NAMES AND OBSTINATE RIGIDITY Brendan Murday Ithaca College

Similar documents
Objections to the two-dimensionalism of The Conscious Mind

On possibly nonexistent propositions

On Possibly Nonexistent Propositions

KAPLAN RIGIDITY, TIME, A ND MODALITY. Gilbert PLUMER

Theories of propositions

Contextual two-dimensionalism

Necessity. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Pp. i-ix, 379. ISBN $35.00.

Analyticity and reference determiners

Unnecessary Existents. Joshua Spencer University of Wisconsin-Milwaukee

Generalizing Soames Argument Against Rigidified Descriptivism

Externalism and a priori knowledge of the world: Why privileged access is not the issue Maria Lasonen-Aarnio

Coordination Problems

Direct Reference and Singular Propositions

Understanding Belief Reports. David Braun. In this paper, I defend a well-known theory of belief reports from an important objection.

An argument against descriptive Millianism

Truth At a World for Modal Propositions

Australasian Journal of Philosophy

The Two Indexical Uses Theory of Proper Names and Frege's Puzzle

A Problem for a Direct-Reference Theory of Belief Reports. Stephen Schiffer New York University

Existentialism Entails Anti-Haecceitism DRAFT. Alvin Plantinga first brought the term existentialism into the currency of analytic

Millian responses to Frege s puzzle

A flaw in Kripke s modal argument? Kripke states his modal argument against the description theory of names at a number

Singular Propositions *

Varieties of Apriority

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW

Russellianism and Explanation. David Braun. University of Rochester

Reply to Kit Fine. Theodore Sider July 19, 2013

Kripke s revenge. Appeared in Philosophical Studies 128 (2006),

Definite Descriptions and Semantic Pluralism Brendan Murday

Predict the Behavior. Leonardo Caffo. Propositional Attitudes and Philosophy of Action. University of Milan - Department of Philosophy

Ambitious Two-Dimensionalism

Moral Twin Earth: The Intuitive Argument. Terence Horgan and Mark Timmons have recently published a series of articles where they

Puzzles of attitude ascriptions

Fatalism and Truth at a Time Chad Marxen

Cognitive Significance, Attitude Ascriptions, and Ways of Believing Propositions. David Braun. University of Rochester

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

Draft January 19, 2010 Draft January 19, True at. Scott Soames School of Philosophy USC. To Appear In a Symposium on

Generic truth and mixed conjunctions: some alternatives

A Defense of Contingent Logical Truths

Philosophy 125 Day 21: Overview

BOOK REVIEWS. Duke University. The Philosophical Review, Vol. XCVII, No. 1 (January 1988)

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

1 What is conceptual analysis and what is the problem?

In Epistemic Relativism, Mark Kalderon defends a view that has become

Predict the Behavior. Propositional Attitudes and Philosophy of Action

TEMPORAL NECESSITY AND LOGICAL FATALISM. by Joseph Diekemper

A defense of contingent logical truths

Resemblance Nominalism and counterparts

BENEDIKT PAUL GÖCKE. Ruhr-Universität Bochum

Stang (p. 34) deliberately treats non-actuality and nonexistence as equivalent.

Empty Names and Two-Valued Positive Free Logic

NEPTUNE BETWEEN HESPERUS AND VULCAN. ON DESCRIPTIVE NAMES AND NON-EXISTENCE. Agustin Arrieta Urtizberea **

1. Introduction. Against GMR: The Incredulous Stare (Lewis 1986: 133 5).

Comments on Truth at A World for Modal Propositions

Foreknowledge, evil, and compatibility arguments

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

Definite Descriptions and the Argument from Inference

Faith and Philosophy, April (2006), DE SE KNOWLEDGE AND THE POSSIBILITY OF AN OMNISCIENT BEING Stephan Torre

THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE

Bennett and Proxy Actualism

Published in Analysis 61:1, January Rea on Universalism. Matthew McGrath

Class #9 - The Attributive/Referential Distinction

Some Good and Some Not so Good Arguments for Necessary Laws. William Russell Payne Ph.D.

What is the Frege/Russell Analysis of Quantification? Scott Soames

Putnam: Meaning and Reference

How Do We Know Anything about Mathematics? - A Defence of Platonism

Two-Dimensionalism and Kripkean A Posteriori Necessity

On Truth At Jeffrey C. King Rutgers University

A set of puzzles about names in belief reports

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

DEFEASIBLE A PRIORI JUSTIFICATION: A REPLY TO THUROW

From Necessary Truth to Necessary Existence

Against the Contingent A Priori

On A New Cosmological Argument

On a priori knowledge of necessity 1

Understanding Truth Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002

Russell: On Denoting

What God Could Have Made

PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE

IN his paper, 'Does Tense Logic Rest Upon a Mistake?' (to appear

Epistemic two-dimensionalism

Philosophy of Religion 21: (1987).,, 9 Nijhoff Publishers, Dordrecht - Printed in the Nethenanas

Modal Realism, Counterpart Theory, and Unactualized Possibilities

POWERS, NECESSITY, AND DETERMINISM

METHODISM AND HIGHER-LEVEL EPISTEMIC REQUIREMENTS Brendan Murday

Skepticism and Internalism

A User's Guide to Proper Names, Their Pragmatics and Semantics Pilatova, Anna

Unit VI: Davidson and the interpretational approach to thought and language

Phil 435: Philosophy of Language. [Handout 7] W. V. Quine, Quantifiers and Propositional Attitudes (1956)

Can Rationality Be Naturalistically Explained? Jeffrey Dunn. Abstract: Dan Chiappe and John Vervaeke (1997) conclude their article, Fodor,

5 A Modal Version of the

Kripke s famous thesis that proper names are rigid designators is accepted by many and

Saul Kripke, Naming and Necessity

PHILOSOPHICAL PROBLEMS & THE ANALYSIS OF LANGUAGE

WHAT DOES KRIPKE MEAN BY A PRIORI?

