Personal identity and the radiation argument

Similar documents
Time travel and the open future

Noonan, Harold (2010) The thinking animal problem and personal pronoun revisionism. Analysis, 70 (1). pp ISSN

Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible?

What does Functionalism Tell Us about Personal Identity?

Could have done otherwise, action sentences and anaphora

Divine omniscience, timelessness, and the power to do otherwise

Nancey Murphy, Bodies and Souls, or Spirited Bodies? (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006). Pp. x Hbk, Pbk.

Stem Cell Research on Embryonic Persons is Just

Resemblance Nominalism and counterparts

Is there a good epistemological argument against platonism? DAVID LIGGINS

Material Coincidence and the Indiscernibility Problem Eric T. Olson

Bigelow, Possible Worlds and The Passage of Time

Moral requirements are still not rational requirements

The self, part II: personal identity as psychological continuity

Personal Identity. 1. The Problems of Personal Identity. First published Tue Aug 20, 2002; substantive revision Thu Jul 9, 2015

There might be nothing: the subtraction argument improved

Why Counterpart Theory and Four-Dimensionalism are Incompatible. Suppose that God creates ex nihilo a bronze statue of a

KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST. Arnon Keren

EXTERNALISM AND THE CONTENT OF MORAL MOTIVATION

Experiences Don t Sum

What We Are: Our Metaphysical Nature & Moral Implications

THINKING ANIMALS AND EPISTEMOLOGY

Knowledge and Reality

ON THE TRUTH CONDITIONS OF INDICATIVE AND COUNTERFACTUAL CONDITIONALS Wylie Breckenridge

Searle vs. Chalmers Debate, 8/2005 with Death Monkey (Kevin Dolan)

PARFIT'S MISTAKEN METAETHICS Michael Smith

Chapter 6. Fate. (F) Fatalism is the belief that whatever happens is unavoidable. (55)

Many Minds are No Worse than One

HAVE WE REASON TO DO AS RATIONALITY REQUIRES? A COMMENT ON RAZ

*Please note that tutorial times and venues will be organised independently with your teaching tutor.

Review Tutorial (A Whirlwind Tour of Metaphysics, Epistemology and Philosophy of Religion)

Outsmarting the McKinsey-Brown argument? 1

The Zygote Argument remixed

Philosophy of Religion 21: (1987).,, 9 Nijhoff Publishers, Dordrecht - Printed in the Nethenanas

spring 05 topics in philosophy of mind session 7

A New Argument Against Compatibilism

The Zombies Among Us. Eric T. Olson To appear in Nous.

TEMPORAL NECESSITY AND LOGICAL FATALISM. by Joseph Diekemper

This is a repository copy of An Argument for Animalism. White Rose Research Online URL for this paper:

Craig on the Experience of Tense

1. The narrow criterion Derek Parfit endorses a view of personal identity over time that he puts like this:

Today we turn to the work of one of the most important, and also most difficult, philosophers: Immanuel Kant.

Humean Supervenience: Lewis (1986, Introduction) 7 October 2010: J. Butterfield

Maximality and Microphysical Supervenience

Can Rationality Be Naturalistically Explained? Jeffrey Dunn. Abstract: Dan Chiappe and John Vervaeke (1997) conclude their article, Fodor,

Moore s paradoxes, Evans s principle and self-knowledge

Some Good and Some Not so Good Arguments for Necessary Laws. William Russell Payne Ph.D.

FOUNDATIONALISM AND ARBITRARINESS

MULTI-PEER DISAGREEMENT AND THE PREFACE PARADOX. Kenneth Boyce and Allan Hazlett

Keywords precise, imprecise, sharp, mushy, credence, subjective, probability, reflection, Bayesian, epistemology

Think by Simon Blackburn. Chapter 4b Free Will/Self

Thomas Reid on personal identity

Trinity & contradiction

Lawrence Brian Lombard a a Wayne State University. To link to this article:

PHILOSOPHY 4360/5360 METAPHYSICS. Methods that Metaphysicians Use

Who or what is God?, asks John Hick (Hick 2009). A theist might answer: God is an infinite person, or at least an

SUPPORT MATERIAL FOR 'DETERMINISM AND FREE WILL ' (UNIT 2 TOPIC 5)

Today we turn to the work of one of the most important, and also most difficult, philosophers: Immanuel Kant.

