Prompt: Explain van Inwagen s consequence argument. Describe what you think is the best response

Similar documents
Final Paper. May 13, 2015

Philosophical Perspectives, 14, Action and Freedom, 2000 TRANSFER PRINCIPLES AND MORAL RESPONSIBILITY. Eleonore Stump Saint Louis University

Foreknowledge, evil, and compatibility arguments

Truth and Molinism * Trenton Merricks. Molinism: The Contemporary Debate edited by Ken Perszyk. Oxford University Press, 2011.

PETER VAN INWAGEN AND DETERMINISM* (Received 18 March, 1974)

Am I free? Free will vs. determinism

Freedom, Responsibility, and Frankfurt-style Cases

The Problem of Evil. Prof. Eden Lin The Ohio State University

What God Could Have Made

WHY PLANTINGA FAILS TO RECONCILE DIVINE FOREKNOWLEDGE

Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible?

HABERMAS ON COMPATIBILISM AND ONTOLOGICAL MONISM Some problems

Lecture 3. I argued in the previous lecture for a relationist solution to Frege's puzzle, one which

The problem of evil & the free will defense

Compatibilism and the Basic Argument

Searle vs. Chalmers Debate, 8/2005 with Death Monkey (Kevin Dolan)

Philosophy of Religion 21: (1987).,, 9 Nijhoff Publishers, Dordrecht - Printed in the Nethenanas

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

The free will defense

THE SENSE OF FREEDOM 1. Dana K. Nelkin. I. Introduction. abandon even in the face of powerful arguments that this sense is illusory.

Local Miracle Compatibilism. Helen Beebee

INHISINTERESTINGCOMMENTS on my paper "Induction and Other Minds" 1

Russell: On Denoting

Comments on Truth at A World for Modal Propositions

Van Inwagen's modal argument for incompatibilism

Vol. II, No. 5, Reason, Truth and History, 127. LARS BERGSTRÖM

DENNETT ON THE BASIC ARGUMENT JOHN MARTIN FISCHER

Can Negation be Defined in Terms of Incompatibility?

The Mind Argument and Libertarianism

Free will and the necessity of the past

What would be so bad about not having libertarian free will?

The Mystery of Free Will

2 FREE CHOICE The heretical thesis of Hobbes is the orthodox position today. So much is this the case that most of the contemporary literature

Free Will. Christian Wüthrich Metaphysics Fall 2012

Can Negation be Defined in Terms of Incompatibility?

A CRITIQUE OF THE FREE WILL DEFENSE. A Paper. Presented to. Dr. Douglas Blount. Southwestern Baptist Theological Seminary. In Partial Fulfillment

POWERS, NECESSITY, AND DETERMINISM

The Problem with Complete States: Freedom, Chance and the Luck Argument

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

10 CERTAINTY G.E. MOORE: SELECTED WRITINGS

Criticizing Arguments

The Paradox of Free Will

Kane is Not Able: A Reply to Vicens Self-Forming Actions and Conflicts of Intention

In Defense of The Wide-Scope Instrumental Principle. Simon Rippon

A Compatibilist Account of the Epistemic Conditions on Rational Deliberation 1. Derk Pereboom, Cornell University

MORAL RESPONSIBILITY, DETERMINISM, AND THE ABILITY TO DO OTHERWISE

BENEDIKT PAUL GÖCKE. Ruhr-Universität Bochum

CONSCIOUSNESS, INTENTIONALITY AND CONCEPTS: REPLY TO NELKIN

Divine omniscience, timelessness, and the power to do otherwise

From Necessary Truth to Necessary Existence

Molinism and divine prophecy of free actions

Is Innate Foreknowledge Possible to a Temporal God?

This is an electronic version of a paper Journal of Philosophical Logic 43: , 2014.

