This handout follows the handout on Determinism. You should read that handout first.

Similar documents
A Compatibilist Account of Free Will and Moral Responsibility

Moral Psychology

This handout follows the handout on Hume on causation. You should read that handout first.

Hence, you and your choices are a product of God's creation Psychological State. Stephen E. Schmid

SUPPORT MATERIAL FOR 'DETERMINISM AND FREE WILL ' (UNIT 2 TOPIC 5)

PHLA Freedom and Determinism II

Free Will: Do We Have It?

Does Theism Imply Determinism? Questions about Hard Determinism. Objections to Hard Determinism, I. Objections to Hard Determinism, II

METAPHYSICS. The Problem of Free Will

Harry Frankfurt Freedom of the Will and the Concept of a Person

Causation and Free Will

Final Paper. May 13, 2015

Philosophical Perspectives, 14, Action and Freedom, 2000 TRANSFER PRINCIPLES AND MORAL RESPONSIBILITY. Eleonore Stump Saint Louis University

Free Will as an Open Scientific Problem

The Consequence Argument

David Hume. Walter Terence Stace. Soft Determinism. Dan Dennett

DOES NEUROSCIENCE UNDERMINE RESPONSIBILITY?

Free Will and Determinism

The knowledge argument

Compatibilist Objections to Prepunishment

Think by Simon Blackburn. Chapter 3b Free Will

Philosophy 203 History of Modern Western Philosophy. Russell Marcus Hamilton College Spring 2014

David Hume, Liberty and Necessity. An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding Section VIII

The Problem of Freewill. Blatchford, Robert, Not Guilty

Predictability, Causation, and Free Will

Free Will. Christian Wüthrich The Nature of Reality

FREE WILL AND DETERMINISM: AN ADOPTION STUDY. James J. Lee, Matt McGue University of Minnesota Twin Cities

Ending The Scandal. Hard Determinism Compatibilism. Soft Determinism. Hard Incompatibilism. Semicompatibilism. Illusionism.

Hard Determinism, Humeanism, and Virtue Ethics

DETERMINISM is the view that all events without exception are effects or, a little

Chapter 5: Freedom and Determinism

The Incoherence of Compatibilism Zahoor H. Baber *

Kane on. FREE WILL and DETERMINISM

Chance, Chaos and the Principle of Sufficient Reason

Determinism defined: Every event has a cause/set of causes; if its cause occurs, then the effect must follow.

The Mystery of Libertarianism

Q: What does freedom mean from a philosophical and a theological viewpoint?

This handout follows the handout on The nature of the sceptic s challenge. You should read that handout first.

PHL340 Handout 8: Evaluating Dogmatism

Molinism and divine prophecy of free actions

Agency Implies Weakness of Will

EXERCISES, QUESTIONS, AND ACTIVITIES. 1) Aluminum is a limited and valuable natural resource. Therefore it s important to recycle aluminum cans.

Journal of Cognition and Neuroethics

Journal of Philosophy, Inc.

Chapter 5: Freedom and Determinism

Walter Terence Stace. Soft Determinism

Unit 3. Free Will and Determinism. Monday, November 21, 11

ALTERNATIVE POSSIBILITIES AND THE FREE WILL DEFENCE

Reflection on what was said about coercion above might suggest an alternative to PAP:

The William Glasser Institute

DOES STRONG COMPATIBILISM SURVIVE FRANKFURT COUNTER-EXAMPLES?

Libertarian Free Will and Chance

FREE WILL Galen Strawson

Benjamin Vilhauer, William Paterson University of New Jersey. Abstract

Think by Simon Blackburn. Chapter 3d Free Will

An Alternate Possibility for the Compatibility of Divine. Foreknowledge and Free Will. Alex Cavender. Ringstad Paper Junior/Senior Division

SITUATIONS AND RESPONSIVENESS TO REASONS * Carolina Sartorio. University of Arizona

Free Will. Course packet

If God brought about the Big Bang, did he do that before the Big Bang?

Lecture 25 Hume on Causation

British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 62 (2011), doi: /bjps/axr026

PRELIMINARY QUIZ OPTIMISTS AND PESSIMISTS OPTIMISTS AND PESSIMISTS THE REACTIVE ATTITUDES OPTIMISTS AND PESSIMISTS 10/18/2016

The Mystery of Free Will

MANIPULATION AND INDEPENDENCE 1

Free Will. Christian Wüthrich Metaphysics Fall 2012

What is the problem?