2014 THE BIBLIOGRAPHIA ISSN: Online First: 21 October 2014

DISCUSSION PRACTICAL POLITICS AND PHILOSOPHICAL INQUIRY: A NOTE

Semantic Pathology and the Open Pair

Prisoners' Dilemma Is a Newcomb Problem

Self-Evidence and A Priori Moral Knowledge

Hume's Functionalism About Mental Kinds

SCIENCE AND METAPHYSICS Part III SCIENTIFIC EPISTEMOLOGY? David Tin Win α & Thandee Kywe β. Abstract

Virtuous act, virtuous dispositions

Saul Kripke, Naming and Necessity

the notion of modal personhood. I begin with a challenge to Kagan s assumptions about the metaphysics of identity and modality.

THE CAMBRIDGE SOLUTION TO THE TIME OF A KILLING LAWRENCE B. LOMBARD

Fr. Copleston vs. Bertrand Russell: The Famous 1948 BBC Radio Debate on the Existence of God

1/9. The First Analogy

THE CONCEPT OF OWNERSHIP by Lars Bergström

G.E. Moore A Refutation of Skepticism

POWERS, NECESSITY, AND DETERMINISM

Epistemicism, Parasites and Vague Names * vagueness is based on an untenable metaphysics of content are unsuccessful. Burgess s arguments are

Dworkin on the Rufie of Recognition

PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE AND META-ETHICS

ISSA Proceedings 1998 Wilson On Circular Arguments

The Blackwell Guide to. Metaphysics. Edited by Richard M. Gale. Blackwell Publishers

Scots Philosophical Association University of St. Andrews

On A New Cosmological Argument

in defence of an argument for evans s principle 167

Scope Fallacies and the "Decisive Objection" Against Endurance

David O Connor. Hume on Religion H. O. Mounce Hume Studies Volume XXVIII, Number 2 (November, 2002)

DO WE NEED A THEORY OF METAPHYSICAL COMPOSITION?

Yuval Dolev, Time and Realism, MIT Press, 2007

Department of Philosophy at the University of Sheffield

HUME, CAUSATION AND TWO ARGUMENTS CONCERNING GOD

Hardback?18.00 ISBN

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

Are There Reasons to Be Rational?

Wittgenstein on the Fallacy of the Argument from Pretence. Abstract

On Some Alleged Consequences Of The Hartle-Hawking Cosmology. In [3], Quentin Smith claims that the Hartle-Hawking cosmology is inconsistent with

Logical Puzzles and the Concept of God

Oxford University Press and The Analysis Committee are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Analysis.

Pojman, Louis P. Introduction to Philosophy: Classical and Contemporary Readings. 3rd Ed. New York: Oxford University Press, 2004.

IS PERSONAL IDENTITY WHAT MATTERS?

AGENT CAUSATION AND RESPONSIBILITY: A REPLY TO FLINT

10 CERTAINTY G.E. MOORE: SELECTED WRITINGS

Transcription:

38 ERIC T. OLSON the unique proposition of travel through time - whether time is an A-series or not. At this point, the reasonable move for the advocate of the multiverse who would defend the legitimacy of universe travel might be to cut his losses and fall back upon the claim that time is a B-series. We can see now, however, that this move draws him perilously close to Ockham's razor, for if he were to accept that the temporal series is non-tensory, the theory of the multiverse would itself become superfluous. Recall that the initial motivation for such a theory was the fear of paradox. If there is no becoming, however, paradox can as well be avoided on a unidimensional view in the way (for instance) that Lewis (1976) has argued. And while this may saddle the defender of time travel with commitments to causal loops and the other oddities that burgeon from the tales of science fiction, these oddities at least need not be impossibilities and, in the end, need not force us into the greater sin of ontological glut.s Box 1918, Brown University Providence, RI 02912, USA JohnAbbruzzese@brown.edu References Deutsch, D. and M. Lockwood. 1994. The quantum physics of time travel. Scientific American March: 68-74. Lewis, D. 1976. The paradoxes of time travel. American Philosophical Quarterly 13: 145-52. McTaggart, J. 1908. The unreality of time. Mind 17: 457-74. 5 My thanks to the anonymous referee whose incisive comments helped considerably in preparing this paper. Personal identity and the radiation argument ERIC T. OLSON 1. Imagine a society of beings like ourselves but more technologically advanced. They have a machine that records the entire state of a human brain and imposes it on another brain (destroying the first brain in the process), creating a person psychologically indistinguishable from the original. These beings - call them the Progressives - often have this done because high levels of radiation in their environment would otherwise ruin ANALYSIS 61.1, January 2001, pp. 38-44.? Eric T. Olson