Artificial Intelligence: Valid Arguments and Proof Systems. Prof. Deepak Khemani. Department of Computer Science and Engineering

The Metaphysics of Freedom

Humean Compatibilism Helen Beebee and Alfred Mele

Journal of Cognition and Neuroethics

PLANTINGA ON THE FREE WILL DEFENSE. Hugh LAFoLLETTE East Tennessee State University

Could have done otherwise, action sentences and anaphora

WHY THERE REALLY ARE NO IRREDUCIBLY NORMATIVE PROPERTIES

Pre-publication version: DO NOT CITE HUMEAN COMPATIBILISM. Helen Beebee &Alfred R. Mele, Mind, 111 (2 2):

I will briefly summarize each of the 11 chapters and then offer a few critical comments.

Note: This is the penultimate draft of an article the final and definitive version of which is

Compatibilist Objections to Prepunishment

Causation and Free Will

Comments on Van Inwagen s Inside and Outside the Ontology Room. Trenton Merricks

In Defense of the Direct Argument for Incompatibilism

Philosophy 1100: Introduction to Ethics. Critical Thinking Lecture 1. Background Material for the Exercise on Validity

Compatibilism vs. incompatibilism, continued

(1) A phrase may be denoting, and yet not denote anything; e.g., 'the present King of France'.

An Alternate Possibility for the Compatibility of Divine. Foreknowledge and Free Will. Alex Cavender. Ringstad Paper Junior/Senior Division

How Necessary is the Past? Reply to Campbell MATTHEW H. SLATER

5 A Modal Version of the

Free will & divine foreknowledge

Faith and Philosophy, April (2006), DE SE KNOWLEDGE AND THE POSSIBILITY OF AN OMNISCIENT BEING Stephan Torre

Revelation, Humility, and the Structure of the World. David J. Chalmers

Truth At a World for Modal Propositions

SAVING RELATIVISM FROM ITS SAVIOUR

Tutorial A02: Validity and Soundness By: Jonathan Chan

ALTERNATIVE POSSIBILITIES AND THE FREE WILL DEFENCE

Ayer on the criterion of verifiability

THE MORAL ARGUMENT. Peter van Inwagen. Introduction, James Petrik

The Development of Knowledge and Claims of Truth in the Autobiography In Code. When preparing her project to enter the Esat Young Scientist

What is the Frege/Russell Analysis of Quantification? Scott Soames

THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE

Introduction. I. Proof of the Minor Premise ( All reality is completely intelligible )

This is a collection of fourteen previously unpublished papers on the fit

Fatalism and Truth at a Time Chad Marxen

INTERMEDIATE LOGIC Glossary of key terms

NECESSARY BEING The Ontological Argument

Free Will and Theism. Connections, Contingencies, and Concerns. edited by Kevin Timpe and Daniel Speak

Am I free? Freedom vs. Fate

Free Will as an Open Scientific Problem

Que sera sera. Robert Stone

The Fall of the Mind Argument and Some Lessons about Freedom

Free will and foreknowledge

Stout s teleological theory of action

THE FALL OF THE MIND ARGUMENT AND SOME LESSONS ABOUT FREEDOM

THE CASE OF THE MINERS

Transcription:

Prompt: Explain van Inwagen s consequence argument. Describe what you think is the best response to this argument. Does this response succeed in saving compatibilism from the consequence argument? Why or why not? A Can of Worms by William Hoza In The Incompatibility of Free Will and Determinism [1], Peter van Inwagen argues that if the universe is deterministic, then free will does not exist. (He is silent about whether the universe is in fact deterministic and about whether free will in fact exists.) This is in contrast to the compatibilist position, which holds that free will and determinism are not contradictory. Briefly, van Inwagen s argument is that when an agent with free will performs some action, she (by definition of free will ) could have performed a different action. But in a deterministic universe, acting a different way requires either altering the past or violating the laws of physics. So van Inwagen concludes that the free agent could have either altered the past or violated the laws of physics. Finally, van Inwagen says that it is obvious that nobody can alter the past, and by definition of the phrase law of physics, nobody can violate the laws of physics either. So our hypothetical free agent in a deterministic universe cannot exist. I will argue that van Inwagen s argument does not succeed in ruling out the possibility of free will in a deterministic universe, because his idea of what it means to say that an agent could have done otherwise is not the relevant notion for free will. When the phrase could have is analyzed correctly (using the standard conditional analysis ), van Inwagen s argument breaks down in a perhaps counterintuitive way: From the facts that an agent could have done X and that doing X requires doing Y, it does not follow that the agent could have done Y. I ll begin by explaining van Inwagen s argument in more detail. He defines determinism to be the conjunction of these two theses: (a) For every instant of time, there is a proposition that expresses the state of the world at that instant. (b) If A and B are any propositions that express the state of the world at some instants, then the conjunction of A with the laws of physics entails B. [2, page 214] He leaves the phrase law of physics undefined, but promises to only make assumptions about the phrase which any reasonable person would agree must come out true under any legitimate analysis of the phrase. I have no complaints with van Inwagen s usage of the phrase. 1