The Inscrutability of Reference and the Scrutability of Truth

propositional attitudes: issues in semantics

DENNETT ON THE BASIC ARGUMENT JOHN MARTIN FISCHER

Metaphysical Necessity: Understanding, Truth and Epistemology

xiv Truth Without Objectivity

Transcription:

NAMES AND OBSTINATE RIGIDITY Brendan Murday Ithaca College For the finished version of this paper, please see The Southern Journal of Philosophy, volume 51 (2), June 2013 ABSTRACT Names are rigid designators, but what kind of rigidity do they exhibit? Both obstinate and persistently rigid designators pick out O at every world at which they pick out anything at all. They differ in that obstinately rigid designators also pick out O at worlds at which O fails to exist; persistently rigid designators have no extension whatsoever at worlds at which O fails to exist. The question whether names are obstinate or persistent arises in two contexts in arguments against rigidified descriptivism (on the grounds that names and rigidified descriptions exhibit different kinds of rigidity), and in considerations about what it means for an expression to be directly referential. This paper contends that names are persistent, not obstinate. The position thus clarifies the relationship between Millian theories of names and rigid designation, in addition to undermining attempts to rehabilitate the modal argument against rigidified descriptivism. Names are rigid designators. While that thesis is no longer controversial, multiple debates about the meaning of names continue. There is first the skirmish between rigidified descriptivists and their Kripkean opponents. Secondly, anti-descriptivists disagree amongst themselves about the meaning of names. In both of these debates, one sometimes hears the claim that names are obstinately rigid as opposed to being merely rigid. This paper argues that such a claim is erroneous; whether descriptivism is true or not, names (like rigid descriptions) are merely persistently rigid. The paper will proceed as follows: 1 defines obstinacy and explains the relevance to Kripke s modal argument. 2 reviews David Kaplan s content/extension distinction, which is presupposed throughout the paper. 3 and 4 address and rebut arguments alleging a direct connection between obstinate rigidity and direct reference and/or Millian theories of names. Finally, 5 returns to the debate between rigidified descriptivism and its opponents, rebutting 1 P a g e

three anti-descriptivist arguments for obstinacy. No stance is taken here on the debate between Millianism and rigidified descriptivism; the aim is to show that both parties should accept that names are persistently rigid, and to observe as a corollary that the modal argument against descriptivism fails. 1. The Revised Modal Argument The distinction between rigid and non-rigid designators will be familiar to most readers; that distinction is illustrated by contrasting the descriptions the sum of 2 and 3 and the first person to walk on the moon. The former expression designates the number 5 in every possible world, and hence it rigidly designates the number 5. The first person to walk on the moon, however, designates different individuals in different possible worlds; the expression in fact designates Neil Armstrong, but had events progressed differently, the expression would have designated someone else. The expression the first person to walk on the moon thus non-rigidly designates Armstrong. With the distinction between rigid and non-rigid designators in place, we can shift our focus from definite descriptions to names. Descriptivists are those who think that the names are semantically equivalent (in some fashion) to definite descriptions. Naïve descriptivists identify the meanings of names with definite descriptions that are typically nonrigid. Saul Kripke (1980) deployed a modal argument (among others) against naïve descriptivism. The argument observes that natural language names are rigid 1 while definite descriptions are [typically] non-rigid. This difference is taken to constitute their semantic nonequivalence. Some descriptivists have countered that natural language names are equivalent to 2 P a g e 1 Stanley (1997) discusses the case for the rigidity of names.

rigidified descriptions. Perhaps Aristotle is semantically equivalent to a rigid description such as the actual teacher of Alexander the Great. The extension of the actual teacher of Alexander the Great is Aristotle for any world of evaluation, because we evaluate that content by looking for the extension of the teacher of Alexander the Great at the actual world @. Since names and rigid descriptions have the same modal profile, rigidified descriptivism undermines a crucial premise in Kripke s modal argument. A revised modal argument, 2 however, attacks rigidified descriptivism. The argument suggests that while actualized descriptions are rigid designators, they are not rigid in the same way that names are rigid, and therefore names and actualized descriptions are not semantically equivalent. How do rigid names and rigid descriptions differ? Nathan Salmon [1981: 32-36] suggests the following: an obstinate (or obstinately rigid ) designator is insensitive to the question of whether [its designatum exists] in a given possible world; [it designates] the same thing with respect to every possible world, whether that thing exists there or not. 3 In contrast, a persistent (or persistently rigid ) designator is an expression which designates the same thing with respect to every possible world in which that thing exists, and which designates nothing with respect to possible worlds in which that thing does not exist. 4 Thus the difference between an obstinate and a persistent designator of O depends on whether the expression designates O when evaluated at worlds where O does not exist. Crucially, we are not asking whether the word as used in an O-less world designates O; 2 See Salmon (1981), Almog (1986), Branquinho (2003), and Brock (2004). 3 Salmon (1981: 34). 4 Salmon (1981: 33-4). 3 P a g e

all parties in this debate agree that such a use would fail to designate. But if a term is obstinate, then our use of the term, when evaluated at an O-less world, will designate O; if a term is persistent, then our use of the term when evaluated at an O-less world will fail to designate anything. The distinction between obstinacy and persistence emerges only when we inquire whether evaluating the term at a world where O does not exist will determine a [non-degenerate] extension. The obstinacy theorist holds that the extension is O, because she does not require that O exists in world w in order to be the extension of a term evaluated at w. The persistence theorist, on the other hand, holds that the evaluation fails to determine a [non-degenerate] extension, because she requires that O exists in w in order to be the extension of a term evaluated at w. The revised modal argument against rigidified descriptivism is thus: names are obstinately rigid 5, but rigidified descriptions are persistently rigid. Since they have different modal profiles, names are not semantically equivalent to rigidified descriptions. Why think that rigidified descriptions are persistently rigid? Given the Russellian treatment of descriptions and an actualist interpretation of the existential quantifier, then in evaluating the actual F at w, we determine an individual O so long as O is the unique individual at w who is actually F. 6 If there is no unique individual at w who is actually F, the description 5 See Kaplan (1973) and (1989) (both reprinted in Davidson (2007)), Salmon (1981), Almog (1986), and Smith (1984) and (1987) in favor of obstinacy. Plumer (1989), Steinman (1985), and Stanley (1997: 567) express reservations about some arguments for obstinacy. 6 Perhaps instead we determine an individual O so long as O exists at w and is the one and only individual who is F-at-the-actual-world-@; the difference between these two formulations consists in where the uniqueness is required to obtain, but that question need not trouble us here; see Soames (2005: 30n22). 4 P a g e

