Prisoners' Dilemma Is a Newcomb Problem

Similar documents
Robert Nozick s seminal 1969 essay ( Newcomb s Problem and Two Principles

Detachment, Probability, and Maximum Likelihood

There are various different versions of Newcomb s problem; but an intuitive presentation of the problem is very easy to give.

Gandalf s Solution to the Newcomb Problem. Ralph Wedgwood

Ensuring Two Bird Deaths With One Throw

The St. Petersburg paradox & the two envelope paradox

Theories of epistemic justification can be divided into two groups: internalist and

The Zygote Argument remixed

what makes reasons sufficient?

OSSA Conference Archive OSSA 8

Abstract. challenge to rival Causal Decision Theory (CDT). The basis for this challenge is that in

Moral Twin Earth: The Intuitive Argument. Terence Horgan and Mark Timmons have recently published a series of articles where they

6.041SC Probabilistic Systems Analysis and Applied Probability, Fall 2013 Transcript Lecture 3

How Not to Defend Metaphysical Realism (Southwestern Philosophical Review, Vol , 19-27)

Lecture 6 Workable Ethical Theories I. Based on slides 2011 Pearson Education, Inc. Publishing as Pearson Addison-Wesley

occasions (2) occasions (5.5) occasions (10) occasions (15.5) occasions (22) occasions (28)

ON THE TRUTH CONDITIONS OF INDICATIVE AND COUNTERFACTUAL CONDITIONALS Wylie Breckenridge

Interest-Relativity and Testimony Jeremy Fantl, University of Calgary

HUME, CAUSATION AND TWO ARGUMENTS CONCERNING GOD

NICHOLAS J.J. SMITH. Let s begin with the storage hypothesis, which is introduced as follows: 1

Final Paper. May 13, 2015

Binding and Its Consequences

KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST. Arnon Keren

Goldman on Knowledge as True Belief. Alvin Goldman (2002a, 183) distinguishes the following four putative uses or senses of

proper construal of Davidson s principle of rationality will show the objection to be misguided. Andrew Wong Washington University, St.

Philosophy of Religion 21: (1987).,, 9 Nijhoff Publishers, Dordrecht - Printed in the Nethenanas

AN EPISTEMIC PARADOX. Byron KALDIS

Luck, Rationality, and Explanation: A Reply to Elga s Lucky to Be Rational. Joshua Schechter. Brown University

Saying too Little and Saying too Much. Critical notice of Lying, Misleading, and What is Said, by Jennifer Saul

THINKING ANIMALS AND EPISTEMOLOGY

Knowledge and Reality

Australasian Journal of Philosophy Vol. 73, No. 1; March 1995

Jeffrey, Richard, Subjective Probability: The Real Thing, Cambridge University Press, 2004, 140 pp, $21.99 (pbk), ISBN

The Problem with Complete States: Freedom, Chance and the Luck Argument

ESSAYS IN HONOR OF CARL G. HEMPEL

PLEASESURE, DESIRE AND OPPOSITENESS

The Kripkenstein Paradox and the Private World. In his paper, Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Languages, Kripke expands upon a conclusion

Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000)

Moore s paradoxes, Evans s principle and self-knowledge

Can A Priori Justified Belief Be Extended Through Deduction? It is often assumed that if one deduces some proposition p from some premises

Computing Machinery and Intelligence. The Imitation Game. Criticisms of the Game. The Imitation Game. Machines Concerned in the Game

Against Monism. 1. Monism and pluralism. Theodore Sider

175 Chapter CHAPTER 23: Probability

SCHAFFER S DEMON NATHAN BALLANTYNE AND IAN EVANS

What is a counterexample?

Sensitivity hasn t got a Heterogeneity Problem - a Reply to Melchior

Andrea Westlund, in Selflessness and Responsibility for Self, argues

Consider... Ethical Egoism. Rachels. Consider... Theories about Human Motivations

Contradictory Information Can Be Better than Nothing The Example of the Two Firemen

NOTES ON WILLIAMSON: CHAPTER 11 ASSERTION Constitutive Rules

Review of Views Into the Chinese Room

Comments on Lasersohn

The Lion, the Which? and the Wardrobe Reading Lewis as a Closet One-boxer

In his pithy pamphlet Free Will, Sam Harris. Defining free will away EDDY NAHMIAS ISN T ASKING FOR THE IMPOSSIBLE. reviews/harris

Am I free? Free will vs. determinism

LODGE VEGAS # 32 ON EDUCATION

Warrant and accidentally true belief

Epistemic Utility and Theory-Choice in Science: Comments on Hempel

* I am indebted to Jay Atlas and Robert Schwartz for their helpful criticisms

Philosophical Issues, vol. 8 (1997), pp

Law as a Social Fact: A Reply to Professor Martinez

In essence, Swinburne's argument is as follows:

POWERS, NECESSITY, AND DETERMINISM

Moral Epistemology Naturalized, edited with Bruce Hunter, Supplementary Volume 26 of The Canadian Journal of Philosophy (2000), 322 pages.

