Journal of Philosophy, Inc.

Similar documents
Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Philosophical Review.

Compatibilism and the Basic Argument

DENNETT ON THE BASIC ARGUMENT JOHN MARTIN FISCHER

Philosophical Review.

Mind Association. Oxford University Press and Mind Association are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Mind.

Bad Luck Once Again. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Vol. LXXVII No. 3, November 2008 Ó 2008 International Phenomenological Society

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

Comprehensive. Hard Determinism Compatibilism. Compatibilism. Soft Determinism. Hard Incompatibilism. Semicompatibilism. Illusionism.

Philosophical Perspectives, 14, Action and Freedom, 2000 TRANSFER PRINCIPLES AND MORAL RESPONSIBILITY. Eleonore Stump Saint Louis University

POWERS, NECESSITY, AND DETERMINISM

Equality of Resources and Equality of Welfare: A Forced Marriage?

A New Argument Against Compatibilism

THE MORAL FIXED POINTS: REPLY TO CUNEO AND SHAFER-LANDAU

DOES STRONG COMPATIBILISM SURVIVE FRANKFURT COUNTER-EXAMPLES?

The Philosophical Review, Vol. 100, No. 3. (Jul., 1991), pp

The Philosophical Review, Vol. 110, No. 3. (Jul., 2001), pp

Free Will. Course packet

The Zygote Argument remixed

History of Education Society

PHILOSOPHY DEPARTMENT FALL SEMESTER 2009 COURSE OFFERINGS

Can Rationality Be Naturalistically Explained? Jeffrey Dunn. Abstract: Dan Chiappe and John Vervaeke (1997) conclude their article, Fodor,

Free Will as an Open Scientific Problem

Kane is Not Able: A Reply to Vicens Self-Forming Actions and Conflicts of Intention

Preface. Hard Determinism Compatibilism. Soft Determinism. Hard Incompatibilism. Semicompatibilism. Illusionism. Impossibilism.

Note: This is the penultimate draft of an article the final and definitive version of which is

Alfred Mele s Modest. Hard Determinism Compatibilism. Libertarianism. Soft Determinism. Hard Incompatibilism. Semicompatibilism.

Tuukka Kaidesoja Précis of Naturalizing Critical Realist Social Ontology

Kantian Humility and Ontological Categories Sam Cowling University of Massachusetts, Amherst

Fischer-Style Compatibilism

Luck, Rationality, and Explanation: A Reply to Elga s Lucky to Be Rational. Joshua Schechter. Brown University

Compatibilist Objections to Prepunishment

The Principle of Sufficient Reason and Free Will

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

HABERMAS ON COMPATIBILISM AND ONTOLOGICAL MONISM Some problems

TWO ACCOUNTS OF THE NORMATIVITY OF RATIONALITY

Ending The Scandal. Hard Determinism Compatibilism. Soft Determinism. Hard Incompatibilism. Semicompatibilism. Illusionism.

Chapter Six Compatibilism: Mele, Alfred E. (2006). Free Will and Luck. Oxford University Press: Oxford.

Human Nature & Human Diversity: Sex, Love & Parenting; Morality, Religion & Race. Course Description

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

If God brought about the Big Bang, did he do that before the Big Bang?

Bayesian Probability

2 FREE CHOICE The heretical thesis of Hobbes is the orthodox position today. So much is this the case that most of the contemporary literature


Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

To appear in Metaphysics: Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 82, Cambridge University Press, 2018.

Templeton Fellowships at the NDIAS

Journal of Philosophy, Inc.

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

The Mystery of Free Will

The Mind Argument and Libertarianism


Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Understanding Truth Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002

To appear in The Journal of Philosophy.

A Taxonomy of Free Will Positions

On Searle on Human Rights, Again! J. Angelo Corlett, San Diego State University

Deontological Perspectivism: A Reply to Lockie Hamid Vahid, Institute for Research in Fundamental Sciences, Tehran

Purple Haze: The Puzzle of Consciousness

Philosophical Issues, vol. 8 (1997), pp

Evidence and Transcendence

In Defense of Pure Reason: A Rationalist Account of A Priori Justification, by Laurence BonJour. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,

The Journal of Philosophy, Vol. 83, No. 5. (May, 1986), pp

Huemer s Problem of Memory Knowledge

DISCUSSION PRACTICAL POLITICS AND PHILOSOPHICAL INQUIRY: A NOTE

BOOK REVIEW: Gideon Yaffee, Manifest Activity: Thomas Reid s Theory of Action

Reply to Robert Koons

NATURALISED JURISPRUDENCE

Vol. II, No. 5, Reason, Truth and History, 127. LARS BERGSTRÖM

Answers to Five Questions

Free Acts and Chance: Why the Rollback Argument Fails Lara Buchak, UC Berkeley

Divine omniscience, timelessness, and the power to do otherwise

Max Deutsch: The Myth of the Intuitive: Experimental Philosophy and Philosophical Method. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, xx pp.

