DO TROPES RESOLVE THE PROBLEM OF MENTAL CAUSATION?

Similar documents
Externalism and a priori knowledge of the world: Why privileged access is not the issue Maria Lasonen-Aarnio

Divine omniscience, timelessness, and the power to do otherwise

PHILOSOPHY OF MIND (7AAN2061) SYLLABUS: SEMESTER 1

SIMON BOSTOCK Internal Properties and Property Realism

Moral requirements are still not rational requirements

The readings for the course are separated into the following two categories:

On An Alleged Non-Equivalence Between Dispositions And Disjunctive Properties

Philosophical Issues, vol. 8 (1997), pp

proper construal of Davidson s principle of rationality will show the objection to be misguided. Andrew Wong Washington University, St.

Resemblance Nominalism and counterparts

CHAPTER 11. There is no Exclusion Problem

DO SENSE EXPERIENTIAL STATES HAVE CONCEPTUAL CONTENT?

Outsmarting the McKinsey-Brown argument? 1

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW

Why I Am Not a Property Dualist By John R. Searle

The deepest and most formidable presentation to date of the reductionist interpretation

TEMPORAL NECESSITY AND LOGICAL FATALISM. by Joseph Diekemper

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

THE PROBLEM WITH SOCIAL TRINITARIANISM: A REPLY TO WIERENGA

Merricks on the existence of human organisms

To appear in J. Greco, ed., Philosophers and their Critics: Ernest Sosa, Oxford: Blackwell. Sosa on Abilities, Concepts and Externalism

Against the Vagueness Argument TUOMAS E. TAHKO ABSTRACT


New Aristotelianism, Routledge, 2012), in which he expanded upon

Is there a good epistemological argument against platonism? DAVID LIGGINS

Markie, Speckles, and Classical Foundationalism

Buck-Passers Negative Thesis

A note on Bishop s analysis of the causal argument for physicalism.

The Argument for Anomalous Monism, Again Deren Olgun

TWO ACCOUNTS OF THE NORMATIVITY OF RATIONALITY

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

Bertrand Russell Proper Names, Adjectives and Verbs 1

Quine s Naturalized Epistemology, Epistemic Normativity and the. Gettier Problem

Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible?

Experiences Don t Sum

The Zygote Argument remixed

Under contract with Oxford University Press Karen Bennett Cornell University

Kantian Humility and Ontological Categories Sam Cowling University of Massachusetts, Amherst

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori

Skepticism and Internalism

Wright on response-dependence and self-knowledge

THE CAMBRIDGE SOLUTION TO THE TIME OF A KILLING LAWRENCE B. LOMBARD

Lecture 3: Properties II Nominalism & Reductive Realism. Lecture 3: Properties II Nominalism & Reductive Realism

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Jeffrey, Richard, Subjective Probability: The Real Thing, Cambridge University Press, 2004, 140 pp, $21.99 (pbk), ISBN

The Paradox of the stone and two concepts of omnipotence

Philosophical Perspectives, 16, Language and Mind, 2002 THE AIM OF BELIEF 1. Ralph Wedgwood Merton College, Oxford

Note: This is the penultimate draft of an article the final and definitive version of which is

Subjective Character and Reflexive Content

DANCY ON ACTING FOR THE RIGHT REASON

SWINBURNE ON THE EUTHYPHRO DILEMMA. CAN SUPERVENIENCE SAVE HIM?

SIMPLICITY AND ASEITY. Jeffrey E. Brower. There is a traditional theistic doctrine, known as the doctrine of divine simplicity,

The Paradox of the Question

Ayer and Quine on the a priori

BOOK REVIEWS. Duke University. The Philosophical Review, Vol. XCVII, No. 1 (January 1988)

Epistemic Consequentialism, Truth Fairies and Worse Fairies

Nozick and Scepticism (Weekly supervision essay; written February 16 th 2005)

The Kripkenstein Paradox and the Private World. In his paper, Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Languages, Kripke expands upon a conclusion

Excluding the Problem: Bennett on Counterfactual Tests and Backtracking

Rule-Following and the Ontology of the Mind Abstract The problem of rule-following

Philosophy 125 Day 13: Overview

Philosophy 125 Day 12: Overview

Book Reviews 427. University of Manchester Oxford Rd., M13 9PL, UK. doi: /mind/fzl424

Philosophy Epistemology Topic 5 The Justification of Induction 1. Hume s Skeptical Challenge to Induction

UC Berkeley UC Berkeley Previously Published Works

Could have done otherwise, action sentences and anaphora

Intro to Ground. 1. The idea of ground. 2. Relata. are facts): F 1. More-or-less equivalent phrases (where F 1. and F 2. depends upon F 2 F 2