PERSONAL IDENTITY AND THE RADIATION ARGUMENT 39 their health. They use another machine to make duplicates of themselves with blank brains, which they keep in lead vaults for this purpose. The Progressives take themselves to survive the 'brain-state-transfer' procedure, and act accordingly. They speak of what they themselves will do after their next 'body-change', and of what they did before the previous one. They hold people responsible for the actions of the person from whom they inherited their brain state. Their laws and customs reflecthis: the brain-state recipient is entitled to the brain-state donor's property, is legally married to the donor's spouse, is considered the parent of his or her children, and so on. Imagine further tha the actualaws of nature operate, and that there are no immaterial souls or the like. The Progressives know this, and know all the relevant physical facts about how the transfer procedure works. According to Sydney Shoemaker, this story suggests that we could literally move from one human being to another by having our brain state 'transferred'. He writes, There is no clear sense in which [the Progressives] can be said to be mistaken about a matter of fact in regarding the procedure as personpreserving. If we confronted such a society, there would, I think, be a very strong case for saying that what they mean by 'person' is such that the BST-procedure is person-preserving (using'person' in their sense)... But there would also be a strong reason for saying that what they mean by 'person' is what we mean by it; they call the same things persons, offer the same characterizations of what sorts of things persons are, and attach the same kinds of social consequences to judgments of personal identity - that is, personal identity has with them the same connections with moral responsibility, ownership of property, etc. as it does with us. But if they are right in thinking that the BST-procedure is person-preserving, and if they mean the same by 'person' as we do, then it seems that we ought to regard the BSTprocedure as person-preserving. (1984: 109f. See also 1997: 299f. For a similar argument, not involving radiation, see Hirsch 1982: 290f.) I will call this the Radiation Argument. Naturally radiation, or for that matter brain-state transfer, is only an accidental feature of it. Shoemaker takes much the same argument to show that a person would go along with his transplanted cerebrum (1999: 292-94). Other variants are easily imagined. The argument has two main premisses. First, the Progressives are correct in believing that they survive brain-state transfer. More precisely, what they mean by 'person' is such that 'persons' in that sense survive it. I take this to mean that the things they use their personal pronouns and proper names to denote really do survive brain-state transfer. Second, they mean the same

40 ERIC T. OLSON by 'person' as we do. A Progressive who says, 'I am fiftyears old,' means the same as you and I mean when we say it. I take this to imply that the referents of their personal pronouns are the same beings, or at any rate the same kind of beings, as the referents of our own pronouns. Now if what the Progressives mean by 'person' is such that persons in that sense really do survive brain-state transfer, and they mean by 'person' what we mean by it, so that we ourselves are persons in that sense, then it follows that we too can survive brain-state transfer. Hence, a liberal sort of psychological continuity would be sufficient for us to persist through time, and physical or spatio-temporal continuity would be unnecessary. This would be an important result, ruling out a wide range of alternative views about our identity through time. 2. What are we to make of this argument? Perhaps the most obvious question is why the Progressives couldn't be mistaken in believing that their machine moves them from one human being to another. If the argument is to have any force, there must be some reason to suppose their belief to be true other than the antecedent conviction that we ourselves, or persons in general, could survive this. Why should anyone unsure about whether we could survive brain-state transfer agree that the Progressives could survive it? What principle lies behind the claim that, because the Progressives understand how the procedure works, their belief that they survive it must be true? Presumably Shoemaker doesn't think that their belief is made true by the mere fact that they hold it and act as if it were true. A society can believe virtually anything and act accordingly. They might believe in a theistic god and live sincerely religious lives. Clearly that wouldn't make it the case that there was a theistic god. Nor can we suppose that the Progressives' believing that they survive brain-state transfer is strong evidence for their surviving it. We are given no reason to think that they are especially acute metaphysicians. The view, rather, is that there is somehow nothing for them to be mistaken about. We could understand how they might be mistaken, Shoemaker says, if their belief were based on the false assumption that the machine transferred immaterial soul. But they are supposed to be 'under no misconception concerning matters of fact' (1984: 109). This is puzzling. Isn't it a matter of fact whether someone whose brain is altered in a certain way survives or perishes? Either she does or she doesn't (or it is indeterminate). Whichever it is, anyone who thinks otherwise is mistaken. How could there be nothing to get wrong? And if there is nothing to get wrong, how could there be something to get right? We could understand Shoemaker's claim if the Progressives' talk of personal identity were not about numerical identity at all, but about some other relation that uncontroversially holds in the relevant situations.