fails to denote. Thus, the rigid description will be persistent, not obstinate. 7 We have in this section characterized the obstinacy/persistence distinction, while additionally observing the first way in which obstinacy matters to debates about the meaning of names. The second way in which obstinacy arises in the literature on names is in Kaplan s explanation of the notion of direct reference. To present the alleged connection between obstinacy and direct reference, we should first review Kaplan s distinction between content and extension. 2. Content and Rigidity Millians and actualized descriptivists disagree about the semantic content of a name. An actualized descriptivist might represent the semantic content of Obama as: 7 Carter (1983) argues that rigidified descriptions are in fact obstinate; Kaplan might also think that actualized descriptions are obstinate (though not directly referential). Kaplan says one who believes that a name is connected to its referent by a description... can achieve rigidity, even obstinate rigidity, through the use of rigidifying operators. Thus, a Fregean... need only add something like actuality to the content in order to account for the rigidity of proper names. We then have... rigid designation without direct reference. [Kaplan (1989: 577), reprinted in Davidson (2007: 790); italics in original, underlining added for emphasis]. It is unclear whether Kaplan meant that any description can be thus modified to create an obstinately rigid designator, or merely that some descriptions can become obstinate when rigidified. The latter claim is true in virtue of a description which contingently designates a necessary entity, since upon rigidification the resulting description would be both obstinate and persistent; the former claim would be more controversial. Contrast Carter s view with the more common treatment of actualized descriptions presented in Salmon (1981: 35): if a definite description... denotes a contingent individual i, then even the rigid designator ( x)a (x), i.e., the unique individual who is, in actuality, such that, where A is the sentential actuality operator, only persistently designates i. (Italics in original, underlining added for emphasis). Soames (2002: 41; 2005: 27n18) agrees with Salmon that actualized descriptions are persistent; however, Soames also holds (2002: 49; 2005: 28-29) that descriptions rigidified with Kaplan s dthat operator would be obstinate. Carter s (1983) position differs from the one taken in this paper concerning the modal profile of rigidified descriptions, but it is interesting to note that both positions provide the rigidified descriptivist with a response to the revised modal objection names and actualized descriptions would have the same modal profile, and so modal arguments against descriptivism would fail. 5 P a g e

<being the unique bearer of (44 th President of the United States) at @, and...> On the Millian view, the content of Aristotle is simply the individual, so a Millian might represent the content as: <Obama> Millianism and actualized descriptivism are thus two views about the content of a name. By contrast, the rigidity of an expression concerns the expression s extension. Let us step back for a moment. An expression generates a content when it is uttered in a particular context, so we can construe a content as the product of an expression paired with a context of utterance: Expression Content Context-of-Utterance Once a content has been generated, we evaluate that content to determine an extension. The extension of a name or a definite description is an individual; we find the extension by evaluating the content at a world: Content Extension World-of-Evaluation If the extension of a singular term changes when we change the evaluation-world, the term is non-rigid. 8 Salmon s distinction between obstinacy and persistence is a distinction 8 This is a terse but imprecise definition of rigidity. An incautious definition of rigidity such as this will entail that persistent rigid designation is not rigid designation at all, since at some worlds the extension is the individual in question while at other worlds there is no extension at all. A more nuanced definition of rigidity allows that both obstinate and persistent 6 P a g e

between types of rigidity; that distinction concerns extension, not content. 7 P a g e The contrast between obstinacy and persistence matters only when the world of evaluation is one at which the relevant individual does not exist it is only in that situation that obstinacy and persistence predict different results. 9 The results differ with respect to the extension of the expression. Nothing in the definitions of these two types of rigidity commits to one or the other view about content the definitions of obstinacy and persistence make no explicit commitments to Millianism or actualized descriptivism. This point is sometimes blurred. Kaplan [1978a] employs the term direct reference, distinguishing it from rigid designation. Kaplan [1989] clarifies that in calling a term directly referential he means both that it has a Millian content 10 and is obstinately rigid. 11 Kaplan seems to assume that any term expressing a Millian content is obstinate, and this assumption seems to be commonly accepted (though rarely discussed). This assumption will be challenged in 3 and 4. 3 Names as Persistently Rigid As noted above, if names are equivalent to rigidified descriptions, we have good reason to think that they will be obstinately rigid. The claim that names would be persistently rigid on a designators count as rigid; for instance: A rigid designator designates the same object in all possible worlds in which that object exists and never designates anything else (LaPorte, 2006). 9 An assumption in this paper is that some individuals are contingent beings; for a contrary view, see Williamson (2002). 10 The direct of direct reference means unmediated by any propositional component... Whatever rules, procedures, or mechanisms there are that govern the search for the referent, they are irrelevant to the propositional component, to content. When the individual is determined... it is loaded into the proposition. [Kaplan (1989: 569), reprinted in Davidson (2007: 784), italics added for emphasis]. 11 All directly referential terms will be obstinately rigid [Kaplan (1989: 571), reprinted in Davidson (2007: 786)]. The converse does not hold, however, since rigid descriptions denoting a necessary individual are obstinate.

