Attfield, Robin, and Barry Wilkins, "Sustainability." Environmental Values 3, no. 2, (1994):

Similar documents
A solution to the problem of hijacked experience

The Paradox of the stone and two concepts of omnipotence

Legal Positivism: the Separation and Identification theses are true.

Two More for the Knowledge Account of Assertion

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

Law and Authority. An unjust law is not a law

Resemblance Nominalism and counterparts

International Environmental Law, Policy, and Ethics

Realism and instrumentalism

SIMON BOSTOCK Internal Properties and Property Realism

BELIEF POLICIES, by Paul Helm. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, Pp. xiii and 226. $54.95 (Cloth).

b. Use of logic in reasoning; c. Development of cross examination skills; d. Emphasis on reasoning and understanding; e. Moderate rate of delivery;

Dave Elder-Vass Of Babies and Bathwater. A Review of Tuukka Kaidesoja Naturalizing Critical Realist Social Ontology

Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords

Against the Vagueness Argument TUOMAS E. TAHKO ABSTRACT

Rule-Following and the Ontology of the Mind Abstract The problem of rule-following

Shieva Kleinschmidt [This is a draft I completed while at Rutgers. Please do not cite without permission.] Conditional Desires.

Two Kinds of Moral Relativism

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

Korsgaard and Non-Sentient Life ABSTRACT

Vol. II, No. 5, Reason, Truth and History, 127. LARS BERGSTRÖM

Rawls s veil of ignorance excludes all knowledge of likelihoods regarding the social

What is the "Social" in "Social Coherence?" Commentary on Nelson Tebbe's Religious Freedom in an Egalitarian Age

A note on reciprocity of reasons

SUNK COSTS. Robert Bass Department of Philosophy Coastal Carolina University Conway, SC

Who or what is God?, asks John Hick (Hick 2009). A theist might answer: God is an infinite person, or at least an

Reflections on sociology's unspoken weakness: Bringing epistemology back in

Response to Earl Wunderli's critique of Alma 36 as an Extended Chiasm

Natural Resources Journal

CONVENTIONALISM AND NORMATIVITY

Religious Undercurrents in Environmentalism and Forestry: Introduction to the Working Group Session. Environmentalism, Green Religion, Scientism, Why?

Names Introduced with the Help of Unsatisfied Sortal Predicates: Reply to Aranyosi

2. Public Forum Debate seeks to encourage the development of the following skills in the debaters: d. Reasonable demeanor and style of presentation

Are There Reasons to Be Rational?

POWERS, NECESSITY, AND DETERMINISM

Follow links for Class Use and other Permissions. For more information send to:

To link to this article:

ALTERNATIVE SELF-DEFEAT ARGUMENTS: A REPLY TO MIZRAHI

ISSA Proceedings 1998 Wilson On Circular Arguments

Citation for published version (APA): Petersen, T. S. (2011). What Is Legal Moralism? Sats, 12(1), DOI: /sats.

Semantic Pathology and the Open Pair

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism

Moral requirements are still not rational requirements

Situations in Which Disjunctive Syllogism Can Lead from True Premises to a False Conclusion

McCLOSKEY ON RATIONAL ENDS: The Dilemma of Intuitionism

Faults and Mathematical Disagreement

The Critical Mind is A Questioning Mind

Moral Twin Earth: The Intuitive Argument. Terence Horgan and Mark Timmons have recently published a series of articles where they

Is Truth the Primary Epistemic Goal? Joseph Barnes

The Morality. of God

HART ON THE INTERNAL ASPECT OF RULES

Positivism A Model Of For System Of Rules

The Principle of Sufficient Reason and Free Will

Propositional Revelation and the Deist Controversy: A Note

Is God Good By Definition?

