Journal of Cognition and Neuroethics

Similar documents
ORGANISMS, PERSONS AND BIOETHICS II

APA PANEL TALK ON ORGANISMS, PERSONS AND BIOETHICS

Noonan, Harold (2010) The thinking animal problem and personal pronoun revisionism. Analysis, 70 (1). pp ISSN

Can Ordinary Materialists be Autonomous? Abstract

Philosophy and Theology: Notes on Diachronic Personal Identity

Bad Luck Once Again. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Vol. LXXVII No. 3, November 2008 Ó 2008 International Phenomenological Society

Nancey Murphy, Bodies and Souls, or Spirited Bodies? (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006). Pp. x Hbk, Pbk.

the notion of modal personhood. I begin with a challenge to Kagan s assumptions about the metaphysics of identity and modality.

Well-Being, Time, and Dementia. Jennifer Hawkins. University of Toronto

The Theory and Practice of Personal Identity

Jeff McMahan, The Ethics of Killing: Problems at the Margins of Life. Oxford: Oxford University Press, xiii pp.

What Matters in Survival: The Fission Problem, Life Trajectories, and the Possibility of Virtual Immersion

Philosophical Review.

IA Metaphysics & Mind S. Siriwardena (ss2032) 1 Personal Identity. Lecture 4 Animalism

Compatibilist Objections to Prepunishment

24.03: Good Food 3 April Animal Liberation and the Moral Community

Who is a person? Whoever you want it to be Commentary on Rowlands on Animal Personhood

LOWE S DEFENCE OF CONSTITUTION AND THE PRINCIPLE OF WEAK EXTENSIONALITY David B. Hershenov

A Compatibilist Account of Free Will and Moral Responsibility

Luck, Rationality, and Explanation: A Reply to Elga s Lucky to Be Rational. Joshua Schechter. Brown University

Journal of Cognition and Neuroethics

Can Rationality Be Naturalistically Explained? Jeffrey Dunn. Abstract: Dan Chiappe and John Vervaeke (1997) conclude their article, Fodor,

An Alternative to Brain Death

Personal Identity. 1. The Problems of Personal Identity. First published Tue Aug 20, 2002; substantive revision Thu Jul 9, 2015

What We Are: Our Metaphysical Nature & Moral Implications

Legal Positivism: the Separation and Identification theses are true.

POWERS, NECESSITY, AND DETERMINISM

The Argument for Subject-Body Dualism from Transtemporal Identity

the aim is to specify the structure of the world in the form of certain basic truths from which all truths can be derived. (xviii)

ORGANISMS, BRAINS AND THEIR PARTS UB PHILOSOPHY OF BIOLOGY CONFERENCE

DOES STRONG COMPATIBILISM SURVIVE FRANKFURT COUNTER-EXAMPLES?

SITUATIONS AND RESPONSIVENESS TO REASONS * Carolina Sartorio. University of Arizona

Varieties of Apriority

1. The narrow criterion Derek Parfit endorses a view of personal identity over time that he puts like this:

FISSION, FIRST PERSON THOUGHT, AND SUBJECT- BODY DUALISM* KIRK LUDWIG Indiana University ABSTRACT

Belief Ownership without Authorship: Agent Reliabilism s Unlucky Gambit against Reflective Luck Benjamin Bayer September 1 st, 2014

Coordination Problems

The Paradox of the stone and two concepts of omnipotence

1 Hans Jonas, The Imperative of Responsibility: In Search of an Ethics for the Technological Age (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984), 1-10.

The elimination argument

According to Russell, do we know the self by acquaintance? (hint: the answer is not yes )

Skepticism and Internalism

Why I Am Not a Property Dualist By John R. Searle

*Please note that tutorial times and venues will be organised independently with your teaching tutor.

Unit VI: Davidson and the interpretational approach to thought and language

WHAT S IDENTITY GOT TO DO WITH IT? THE UNIMPORTANCE OF PERSONAL IDENTITY FOR BIOETHICS

Introduction to Cognitivism; Motivational Externalism; Naturalist Cognitivism

Equality, Fairness, and Responsibility in an Unequal World

Philosophy 1100 Introduction to Ethics. Lecture 3 Survival of Death?