Millian view, however, is highly contentious. This section considers how one could formulate a view that combines Millian semantics and persistent rigidity; 4 addresses the rival view that Millianism demands obstinacy. Consider the way we evaluate the shortest spy we generate a descriptive content, and then look for the thing at the evaluation-world that satisfies that description. Consider too the way we evaluate complete sentences we find the content generated by the sentence at the context of utterance, and then determine the truth-value of that proposition at the evaluationworld. Now consider proper names; suppose that Obama exists at our world @, but not at world. What are we doing when we evaluate the Millian content <Obama> (which, let us stipulate, is the content of @-utterances of Obama ) at? Here is one proposal: we are looking for the individual at corresponding to this content. What thing at is Obama? Nothing. Obama does not exist at, so our search comes up empty. Since no individual in is the extension determined by < Obama> at, there is no extension at. The search for an extension at has been characterized in terms of looking for the right sort of individual at. Whether the expression is a description, a sentence, or a name, the content is generated at the context of utterance, and we then look in the evaluation world to see what extension is determined by that content. The proposal thus suggests that the evaluation of Millian contents resembles the evaluation of any other content in this respect that content is generated at the world of utterance, and the extension is then determined by using the content to find the appropriate object/truth-value in the evaluation world. Of course, a Millian insists on a crucial difference between the ways that Millian and non-millian contents designate; Kaplan [(1977: 485-486), reprinted in Davidson (2007: 722)] takes pains to emphasize this point. Before 8 P a g e

we can accept the proposal at issue, then, we must be sure that it does not conflate the evaluation of a name and the evaluation of a description. The worry is that the proposal amounts to evaluating at a Millian content < Obama> by looking for something that satisfies a description in that world. But that worry can be dismissed; we can pair Millianism with the view that names are persistently rigid without thereby conflating Millianism and descriptivism. The descriptive content <being the unique bearer of 44 th President of the United States at the actual world> is evaluated by finding the unique exemplifier of that property at the world of evaluation. To evaluate a Millian content at, on the other hand, we are simply asking which individual at is that guy. Who at is Obama who at is that guy? No one. If anyone at were Obama, it would surely be Obama. But there is no such person at, so no one at is Obama. Evaluating <Obama> in this way differs from the evaluation of <being the unique bearer of 44 th President of the United States at the actual world> or even <being the unique bearer of identical with Obama >, though the difference in the latter case is subtle. An individual exemplifies the property identical with Obama just in case that individual is Obama, so the evaluations of <being the unique bearer of identical with Obama> and < Obama> will be extensionally equivalent. But one should not take that extensional equivalence to demonstrate that we are conflating the two contents; when we evaluate the Millian content we are not asking which individual exemplifies a property. There is therefore a coherent view which pairs Millianism and persistent rigidity; it is a further claim, however, that Millians should adopt this view. The following section identifies a difficulty for the orthodox view that Millianism entails obstinacy. 4 Severing the Link between Millianism and Obstinacy Why might a Millian think that names are obstinate? Consider Kaplan s comments about 9 P a g e

direct reference: I intend to use directly referential for an expression whose referent, once determined, is taken as fixed for all possible circumstances, i.e., is taken as being the propositional component. (Kaplan [1978a: 493], reprinted in Davidson [2007: 727]; italics in original) The claim that the referent is fixed for all possible circumstances suggests that the term has that referent at every point of evaluation, whether or not the referent exists there. 12 To say that the referent just is the propositional component is to endorse Millianism. The use of i.e. might suggest that Kaplan is taking obstinacy and Millianism to be two sides of the same coin. 13 Kaplan (1989) characterizes direct reference as the pairing of Millianism and obstinacy. 14 He suggests further that obstinacy is a consequence of Millianism: If the individual is loaded into the proposition (to serve as the propositional component) before the proposition begins its round-the-worlds journey, it is hardly surprising that the proposition manages to find that same individual at all of its stops, even those in which the individual had no prior, native presence. The proposition conducted no search for a native who meets propositional specifications; it simply discovered what it had carried in. (Kaplan [1989: 569], reprinted in Davidson [2007: 784]) Kaplan employs here the carrying in metaphor; he uses it again later: I see... a central distinction... between what exists at a given point and what can be carried in to be evaluated at that point, though it may exist only elsewhere. My circumstances of evaluation evaluate contents that may have no native existence at the circumstances but can be expressed elsewhere and carried in for evaluation. (Kaplan [1989: 613], reprinted in Davidson [2007: 820]) Why would the evaluation of Millian content entail obstinacy? One proposal can be considered and quickly dismissed: one could interpret Kaplan s talk of carrying in to mean that 12 When Kaplan says all possible circumstances of evaluation, he means all -- he is not overlooking circumstances of evaluation at which the individual fails to exist. The quoted passage directly follows a distinction between obstinate and persistent rigidity. 13 It is surprising that Kaplan writes i.e. here; as noted above, he recognizes that a rigid description of a necessary individual is obstinately rigid without thereby expressing a Millian content. 14 See notes 10 and 11 for the original passages. 10 P a g e

in evaluating a proposition containing Obama as a constituent at, Obama becomes an eligible extension in virtue of arriving with the content. But we certainly should not think that evaluating a singular content at adds to the domain of in any way. The content tells us what extension we are looking for in the evaluation world, but it does not increase the stock of individuals eligible to serve as extensions. Another attempt to derive obstinacy from Millianism might seize on the suggestion that the individual has been determined prior to the evaluation; Kaplan (1989: 569) says something like this, as does Scott Soames: the content is identified with [the] referent. Since an object has already been determined, there is no further object determination to be done with respect to [the world of evaluation]. (Soames [2005: 27n18]) One might attempt to construct from this turn of phrase an argument that Millianism entails obstinacy: to evaluate a Millian content, we must first construct that content, and we cannot construct the content unless we already have the individual. 15 Content-generation precedes determination of an extension, since the latter is executed by carrying the content to a world of evaluation. Thus in the case of singular propositions, we have the individual before we evaluate that content to determine an extension. Since we have the individual already, regardless whether the individual exists at the world of evaluation, why not think that the extension determined will be that individual, no matter what the world of evaluation is like? We already have the individual, so there is no reason to say that for some points of evaluation the Millian content fails to determine any individual. 15 Plantinga defines existentialism as the view that a singular proposition cannot exist at w unless the relevant individual exists at w. If singular propositions are set-theoretic entities, existentialism is plausible, since it is natural to think that a set is built up out of its members, such that if the members did not exist the set would not exist either. Although Plantinga (1979) and (1983) rejects existentialism, the thesis bears some plausibility. 11 P a g e