Wittgenstein on The Realm of Ineffable

REASONS-RESPONSIVENESS AND TIME TRAVEL

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

AN ACTUAL-SEQUENCE THEORY OF PROMOTION

FOREWORD: ADDRESSING THE HARD PROBLEM OF CONSCIOUSNESS

REASON AND PRACTICAL-REGRET. Nate Wahrenberger, College of William and Mary

Predictability, Causation, and Free Will

Phil 1103 Review. Also: Scientific realism vs. anti-realism Can philosophers criticise science?

UC Berkeley UC Berkeley Previously Published Works

MANIPULATION AND INDEPENDENCE 1

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Quine s Naturalized Epistemology, Epistemic Normativity and the. Gettier Problem

Reading a Philosophy Text Philosophy 22 Fall, 2019

Defending Hard Incompatibilism Again

Free Agents as Cause

Christianity and Science. Understanding the conflict (WAR)? Must we choose? A Slick New Packaging of Creationism

Daniel von Wachter Free Agents as Cause

Journal of Philosophy, Inc.

International Phenomenological Society

Under contract with Oxford University Press Karen Bennett Cornell University

Free Will and Theism. Connections, Contingencies, and Concerns. edited by Kevin Timpe and Daniel Speak

Who is a person? Whoever you want it to be Commentary on Rowlands on Animal Personhood

ON PROMOTING THE DEAD CERTAIN: A REPLY TO BEHRENDS, DIPAOLO AND SHARADIN

Causation and Free Will

Rationality in Action. By John Searle. Cambridge: MIT Press, pages, ISBN Hardback $35.00.

Naturalism and is Opponents

Transcription:

Journal of Philosophy, Inc. Review: [untitled] Author(s): John Martin Fischer Source: The Journal of Philosophy, Vol. 100, No. 12 (Dec., 2003), pp. 632-637 Published by: Journal of Philosophy, Inc. Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/3655525. Accessed: 24/02/2011 13:31 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at. http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at. http://www.jstor.org/action/showpublisher?publishercode=jphil.. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org. Journal of Philosophy, Inc. is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Journal of Philosophy. http://www.jstor.org

632 THE JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY BOOK REVIEWS Freedom Evolves. DANIEL C. DENNETT. New York: Viking, 2003. xiii + 347 p. Cloth $24.95.* Freedom Evolves is a vigorous and lively defense of a naturalistic, compatibilistic notion of freedom (and moral responsibility). It shows how these sorts of phenomena can be given evolutionary explanations; also, it exhibits the evolution of Daniel Dennett's own account of freedom, which he presented in his important contribution to the free will debates, Elbow Room: The Varieties of Free Will Worth Wanting.' It responds to various objections to his sort of compatibilist account, comments on some contemporary philosophical literature, and also exhibits the connections between Dennett's approach to freedom and his influential accounts of consciousness, the self, and Darwinian evolutionary theory. Notably, Dennett connects the philosophical issues pertaining to free will with the insights and methodologies of contemporary psychologists such as Daniel Wegner and George Ainslie, economists such as Robert Frank, and biologists such as Richard Dawkins,Jared Diamond, Edward O. Wilson, and David Sloan Wilson. This is a synoptic and compendious book, not likely to be appealing to the more meticulous analytic philosophers. Its target, I would think, is primarily a more general audience of intellectuals and scholars in other fields, although even the most fastidious philosopher may find some intriguing, suggestive, and provocative observations. The package of theses defended by Dennett is fairly familiar. Dennett argues that a "real" and robust sort of freedom is entirely compatible with a thoroughgoing, naturalistic causal determinism. The following statement nicely (if somewhat vaguely) captures Dennett's presuppositions and methodology: "My fundamental perspective is naturalism, the idea that philosophical investigations are not superior to, or prior to, investigations in the natural sciences, but in partnership with those truth-seeking enterprises, and that the proper job for philosophers here is to clarify and unite the often warring perspectives into a single vision of the universe" (15). He contends that nothing * I am grateful for helpful comments by Al Mele and Manuel Vargas. 1 Cambridge: MIT, 1984. 0022-362X/03/0012/632-37? 2003 The Journal of Philosophy, Inc.