What is the problem?

Phil 108, August 10, 2010 Punishment

Freedom, Responsibility, and Frankfurt-style Cases

Free Will [The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy]

Hume s An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding

The Problem with Complete States: Freedom, Chance and the Luck Argument

Journal of Philosophy, Inc.

Prompt: Explain van Inwagen s consequence argument. Describe what you think is the best response

R. G. Collingwood, An Essay on Metaphysics, Clarendon Press, Oxford p : the term cause has at least three different senses:

What God Could Have Made

A New Argument Against Compatibilism

HABERMAS ON COMPATIBILISM AND ONTOLOGICAL MONISM Some problems

Comprehensive. Hard Determinism Compatibilism. Compatibilism. Soft Determinism. Hard Incompatibilism. Semicompatibilism. Illusionism.

FRANKFURT-TYPE EXAMPLES FLICKERS AND THE GUIDANCE CONTROL

Four Views on Free Will. John Martin Fischer, Robert Kane, Derk Pereboom, and Manuel Vargas

Boethius, The Consolation of Philosophy, book 5

Some Reflections on Hanoch Ben-Yami s Defence of Compatibilism

POWERS, NECESSITY, AND DETERMINISM

Harry Frankfurt. Freedom of the Will and the Concept of a Person

A Coherent and Comprehensible Interpretation of Saul Smilansky s Dualism

EXERCISES, QUESTIONS, AND ACTIVITIES My Answers

Jonathan Edwards and Free Will

In his pithy pamphlet Free Will, Sam Harris. Defining free will away EDDY NAHMIAS ISN T ASKING FOR THE IMPOSSIBLE. reviews/harris

Freedom and Determinism

Neurophilosophy and free will VI

Fischer-Style Compatibilism

The Zygote Argument remixed

I will briefly summarize each of the 11 chapters and then offer a few critical comments.

Attraction, Description, and the Desire-Satisfaction Theory of Welfare

Free Will or Determinism - A Conundrum Mark Dubin February 14, 1994

Hume s emotivism. Michael Lacewing

The Problem of Divine Foreknowledge and Human Freedom

B In many cases the author has agreed to permit copying upon completion of a Copyright Declaration.

All the Freedom You Can Want: The Purported Collapse of the Problem of Free Will

Transcription:

Michael Lacewing Compatibilism This handout follows the handout on Determinism. You should read that handout first. COMPATIBILISM I: VOLUNTARY ACTION AS DEFINED IN TERMS OF THE TYPE OF CAUSE FROM WHICH IT ISSUES Compatibilism is the view that determinism is not incompatible with free will, i.e. even if determinism is true, we still have free will. A first form of compatibilism argues that to have free will is simply for one s choice to cause one s action. To do what you want to do is the essence of free will. So, for example, Hume says that free will is simply a power of acting or not acting, according to the determinations of the will. (Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding, p. 159) In other words, I act as I do because of what I chose to do. If I had chosen to act differently, then I would have acted differently. This does not conflict with determinism. My action is caused by my choice. And my choice may in turn be caused by other events. So there is a causal story for my choice and action. And determinism agrees that if my choice had been different, then I would have acted differently (different cause, different effect). Objection But we can object that this is too weak a notion of free will. It is not enough to say that I would have acted differently if I had chosen differently. We also need to say that I could have chosen differently. Someone may choose to act as they do, but be motivated by a compulsion or addiction. For example, if I am addicted to smoking, there may be times when I feel I have to have a cigarette I can t chose not to. Yet it would still be true, that if I did chose not to, then I wouldn t. But I m not free to chose not to have a cigarette. Another example: suppose that someone has inserted a chip into my brain and is able to cause me to choose to act in a particular way. It is true that if I had chosen differently, I would have acted differently. But I couldn t have chosen differently, because someone is controlling what I choose. In both examples, what I choose determines what I do, yet I could not choose anything else, so in what sense are my choices free? COMPATIBILISM II: VOLUNTARY ACTION AS CAUSALLY DETERMINED AND YET DISTINGUISHABLE FROM PSYCHOLOGICALLY OR PHYSICALLY CONSTRAINED ACTION A second form of compatibilism argues that it is a confusion to oppose free will and causation. The opposite of caused is uncaused; the opposite of free is constrained. Events are caused or uncaused, actions are free or constrained. So the opposite of a free