This argument is clearly flawed. A content is generated at a context of utterance; to express a Millian content, we must have the individual in that context [at least given certain assumptions]. But the fact that we have the individual in the context of utterance does not entail that we have the individual in the world of evaluation. It is a mistake to reason that if we have the individual before content-generation, and we generate the content before extensiondetermination, then we have the individual before extension-determination, and therefore that individual is always available to be the extension. The mistake trades on an ambiguity in the then clause; we have the individual at the context of utterance before we evaluate the singular content at a circumstance of evaluation, but that is no reason to think that the individual is eligible to serve as the extension determined at that circumstance of evaluation. Rather, the world of evaluation provides the individuals eligible to serve as the extension, and thus in evaluating a content at the Obama-less world, Obama is not available to be the extension. Perhaps we can find another way to formulate the thought that seems to motivate those who think that obstinacy goes hand-in-hand with Millianism. When one evaluates a singular content at a world, the individual determined is simply the constituent of the singular content; the thought may be that unlike the case of descriptive contents, for which one must go looking in the world of evaluation for an individual who satisfies the description, the extension determined by a singular content is simply the constituent of that content. 16 If the Millian endorses this, however, she will encounter some of the problems already canvassed. On this characterization, the determination of the extension takes place independently of the world of evaluation. If the extension is determined by the content alone, in 12 P a g e 16 Thanks to an anonymous referee for suggesting this formluation.

what sense are we determining extensions by evaluation at a possible world at all? The proposal here seems to break with the priority of content to extension reviewed in 2. Direct reference theorists might embrace this; Kaplan says of direct reference that it makes the referent prior to the propositional component and that it reverses the arrow from propositional content to individual [(1989: 569), reprinted in Davidson (2007: 784)] So Millians might say that the extension of a name is determined not by finding an individual at the evaluation-world who corresponds to the content, but rather that the extension is determined logically prior to the evaluation-world. That suggestion, however, is needlessly revolutionary. The Millian needs to say that the individual is identified and loaded into the proposition directly, but there is no reason to say that this counts as the determination of the extension. The evaluation of every other lexical item proceeds by finding the content generated at the context of utterance, taking that content to an evaluation-world, and finding the extension determined by that pairing of content and world. As noted in 3, we can say the same thing about singular contents a proposition containing Obama as a constituent is generated at the context of utterance, and we evaluate that proposition by finding the individual at the evaluation-world who is Obama (if he is there) and determining whether that individual exemplifies the property attributed to him by the singular proposition. In so doing, we allow that a name, like any other term, generates a content, which then determines an extension at the evaluation-world. But the counter-proposal on the table is that the extension of Obama is Obama even at worlds where the individual does not exist, because Obama is a constituent of the proposition because we have that individual when we generate the content. We find the extension of the sentence at β by seeing whether that individual has the right property at β, but we find the extension of the name at β without looking at β at all. One could 13 P a g e

adopt that view about the evaluation of Millian contents, but it is a radically different picture of evaluation than we adopt about other terms, and there is no reason to adopt it. The key principle motivating Millianism is that names latch onto an extension directly, not by mediation through some description. Singular propositions give us that; we satisfy the Millian by formulating a theory about the content of names. There is no need to additionally offer a novel theory about how such a content determines an extension. The extension of Obama is determined not by finding an individual who satisfies the right description; it is determined by finding the individual who is Obama. The extension of a description is determined by finding an individual, whomever she may be, who has the right properties; the extension of a name is determined by the particular individual we are looking for. Millians need a novel picture of the content of names. But they do not need a novel picture of the evaluation of that content, of the way that the content determines an extension. When a novel picture is not needed, it should not be adopted. There is still another place we might look for an argument that Millianism entails obstinacy. Kaplan attributes the inspiration for direct reference to logic: It is a striking and important feature of the possible world semantics for quantified intensional logics, which Kripke did so much to create and popularize, that variables, those paradigms of rigid designation, designate the same individual in all possible worlds whether the individual exists or not. (Kaplan [1978a: 493], reprinted in Davidson [2007: 727]) This conception of direct reference takes the variable under an assignment of value as its paradigm. In evaluating Fx at a world w, we do not ask whether its value exists in w, we only ask what value was assigned to the variable before the process of evaluation at w began. Until a value is assigned we have nothing to evaluate. (Kaplan [1989: 571], reprinted in Davidson [2007: 786]) Significantly, in the latter passage Kaplan proceeds to explain that direct reference is a theory featuring Millian contents. Millianism seems to form the core of Kaplan s notion of direct reference the appeal to variables in logic is meant to emphasize that the assignment of an individual to a variable is unlike the way a descriptive content determines an extension. But as 14 P a g e