A Problem for a Direct-Reference Theory of Belief Reports. Stephen Schiffer New York University

Rawls, rationality, and responsibility: Why we should not treat our endowments as morally arbitrary

In this paper I offer an account of Christine Korsgaard s metaethical

Bart Streumer, Unbelievable Errors, Oxford: Oxford University Press, ISBN

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy

Immortality Cynicism

The Many Faces of Besire Theory

QCAA Study of Religion 2019 v1.1 General Senior Syllabus

Explanatory Indispensability and Deliberative Indispensability: Against Enoch s Analogy Alex Worsnip University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

7. The Universal Audience

the notion of modal personhood. I begin with a challenge to Kagan s assumptions about the metaphysics of identity and modality.

Reason and Argument. Richard Feldman Second Edition

Royal Institute of Philosophy

AS HISTORY Paper 2C The Reformation in Europe, c Mark scheme

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Précis of Democracy and Moral Conflict

Phil 114, April 24, 2007 until the end of semester Mill: Individual Liberty Against the Tyranny of the Majority

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE AND META-ETHICS

[3.] Bertrand Russell. 1

Christ-Centered Critical Thinking. Lesson 6: Evaluating Thinking

Epistemic Normativity for Naturalists

BIG IDEAS OVERVIEW FOR AGE GROUPS

Based on the translation by E. M. Edghill, with minor emendations by Daniel Kolak.

A New Argument Against Compatibilism

Action in Special Contexts

REASON AND PRACTICAL-REGRET. Nate Wahrenberger, College of William and Mary

Human Dignity 1. Universität Zürich Institut für Sozialethik Prof. Dr. Johannes Fischer November in Zürich.

Philosophy. Aim of the subject

Theories of propositions

Convergence liberalism and the problem of disagreement concerning public justification*

Practical Rationality and Ethics. Basic Terms and Positions

World Religions. These subject guidelines should be read in conjunction with the Introduction, Outline and Details all essays sections of this guide.

On Interpretation. Section 1. Aristotle Translated by E. M. Edghill. Part 1

In the preface to Law and Justice in Community the authors say:

Does law have to be effective in order for it to be valid?

THE RELATION BETWEEN THE GENERAL MAXIM OF CAUSALITY AND THE PRINCIPLE OF UNIFORMITY IN HUME S THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE

Utilitarianism: For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), pp Reprinted in Moral Luck (CUP, 1981).

Class #14: October 13 Gödel s Platonism

Book Reviews 427. University of Manchester Oxford Rd., M13 9PL, UK. doi: /mind/fzl424

Warrant, Proper Function, and the Great Pumpkin Objection

HUME, CAUSATION AND TWO ARGUMENTS CONCERNING GOD

National Quali cations

Transcription:

The White Horse Press Full citation: Attfield, Robin, and Barry Wilkins, "Sustainability." Environmental Values 3, no. 2, (1994): 155-158. http://www.environmentandsociety.org/node/5515 Rights: All rights reserved. The White Horse Press 1994. Except for the quotation of short passages for the purpose of criticism or review, no part of this article may be reprinted or reproduced or utilised in any form or by any electronic, mechanical or other means, including photocopying or recording, or in any information storage or retrieval system, without permission from the publishers. For further information please see http://www.whpress.co.uk.