Saul Kripke, Naming and Necessity

It is advisable to refer to the publisher s version if you intend to cite from the work.

Free Will. Course packet

R. G. Collingwood, An Essay on Metaphysics, Clarendon Press, Oxford p : the term cause has at least three different senses:

Epistemic Contextualism as a Theory of Primary Speaker Meaning

Framing the Debate over Persistence

A New Argument Against Compatibilism

This is the peer reviewed version of the following article: Árnadóttir, S. T. (2013), Bodily Thought and the Corpse Problem. European Journal of

Andrea Westlund, in Selflessness and Responsibility for Self, argues

Ethics Handout 19 Bernard Williams, The Idea of Equality. A normative conclusion: Therefore we should treat men as equals.

A Contractualist Reply

Primitive Concepts. David J. Chalmers

Merrick s Identification of the Person and Organism

Future People, the Non- Identity Problem, and Person-Affecting Principles

Naturalism Primer. (often equated with materialism )

STEWART COHEN AND THE CONTEXTUALIST THEORY OF JUSTIFICATION

Attraction, Description, and the Desire-Satisfaction Theory of Welfare

The Zygote Argument remixed

Anselmian Theism and Created Freedom: Response to Grant and Staley

Sensitivity to Reasons and Actual Sequences * Carolina Sartorio (University of Arizona)

EXERCISES, QUESTIONS, AND ACTIVITIES

Personal Identity and What Matters 1

ZAGZEBSKI ON RATIONALITY

New Aristotelianism, Routledge, 2012), in which he expanded upon

Trinity & contradiction

Stem Cell Research on Embryonic Persons is Just

Utilitarianism: For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), pp Reprinted in Moral Luck (CUP, 1981).

Quine s Naturalized Epistemology, Epistemic Normativity and the. Gettier Problem

DIVIDED WE FALL Fission and the Failure of Self-Interest 1. Jacob Ross University of Southern California

Let us begin by first locating our fields in relation to other fields that study ethics. Consider the following taxonomy: Kinds of ethical inquiries

Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Introduction

Moral Psychology

Note: This is the penultimate draft of an article the final and definitive version of which is

Semantic Externalism, by Jesper Kallestrup. London: Routledge, 2012, x+271 pages, ISBN (pbk).

Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly *

Are There Reasons to Be Rational?

EXERCISES, QUESTIONS, AND ACTIVITIES My Answers

1. Introduction. 2. Clearing Up Some Confusions About the Philosophy of Mathematics

Theories of propositions

THE SEMANTIC REALISM OF STROUD S RESPONSE TO AUSTIN S ARGUMENT AGAINST SCEPTICISM

Introduction. Steven Luper

The normativity of content and the Frege point

BOOK REVIEWS. The Philosophical Review, Vol. 111, No. 4 (October 2002)

Contextualism and the Epistemological Enterprise

Is the Identity of Indiscernibles refuted by Max Black's thought experiment? What is the Principle of Identity of Indiscernibles (PII)?

Free Agents as Cause

WhaT does it mean To Be an animal? about 600 million years ago, CerTain

SWINBURNE ON SUBSTANCES, PROPERTIES, AND STRUCTURES

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

Why Four-Dimensionalism Explains Coincidence

Free Will as an Open Scientific Problem

Transcription:

Journal of Cognition and Neuroethics Identity and Freedom A.P. Taylor North Dakota State University David B. Hershenov University at Buffalo Biographies David B. Hershenov is a professor and chair of the philosophy department at the University at Buffalo. He works primarily on issues at the intersection of personal identity and bioethics. A.P. Taylor is a lecturer in philosophy at North Dakota State university. He works on personal identity and the metaphysical foundations of well-being. Publication Details Journal of Cognition and Neuroethics (ISSN: 2166-5087). March, 2015. Volume 3, Issue 1. Citation Taylor, A.P., and David B. Hershenov. 2015. Identity and Freedom. Journal of Cognition and Neuroethics 3 (1): 383 391.