argued in 3, we do not get obstinate rigidity simply from Millianism we can accept that a term has Millian content, yet explain the evaluation of that content in a way such that the term is persistently rigid rather than obstinate. Smith [1987] appeals to the analogy with logic in a slightly different way that may help the case for obstinacy: With names, designata are specified in the base-clauses of our semantic theory antecedently to the running of the possible-worlds machinery. It is for this reason that names can be uniformly assigned designata with respect to worlds independently of the issue of whether those designata exist in those worlds since this latter issue will be relevant only to the working out of satisfaction at worlds that is irrelevant to names. (Smith [1987: 87-88]; underlining added for emphasis). Smith, unlike Kaplan, emphasizes the suggestion that the extension (the designation) of a name is determined prior to the possible worlds machinery. But as argued in this section, it is more compelling to take the relationship between content and extension articulated by Kaplan and apply it to names as well allow that the name generates a Millian content at the context of utterance, but still maintain Kaplan s view that contents are evaluated at a world, and that the extension is determined through that evaluation. Understood this way, we can endorse Millianism while also holding that extensions are determined by evaluating contents at worlds. 17 17 There is one other thought we might pursue. We could generate an argument for obstinacy that does not attempt to derive that view from direct reference if we distinguish between existence-at-w and membership-in-the-domain-of-w, and supposed further that every individual is a member of every world s domain. We could then say that an extension is determined at W by finding the appropriate individual in the domain of W (whether or not the individual exists at that world). Now the extension of Obama will be that guy at every evaluation-world, since Obama (like every individual) is a member of every world s domain. This move, however, would trivialize the obstinacy thesis. This tactic would make both names and rigidified descriptions count as obstinate, and the Millian wants to say that names are special in virtue of being obstinate. So divorce existing-at-w from membership-in-the-domainof-w will be of no interest to the obstinacy theorist. The tactic might nevertheless be of interest in providing an argument that both names and rigidified descriptions are obstinate. But divorcing existence-at-w and membership-in-thedomain-of-w is a radical move in its own right, and it is hard to see any compelling motivation in 15 P a g e

5. Arguments for Obstinacy The previous section argues that Millianism does not entail obstinate designation, but one might come to believe that names are obstinate by a different route by arguing that the truth of certain sentences can only be explained by obstinacy. Those who deploy the revised modal argument against rigidified descriptivism, for instance, adopt precisely this tactic; this section argues that the truth of the sentences in question can be explained without any appeal to obstinacy. 5.1. The Negative Existential Argument for Obstinacy One argument for obstinacy is motivated by negative existentials. Consider the proposition expressed by @-denizens in uttering (1) Obama does not exist. The proposition is false when evaluated at @, but true when evaluated at. Nathan Salmon suggests that (1) expresses the singular proposition attributing nonexistence to Obama: (2) <Obama, nonexistence> The argument for obstinacy now runs as follows: (2) is true when evaluated at, and this is because the extension of <Obama> at exemplifies nonexistence at. If Obama were persistently rigid, <Obama> would be extensionless at, so we would not have designated an individual who would be exemplifying the property nonexistence. According to the argument, if (2) is true at, <Obama> must determine an extension at ; the extension of <Obama> is Obama its favor besides perhaps an attempt to explain how negative existentials can be true. 5.1 argues that we do not need so radical a solution to negative existentials. 16 P a g e

(even at ), and that individual exemplifies nonexistence at. 18 Salmon s argument is thus that we need some explanation of the truth of (2) at, and that the best explanation of this truth requires the assumption that Obama is obstinate that Obama is an element of the domain of all worlds, even worlds of which we want to say that Obama does not exist. This argument for obstinacy is not compelling; the persistence theorist can easily explain the truth of (2) at without giving up the benefits of persistence adduced in section 3; 19 consider the singular proposition (3) <Obama, existence> To say that (1) is true when evaluated at β is to say that (3) is false when so evaluated. The persistence theorist can easily explain why (3) is false when evaluated at β <Obama> fails to determine an individual, and hence we have no individual to go looking for in the extension of existence at β. Critically, this story does not require the claim that (3) exists at β, nor need we say that (3) exemplifies a truth-value at β. We need only say that the proposition can be evaluated at a world at which it does not exist, and this can be explained as above by asking whether the individual determined by <Obama> at β falls in the extension of existence at β. We have focused here on the evaluation of (3) at β; what about the evaluation of (2) at such a world? Salmon explains the truth of (1) by saying that Obama exemplifies the property nonexistence at β. The persistence theorist ought to disagree. Nothing exemplifies the property nonexistence, at this world or any other. We demand that 17 P a g e 18 See Salmon (1981: 37-8) and (1998: 287). 19 See Plantinga (1974: chapter 8), Smiley (1960), and Stanley (1997), for instance.

negative existentials can turn out true; we do not demand (nor have we any intuitive reason to think) that individuals can exemplify nonexistence. So the persistence theorist will deny that (2) is true when evaluated at β, but this is not a cost of persistence, it is a benefit. We can explain the truth-at-β of (1) without having to pay the price of saying that individuals can exemplify nonexistence. One might still worry that the persistence theorist cannot explain the truth at β of (4) <Negation, <Obama, existence> > But this worry turns on a mistake. (4) does not exist at β, but that does not prevent us from evaluating the proposition at β. Critically, the persistence theorist does not claim that the nonexistence of Obama at β makes false every proposition that has Obama as a constituent in some way. (4) is true at β for the same reason that (3) is false at β -- <Obama> evaluated at β fails to determine an individual falling within the extension of existence at β. Having seen that the persistence theorist can explain these negative existentials easily enough, there is no reason to agree with Salmon that they provide a reason to prefer obstinacy. 5.2. Modality and Time There is a second argument for obstinacy; in broad strokes, the argument is that proper names are temporally obstinate, and since modality and time are analogous, we should think that names are modally obstinate as well. 20 (1981: 36-40). 20 See Kaplan [(1973: 503-505, reprinted in Davidson (2007: 247-9)] and Salmon 18 P a g e