Modal Realism, Counterpart Theory, and Unactualized Possibilities

1/13. Locke on Power

Philosophical Writings Vol. 43 No.1 HOW NOT TO NATURALISE ACTION

SMITH ON TRUTHMAKERS 1. Dominic Gregory. I. Introduction

Generic truth and mixed conjunctions: some alternatives

The Exclusion Problem Meets the Problem of Many Causes Matthew C. Haug The College of William & Mary

Bertrand Russell and the Problem of Consciousness

Kant s Freedom and Transcendental Idealism

On the Prospects of Confined and Catholic Physicalism. Andreas Hüttemann

Humean Supervenience: Lewis (1986, Introduction) 7 October 2010: J. Butterfield

Conditions of Fundamental Metaphysics: A critique of Jorge Gracia's proposal

Stang (p. 34) deliberately treats non-actuality and nonexistence as equivalent.

Faith and Philosophy, April (2006), DE SE KNOWLEDGE AND THE POSSIBILITY OF AN OMNISCIENT BEING Stephan Torre

Predictability, Causation, and Free Will

A Review of Neil Feit s Belief about the Self

Philosophical Perspectives, 14, Action and Freedom, 2000 TRANSFER PRINCIPLES AND MORAL RESPONSIBILITY. Eleonore Stump Saint Louis University

Truthmakers and explanation

THINKING ANIMALS AND EPISTEMOLOGY

DOES STRONG COMPATIBILISM SURVIVE FRANKFURT COUNTER-EXAMPLES?

Are There Reasons to Be Rational?

Issue 4, Special Conference Proceedings Published by the Durham University Undergraduate Philosophy Society

THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE

Vagueness in sparseness: a study in property ontology

Is anything knowable on the basis of understanding alone?

SUBJECTIVISM ABOUT NORMATIVITY AND THE NORMATIVITY OF INTENTIONAL STATES Michael Gorman

Quine on the analytic/synthetic distinction

Formative Assessment: 2 x 1,500 word essays First essay due 16:00 on Friday 30 October 2015 Second essay due: 16:00 on Friday 11 December 2015

Utilitarianism: For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), pp Reprinted in Moral Luck (CUP, 1981).

A PROBLEM WITH DEFINING TESTIMONY: INTENTION AND MANIFESTATION:

POWERS, NECESSITY, AND DETERMINISM

British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 62 (2011), doi: /bjps/axr026

The Metaphysics of Perfect Beings, by Michael Almeida. New York: Routledge, Pp $105.00

Transcription:

DO TROPES RESOLVE THE PROBLEM OF MENTAL CAUSATION? 221 DO TROPES RESOLVE THE PROBLEM OF MENTAL CAUSATION? BY PAUL NOORDHOF One of the reasons why the problem of mental causation appears so intractable is that there is no general agreement about what would constitute a legitimate way of dealing with the problem. For instance, Donald Davidson appears to think that there is no problem for his theory because (i) Mental events are physical events (ii) These physical events are efficacious (iii) Causal relations hold between particulars and not in virtue of properties of particulars (iv) Events are particulars. 1 But his critics think that there is a separate question of whether mental events cause other events in virtue of their physical properties or their mental properties. They claim (falsely in my opinion) that other parts of Davidson s theory suggest that he is committed to replying in virtue of their physical properties, if only he would allow the question. 2 Precisely the same difficulty arises with regard to David Robb s recent paper. 3 Robb puts forward the idea that if we take tropes to be those things in virtue of which causal relations hold ( the properties of causation, p. 187), we can resolve one pressing problem of mental causation. Tropes are abstract particulars, wholly present in individuals but logically incapable of being present in two individuals at the same time. By contrast, universals are wholly present in individuals and capable of being present in more than one individual at the same time. To give Robb s illustration, on the trope view the yellowness of two bananas involves two distinct tropes of yellow. It is admitted that these two tropes are similar, but we must be careful not to say that they are similar because they share the trope yellow. Concrete particulars, on the other hand, have tropes bananas have yellow tropes. Officially, Robb is neutral about types that is, about whatever explains the fact that we can truly say two yellow bananas have the same colour. Types are either sets of resembling tropes or universals (see pp. 186 8). 1 Donald Davidson, Thinking Causes, in J. Heil and A. Mele (eds), Mental Causation (Oxford UP, 1993), pp. 3 17. 2 For instance J. Kim, Can Supervenience and Non-Strict Laws Save Anomalous Monism?, in Heil and Mele, pp. 19 26, at p. 23; B.P. McLaughlin, On Davidson s Response to the Charge of Epiphenomenalism, in Heil and Mele, pp. 27 40, at pp. 37 9; E. Sosa, Davidson s Thinking Causes, in Heil and Mele, pp. 41 50, at pp. 45 8. 3 D. Robb, The Properties of Mental Causation, The Philosophical Quarterly, 47 (1997), pp. 178 94.