BOOK REVIEWS 633 in our practices or in critical reflection on them entails that we need to assume that indeterminism is true, or that we have (what he takes to be) mysterious, irreducible powers to "agent-cause" our behavior, or that materialism is false, and so forth. Further, the freedom we care about and our practices of holding each other morally responsible do not presuppose a kind of possibility to do otherwise that holds fixed all the details of the past and the natural laws. Nothing of significance is lost, then, if we give up this "libertarian" notion of freedom. Although some theorists have evidently concluded from Dennett's previous defenses of materialistic accounts of mental states, consciousness, and the self, that "there is no room for Free Will" (on such an account), Dennett points out that this is a mistake. He develops a series of thought experiments, or, in his much-preferred terminology, '"Just-So Stories," that employ insights and analytical approaches from evolutionary biology, economics, and psychology to show how one can defend a strong notion of freedom even in a materialistic, causally deterministic world. Of course, the tools for defending such a view will include the recognition of the extraordinary complexity of (physical) creatures like us, and the appropriateness of different levels of description of or different stances to, such organisms. Dennett tells an elaborate Just-So Story in which initially simple organisms evolve into complex creatures that have and respond to reasons, make choices, and have freedom, even in a causally deterministic world. A landmark event in this Story takes place when the creatures develop the ability to speculate about the future, to consider possible threats thatjeopardize their interests and plans, and to make choices that help them to avoid those projected future threats. "Evitability," then, is a significant achievement, and clearly confers an important evolutionary advantage. And, Dennett argues, the sort of evitability in question is not understood in terms of the "possibility to do otherwise, holding all the details of the past and natural laws fixed"; it is perfectly compatible with causal determinism. Much of what is of value in this book is contained in the details of the Just-So Stories. There are also intriguing critical discussions of the indeterministic theory of free will presented by Robert Kane, and some of the views about the human will suggested by the neuroscientist, Benjamin Libet. Dennett builds on previous work that suggests a helpful kind of skepticism about simple thought experiments in general, and, in particular, those that posit the weird inculcation of beliefs, desires, and other mental states (by nefarious neurosurgeons and their ilk). Dennett here explores Alfred Mele's example of Ann and Beth, who are allegedly psychologically isomorphic except that Beth has had crucial mental states induced by a neuroscientist. Al-

634 THE JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY though Mele's point was primarily to defend a historical account of autonomy, Dennett addresses some complexities in such putative examples of induction of mental states. I agree with Dennett about a lot: that causal determinism is compatible with a sort of freedom and also with moral responsibility, that moral responsibility is properly understood in terms of a kind of sensitivity to reasons, that this sensitivity can be present even in the absence of libertarian freedom, and so forth. I am also comfortable with a "naturalistic" methodology (on most plausible understandings of "naturalism"), although I suppose that I would want something slightly different: an approach that is compatible with naturalism, even if it does not entail it.2 Nevertheless, I have some significant disagreements with Dennett. One of these disagreements pertains to what might be called "libertarian freedom." Both of us hold that such freedom is not necessary for moral responsibility. But I take seriously the libertarian's wish to have such freedom, and take it as significant that causal determinism evidently rules out such freedom; Dennett, in contrast, dismisses this sort of freedom as uninteresting. For example, Dennett says: Many philosophers have assumed without specific argument that when we ask a question about what was possible, we are-and should beinterested in knowing whether, in exactly the same circumstances, the same event would recur. We have argued that in spite of its traditional endorsement by philosophers, this policy is never followed by serious investigators of possibility and is, in any event, unmotivated: It couldn't give you an answer that could satisfy your curiosity. The burden now rests with those who think otherwise to explain why 'real' possibility demands a narrow choice of X [the set of possible worlds relevant to the possibility-claim]-or why we should be interested in such a concept of possibility, regardless of its 'reality'(82). It is completely uncontroversial that there are various kinds of possibility, and thus various corresponding sets of possible worlds (relevant to the possibility-claims in question). Further, I absolutely agree with Dennett that different contexts of inquiry will render different notions of possibility relevant, and there are important contexts of inquiry to which broader, rather than narrower, notions of possibil- 2 The term, 'naturalism', is bandied about quite promiscuously, and it is often unclear what a theorist means by this term. I would not want a theory of moral responsibility that entails or presupposes materialism about the mind, for example (although I myself am inclined to accept materialism). It would also be unattractive to make it a requirement of an adequate theory of moral responsibility that God does not exist.

