Phenomenology and Metaphysical Realism 1. Robert D. Stolorow. Abstract: This article examines the relationship between totalitarianism and the

Similar documents
Janus Head: Journal of Interdisciplinary Studies in Literature, Continental Philosophy, Phenomenological Psychology, and the Arts, in press.

Love, Loss, and Finitude

Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics 1. By Tom Cumming

THE TRAGIC AND THE METAPHYSICAL IN PHILOSOPHY AND PSYCHOANALYSIS

Theories of the mind have been celebrating their new-found freedom to study

Perspectival Methods in Metaphysics

Wittgenstein on The Realm of Ineffable

TILLICH ON IDOLATRY. beyond the God of theism... the ground of being and meaning" (RS, p. 114). AUL TILLICH'S concept of idolatry, WILLIAM P.

Issue 4, Special Conference Proceedings Published by the Durham University Undergraduate Philosophy Society

Introduction to SUNY Series in Constructive Postmodern Thought 1

Can A Priori Justified Belief Be Extended Through Deduction? It is often assumed that if one deduces some proposition p from some premises

Follow this and additional works at: Part of the Philosophy Commons

Political Science 206 Modern Political Philosophy Spring Semester 2011 Clark University

Response to The Problem of the Question About Animal Ethics by Michal Piekarski

Why I Am Not a Property Dualist By John R. Searle

Verificationism. PHIL September 27, 2011

At the Frontiers of Reality

In essence, Swinburne's argument is as follows:

Guest Editor s Preface On the premises of the mind-body problem: an unexpected German path?

Ayer on the criterion of verifiability

SIMON BOSTOCK Internal Properties and Property Realism

Can Rationality Be Naturalistically Explained? Jeffrey Dunn. Abstract: Dan Chiappe and John Vervaeke (1997) conclude their article, Fodor,

Rule-Following and the Ontology of the Mind Abstract The problem of rule-following

MY PURPOSE IN THIS BOOK IS TO PRESENT A

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

Issues in Thinking about God. Michaelmas Term 2008 Johannes Zachhuber

Skepticism and Internalism

COURSE SYLLABUS PHL 551: BEING AND TIME II

A Philosophical Study of Nonmetaphysical Approach towards Human Existence

EXAM PREP (Semester 2: 2018) Jules Khomo. Linguistic analysis is concerned with the following question:

1 Hans Jonas, The Imperative of Responsibility: In Search of an Ethics for the Technological Age (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984), 1-10.

NATURALISED JURISPRUDENCE

Process Thought and Bridge Building: A Response to Stephen K. White. Kevin Schilbrack

Heidegger's What is Metaphysics?

DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA, RIVERSIDE. Graduate course and seminars for Fall Quarter

Martin s case for disjunctivism

Contemporary Theology I: Hegel to Death of God Theologies

COURSE SYLLABUS PHL 550: BEING AND TIME I

SUPPOSITIONAL REASONING AND PERCEPTUAL JUSTIFICATION

The Middle Path: A Case for the Philosophical Theologian. Leo Strauss roots the vitality of Western civilization in the ongoing conflict between

Experiences Don t Sum

The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel s Idealism

Philosophical dialogues against totalitarianism Anne Schjelderup

Two books, one title. And what a title! Two leading academic publishers have

Broad on Theological Arguments. I. The Ontological Argument

Tuukka Kaidesoja Précis of Naturalizing Critical Realist Social Ontology

In Search of a Political Ethics of Intersubjectivity: Between Hannah Arendt, Emmanuel Levinas and the Judaic

Canadian Society for Continental Philosophy

POWERS, NECESSITY, AND DETERMINISM

The Cosmological Argument, Sufficient Reason, and Why-Questions

Friedrich Nietzsche and European Nihilism Paul van Tongeren

Review of This Is Not Sufficient: An Essay on Animality and Human Nature in Derrida. Leonard Lawlor Columbia University Press pp.

PHILOSOPHY (PHIL) Philosophy (PHIL) 1

Edmund Husserl s Transcendental Phenomenology by Wendell Allan A. Marinay

Philosophy of Science. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

Craig on the Experience of Tense

On the Rationality of Metaphysical Commitments in Immature Science

Haecceitas and the Question of Being: Heidegger and Duns Scotus

Philosophy of Consciousness

ALTERNATIVE SELF-DEFEAT ARGUMENTS: A REPLY TO MIZRAHI

From Necessary Truth to Necessary Existence

Summary of Sensorama: A Phenomenalist Analysis of Spacetime and Its Contents

Martin Heidegger: Nature History State

Metametaphysics. New Essays on the Foundations of Ontology* Oxford University Press, 2009

How Will I Be Graded in This Class?