The Problem of Evil Chapters 14, 15. B. C. Johnson & John Hick Introduction to Philosophy Professor Doug Olena

In his celebrated article Toward a Reconstruction of Utility and Welfare Economics,

MATH 1000 PROJECT IDEAS

Introduction to Statistical Hypothesis Testing Prof. Arun K Tangirala Department of Chemical Engineering Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Self-Evidence and A Priori Moral Knowledge

Proof as a cluster concept in mathematical practice. Keith Weber Rutgers University

Saying too Little and Saying too Much Critical notice of Lying, Misleading, and What is Said, by Jennifer Saul

MULTI-PEER DISAGREEMENT AND THE PREFACE PARADOX. Kenneth Boyce and Allan Hazlett

Newcomb's Problem. by Marion Ledwig. Philosophical Dissertation

Nozick s fourth condition

MARK KAPLAN AND LAWRENCE SKLAR. Received 2 February, 1976) Surely an aim of science is the discovery of the truth. Truth may not be the

Logic & Proofs. Chapter 3 Content. Sentential Logic Semantics. Contents: Studying this chapter will enable you to:

Reliabilism: Holistic or Simple?

SUPPORT MATERIAL FOR 'DETERMINISM AND FREE WILL ' (UNIT 2 TOPIC 5)

WHEN is a moral theory self-defeating? I suggest the following.

INFINITE "BACKWARD" INDUCTION ARGUMENTS. Given the military value of surprise and given dwindling supplies and

Some proposals for understanding narrow content

IS PERSONAL IDENTITY WHAT MATTERS?

Today s Lecture. Preliminary comments on the Problem of Evil J.L Mackie

Philosophical Perspectives, 16, Language and Mind, 2002 THE AIM OF BELIEF 1. Ralph Wedgwood Merton College, Oxford

In his paper Studies of Logical Confirmation, Carl Hempel discusses

On David Chalmers's The Conscious Mind

Magic, semantics, and Putnam s vat brains

How should I live? I should do whatever brings about the most pleasure (or, at least, the most good)

Lecture 6 Kantianism. Based on slides 2011 Pearson Education, Inc. Publishing as Pearson Addison-Wesley

Chapter 5: Freedom and Determinism

Journal of Philosophy, Inc.

On Breaking the Spell of Irrationality (with treatment of Pascal s Wager) Selmer Bringsjord Are Humans Rational? 11/27/17 version 2 RPI

Nozick and Scepticism (Weekly supervision essay; written February 16 th 2005)

Chapter 6. Fate. (F) Fatalism is the belief that whatever happens is unavoidable. (55)

Realism and instrumentalism

Humean Supervenience: Lewis (1986, Introduction) 7 October 2010: J. Butterfield

What God Could Have Made

CAN TWO ENVELOPES SHAKE THE FOUNDATIONS OF DECISION- THEORY?

McCLOSKEY ON RATIONAL ENDS: The Dilemma of Intuitionism


Transcription:

DAVID LEWIS Prisoners' Dilemma Is a Newcomb Problem Several authors have observed that Prisoners' Dilemma and Newcomb's Problem are related-for instance, in that both involve controversial appeals to dominance., But to call them "related" is an understatement. Considered as puzzles about rationality, or disagreements between two conceptions thereof, they are one and the same problem. Prisoners' Dilemma is a Newcomb Problem-or rather, two Newcomb Problems side by side, one per prisoner. Only the inessential trappings are different. Let us make them the same. You and I, the "prisoners," are separated. Each is offered the choice: to rat or not to rat. (The action of "ratting" is so called because I consider it to be rational-but that is controversial.) Ratting is done as follows: one reaches out and takes a transparent box, which is seen to contain a thousand dollars. A prisoner who rats gets to keep the thousand. (Maybe ratting is construed as an act of confessing and accusing one's partner, much as taking the Queen's shilling was once construed as an act of enlisting-but that is irrelevant to the decision problem.) If either prisoner declines to rat, he is not at all rewarded; but his partner is presented with a million dollars, nicely packed in an opaque box. (Maybe each faces a long sentence and a short sentence x. Robert Nozick, "Newcomb's Problem and Two Principles of Choice" in Essays in Honor of Carl G. Hempel, ed. N. Rescher (Dordrecht: Reidel, 1969), pp. 130-131; Steven J. Brams, "Newcomb's Problem and Prisoners' Dilemma," Journal of Conflict Resolution i9 (1975): 596-612; Lawrence H. Davis, "Prisoners, Paradox, and Rationality," American Philosophical Quarterly 14 (1977): 321; and J. Howard Sobel, Chance, Choice, and Action: Newcomb's Problem Resolved (duplicated manuscript. July 1978), pp. I67-I68.? I979 by Princeton University Press Philosophy & Public Affairs 8, no. 3 0048-3915/79/030235-6$oo.50o/I