222 PAUL NOORDHOF Everybody can agree that tropes are causes. 4 Robb seeks to establish that causal relations hold in virtue of tropes rather than types. His aim is to challenge the assumption that the properties of resemblance are the properties of causation (e.g., at p. 192). So when we say the pear depressed the scale pan in virtue of having weight that the pear s weight was causally relevant we are talking of a weight trope, not type. 5 My aim is to consider whether Robb s trope approach is successful in resolving the problem he identifies (the answer will be No ), and to compare his approach with the event approach criticized by him. I shall argue that no advance has been made on this other approach and, indeed, that the trope approach in general will not help us to resolve the problem of mental causation. The problem Robb addresses is generated by the following three claims: Distinctness: mental properties are not physical properties (p. 182) Closure: every physical event has in its causal history only physical events and properties (p. 183) Relevance: mental properties are (sometimes) causally relevant to physical events (p. 180). Robb accepts that mental types are distinct from physical types hence Distinctness holds for types. However, he denies that mental tropes are distinct from physical tropes. Hence he retains Closure for tropes reading tropes for properties in the formulation above. But since mental tropes are physical tropes, he can retain Relevance reading tropes for properties there too. So all is well with the world. On hearing this solution, one is tempted to ask the same question as Davidson has been asked. Is it in virtue of a trope s being a mental trope that mental tropes cause things? Question not allowed. It is a singular merit of Robb s paper that he presents considerations to show how this question is less appropriate than the question posed for Davidson, and attempts to massage our objections away. But it is hard not to remain unsatisfied, feeling that the problem has been dealt with by metaphysical sleight of hand and by a suitable dose of obstinacy at certain points. How can we resolve the issue? It is one thing to have nagging worries; it is quite another to have a substantial line of complaint. I suggest the following constraint upon any solution of the problem of mental causation (indeed, I suspect that the constraint has more general application and is fairly widely recognized) the bulge in the carpet constraint: 4 See D. Ehring, Mental Causation, Determinables, and Property Instances, Noûs, 30 (1996), pp. 461 80, at pp. 465 7. 5 The position has also been advanced in C. and G. Macdonald, Mental Causes and the Explanation of Action (MCEA), The Philosophical Quarterly, 36 (1986), pp. 145 58, repr. in L.F. Stevenson et al. (eds), Mind, Causation and Action (Oxford: Blackwell, 1986), pp. 35 48 (page references below to the latter), at pp. 37 40; G. Macdonald, The Nature of Naturalism (NN), Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Suppl. Vol. 66 (1992), pp. 225 44, at pp. 231, 235 7; C. and G. Macdonald, How to be Psychologically Relevant (HPR), in C. and G. Macdonald (eds), Philosophy of Psychology (Oxford: Blackwell, 1995), pp. 60 77; J. Heil, The Nature of True Minds (Cambridge UP, 1992), pp. 135 9. In HPR the Macdonalds talk in terms of property-instances, but claim that these are not tropes because the latter are essentially typed whereas the former are not (p. 74 fn. 9). Not much is made of this difference; we can safely ignore it here.