A phenomenological interpretation of religion via pre-socratic thinking. University of Notre Dame Australia

Department of Philosophy, UOH. Course code: PH701. Class: M. Phil. Semester: I. Number of credits 4. Method of evaluation:

OBJECTIVITY WITHOUT THE PHILOSOPHER S SPECIAL OBJECTS: A PRIORIAN PROGRAM. James Van Cleve, University of Southern California

Authentic Historicality and National Socialism in Being and Time

Tuomas E. Tahko (University of Helsinki)

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg

Alternative Conceptual Schemes and a Non-Kantian Scheme-Content Dualism

This is a collection of fourteen previously unpublished papers on the fit

Sometimes doing what is Right has No Right Answer: On Hilary Putnam s Pragmatism with Existential Choices

Heidegger s Unzuhandenheit as a Fourth Mode of Being

Welcome back to week 2 of this edition of 5pm Church Together.

PART TWO: DEATH AS AN ONTIC EVENT: coming to terms with the phenomenon of death as a determinate possibility

Kevin MacNeil, Culver Academies

Metaphysics: Objects, People, and Possible Worlds. Syllabus

The Illusion of Scientific Realism: An Argument for Scientific Soft Antirealism

Yuval Dolev, Time and Realism, MIT Press, 2007

The Exeter College Summer Programme at Exeter College in the University of Oxford. Good Life or Moral Life?

PHILOSOPHY DEPARTMENT FALL SEMESTER 2009 COURSE OFFERINGS

Higher-Order Approaches to Consciousness and the Regress Problem

This form of plagiarism also includes getting somebody else to write your work for you (ghost-writing).

3 Supplement. Robert Bernasconi

Fabrizio Luciano, Università degli Studi di Padova

Realism and instrumentalism

UNITY OF KNOWLEDGE (IN TRANSDISCIPLINARY RESEARCH FOR SUSTAINABILITY) Vol. I - Philosophical Holism M.Esfeld

Review on Heidegger and Philosophical Atheology

UNCORRECTED PROOF GOD AND TIME. The University of Mississippi

SUBSISTENCE DEMYSTIFIED. Arnold Cusmariu

Positivism A Model Of For System Of Rules

No t e s, In s i g h t s, a n d Fl a s h e s

McTaggart s Proof of the Unreality of Time

Appropriating Heidegger

Curriculum Vitae. PAUL LIVINGSTON Department of Philosophy MSC University of New Mexico Albuquerque, NM

BOOK REVIEWS. The arguments of the Parmenides, though they do not refute the Theory of Forms, do expose certain problems, ambiguities and

Final Paper. May 13, 2015

Conceivability and Possibility Studies in Frege and Kripke. M.A. Thesis Proposal. Department of Philosophy, CSULB. 25 May 2006

Transcription:

Phenomenology and Metaphysical Realism 1 Robert D. Stolorow Abstract: This article examines the relationship between totalitarianism and the metaphysical illusions on which it rests. Phenomenological investigation is claimed to loosen the grip of totalitarian ideology by exposing its origins in the resurrective illusions that seek to overcome the impact of collective trauma. Phenomenology is thus shown to have emancipatory power. Keywords: phenomenology, metaphysical illusion, resurrective ideology, Manichaeism, collective trauma, finitude, Martin Heidegger, Hannah Arendt, Paul Ricoeur "Philosophical pleading for subjectivity is becoming the citizen's only recourse against the tyrant."--paul Ricoeur, 1977, p. 155 This essay extends an earlier article co-written with George Atwood (Stolorow & Atwood, 2017) in which we joined Wilhelm Dilthey s conception of the metaphysical impulse as a flight from the tragedy of human finitude with Ludwig Wittgenstein s understanding of how language bewitches intelligence. We contended that there are features of the phenomenology of language identified by Wittgenstein in particular, the projection of reified pictures as the meaning of words that play a constitutive and pervasive role in the creation of metaphysical illusion. Unlike Dilthey, who largely 1 Presented at the Annual Southwest Seminar in Continental Philosophy, June 8-10, 2017, California State University, Northridge. 1

reserved the metaphysical impulse to abstract philosophical systems, we extended it to everyday life as well. And unlike Wittgenstein, who believed that the bewitchment of intelligence by language could be overcome by good philosophizing, we argued that such bewitchment is an indelible feature of the never-ending struggle against the traumatizing impact of finitude. Our account of the genesis of metaphysical illusion provides a means of unpacking the claim by Ricoeur with which the present essay begins. Typically, tyranny is supported by some form of totalitarian ideology, and totalitarian ideology, in turn, is ordinarily rooted in a framework of metaphysical illusion or what is oxymoronically characterized as metaphysical realism. In her study of totalitarianism, Hannah Arendt (1951) provided a cogent analysis of the essence of political ideology. Such isms, she said, claim to explain all historical happenings by deducing them from a single self-evident idea or premise for example, that history progresses through the elimination of inferior races (Nazism) or decadent classes (communism). Once established, these ironclad logical systems become, like paranoid delusions, immune to the impact of actual experience. Further, they readily devolve into systems of genocidal terror, as they give warrant to the unbridled liquidation of anyone or anything believed to impede the historical process. An all-too-common form of totalitarian ideology is found in the rhetoric of evil. The seeds of the rhetoric of evil can be found in the ancient religious ideology, originating in Persia and pervasive in contemporary religious fundamentalism, known as Manichaeism the idea that the movement of history is explained by an 2