Identity and Freedom A.P. Taylor and David B. Hershenov Abstract Few philosophers will think someone is free and responsible if he forms his intentions while either thinking that he is someone else, say Barack Obama, or is considering only Obama s values and interests while kept ignorant of his own. We ll argue that there is an analogous problem for all the major materialist theories that understand human persons to be essentially thinking beings that physically overlap but are distinct from human animals. The source of the problem is that these accounts posit that there exist more than one entity possessing the same brain the person and the animal. Since the former can use the brain to think, so can the latter. If there s more than one overlapping thinker and their interests diverge then there ll arise the problem that each cannot exercise his free will without undermining the other s free will. We conclude that, among materialist theories of personal identity, only an animalist metaphysics that identifies material persons and animals will provide a necessary condition for our being free. Keywords Free Will, Animalism, Personal Identity, Materialism Introduction It would certainly be unwelcome if one s preferred metaphysics of the person often makes free will and moral responsibility impossible. We contend that this is the fate of all the major materialist theories that understand human persons to be essentially thinking beings that physically overlap human animals. The source of the problem is that these accounts posit that there exist more than one entity possessing the same brain the person and the animal. If the former can use the brain to think, so can the other. As a result, such theories are afflicted by The Problem of Too Many Thinkers. Our focus is on an overlooked moral version of the Problem of Too Many Thinkers. If there is more than one overlapping thinker then there ll arise the problem that each cannot freely and responsibly act in a way that respects the exercise of the other s freedom. The trouble comes about because the overlapping thinkers can t simultaneously think and act on their interests and govern their lives in accordance with their values. And their interests and values will diverge due to their having different persistence conditions. We will show that there could be many occasions where only the person will give her free consent. The human animal overlapping the person won t freely consent to the same 384

Taylor and Hershenov intention or action because he will either wrongly think that he is the person or will just be considering what is in the person s interests. Our contention is that the only prominent materialist account to avoid such problems is the animalist theory that identifies the human person and the human animal and adopts a sparse ontology. We reach this conclusion in part because we accept a methodology in which ethical considerations and action-theoretic claims can weigh against certain metaphysical accounts of the person. So we aren t forced by methodological principles to claim that certain metaphysical conceptions of the person show that there is no free and responsible action; rather, we can plausibly claim that practical considerations strongly suggest that those metaphysical approaches to personal identity are false. One reason why we believe practical considerations should be included in the weighing of reasons in favor and against a metaphysical theory is that if there are moral truths then they must be consistent with metaphysical truths. If one adopts a metaphysic in which thinking beings overlap then one must reject certain seemingly obvious moral truths like we ought to respect the free choice and bodily integrity of beings like ourselves. We find it plausible that such considerations should tilt the scales against that metaphysics rather than show such core moral principles to be false. But even if one is an anti-realist about ethics and thus under no pressure to make metaphysical truths cohere with moral truths for there are not any of the latter, there are still true action-theoretic claims about free action that we think a metaphysic should accommodate. For instance, if a metaphysic makes it impossible for everyone intelligent enough to understand these sentences to also freely endorse and act upon their interests and values, then that too provides a reason to doubt the metaphysics rather than accept the impossibility of such creatures being free. The Moral Problem of Too Many Thinkers We believe that greater success in resolving The Problem of Too Many Thinkers is the closest there is to a criterion to choose between competing metaphysical theories of the person. If a theory implies that there exists more than one thinker under your clothes, then that is a major strike against the theory. This reason may not be strong enough on its own to warrant rejecting the theory outright, but it will greatly weigh against it, tilting the scales further in the direction of a view that avoids the problem. Let s assume that persons are essentially thinking beings that are spatially coincident but numerically distinct from animals. The problem which arises is that if the person can 385