DO TROPES RESOLVE THE PROBLEM OF MENTAL CAUSATION? 223 No candidate solution to a philosophical problem should raise another problem which appears just as intractable and which requires the resolution of an issue similar to that which made the original problem so intractable. If it does, then it is plausible that the solution has been achieved by linguistic fiat and the problem has not gone away. So I counsel looking at Robb s proposal to see whether the problem of mental causation can be raised in a new way. To get our bearings, let us return to the disallowed question. The issue is whether it is legitimate to ask Was it in virtue of being a mental trope or a physical trope that this particular trope caused E?. Robb says (p. 191) that A causally relevant property F simply does not have various aspects such that one can legitimately ask whether some but not others are responsible for F s being causally relevant. We do not ask whether mass was efficacious in virtue of being mass. He suggests that this point applies whatever view one adopts of the properties of causation. In fact it does not seem to apply for any view, as the property of being air shows. My house burns down. It is quite legitimate to ask which aspect of air was responsible. The answer is that the air was causally relevant in virtue of being part oxygen. So it seems that complex properties do have aspects concerning which one can ask Was that responsible?, namely, their constituents. In Robb s own example a red ball is dropped on a sheet of metal, causing a dent. He suggests that, once we have recognized that there was a dent because the ball had mass, we should not ask the further question But was the mass causally relevant qua mass?. This appears wrong. Suppose that cricket balls would have dented the metal whereas tennis balls (with less mass) would not. We might allow that the red ball causes a dent qua having mass, but go on to say that, more specifically, it was qua having a mass of 5lb. rather than just qua mass. It also seems that, if two properties stand as determinate to determinable, we can ask Which is relevant?. So we have two perfectly clear senses in which properties can have aspects which raise questions of causal relevance. Robb suggests that another reason for rejecting this type of question is that there is a danger of vicious regress. If we allow that we can ask whether or not a particular aspect of a property is causally relevant, then we should also allow that we can ask whether a particular aspect of an aspect was causally relevant, and so on. This worry seems overstated. First, it is hard to see why the regress is vicious. Either there are aspectless properties or there are not. If there are aspectless properties, then there will be properties for which the regress comes to an end. If there are no aspectless properties, then it is true that there will always be a further question about whether an aspect of a particular property was causally relevant. But this seems entirely legitimate, given that there will always be aspects of aspects. The regress just reflects the way the world is, and there is nothing we can do about that. If Robb s argument did work, we could provide a similar argument to show that there must be some properties without aspects. If there were no aspectless properties, then we would have a regress. For each property, we would be able to ask what aspects it had. This would give rise to a whole series of questions of the sort Robb counsels against. So

224 PAUL NOORDHOF there must be aspectless properties. But if there are aspectless properties, then there will be no regress in the case of causal relevance because we would reach bedrock with these aspectless properties. The upshot is that, if I am wrong about the regress not being vicious, then it seems we can appeal to this fact to demonstrate that it is all right to enquire about the causal relevance of aspects of properties. These points at least throw into question Robb s claim (p. 191) that our practice of assuming that types are causally relevant is incoherent or misconceived. However, it is worth considering whether Robb can defend his strategy as a reform of our practice of attributing causal relevance even if it cannot capture unreconstructedly all that we are inclined to say. The thought would be that since the problem of mental causation does not arise in the new perspective, and since the three claims (Distinctness, Closure and Relevance) are independently compelling, we should reform our practice in the way that Robb indicates. Unfortunately, the problem does arise. It is only because a particular issue is ducked in Robb s paper that it apparently does not. The distinctive feature of the trope approach is that what unites tropes under one type is not something that can be considered causally relevant. So the following two questions are disallowed, depending on how one understands types: (a) (b) Was it the ball s possession of the universal mass or of the universal 5lb.-mass which was causally relevant? Was it the ball s exact resemblance to other balls in respect of mass or in respect of 5lb.-mass which was causally relevant? But we can find other ways of asking the same question within the trope perspective. Thus (c) Was the mass trope or the 5lb.-mass trope causally relevant? (Alternatively, was the ball s possession of a mass trope or its possession of a 5lb.-mass trope causally relevant?) Why does Robb think that such questions cannot arise? It seems to me that the answer is that he has a certain view of when two tropes are identical. In this case, he thinks that the mass trope and the 5lb.-mass trope are identical, and so the contrast which question (c) draws is not appropriate. But now I think he faces something of a dilemma. Either (since tropes are the properties of causation) the legitimacy of these questions suggests he has the wrong view of trope identity, or their legitimacy is evidence that tropes are not the properties of causation. Let tripes be thought of as property instances which make up the various aspects of tropes. Then perhaps it is tripes rather than tropes that are the properties of causation. The force of this dilemma becomes very clear when Robb squares up to the objection that the trope approach makes too many properties causally relevant. So I suggest that Robb should be taken as conceding that the trope view is open to the objection that faces Davidson s view (if that objection is phrased properly), and as attempting to provide a reply to it in his reply to a related objection from Yablo. 6 6 S. Yablo, Mental Causation, The Philosophical Review, 101 (1992), pp. 245 80, at pp. 259 60.