Sustainability ROBIN ATTFIELD AND BARRY WILKINS Philosophy Section School of English Studies, Journalism and Philosophy University of Wales College of Cardiff PO Box 94, Cardiff CF1 3XB, UK ABSTRACT: This paper supplies a critique of the view that a practice which ought not to be followed is ipso facto not sustainable, a view recently defended by Nigel Dower. It is argued that there are ethical criteria independent of the criterion of sustainability. The concept of sustainability is thus retrieved for the distinctive role and the important service in which environmental and social theorists (paradoxically including Dower) have hitherto employed it, not least when debating the nature, merits and demerits of sustainable development. KEYWORDS: sustainability, arguments, development, beneficiality, justice A widespread consensus exists both among the proponents of economic and social development and among environmentalists that development must be sustainable. Processes which undermine themselves or which for some other reason cannot be continued into the future are recognised as unlikely to contribute to the solution of problems of development or to conservation of the natural environment. 1 Sustainability thus seems to be a crucial quality of acceptable plans and policies for a great many future purposes. But does the sustainability of a practice (e.g. a process of production or of development) actually imply that it passes all ethical tests and is morally beyond reproof? Desirable as sustainability may be, is it wise to give the concept of sustainability all this work to do? One analogy suggesting an affirmative answer arises from the ascription of sustainable to arguments which are sound or successful: for here sustainable has a normative role, and serves to give top marks to the argument in question for rationality. So maybe sustainable has a parallel normative role when ascribed to processes. Yet even with arguments, sustainable is not always so used; sometimes what is conveyed is just that the argument is capable of being defended (or of being defended in public), not that in rational terms it succeeds. So the analogies from rational sustainability are far from unequivocal. Environmental Values 3 (1994): 155-8 1994 The White Horse Press, Cambridge, UK.

156 ROBIN ATTFIELD AND BARRY WILKINS Nigel Dower 2 maintains nevertheless that a practice is sustainable only if it satisfies moral criteria, and thus is worth pursuing or ought to be pursued; otherwise it is every bit as unsustainable as it would be if sustaining it were impossible. Sustainable thus actually has a similar logic to desirable ; indeed Dower cites G.E. Moore s criticism of John Stuart Mill s use of desirable as analogous to his own criticism of the view that sustainable simply means able to be sustained. And there can be no doubt that this is intended as an analytic point; thus Dower writes: What is important, analytically, is that any form of sustainable development which someone is prepared to endorse will be a form which satisfies the range of moral criteria which that person accepts, whatever those may be. 3 While Dower accepts that not everyone will accept his own evaluative positions, perspective is added, and Dower s view more adequately represented, through a quotation of the following passage in which these positions are embodied: A form of development worth sustaining will at the very least not only protect the future, but also be: (a) just in terms of the present social structures and practices of the society; (b) non-damaging to the natural environment; (c) non-damaging to people in other countries; and (d) fair in relation to the like aspirations of other countries. 4 We have no wish to criticise at least the last three conditions given here as criteria of desirable practices. But it should be stressed that Dower is saying that unless all these conditions (protecting the future included) are satisfied, a form of development is not sustainable because it is not worth sustaining. Our own view, by contrast, is that a practice may fail to be worth sustaining, but still be sustainable. We are not denying that sustainability is frequently a merit (for it frequently is), but rather we are pointing out that to have it is not essentially to have all the merits possible for forms of development. It may first help to ask whether sustainable is really logically akin to desirable. Now where sustainable arguments are sound or successful ones, they are admittedly arguments fit to be credited, and their sustainability could thus be held to put them on a par with desirable entities in respect of their being fit to be desired. But where sustainable arguments are merely ones which are defensible, they may fail to be fit to be credited; and the lack of normative import in this variety of sustainability also attaches, we maintain, to processes and practices which are sustainable. Often, of course, their very capacity for indefinite continuation itself makes sustainable processes or practices desirable; but this is far from invariably true, and thus, importantly, not a necessary truth. Nor are we aware of any other ground for regarding sustainable processes or practices as essentially fit to be sustained, let alone ones which there is a duty to sustain. At this point a second question arises; cannot a practice be both sustainable