Journal of Cognition and Neuroethics think, then it would seem that the animal should also be able to think since it shares the same brain. Olson (1997; 2002; 2007) highlights the epistemic problem that arises if both the person and the animal can think, then you have no reason to think you are the person rather than the animal. Either you or your co-located thinker will be wrong when you both say I am essentially a person. The first person pronoun refers to each of the speakers and so one is falsely predicating personhood to itself. How can you be so sure that you are not the deluded animal making the erroneous self-ascription? Noonan (2010) attempts to avoid the epistemic problem by endorsing what has become known as Pronoun Revisionism. Noonan suggests that to have thoughts about one s thoughts is not enough to make an entity a person, rather an individual must have the appropriate psychological persistence conditions. That is, the person goes out of existence if he loses certain psychological capabilities. So the thinking animal is never a referent of the personal pronoun I for the term doesn t pick out any entity thinking or uttering the word I, rather it just refers to the person. However, even if Noonan is right about the animal s use of the personal pronoun, this will not be enough to mitigate the ethical problems. While we ll draw mostly upon bioethical examples involving what is known as informed consent, readers can easily imagine similar scenarios in other domains that would likewise undermine free will. If there are non-persons such as human animals that can t refer to themselves with the firstperson pronoun, then how can they be said to freely agree to any immediate treatment or make provisions for their future with say a living will? While we don t have a favored theory of free will to expound, it would seem safe to say that one couldn t be free if unable to reflect upon one s interests, desires, values, intentions as one s own, and then act on the basis of the reasons they provide. If we assume pronoun revisionism, a problem is that the animal is thinking about the person s interests as the person does, for the animal refers to the person when it uses first person pronouns to entertain thoughts of the following types: I would prefer such and such a course of treatment for it increases my well-being or I would prefer to forgo all treatments so I can lead the remainder of my life in accordance with my values. Our worry is that the animal might have interests and values that are not the same as those of the person because of their different persistent conditions. Thus the animal s choosing to act on the basis of what the person has reason to do cannot be understood to be a free and responsible action of the animal who didn t reflect upon the action qua animal, i.e., did not think of himself as an animal engaged in that action. A similar lesson can be drawn in the absence of pronoun revisionism if the animal uses the first person pronoun to self-refer but is ignorant of his kind membership, wrongly thinking he is the person. He will be choosing actions on the 386

Taylor and Hershenov basis of the person s interests and values and so the action cannot be said to emerge from him in a way characteristic of freedom. We ll provide examples below in which overlapping thinkers won t be self-governing on any of the leading theories of free will. On psychological accounts like those of Noonan, Shoemaker, Parfit, Baker and Hudson, persons go out of existence with the loss of certain sophisticated psychological capacities while human animals can survive the loss of such capacities, existing in impaired mental states. We contend that the animal might have an interest in continuing to exist in a childlike state after the rational, self-conscious person has ceased to exist as a result of injury or stroke. Conversely, persons might have interests that are not strictly those of our animals. A conflict can be generated if there is an experimental drug that may prevent the further decline into Alzheimer s disease, but will far more likely kill its user. The person, who inevitably goes out of existence with the loss of self-consciousness, might think she has nothing to lose since either the disease or the drug s unwanted side effect will end her existence. However, it may be in the interest of the human animal not to take the drug since it could survive with the minimal sentience of late stage Alzheimer s disease. We don t think such a choice could be considered free for both the animal and the person on any of the leading accounts of freedom. It doesn t matter if such accounts stress the endorsement of desires that we act on by higher order desires or values (Dworkin 1970; Frankfurt 1971; Watson 1975), emphasize the history of how those higher order attitudes arose (Wolf 1990), insist upon choices meshing with long term plans (Bratman 2010), require a reason responsiveness and a mechanism that is sensitive to reasons (Fischer and Ravizza 1998), or insist that the agent exercise his causal power to choose between alternatives regardless of antecedent circumstances (Clark 1996; O Connor 2008). The overlapping thinkers in the above and below scenarios could consider in succession that they were the person and then the animal, the result being that if they first each thought they were an animal they would endorse different acts, be alienated from different parts of a shared history, have divergent long term plans, be sensitive to different reasons, and exercise agent causation differently from how they would if they thought they were the person. The Alzheimer s drug isn t the only scenario where free will cannot be exercised by overlapping thinkers. Conflicts between the person and the animal could prevent them from both freely endorsing the same advanced directive. For instance, the person may not want his resources to be spent on sustaining an organism with dementia with whom it is not identical. That person would have written a very different advanced directive if he had thought he was the animal. Or the person might leave directions to try an extremely 387