DO TROPES RESOLVE THE PROBLEM OF MENTAL CAUSATION? 225 Here is Robb s attempt to deal with the objection in terms of Yablo s example. Suppose (as Robb does) that there is one volume trope in Ella s voice as a result of which it is true that she sings at 70dB or more, 80dB and under 90dB. Any note of over 70dB will shatter the glass. Robb suggests that our inclination to say that 1. Ella s voice caused the glass to shatter in virtue of being over 70dB is true, while 2. Ella s voice caused the glass to shatter in virtue of being under 90dB is false should be explained by their different pragmatic implications. For (1) pragmatically implies that having an over-70db trope is sufficient for causing the glass to shatter which is true. Whereas (2) pragmatically implies that having an under- 90dB trope is sufficient for causing the glass to shatter which is not. There are occasions when it may be identical with a 50dB trope and have no such effect. For the sake of argument, let us agree that this explanation has a certain degree of plausibility in this case. It seems to me that we have only captured the notion of causal relevance by these means if this manœuvre is not available for cases where we would clearly deny that a causal relation held in virtue of the property P. But this is not so. Here is a case of causal relevance that has informed the discussion. Did the glass shatter as a result of the soprano s singing a note in virtue of its pitch or its meaning? We want the answer that it is the pitch which is causally relevant and not the meaning. The question is, how does the trope theorist get this answer? What stops someone from saying that the meaning of the note is causally relevant because the meaning trope is identical to the pitch trope? It is one thing to explain away borderline cases in the way that Robb recommends. It is quite another to appeal to different pragmatic implications to account for our feeling that something is not causally relevant, in cases absolutely central to our understanding of relevance. Until more has been said, any property which co-occurs with an instance of another property which is efficacious can be counted as causally relevant dismissing possible objections that it is not as a matter of pragmatics. The obvious thing to do at this stage is formulate constraints upon when two tropes can legitimately be considered identical and when they cannot. Presumably these conditions cannot just be that two tropes are identical if and only if the causal relevance of one implies the causal relevance of the other. That would trivialize the whole approach. Instead, we must provide an independent account of when two tropes are identical. For instance, we might hold that two types have the same trope on an occasion if one type supervenes on the other. 7 But then we have to go on to explain why properties with these identity-conditions rather than those of tripes which, let us suppose, involve identity (or necessary co-extension) of types rather than mere one-way supervenience are the properties of causation. This just involves us in the problem of mental causation all over again. What we would now need to do is establish that mental tropes are identical to physical tropes according to our account of their identity-conditions, and then show that that makes mental tropes causally relevant. It is the second part the need to show that trope identity 7 See MCEA pp. 39 40, 46 7; NN pp. 237 8; Heil pp. 135 9; HPR pp. 65 7.

226 PAUL NOORDHOF brings with it relevance that resurrects the problem. It is for this reason that I think that Robb s account (indeed, any trope account) fails to satisfy the bulge in the carpet constraint. The problem of mental causation has just been filtered through the problem of trope identity. But it is still there. It is worth underlining this point because it is fundamental. Our commitment to the causal relevance of mental properties is sufficiently strong to provide us with grounds for believing any metaphysical story that succeeds over others in making mental properties causally relevant. This is the basis of claims that the mental properties must be identical with physical properties, or be determinables to determinate properties, or be properties which supervene upon physical properties (see Kim and Yablo). The question is whether the trope approach can provide a satisfying account of the causal relevance of the mental. If it is too easy to be identical to a causally relevant trope, this will provide no solace. So the burden is upon the proponent of such a solution to defend a particular account of when two tropes are identical which succeeds in denying efficacy to those properties that seem causally irrelevant and in allowing causal relevance to those which seem relevant the very problem with which we started. One way of driving this point home is to remark how little further forward we are from the position Robb ascribes to Davidson. Robb criticizes him for being unable to explain how mental properties are causally relevant. But Davidson could say that causal relations between events do not hold in virtue of properties at all, but rather (if anything) in virtue of the very events themselves. He could then give precisely the account of what we are inclined to think about causal relevance to which Robb seems ultimately driven. He could say that (a) (b) The singing of the note caused the shattering of the glass in virtue of its being a singing of a note with a certain meaning The singing of the note caused the shattering of the glass in virtue of its being a singing of a note with a certain pitch were both true. That is because the descriptions following the in virtue of phrase pick out classes of events. In this case, an efficacious event belonged to both classes. The only reason for judging (a) to be false and (b) to be true is that (a) and (b) respectively pragmatically imply that a singing of a note with a certain meaning and a singing of a note with a certain pitch are sufficient for the shattering of the glass. But the former pragmatic implication does not hold. If Robb was not satisfied with such an answer for Davidson, then he should not be satisfied with his own response on behalf of tropes. A satisfactory reply in both cases is an account of trope identity or event identity that does not lose the distinctions we want to make about what is causally relevant and what is not. Until then, it is no comfort that mental tropes are physical tropes. Either the trope solution is false or, at best, it comes in just when the problem has been solved. 8 University of Nottingham 8 I would like to thank Michael Clark and Bob Kirk for helping me to improve this paper.