236 Philosophy & Public Affairs to be served consecutively; escape from the long sentence costs a million, and escape from the short sentence costs a thousand. But it is irrelevant how the prisoners propose to spend their money.) So the payoff matrix looks like this. I rat I don't rat You I get $i,ooo I get $o rat You get $i,ooo You get $i,ooi,ooo donut I get $I,OOI,OOO I get $i,ooo,ooo don't You get $o You get $i,ooo,ooo rat There we have it: a perfectly typical case of Prisoners' Dilemma. My decision problem, in a nutshell, is as follows; yours is exactly similar. ( i ) I am offered a thousand-take it or leave it. (2) Perhaps also I will be given a million; but whether I will or not is causally independent of what I do now. Nothing I can do now will have any effect on whether or not I get my million. (3) I will get my million if and only if you do not take your thousand. Newcomb's Problem is the same as regards points (i) and (2). The only difference-if such it be-is that point (3) is replaced by (3') I will get my million if and only if it is predicted that I do not take my thousand. "Predicted" need not mean "predicted in advance." Not so in English: we credit new theories with success in "predicting" phenomena already observed. And not so in Newcomb's Problem. While it dramatizes the problem to think of the million already there, or else already not there, in the opaque box in front of me as I deliberate, it is agreed all around that what really matters is (2), and hence that the "prediction" should be causally independent of my decision. Making the

237 Prisoners' Dilemma Is a Newcomb Problem prediction ahead of time is one good way to secure this causal independence. But it is not the only way.2 Provided that I can have no effect on it, the prediction could just as well be made simultaneously with my decision or even afterwards, and the character of Newcomb's Problem would be unchanged.3 Likewise in the case of Prisoners' Dilemma nothing need be assumed-and in my telling of the story, nothing was assumed-about whether the prisoners are put to the test simultaneously or one after the other. Also it is inessential to Newcomb's Problem that any predictionin advance, or otherwise-should actually take place. It is enough that some potentially predictive process should go on, and that whether I get my million is somehow made to depend on the outcome of that process. It could all be automated: if the predictive computer sends a pulse of current to the money-putting machine I get my million, otherwise not. Or there might be people who put the million in the box or not depending on the outcome of the process, but who do not at all think of the outcome as a prediction of my choice, or as warrant for a prediction. It makes no difference to my decision problem whether someone-the one who gives the million, or perhaps some bystander -does or doesn't form beliefs about what I will do by inference from the outcome of the predictive process. Eliminating inessentials, then, Newcomb's Problem is characterized by (i), (2), and (3") I will get my million if and only if a certain potentially predictive process (which may go on before, during, or after my choice) yields the outcome which could warrant a prediction that I do not take my thousand. The potentially predictive process par excellence is simulation. To predict whether I will take my thousand, make a replica of me, put my replica in a replica of my predicament, and see whether my replica takes his thousand. And whether or not anybody actually makes a 2. And perhaps not an infallible way. See David Lewis, "The Paradoxes of Time Travel," American Philosophical Quarterly 13 (1976): 145-152. 3. That is noted by Nozick, "Newcomb's Problem," p. 132, and I have not seen it disputed.