PERSONAL IDENTITY AND THE RADIATION ARGUMENT 41 Suppose that what made it true to say that Martha went in for her brainstate transfer yesterday and came out with a new body today was not that any one being did both those things, but tha the one who did the first related in a certain way that did not imply numerical identity to the one who did the second, and that a social convention made it appropriate to speak and act as if beings related in that way were identical. (Compare: what makes it true to say thathe Prime Minister was a woman ten years ago and is a man now is not anyone changed sex, but only that a certain woman of ten years ago relates in a way not implying identity - holding the same political office - to a certain man of today.) Then there would indeed be nothing for the Progressives to be mistaken about, unless they are mistaken about which beings did what when and whether they relate in that way. The way the Progressives think and act would suffice to put the relevant convention in place, and claims made in accordance with it would be true. But Shoemaker says explicitly that we are to take the Progressives' statements to express numerical identity (1999: 393) - as they must if the argument is to show anything about our numerical identity. Or someone might say thathere are rational, intelligent, self-conscious beings that can survive brain-state transfer - BST-survivors for short. In facthere are as many BST-survivors as there are Progressives: every Progressive in some sense coincides with a BST-survivor. In that case, the Progessives' belief that they survive brain-state transfer could be false only if their personal pronouns and proper names failed to denote BSTsurvivors. But the way the Progressives think and act would surely suffice for their pronouns to pick out BST-survivors if there are any to be picked out. Hence their belief, in the circumstances, would be true. But if this is what Shoemaker is assuming (as it seems to be), he owes us an argument for it. Many respected philosophers doubt whether there are or even could be BST-survivors. If this doubt is intelligible, then we can understand perfectly well how the Progressives could be mistaken in thinking thathey survive brain-state transfer: there may simply be nothing heaven or on earth that could survive such a thing. Perhaps the Radiation Argument is simply directed at those who already accepthe existence of BST-survivors. (They are not rare.) Every argument needs premisses, and no argument will persuade everyone. But this would deprive the argument of any real interest. Anyone who believes in the existence of BST-survivors will almost certainly already believe that our identity consists in psychological continuity of the sorthat obtains the brain-state-transfer case. No one ever thought that, although there are BST-survivors, we are not those things. For an argument to have any persuasive force, it must give those who don't yet accept its conclusion a reason to do so. But there is unlikely to be anyone who, before encoun-

42 ERIC T. OLSON tering the Radiation Argument, found its hidden premiss more probable than its conclusion. So it looks as if no one has any use for Shoemaker's argument. 3. Perhaps, somewhere, there are philosophers in need of the Radiation Argument. Or perhaps the first premiss, that the Progressives are not mistaken, can be defended in another way. In any case, the argument faces a second problem, independent of the first. If the Progressives' beliefs about what they can survive must be true, then presumably the same goes for other imaginary societies who hold beliefs about survival inconsistent with theirs. And if whathose other societies believe abouthemselves must hold for us as well, we get a conclusion inconsistent with Shoemaker's. Imagine a second society with the same marvellous technology as the first. They too occasionally have their brain state 'transferred' to another head. But they don' take themselves to survive this. They see it as a way of committing suicide - though a nobler and less selfish way of doing so than the usual method, as it typically results in someone willing and able to look after the dead person's affairs. Those who submit to the procedure take tearful leave of their loved ones and expect never to see them again. No one speaks of what he will do after his next body-change, or what he did before his last one. The recipient of a person's brain state is never held responsible for the donor's actions, does not incur his debts, is not considered married to his spouse, is called by another name, and so on. Imagine further thathese beings - call them the Conservatives - are subject to the same laws of nature as we are, and have no false beliefs about how the device works. If we take the Radiation Argument as our model, it seems we must conclude thathe Conservatives are correct in believing thathey don't survive brain-state transfer. More precisely, whathey mean by 'person' is such that brain-state transfer is not person-preserving. The things they call persons and use their personal pronouns to denote do not and could not survive such a thing. You might think thathe Conservatives and Progressives don't really disagree, but simply mean different things by 'person'. But this is hard to accept given thathe Progressives mean by 'person' what we mean. That, Shoemaker said, was because 'they call the same things persons, offer the same characterizations of what sorts of things persons are, and attach the same kinds of social consequences to judgements of personal identity - that is, personal identity has with them the same connections with moral responsibility, ownership of property, etc. as it does with us' (1984: 110). This holds equally for the Conservatives. Hence, Shoemaker's reasoning suggests thathe Conservatives' personal pronouns refer to the same beings, or at any rate the same kind of beings, as our own.

