prosperity but we want this freedom without being restless and lonely workaholics for whom God is dead. THE INTERCOLLEGIATE REVIEW Fall 2003/Spring 2004 59

Conservative liberals do not seem to offer a way of sustaining this tension against creeping libertarianism, even in the short run. So we turn to Scruton, because he would seem to be something else than a conservative liberal: a liberal conservative. He holds that any true conception of human liberty depends on the primacy of our devotion to society or government in the broad sense. Consequently, human social institutions cannot properly be viewed as merely ministerial to individual ends, even to individual liberty. For Scruton, the individual never completely transcends his civilized formation by his community, and his individuality always depends on his grateful devotion to that 60 THE INTERCOLLEGIATE REVIEW Fall 2003/Spring 2004 community. Scruton shows that the first-person vice of ingratitude is, most of all, a lie about the origin and extent of one s own liberty. In the name of the truth, Scruton therefore attempts to restore the third-person perspective in its integrity. The properly third-person view is detached, but not completely detached. It is that of a participantobserver, an anthropologist concerned about the welfare of the tribe (albeit a tribe which is his own). Because my very being depends on my tribe s flourishing, I must put my tribe or country before myself. Without it, I am not, and insofar as people love life, they will love what gives them life. What at first may seem to be a matter of self-interest concern with one s own being is more properly or naturally expressed in terms of love of one s own. And love of, not to mention pride in, one s own is far from reducible to the self-interest of the individual. So the conservative anthropologist can enjoy the popular self-respect that good citizens have for the order of which they form a part, and for themselves as part of that order. That love that natural instinct of gratitude generates patriotism, respect for law, loyalty to leaders, and a willing deference to privilege that need not be craven or submissive. In Scruton s view, the individual selfconsciousness that opposes itself to our natural social instinct has emerged slowly over time. He believes it used to be the case that social continuity ensured that those who rose to self-consciousness nevertheless departed only in the smallest items of belief from the happier mortals who were fated never to question what they knew. He notes also that individuality as we experience it is Roger Scruton, Liberal Conservative hardly natural; it is an artifact, an achievement which depends on the social life of people. The first-person understanding of oneself is a recent venture of the human spirit, and only recently has that monstrous entity, modern man emerged, the person for whom all connection with an order greater than himself has to be won through an effort of his own. In Scruton s account, modern man must use his mind to recover a truth that people used to possess instinctually: The condition of mankind requires that individuals can act effectively as individuals only because they can first identify themselves with something greater, with some human society which they recognize instinctively as home. It is true that individuals have become sophisticated beings, anxious for a sphere of privacy that seclude[s] their eccentricities. But such privacy must be protected by the state, a social institution. Scruton adds a more psychological obser-

vation: What is eccentricity without the norm against which to measure it? Nothing. So there is no abstract or universal right to privacy, but only Anglo-Saxon privacy, which can be enjoyed only by people who have internalized a particular form of public order. The monstrously deracinated modern individual occupies his time busily running away from substantive goods in pursuit of a liberation that lacks all content and any real promise of happiness. Yet only those who can find some good in what they have been given can enjoy those practices and institutions in which we are at rest, and in which we view ourselves not as means but as ends. If government, the most comprehensive human institution, is understood only in terms of calculation and consent, then that selfish and joyless view infects every other human institution. So one reason Scruton urges us to love the established government is instrumental to protect the family, which is the origin of the self-respect and virtue that are at the foundation of all decent and minimally intrusive government. Government exists, finally, for the sake of the family as well as for all those human institutions in which we experience the human loves and goods we share in common. Scruton seems trapped with the paradox that we cannot view government instrumentally if we expect it to perform its key instrumental function, and the same must also be said of the family. Liberal conservatives know that the first- and third-person perspectives are so entwined that they elude even complete analytical separation. Only a well-established government creates the stable environment in which most of human life can be given over to the leisure enjoyed in relatively autonomous human institutions, such as sports and education. It is through participation in such institutions, along with the family, Scruton observes, that social virtue is really learned. The conservative, far more than the liberal, believes that diverse but not necessarily conflicting institutions embodying various human goods can exist in relative independence without threat to the social order. Ironically, conservatism is much less personally intrusive than liberal ideology. We learn in leisured, non-instrumental institutions the limits of both the first- and third-person perspectives. In educational institutions at their best, for example, we learn that individual fulfillment in the pursuit of the truth is not really compatible with autonomy or the unlimited satisfaction of our desires. The pursuit of the truth is essentially a common pursuit, Scruton notes, and to desire it is to desire that community. In this common endeavor the grip of alienation is loosened, and fellowship is born. The conflict that the self-conscious individual perceives between his own good and the common good fades away, as do the extremes of merely instinctual gratitude for, and self-conscious negation of, what we have been given. We are grateful for our self-consciousness, for our openness to truth, for what connects us truly and not just instrumentally or even historically to our fellow human beings.the misery of alienation is, at the deepest level, still the result of the selfdeceptive vice of ingratitude. Yet surely Scruton goes too far in denying the naturalness of human alienation. Socrates, for example, in his intense selfconsciousness, was certainly alienated from his political community though he, and the ancient philosophers who followed him, were also more aware than we modern individuals are of their necessary dependence on the political community. And according to Christian thinkers such as Saint Augustine, human beings are aliens and pilgrims in the City of Man. A pagan THE INTERCOLLEGIATE REVIEW Fall 2003/Spring 2004 61

might say that Augustine ungratefully underestimated his dependence on Rome. Perhaps Scruton shares that criticism of this instrumental tendency in Christian political thought. But even with this criticism in mind, the Christians are still right to say that alienated individuality is not nearly as new a phenomenon as Scruton says. And this error has consequences in Scruton s account of conservatism. For Scruton does not place religion among the intrinsically fulfilling human institutions that unite the first- and third-person. He views the church, instead, simply from a third-person view as an established political institution for the English. American conservatives cannot help but notice that Scruton s view of religion is far too domesticated, too Anglican. The truth is that even ordinary human beings transcend the confines of their political community, and their gratitude for their very being is not directed so much to their community, but above all to a personal God. Their connection to all other human beings through their common Creator limits their attachment to partially alienates them from any particular political community. Whereas the community that is the City of God includes us all, and not just those who devote their leisure to the highest forms of education. Some recognition of these truths about the human soul is necessary for conservatives to avoid the mistake of trying to engineer a world in which human beings can be completely at home. Scruton himself certainly rejects any project of constructing Arcadia, but he still sometimes falls victim to the romantic view that self-consciousness itself is an historical error that opposes itself to our natural or instinctual goodness. The truth is that self-consciousness is natural to human beings; it is the source of both the greatness and the misery of sinful man, of that perverse being open to the truth about Being and given quite particular moral responsibilities. In the end, Scruton only points us toward, but does not provide, the metaphysics and theology that liberal conservatives need today. But this subtle, brilliantly detailed, and profoundly original book deserves to be ranked among the classics of contemporary political thought. Scruton challenges Americans to show that we too can think intelligently and without nostalgia outside the Locke box. 62 THE INTERCOLLEGIATE REVIEW Fall 2003/Spring 2004