Journal of Cognition and Neuroethics dangerous experimental treatment if his Alzheimer s Disease progresses to a certain state. But the treatment would be contrary to the animal s interests. So the advanced directive written by the animal and the person while the animal thought it was the person or only considered the latter s interests will not do justice to the animal s freedom. We can generate other infringements due to the animal and person s different interests due to their different persistence conditions. Assume the person and the animal both support donating organs at their deaths but not before. Let s add that they even believe they are morally obligated to engage in directed donation and bestow organs upon an ailing friend or relative after they die. However, the possibility of the animal and person s deaths occurring at different times could prevent the full realization of their seemingly shared value. The person is essentially a thinking being and the animal is essentially a living being and so the criteria for their deaths would diverge. The problem is that when the animal dies after its respiration and circulation have irreversibly ceased, less of its organs may be viable for transplant than if organs were taken when just consciousness was lost irreversibly with the onset of a persistent vegetative state. And in the case of directed donation, the person might not be able to donate upon her death because the organism is still alive and doesn t pass away until long after the needy friend or relative dies. It is important to realize that these types of conflicts aren t the standard conflicts of interests between free parties where say a government health official doesn t allow the person to have the experimental drug that he covets, or a court rules that a health insurance company needn t provide payment for the expensive treatment that the patient is interested in, or a doctor refuses to undertake the risky procedure that the patient wants. Each of these individuals can freely formulate an intention and act upon it even if someone else later prevents their action from producing the desired results: the acquisition of the drug requested, the petitioned for payment, the provision of the sought after procedure. Rather, it is impossible for the overlapping animal and person to simultaneously freely endorse an intention that both then act upon. Nor do they each have free control over a personal realm, their body. While you can choose to take a risky experimental drug that I can refuse to take, the spatially located person and animal cannot each make and act on their own choice. If one takes the drug, the other does so as well. If the person donates multiple organs upon his death with the loss of the appropriate mental capacities, the animal will be killed when his vital organs are taken. Conflicts like these make it impossible to respect the bodily integrity of both. So we are not presenting just another instance of the typical problem where someone s freely 388

Taylor and Hershenov endorsed intentions and acts are foiled by the freely produced preferences and deeds of others in the society and without any rights being violated. We don t think one can escape this by appealing to Parfit s famous claim that identity isn t what matters, our prudential-like concern being only with psychological connections to a future person regardless of whether we are one and the same person or distinct persons. 1 If Parfit were right, the overlapping human animal and person would have the same interests and thus would not choose differently. Parfit bases his claim on cases like those involving Adam s cerebrum fissioning and both cerebral hemispheres transplanted into different bodies B and C. Adam would have survived if just one of the hemispheres was successfully transplanted, the other destroyed upon removal. So Parfit reasons that having these two equally good psychological successors is as good as ordinary survival (no fission and no transplants). The claim that identity doesn t matter depends upon Parfit holding an account of identity involving a uniqueness clause. Parfit s criterion for personal identity across time is that it consists of i) the appropriate psychological relation R and ii) being uniquely the possessor of such relations. Since this uniqueness clause, aka no branching clause, is trivial and satisfied by what is extrinsic to us, Parfit insists it can t be what matters to us. So it must be the other component of the personal identity criterion, the psychological relation R, that matters to us. This led Parfit to his famous conclusion that identity doesn t matter. One reason for our skepticism about Parfit s thesis is that it doesn t mesh with our reactions to torture and death following a great change in our psychology due to a stroke. It doesn t seem that we now will view the later torment and death as being less bad since we are less psychologically connected to the being after the stroke than we would be if there had been no damaging stroke. Secondly, Parfit s claim that identity doesn t matter depends upon his interpretation of a fission scenario that violates the rationale behind the only x and y rule. That rule does not allow that our identity in the future can be determined by whether there are two or more equally good candidates as there would be in cases of fission. The rule restricts questions of whether x is identical to y to the internal relationship between x and y, the existence of a z being irrelevant. The rationale for the rule is that there should not be unexplained existences where entities owe their existence to other beings despite the absence of a causal connection between them (Hawley, 2005). The problem with Parfit s cerebral fission and transplant case is that the person in body B would not be there if it wasn t for the existence of the person in body C likewise being psychologically 1. See Parfit (1984). 389