eternal struggle between the metaphysical forces of good and of evil. In the rhetoric of evil, Manichaeism is harnessed for political purposes one s own group is claimed to embody the forces of good, and the opposing group, the forces of evil. Through such attributions, which are inherently nationalistic or ethnocentric, one s political aims are justified as being in the service of the good. What Ricoeur calls philosophical pleading for subjectivity I want to call phenomenology. As Atwood and I have shown (Stolorow & Atwood, 2017), the phenomenological study of language can be effective in deconstructing metaphysical illusions, including those that support totalitarian ideologies. Heidegger (1927/1962), for example, carries out his phenomenological investigation of the meaning of Being in conjunction with a destruction (p. 44) of traditional ontological concepts in which Being is regarded as some sort of metaphysical entity. As distinct from a metaphysical essence that inheres in entities themselves, Heidegger conceives of the Being of entities in terms of how they are intelligible or understandable to us as the entities they are. The Being of entities thus depends on human understanding the clearing that lights up their intelligibility. Heidegger argues that because an unarticulated, pre-philosophical understanding of our own Being is constitutive of our kind of Being, we humans can investigate our own kind of Being by investigating our understanding (and lack of understanding) of that Being. Accordingly, it follows that his investigative method is to be a phenomenological one, aimed at illuminating the fundamental structures of our understanding of our Being: Only as phenomenology, is ontology possible (p. 60). In this formulation, the positing of 3

metaphysical entities and essences gives way to a phenomenological investigation and illumination of how entities, including especially we ourselves, are intelligible. Soon after the publication of Being and Time, Heidegger turned his attention from the Being of entities to Being as such, a phrase that seems to point in a metaphysical direction. Indeed, inspired by the poet Holderlin as his guide to a spiritual awakening, he characterizes Being as such as a divine force or energy, sent to the properly receptive human being (Heidegger 1968/1972). In recent years a debate has been taking place among members of the Heidegger Circle as to whether the later Heidegger remained dedicated to phenomenological inquiry or turned instead to a form of metaphysical realism. The crux of the debate concerns the question of whether Being as such remains dependent on the human being (phenomenology) or is independent of the human beings who experience it (metaphysical realism). Over the years proponents of both sides of the debate have marshaled plausible support from Heidegger s original texts. Perhaps we can conclude that this debate reflects a conflict within Heidegger himself over these two opposing conceptions, a conflict rooted in his own experiential world. There is one context, however, in which Heidegger s pivot toward metaphysical realism is undeniable namely, his embrace of Nazi ideology. Heidegger s version of Nazism reflected his own dream of Being, whereby he seemed to experience the Nazi takeover of Germany as an upsurge of Being itself bursting forth in historical reality. He envisioned a second beginning in the history of Being (the first occurring in ancient Greece) in which he himself would be a spiritual leader. Returning to the claim made by Ricoeur, how can phenomenology help emancipate people from such metaphysical illusions? In a chapter co-written with George Atwood 4

and Donna Orange (in Stolorow, 2011, chapter 9), we argued that for Heidegger Nazism was an example of what we called resurrective ideology, which served to restore a sense of agentic selfhood dismantled by a series of devastating traumatic occurrences. A similar restorative purpose can be served on a socio-political scale by destructive ideologies that take form in the wake of collective trauma witness, for example, the rise of Manichean rhetoric in the aftermath of the terrorist attack on the World Trade Center on September 11, 2001 (Stolorow, 2009). How can phenomenological inquiry loosen the grip of such restorative ideological illusions? It can do so by helping people understand and dwell in the traumas individual or collective that underpin them, thereby providing the emotional devastation with a dialogical home in which it can be held and better borne (Stolorow, 2016), rendering the evasive resurrective ideological illusions less necessary. If, as Braver (2012) quips, Phenomenology lets metaphysicians heal themselves (p. 31), perhaps it can do something similar for ideologues. References Arendt, H. (1951). Totalitarianism. New York: Harcourt. Braver, L. (2012). Groundless Grounds: A Study of Wittgenstein and Heidegger. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Heidegger, M. (1962). Being and Time, trans. J. Macquarrie & E. Robinson. New York: Harper & Row. (Original work published 1927) Heidegger, M. (1972). Time and being. In On Time and Being, ed. J. Stambaugh. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, pp. 1-24. (Original work published 1968) Ricoeur, P. (1977). Patocka, philosopher and resister. Telos, 31:152-155. 5

Stolorow, R. D. (2009). Identity and resurrective ideology in an age of trauma. Psychoanalytic Psychology, 26, 206-209. Stolorow, R. D. (2011). World, Affectivity, Trauma: Heidegger and Post-Cartesian Psychoanalysis. New York: Routledge. Stolorow, R. D. (2016). Pain is not pathology. Existential Analysis, 27(1), 70-74. Stolorow, R. D. & Atwood, G. E. (2017). The phenomenology of language and the metaphysicalizing of the real. Language and Psychoanalysis, 6(1), 4-9. 6