BOOK REVIEWS 635 ity are appropriate. For example, we are often interested in what is physically possible (not just what is physically possible, given a fixed past and set of natural laws). We are interested in what sorts of things are consistent with the laws of nature, and since we do not know the details of the total true description of the past, we will sensibly inquire, in many contexts, simply about what kinds of things are consistent with the laws of nature. Our epistemic limitations, together with our pragmatic goals, make it perfectly appropriate for us to concern ourselves with broad notions of physical possibility in our scientific theo- rizing. But it does not follow that the narrower notion of possibility is not important, and, in particular, that it is not important to our freedom. When we think of ourselves as having various pathways genuinely open to us, it is very plausible to suppose that we are picturing various paths that branch off a fixed path, holding the natural laws fixed. That is, when we think of ourselves as being free to pursue a particular path into the future, we explicitly or implicitly think of that path as an extension of the actual past (holding the laws of nature fixed). We typically do not think of ourselves as having the power so to act that the past would have been different from the way it actually was, or so to act that the laws of nature would have been different. So, the picture is this: the various accessible pathways into the future branch off a fixed past (and contain the actual natural laws), and the reasons relevant to our practical reasoning are reasons that obtain only along the accessible pathways. A benefit that exists along some path is pertinent to my practical reasoning only if I can "get there from here." The above picture lies behind various formalizations of a "Basic Argument" for the incompatibility of causal determinism and free will, in the sense that involves genuine access to alternative possibilities.3 One can deny the picture-that is, one can deny that the past or the laws are fixed in the relevant sense.4 So it is not uncontroversial that the picture corresponds to the correct account of possibility, in the free will sense. But it is an extremely plausible, attractive, and natural picture. I find it hard to give up the idea that my freedom, in a given context, consists in my power to add to the given past, holding the natural laws fixed. The picture of "multiple pasts"- 3 I discuss at greater length Dennett's critique of the Basic Argument in my contri- bution to the "Author-Meets-Critics" session on the book at the American Philosophical Association Pacific Division Meetings, March 2004 (Pasadena, California). 4I discuss such moves in John Martin Fischer, The Metaphysics of Free Will (Cambridge: Blackwell, 1994), pp. 67-86.

636 THE JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY different pasts for each path I could take-is as unintuitive as it is unlovely. And the Humean idea that I can write the laws of nature (and that there are no laws of nature until the end of time) strikes me as somewhat bizarre. This picture of the structure of free will possibility is precisely what must be abandoned by the compatibilist about causal determinism and free will, in the sense that involves genuine access to alternative possibilities. Perhaps then it is not surprising that philosophers have been concerned about precisely this sort of freedom for thousands of years. (By the way, the Basic Argument goes back to Origen-not to be confused with one of Dennett's favorite topics, The Origin of Species!) I, like Dennett, am a compatibilist about moral responsibility and causal determinism. But I do not think that compatibilism makes progress unless it takes the libertarian's concerns seriously. It does not make progress if it abruptly dismisses a set of concerns that not only resonates deeply with common sense, but with thousands of years of philosophical analysis. I wish to end with a few reflections on features of Dennett's method- ology. As is well known, Dennett does not trust philosophical "thought experiments," about which he expresses considerable skepticism. He is particularly wary of thought experiments involving the artificial induction or inculcation of mental states (by "nefarious neurosur- geons"-or even nice ones, presumably). But he engages (especially in this book) in his own story telling. Why exactly are Dennett's Just-So Stories any different from traditional philosophical thought experiments? In both cases there is significant simplification and abstraction. Dennett gives hegemony to the fictional stories that are "dressed up" with technical or "scientific" features, but why? After all, these stories (like the traditional philosophical thought experiments) are abstractions, the conclusions of which need to be applied with delicacy and sensitivity to the nuances of the real world. In my view, a philosophical thought experiment does need to be handled with care and extreme caution; but this does not imply that such thought experiments cannot be useful and illuminating.5 Philosophical thought experiments are stories that invite us to consider our principles more carefully. In some instances, they force us to give a more nuanced analysis that is sensitive to the complexity of the relevant terrain. I often feel that Dennett's discussion could bene- 5 See Fischer and Mark Ravizza, "Introduction," in Fischer and Ravizza, eds., Ethics: Problems and Principles (Fort Worth, TX: Harcourt, 1992), pp. 12-16 and 45-51; and Fischer, "Stories," Midwest Studies in Philosophy, xx (1996): 1-14.

BOOK REVIEWS 637 fit from a subtler, more articulated view of the target phenomena. For just one example, Dennett often speaks of "freedom," without distinguishing what I think are importantly different kinds of freedom. If one abruptly dismisses the thought experiments (as well as other, more traditional forms of philosophical analysis), one can fail to see the complexity of the notions of freedom and responsibility.6 Dennett is at his best when he is essentially challenging philosophers to be broader in our intellectual gaze, rendering philosophical theo- rizing continuous with cutting-edge work in the social and natural sciences. But evidently he feels that the need to avoid parochialism is asymmetric. Here was an opportunity to introduce a broader intellectual audience to the extraordinarily lively and rich contemporary philosophical debates about free will and moral responsibility, but the opportunity was lost. University of California/Riverside JOHN MARTIN FISCHER 6 I do not suppose that we should do without the sorts of scientific approaches and models invoked by Dennett. I simply do not think we should abandon philosophical analysis and abruptly discard philosophical thought experiments. The Rawlsian notion of seeking a wide reflective equilibrium seems particularly appealing here-see Fischer and Ravizza, Responsibility and Control (New York: Cambridge, 1998), pp. 10-11.