There are multiple examples used to motivate temporal obstinacy. Some of them are not compelling; others may be compelling for temporal obstinacy, but have no obvious modal analogues. The absence of modal analogues itself suggests that the analogy between time and modality is insufficient to sustain an argument for modal obstinacy. Let us consider the following examples: (5) Kripke was not yet born. [uttered in 2011, evaluated at 1911.] (6) Kripke will still be influential. 21 [uttered in 2011, evaluated at 2111.] (7) Newman-1 will be famous. 22 [uttered in 2011, evaluated at 2111.] Because (5) features a negation, the temporal persistence theorist can interpret it as denying that some claim about Kripke s birth is true. Following the suggestion made at the end of 5.1, she can argue that such a claim is true at 1911 simply in virtue of the fact that <Kripke, born> is not true when evaluated at 1911. (6) and (7) present more compelling cases for temporal obstinacy; they do not contain negations, so the temporal persistence theorist cannot dispose of them the way she handles (5). But while they [particularly (6)] may motivate temporal obstinacy, they do not have obvious modal analogues that would provide a reason to endorse modal obstinacy. (6) expresses a proposition that is true at 2111 only in virtue of the fact that Kripke s actions have causal effects on events in 2111. In the modal analogue, that does not obtain -- events at this world do not cause events at other worlds. This disanalogy between time and modality that temporal points 21 Both (5) and (6) are inspired by Branquinho (2003), though Branquinho puts references to the past and future times into the utterances themselves. It is critical that 1911 and 2111 serve as the respective times of evaluation for (5) and (6); nothing turns on whether or not 1911 and 2111 also figure into the utterances and the propositions expressed. 22 Suppose Newman-1 is a label used by a 2011 speaker to designate the first person born in the 22 nd century; the example was introduced in Kaplan (1978b). 19 P a g e

are causally interconnected, but modal points are not thus undermines the argument that where a reason to endorse temporal obstinacy exists, an analogous reason to endorse modal obstinacy exists as well. (7) may not even successfully motivate temporal obstinacy, since one might think that 2011-denizens cannot successfully refer using Newman-1. Regardless, in the modal analogue, few of the parties active in the obstinacy/persistence debate are inclined to think that one can refer to merely possible individuals; many have worries about positing merely possible individuals in the first place. None of these three cases present a compelling case for modal obstinacy. Perhaps (6) at least does motivate temporal obstinacy, but at issue here is the putative modal obstinacy of names, and we have thus far found no reason to endorse that view. Reliance on the analogy between time and modality will not help the obstinacy theorist, since the absence of a compelling modal example precisely undermines the claim that the analogy obtains in the relevant respect. 5.3. World-Indexing Operators Consider: (8) Obama is happy. and (9) At @, Obama is happy. The content of the @-utterance of (8) is (10) < Obama, happiness> (10) is false when evaluated at. The persistence theorist has no difficulty here, since <Obama> fails to determine an extension at. (9), however, is troubling for modal persistence. If (8) expresses a proposition true at @, 20 P a g e

(9) apparently expresses a truth at every world of evaluation. There is only one world @, so if p is true at @, it is necessarily the case that at @, p. This poses a threat to persistence: (9) expresses a non-negative proposition containing Obama as a constituent, and that proposition seems to be true at. Obstinacy would solve the problem by allowing that when the content <Obama> is evaluated at, the extension is Obama, and Obama is happy at @. Persistence theorists cannot adopt so straightforward an explanation, so (9) seems to motivate obstinacy. Whether (9) truly threatens persistence depends on the proposition @-denizens express in uttering (9), however, and we have not specified yet what proposition that is. Consider the rendering most likely to pose a problem for persistence: (11) < <Obama, happiness>, truth-at-@> To say that this proposition is true when evaluated at, we must say that (10) exemplifies truthat-@ at. Because Obama does not exist at, and Obama is a constituent of (10), we should deny that (10) exists at. If we denied serious actualism [i.e., if we denied that an exemplification at w entails the existence of an exemplifier at w], then we could maintain that (10) exemplifies truth-at-@ at. But the persistence theorist should not deny serious actualism, since she objects to the obstinacy account of negative existentials precisely on the grounds that such an account is forced to deny serious actualism. As a result, the persistence theorist is forced to deny that (11) is true at ; hence, (11) is not true at all worlds. However, (9) apparently expresses a necessity, and (9) seems to express (11). The persistence theorist must make some sort of concession. We should say that (11) is weakly necessary; that is, (11) is true at all worlds at which the 21 P a g e

proposition exists. 23 (11) does not exist at, of course, since one of its constituents does not exist at. So the persistence theorist concedes that (11) is not a necessary truth in the sense of strong necessity (truth at every world), though it is weakly necessary. This is not a significant theoretical cost. The operator at @ is not part of ordinary language, so we have some flexibility in interpreting it as philosophical needs dictate. The persistence theorist s suggestion that (11) fails to be true at is founded on plausible claims: the constituent proposition (10) does not exist at [assuming the ontological dependence thesis that singular propositions cannot exist at a world unless their constituents exist at that world], and as such (10) cannot exemplify properties at given serious actualism. The philosophical motivation for thinking that (11) is true at turns on the thought that there is only one world @, and hence regardless of the world of evaluation, (11) is true. To preserve serious actualism and the ontological dependence thesis, we should accept that embedding a singular proposition 24 under an operator like At produces a proposition that is merely weakly necessary. That is a price we should be willing to pay. One might wonder, however, whether other examples are less amenable to such a response. Actually, unlike At @, is part of ordinary language, and hence if there are sentences equally problematic for persistence that employ actually, we cannot be so cavalier about proposing an analysis that violates ordinary intuition. Consider: 23 On the connection between serious actualism and weak necessity, see Caplan (2007) and Plantinga (1979) [although Plantinga s appeal to weak necessity arises only in discussing a view he rejects, one which combines serious actualism with existentialism]. 24 If a proposition exists non-contingently, the gap between weak necessity and strong necessity is closed the distinction obtains only if the proposition fails to exist at all worlds. Let us suppose that the only contingent propositions are singular propositions. 22 P a g e