action is not a caused event but a constrained action. Actions that are not constrained are free. The issue of causation is irrelevant. Here are four cases of constraint that bring out the contrast with free action: 1. You trip and fall into someone, knocking them over. Your knocking them over is physically constrained, not something that you had any choice or control over. 2. Someone puts a gun to your head, and tells you to push someone over. You have a kind of choice here you can push them or die. But your action is very constrained, by coercion, a psychological constraint. 3. You are addicted to heroin, and acting on the intense desire for it, you steal from a store to get the money to buy more. You hate your addiction and would chose to be without it if you could. Your action is driven by an addiction, so it is physically (and psychologically) constrained, and not free. 4. Kleptomania is the compulsion to steal, without needing to or profiting from it. If you were a kleptomaniac, you would want to steal things, even things that aren t much use to you. You may even want to not want to steal and try to resist stealing; but you don t (always) succeed. We could argue that being a kleptomaniac is a case of psychological compulsion. These four cases all stand in contrast to what it is to act freely, to act without physical or psychological constraint. This, say compatibilists, is the contrast that matters to whether we are free. Objections and replies The hard determinist someone who believes that determinism is incompatible with free will, and that determinism is true argues that there is no real difference between free and constrained action. All action is similar to being a kleptomaniac or tripping in falling. The reason there is no relevant difference is that in both cases, the action is caused. All that changes is how the action is caused (whether the cause is gravity, a psychological condition or a series of events in the brain that we call choice ). Denying the distinction between free and constrained action is counter-intuitive. But we can ask whether the contrast is clear and reliable. If not, then perhaps free will is not so distinct from constraint, and the determinist isn t wrong after all. To defend the distinction we can ask whether either threats or rational argument would change what the person does. If the action really is constrained, then they will not the person can t change what they do. So, for instance, threatening someone who already has a gun to their head will change nothing; and arguing with someone trips and knocks someone over will not make prevent them from knocking someone over next time they trip. But sometimes drug addicts respond to threats and arguments, and try harder to kick their habit. Perhaps kleptomaniacs would be deterred by greater security in stores. On the other hand, hardened criminals seem not to respond to either does this mean that they are not free? Are they not responsible for their crimes? A second way to defend the distinction is in terms of praise and blame. If we would blame someone for what they did, then they acted freely. If we would not as in the cases above then the action was constrained. But we can object that this gets things the

wrong way around. It tries to define free will in terms of praise and blame. But when is it right to blame someone? Can we say without referring to free will? Surely it is absurd to blame someone unless we already think that they are free. We can t first decide that it is right to blame them, and then conclude that therefore they must be free. The hard determinist, then, will argue that there is no real distinction between free and constrained action. In that case, to oppose free and caused is not a confusion, so the challenge of determinism remains. FRANKFURT: SECOND ORDER DESIRES In Freedom of the Will and the Concept of a Person, Harry Frankfurt argues that in order to define and defend free will, we need to understand the will is complex. Firstorder desires are desires to do or have certain things, e.g. chocolate, seeing a film, etc. Second-order desires are desires about first-order desires. For example, I may not like going to art galleries, but I may want to like going to art galleries. Or again, I may want a cigarette, but I may want not to want a cigarette. What we will relates to desires that actually motivate us to do something. About anything that we will, we can have second-order desires. We can want the desire we are acting on to be what we will, or we can want it not to be. I can want to read philosophy, and this desire gets me to read philosophy, and I want this desire to be what I will. On the other hand, I can want a cigarette, and have one, but want my desire for a cigarette not to move me in this way. In the second case, I am an unwilling smoker. But this is not a conflict between two firstorder desires the desire to smoke and the desire not to. It is a conflict between a firstorder desire to smoke and the second-order desire that the desire to smoke not be my will. This gives the feeling that when I smoke, my will is not free. For my will to be free, I must be able to will what I want to will. Someone has free will if they can will what they want to will. Frankfurt s view explains why just being able to do what I want isn t enough for free will, but his account still identifies free will with a particular kind of cause (compatibilism I), viz. doing what I will when I want to will what I do. His view also provides us with a distinction between voluntary action and psychologically constrained action (compatibilism II). When someone is not able to will what they want to will, then they are psychologically constrained. Objections First, what should we say of a drug addict who is happily an addict? He has the secondorder desire that his addiction is his will. Is he free? Frankfurt can say yes, because he is willing what he wants to will. But Frankfurt can say no, because he is only free if he can bring his will into line with what he wants it to be. His addiction makes this impossible he would continue to want drugs even if he didn t want to want them. Second, does Frankfurt s view answer the challenge from determinism? When I want to will what I do, could I have wanted otherwise? On Frankfurt s definition, I can will otherwise, but this does not mean that I can change what I want to will. This might be determined, e.g. by my character. Frankfurt can reply that this is true but irrelevant. Free