238 Philosophy & Public Affairs prediction about me by observing my replica, still my replica's decision is a potentially predictive process with respect to mine. Disregarding predictive processes other than simulation, if such there be, we have this special case of (3"): (3"') I will get my million if and only if my replica does not take his thousand. There are replicas and replicas. Some are the same sort of thing that I am, others are less so. A flesh-and-blood duplicate made by copying me atom for atom would be one good sort of replica. A working scale model of me, smaller perhaps by a ratio of I: I48, also might serve. So might a pattern of bits in a computer, or beads on an abacus, or marks on paper, or neuron firings in a brain, even though these things are unlike me and replicate me only by way of some complicated isomorphism. Also, some replicas are more reliable than others. There may be grounds for greater or lesser degrees of confidence that my replica and I will decide alike in the matter of the thousand. A replica that matches me perfectly in the respects relevant to my decision (whether duplicate or isomorph) will have more predictive power than a less perfect replica; but even a poor replica may have some significant degree of predictive power. As Newcomb's Problem is usually told, the predictive process involved is extremely reliable. But that is inessential. The disagreement between conceptions of rationality that gives the problem its interest arises even when the reliability of the process, as estimated by the agent, is quite poor-indeed, even when the agent judges that the predictive process will do little better than chance. More precisely, define average estimated reliability as the average of (A) the agent's conditional degree of belief that the predictive process will predict correctly, given that he takes his thousand, and (B) his conditional degree of belief that the process will predict correctly, given that he does not take his thousand. (When the predictive process is a simulation, for instance, we have the average of two conditional degrees of belief that the agent and his replica will decide alike.) Let r be the ratio of the value of the thousand to the value of the million: ooi

239 Prisoners' Dilemma Is a Newcomb Problem if value is proportional to money, perhaps somewhat more under diminishing marginal value. We have a disagreement between two conceptions of rationality if and only if the expected value4 of taking the thousand is less than that of declining it, which is so if and only if the average estimated reliability exceeds (' + r (That is.5005 if 2 value is proportional to money.) This is not a very high standard of reliability. So there can be a fully problematic case of Newcomb's Problem in which the predictive process consists of simulation by some very imperfect and very unreliable replica. The most readily available sort of replica of me is simply another person, placed in a replica of my predicament. For instance: you, my fellow prisoner. Most likely you are not a very exact replica of me, and your choice is not a very reliable predictive process for mine.5 Still, you might well be reliable enough (in my estimation) for a Newcomb Problem.6 So we have this special case of (3"'): (3) I will get my million if and only if you do not take your thousand. Inessential trappings aside, Prisoners' Dilemma is a version of Newcomb's Problem, quod erat demonstrandum. Some who discuss Newcomb's Problem think it is rational to decline the thousand if the predictive process is reliable enough. Their reason is that they believe, justifiably, that those who decline their thousands will probably get their millions. Some who discuss Prisoners' Dilemma 4. As calculated according to the non-causal sort of decision theory presented for instance in Richard Jeffrey, The Logic of Decision (New York: McGraw-Hill, I 965 ). 5. On the other hand, you might be an extremely perfect and reliable replica, as in the Prisoners' Dilemma between twins described by Nozick, "Newcomb's Problem," pp. I30-I3I. 6. If you do not meet even the low standard of estimated reliability just considered, either because you are unlike me or because you and I alike are apt to choose at random or because the payoffs are such as to set r rather high, then we have a situation with no clash between conceptions of rationality; on any conception, it is rational to rat. But even this non-problem might legitimately be called a version of Newcomb's Problem, since it satisfies conditions (i), (2), and (3").

240 Philosophy & Public Affairs think it is rational not to rat if the two partners are enough alike.7 Their reason is that they believe, justifiably, that those who do not rat will probably not be ratted on by their like-thinking partners. These two opinions are one opinion in two guises. But some-i, for one-who discuss Newcomb's Problem think it is rational to take the thousand no matter how reliable the predictive process may be. Our reason is that one thereby gets a thousand more than he would if he declined, since he would get his million or not regardless of whether he took his thousand. And some-i, for onewho discuss Prisoners' Dilemma think it is rational to rat no matter how much alike the two partners may be, and no matter how certain they may be that they will decide alike. Our reason is that one is better off if he rats than he would be if he didn't, since he would be ratted on or not regardless of whether he ratted. These two opinions also are one. Some have fended off the lessons of Newcomb's Problem by saying: "Let us not have, or let us not rely on, any intuitions about what is rational in goofball cases so unlike the decision problems of real life." But Prisoners' Dilemmas are deplorably common in real life. They are the most down-to-earth versions of Newcomb's Problem now available. 7. For instance Davis, "Prisoners, Paradox, and Rationality." He considers the case in Which the partners are alike because they are both rational; but there is also the case where they are alike because they are given to the same sorts of irrationality.