(12) Possibly Obama doesn t exist even though actually he does. 25 Intuitively, this expresses a truth; can the persistence theorist accommodate that intuition? We should first clarify the scope of possibly. Suppose the modal operator takes narrow scope: (13) (Obama doesn t exist) Actually (Obama does exist). Since Obama is actual, there is no issue for a persistence theorist in accounting for the truth of the second conjunct. We have already seen in 5.1 how the persistence theorist can explain the truth of the first conjunct. (13) is thus unproblematic. But there is a genuine threat to a persistence theorist if the modal operator takes wide scope: (14) [(Obama doesn t exist) Actually (Obama does exist)]. p is true when p is true at some accessible world, but given what we have said in this section, a world that makes Obama doesn t exist true is a world at which there are no de re non-negative truths about Obama, and Actually, Obama does exist certainly seems to allege a de re nonnegative truth about Obama. Persistence theorists have two options. On some views, actually has (at least on some occasions of use) the function of canceling a modal operator. 26 Thus (14) would turn out to be semantically equivalent to the unproblematic (13). Nothing about the persistence doctrine requires this view of the semantics of actually, but one could adopt it as a way of dodging the objection. A second [and to my mind more compelling] option embraces the view that there are no de re [non-negative] truths about merely possible individuals, and hence denies the intuition that (14) is true. While denying such an intuition is a concession, there is already some pressure in 23 P a g e 25 Thanks to an anonymous referee for suggesting this example. 26 See Bostock (1988: 360-363), Forbes (1989: 91-102), and Stephanou (2010).

this direction: as Bennett (2005) has argued, 27 if we accept actualism and the possibility of aliens (that is, the claim that there could have been individuals that do not actually exist), we have reason to deny the truth of (14). Those two principles are compelling enough that we should be prepared to sacrifice the intuition that (14) is true. 6. Conclusion We have argued against the view that names are obstinately rigid on the grounds that (a) Millianism does not require obstinate rigidity, (b) a natural way to think about evaluating Millian contents is well-suited to persistent rigidity, and (c) the examples putatively motivating the revised modal argument can be explained without resorting to obstinate rigidity. Denying obstinacy has intuitive merit with little theoretical cost. 28 27 See also Adams (1981) and Fitch (1996). 28 I would like to thank Andre Gallois, Tom McKay, and anonymous referees for their comments and suggestions on prior drafts of this paper. 24 P a g e

References Adams, Robert Merrihew. 1981. Actualism and Thisness. Synthese: An International Journal for Epistemology, Methodology and Philosophy of Science 57 (October): 3-42. Almog, Joseph. 1986. Naming without Necessity. Journal of Philosophy 83 (April): 210-242. Bennett, Karen. 2005. Two Axes of Actualism. Philosophical Review 114 (3): 297-326. Bostock, David. 1988. Necessary Truth and a Priori Truth. Mind: A Quarterly Review of Philosophy 97 (July): 343-379. Branquinho, João. 2003. In Defense of Obstinacy. Nous-Supplement: Philosophical Perspectives 17: 1-23. Brock, Stuart. 2004. The Ubiquitous Problem of Empty Names. Journal of Philosophy 101 (6): 277-298. Caplan, Ben. 2007. A New Defence of the Modal Existence Requirement. Synthese: An International Journal for Epistemology, Methodology and Philosophy of Science 154 (2): 335-343. Carter, W.R. 1983. On Obstinate and Persistent Designators. Philosophical Studies: An International Journal for Philosophy in the Analytic Tradition 43 (May): 415-422. Davidson, Matthew. 2007. On Sense and Direct Reference. Boston: McGraw-Hill. Fitch, G.W. 1996. In Defense of Aristotelian Actualism. Philosophical Perspectives 10: 53-71. Forbes, Graeme. 1989. Languages of Possibility. Oxford: Blackwell. Kaplan, David. 1989. Afterthoughts. In Themes from Kaplan, edited by Joseph Almog, John Perry, and Howard Wettstein, 565-614. New York: Oxford University Press. Kaplan, David. 1978a. Demonstratives. In Themes from Kaplan, edited by Joseph Almog, John Perry, and Howard Wettstein, 481-564. New York: Oxford University Press. Kaplan, David. 1978b. Dthat. In Syntax and Semantics, volume 9: Pragmatics, edited by P. Cole, 221-243. New York: Academic Press. Kaplan, David. 1973. Bob and Carol and Ted and Alice. In Approaches to Natural Language, edited by K.J.J. Hintikka, J.M.E. Moravcsik, and P. Suppes, 236-266. Dordrecht: D. Reidel Publishing Company. Kripke, Saul. 1980. Naming and Necessity. Cambridge: Harvard. LaPorte, Joseph. 2006. Rigid Designators. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2011 Edition), edited by Edward N. Zalta. URL = <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2011/entries/rigid-designators/>. Plantinga, Alvin. 1983. On Existentialism. Philosophical Studies: An International Journal for Philosophy in the Analytic Tradition 44 (July): 1-20. Plantinga, Alvin. 1979. De Essentia. Grazer Philosophische Studien 7/8: 101-121. Plantinga, Alvin. 1974. The Nature of Necessity. Clarendon: Oxford. Plumer, Gilbert. 1989. Mustn t Whatever is Referred to Exist? Southern Journal of Philosophy 27 (Winter): 511-528. Salmon, Nathan. 1998. Nonexistence. Noûs 32 (3): 277-319. Salmon, Nathan. 1981. Reference and Essence. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Smiley, Timothy. 1960. Sense without Denotation. Analysis 20 (6): 125-135. Smith, A.D. 1987. Semantical Considerations on Rigid Designation. Mind: A Quarterly Review of Philosophy 96 (January): 83-92. Smith, A.D. 1984. Rigidity and Scope. Mind: A Quarterly Review of Philosophy 93 (April): 177-193. 25 P a g e