will is about my will being free, i.e. about what I will being responsive to what I want to will. Nothing more is required. A third objection is that second-order desires are beside the point. We want first-order desires to be responsive to what we think we should want, i.e. they should be responsive to our values and reasons for acting rather than just our desires. To choose freely is to choose according to one s values. Fourth, even if Frankfurt accepts this amendment, it is still not enough for free will. If our choices and actions are responsive to our values and reasoning, if someone had provided us with a good reason not to act as we chose to act, we would have chosen differently. However, for free will, it must be true that I could have chosen otherwise in that very situation. Frankfurt s account hasn t said how this is possible if determinism is true. Frankfurt can reply that we are supposing that my choice depends on my values. Is the objection that I haven t chosen my values? But do we choose our values or our reasons for acting? Don t we rather respond to what is valuable? Where is the lack of freedom in that? REGULARITY AND NECESSITY A different defence of compatibilism argues that causation does not rule out free will, because there is no such thing as causal necessity. The determinist has misinterpreted the idea of regularity. Regularity does not entail necessity. Causes don t compel their effects. All we can say is that on each occasion, it is this one effect that occurs. To talk of causation is to talk of unbroken regularities, and so cause and effect are correlated. But we cannot, from this, draw any conclusions about necessity. Causation is about how things are, not how things must be. Without causal necessity, it is not true that we must do whatever it is we do, or that we could not do anything else. What we choose is not compelled, and the motives on which we act don t force us to act as we do. It is not causation that threatens free will; it is causal necessity. If determinism is just the claim that every event has a cause, this is compatible with free will. The hard determinist can respond that our concept of causation does involve necessity by pointing to the way science proceeds. In investigating the laws of nature, when we don t get the same effect in two cases we look for a difference that would explain this. Take Water boils at 100 C at sea level. If we heat water, but it doesn t boil, we would think something about the situation was different from what is specified by the law perhaps the water isn t pure, perhaps we aren t at sea level, perhaps the water isn t yet 100 C. This demonstrates our commitment to the idea that water must boil at 100 C at sea level it is the only possible effect (or the law is wrong). Other things being equal In the handout on Determinism, we argued that our usual causal explanations depend upon other things being equal. To defend causal necessity, and get rid of other things being equal, we introduced the idea of the entire state of the universe from this state, only one state could be produced, in accordance with the laws of nature. But in order to understand causation, are we committed to eliminating other things being equal in every

case? It is not obvious that we are. Our causal explanations usually have a point, a purpose. They pick out what we consider relevant in the event. The other things being equal clause helps us think about what sorts of other thing we need to control for in establishing a cause (with water boiling: purity, height above sea level, etc.). This suggests that talking about the entire state of the universe is not what we mean by other things being equal. If this is right, our idea of causation doesn t commit us to causal necessity and so to determinism in every case. Instead, we can argue that causal necessity is a commitment in scientific investigation if there is a different effect, we continue looking for the difference in the cause. We can then argue that while this commitment is appropriate for natural science, it is inappropriate for other types of (causal) explanation, e.g. in social science, psychology, and accounts of what people do. These explanations don t look for or need exceptionless laws to work. When we explain why someone did something, we don t need to say that anyone in the same situation would do exactly the same thing. So when doing natural science, we are committed to determinism, including causal necessity. When understanding and explaining people, we are not committed in this way, so we can allow that they have free will.