PERSONAL IDENTITY AND THE RADIATION ARGUMENT 43 But now the trouble is only too plain. If the things the Conservatives call persons really cannot survive brain-state transfer, and they are precisely the things we call persons, then it follows that we too cannot survive brainstate transfer. So the sort of mental continuity that obtains in brain-state transfer is not sufficient for us to persist - contrary to the conclusion of the Radiation Argument. And since either argument would appear to be sound if the other is, both must fail. Someone might avoid the conflict by saying that what we mean by 'person' is indeterminate as between what the Progressives mean and what the Conservatives mean. Our concept of a person is not precise enough to determine whether we could survive brain-state transfer. I suppose this means that the way we use our personal pronouns and other expressions does not determine whether they refer to BST-survivors or to rational beings that could not survive brain-state transfer (rational human animals, for instance). But this would not support the Radiation Argument. It contradicts the argument'second premiss, that we mean the same by 'person' as the Progressives mean. Worse, it would make it indeterminate whether 'we' could survive brain-state transfer, whereas the conclusion was meant to be that we could definitely survive it. To defend the Radiation Argument, we must show that the parallel argument commits some fallacy that the original argument avoids. Perhaps the Conservatives could be mistaken about whether they survive brain-state transfer in a way that the Progressives could not be: although there is nothing for the Progressives to be mistaken about, there is somehow room for the Conservatives to get it wrong. Or there may be reason to think that the Conservatives, despite appearances, don't mean by 'person' what we mean by it, a reason that somehow doesn't apply to the Progressives. But the only ground I can see for either claim is the antecedent conviction that, although there are BST-survivors, there are no rational beings that cannot survive brain-state transfer, or, alternatively, that what we mean by 'person' implies that we could survive brain-state transfer. And to suppose such a thing at the outset would be to assume the point at issue. Or someone might think that the second story is impossible or unintelligible in a way that the original is not. In some ways the Conservatives may be harder to imagine than the Progressives. The beings who resulted from brain-state transfer in my story would be in the odd position of apparently remembering all and only the past experiences of what they took to be someone else. They would tend to feel responsible for what they thought were someone else's acts. Their relations with their predecessors' friends and relatives might be awkward. (Imagine trying to persuade a child who resulted from the procedure that she is not the person she thinks she is.) And so on.

44 DAVID SOBEL & DAVID COPP This hardly suggests that the Conservatives are psychologically impossible, especially if we are willing to grant the possibility of brain-state transfer or cerebrum transplant. At best one might argue that, because the Conservatives are harder to imagine than the Progressives, the Progressives are right to think that they survive brain-state transfer while the Conservatives are mistaken to think that they don't. But then Shoemaker's argument would come to little more than this: in a certain frame of mind (trying to imagine what it would be like), we find it easier to believe that we could survive brain-state transfer than to believe the contrary; therefore we could survive it. This may have some force, though it also faces well-known difficulties (in other frames of mind - in listening to an entertaining story, for instance - we find it easy to accept all sorts of things whose possibility would otherwise be doubtful). Whatever its merits, though, this is hardly the substantial new argument Shoemaker appeared to be giving. I conclude that the Radiation Argument provides no new reason to suppose that we could survive brain-state transfer, cerebrum transplant, or anything else.1 Churchill College Cambridge CB3 ODS, UK Eric. Olson@phil.cam.ac.uk References Hirsch, E. 1982. The Concept of Identity. New York: Oxford University Press. Shoemaker, S. 1984. Personal identity: A materialist's account. In S. Shoemaker and R. Swinburne, Personal Identity. Oxford: Blackwell. Shoemaker, S. 1997. Self and substance. Philosophical Perspectives 11: 283-319. Shoemaker, S. 1999. Self, body, and coincidence. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society Suppl. Vol. 73: 287-306. 1 I thank Sydney Shoemaker for comments on an earlier version. Against direction of fit accounts of belief and desire DAVID SOBEL & DAVID COPP Champions of Humean belief-desire psychology have long tried to flesh out Hume's claim that a desire does not contain 'any representative quality, which renders it a copy of any other existence or modification' (Hume ANALYSIS 61.1, January 2001, pp. 44-53.? David Sobel and David Copp