SUSTAINABILITY 157 and either bad or indifferent (valuationally or morally)? Self-reinforcing practices (such as foot-binding probably was) may easily be bad, but perhaps their sustainability would not be granted. Examples should therefore be selected which are widely regarded as paradigms of sustainability. Maximum Sustainable Yield is a policy applicable both to fisheries and to forestry; resources are harvested up to the point where a greater yield would undermine self-replenishment, and resources thus remain available at this level for every succeeding generation. On the other hand, such practices sometimes strike at the interests of other nonhuman species (of the ocean or of the forests), and are thus open to ethical objection. Dower would have to say that if the objection is upheld, such policies were not sustainable after all; but this seems a heroic line to take with policies of Maximum Sustainable Yield, particularly in view of their promise of continuous benefits for humanity into the indefinite future. Those who, like ourselves, would sympathise with some of the ethical objections to such policies are much better advised, in cases where the objections are considered decisive, to characterise the policies as sustainable but unjustified, all things considered. Such a characterisation would seem no less coherent than phrases (used of other practices) such as courageous but foolish (e.g. whistling in the dark) or longsuffering but irresolute (e.g. quietism). The alternative view, as has been seen, is that nothing can be regarded as both morally unjustified and sustainable. While we have already adduced what we consider to be telling arguments against this view, we should now point out that if it came to be the general view, then another concept would need to be invented for processes and practices that can be sustained, whether through human effort or through being naturally self-perpetuating. For it would be important e.g. for planners to identify practices with this characteristic, independently of whether there were overwhelming reasons for adopting them. (Sometimes, for example, there might be pairs of alternative practices with this characteristic, between which a decision could then be made on other grounds.) Our own view, however, is that no such concept needs to be invented, as the concept of sustainability already has this role. It remains to draw some morals. First, it is mistaken to make one concept do the work of several. That way, clear and serviceable concepts like that of sustainability forego their sense. Indeed by the time that sustainable is construed as meaning just, ecologically sound and internationally fair as well as able to be sustained, it is difficult to say why the phrase to be used for the job of expressing this composite concept is sustainable, rather than something like unexceptionable or even perfect in every way. There is a second and related point. There are multiple criteria to be applied to proposals for e.g. development, and terms are needed to allow the proposals to be checked independently against each of these criteria. Thus separate terms are needed to allow distinct judgements to be made about the beneficiality of a proposal, about its sustainability and about its justice. Terms concerning the joint

158 ROBIN ATTFIELD AND BARRY WILKINS class which satisfies all these criteria at once are no substitute for ones allowing them to be considered in turn; and if this were not possible, judgements based on a plurality of criteria would scarcely be possible either. Third, phrases such as a just and sustainable society, much used by Dower in the past, 5 are not pleonasms, as they would be if sustainable already meant just and sustainable : as things are, they remain viable and valid phrases, the distinct conjuncts each supplementing the meaning of the other, and each contributing a meaning sufficiently distinct for its applications to be worth debating. Fourth, the possibility of processes which are sustainable but bad should not be ruled out. (Was not slavery such?) The possibilities of unending benefits and of the continual functioning of interacting social and natural systems make (at least some) sustainable ways of life highly attractive: but sustainability is not everything, and it is important to be wary lest even sustainable processes have a fatal flaw. Finally we should express agreement with Dower that practices which cannot be sustained as part of a sustainable worldwide system are not themselves truly sustainable. But this is not because the term sustainable encapsulates all values. It is because sustainability can have a narrower and a broader scope, and because (in general) the broader the scope of a self-reinforcing process, the greater is the likelihood of its remaining unassailed and intact. Thus truly sustainable processes are liable to operate or be capable of operating worldwide whether for better or for worse. This helps to explain the increasing emphasis placed by people concerned about the future of the planet on this important (but not allimportant) concept. NOTES 1 See, for example, World Commission on Environment and Development, Our Common Future, 1987, chapter 2. 2 Dower 1992; see especially the section entitled Sustainability, at pp. 110-114. 3 Ibid., p.112 4 Ibid., p.112 5 Dower 1983, pp. 91-94; also in the title of his unpublished paper A Just and Sustainable Society. REFERENCES Dower, Nigel 1983. World Poverty: Challenge and Response. York: Ebor Press. Dower, Nigel 1992. Sustainability and the right to development, in Robin Attfield and Barry Wilkins (eds.), International Justice and the Third World, 93-116. London and New York: Routledge. Dower, Nigel, A Just and Sustainable Society (unpublished paper) World Commission on Environment and Development 1987. Our Common Future (the Brundtland Report). Oxford: Oxford University Press.