Journal of Cognition and Neuroethics continuous with Adam. So the person in Body B owes his existence to the person in body C, and vice versa, but there are no causal connections between person in body B and the person in body C despite the existence of each playing a role in the creation or sustaining of the other. So if unexplained existences are to be avoided, then the criterion for identity should not involve a uniqueness rule and psychological relation R. But it is only the extrinsic and trivial features of the uniqueness clause that leads Parfit to the conclusion that only psychological relations matter. If he is not allowed to introduce the uniqueness rule into the account of identity, then fission can t show that identity doesn t matter, merely psychological relation R is of importance. So Parfit s thesis can t save autonomy in the above cases by giving the overlapping thinkers the same interests. Conclusion Thus if you re a materialist and care about freedom and responsibility, then you d better identify yourself with your animal. So this gives us an additional and rather weighty reason to put on the metaphysical scale, perhaps tilting it in favor of the view that we are animals. The animal is the person. And there aren t any other thinkers overlapping the animal. If you don t believe that moral or action-theoretic considerations should be given any weight when considering rival metaphysics, then we suggest that you come up with a radically new ethics. It will be an ethics that downplays satisfying free choice, and autonomous control over one s body due to the recognition of the divergent interests and values of overlapping entities. The new ethics will recommend some sort of compromise between the interests and values of those individuals now being counted by the latest metaphysical census, no doubt abandoning many of our currently established rights in the process. But that is the topic for another paper, or rather book, and one that we hope no one ever has to write. 390

Taylor and Hershenov References Bratman, Michael. 2005. Planning Agency, Autonomous Agency. In Personal Autonomy: New Essays on Personal Autonomy and its Role in Contemporary Moral Philosophy, edited by James Stacey Taylor, 33 57. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Clark, Randolph. 1996. Agent Causation and Event-Causation in the Production of Free Action. Philosophical Topics 24 (2): 19 48. Dworkin, Gerald. 1970. Acting Freely. Nous 4 (November): 367 383. Fischer, John, and Mark Ravizza. 1998. Responsibility and Control: A Theory of Moral Responsibility. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Frankfurt. Harry. 1971. Freedom of the Will and the Concept of the Person. Journal of Philosophy 68 (1): 5 20. Hawley, Katherine. 2005. Fission, Fusion and Intrinsic Facts. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 71 (3): 602 621. Noonan, Harold. 2010. Persons, Animals and Human Beings. In Time and Identity, Edited by Joseph Keim Campbell, Michael O Rourke and Harry S. Silverstein, 185 208. Cambridge: MIT Press. O Connor, Timothy. 2008. Agent-Causal Power. In Dispositions and Causes, edited by Toby Handfield, 366 388. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Olson, Eric. 1997. The Human Animal: Identity without Psychology. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Olson, Eric. 2002. Thinking Animals and the Reference of I. Philosophical Topics 30 (1): 189 207. Olson, Eric. 2007. What Are We? A Study in Personal Ontology. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Parfit, Derek. 1984. Reasons and Persons. Oxford: Oxford Clarendon Press. Watson, Gary. 1975. Free Agency. Journal of Philosophy 72 (April): 205 220. Wolf, Susan. 1990. Freedom within Reason. Oxford: Oxford University Press. 391