Next, van Inwagen discusses what it means to have free will. He says that at the least, if an agent performs an act freely, then that agent could have refrained from performing the act. [2, page 216] As with the phrase law of physics, van Inwagen declines to give a definition for the relevant sense of can / could have. 1 Again, he promises to only make uncontroversial assumptions: [2, page 217] There is, however, considerably less agreement as to how can (in the relevant sense) should be analysed. This is one of the most difficult questions in philosophy. It is certainly a question to which I do not know any nontrivial answer. But, as I said I should do in the case of law of physics, I shall make certain conceptual claims about can (in the power or ability sense) in the absence of any analysis. Any suggested analysis of can that does not support these claims will either be neutral with respect to them, in which case it will be incomplete, since it will not settle all conceptual questions about can, or it will be inconsistent with them, in which case the arguments I shall present in support of these claims will, in effect, be arguments that the analysis fails. Later, I will indeed argue in favor of an analysis of can that does not support van Inwagen s claims about can. Finally, van Inwagen presents his argument. He imagines, as a prototypical example of a free-seeming action, a judge J who decides at time T to not raise his hand. Following van Inwagen, let T 0 be a time prior to J s birth, let P and P 0 be propositions expressing the states of the universe at times T and T 0 respectively, and let L be the conjunction of all the laws of physics. Van Inwagen then argues as follows that if determinism is true, then J could not have raised his hand at time T : Assume for a contradiction that determinism is true and J could have raised his hand at time T. By determinism, (P 0 L) entails P, and hence (by contraposition) P entails ( P 0 L). Since J could have raised his hand at time T, he could have made P true. Then and this is the crucial step which I will criticize van Inwagen says, from the facts that J could have made P true and that P entails ( P 0 L), we may conclude that J could have made ( P 0 L) true. But, van Inwagen says, that s absurd; J can neither affect things that took place before his birth, nor violate the laws of physics. Van Inwagen discusses most steps of this argument in great detail, but he only briefly defends the step with which I take issue: [2, page 221] This premiss [that if J could have rendered P false, and if (P 0 L) entails P, then J could have rendered (P 0 L) false] may be defended as an instance of the following general principle: If S can render R false, and if Q entails R, then S can render Q false. This principle seems to be analytic. For if Q entails R, then the denial of R entails the denial of Q. Thus, any condition sufficient for the falsity of R is also sufficient for the falsity of Q. Therefore, if there is some condition that S can produce that is sufficient for the falsity of R, there is some condition (that same condition) that S can produce that is sufficient for the falsity of Q. 1 Following van Inwagen, I will treat the phrases can and could have as differing only grammatically. 2

I ll refer to this general principle the principle that the set of statements that an agent can render true is closed under entailment as van Inwagen s entailment principle. Van Inwagen s entailment principle sounds plausible at first, but van Inwagen s defense of the principle is circular. To try to establish that S can render Q false, he merely establishes that there is some condition that S can produce that is sufficient for the falsity of Q. Presumably, the sense of sufficiency meant here is that the condition logically entails the falsity of Q. Thus, to arrive at the desired conclusion that S can render Q false, van Inwagen would need precisely the entailment principle that he is trying to prove, with R being the negation of the aforementioned sufficient condition. I think the real reason that van Inwagen s entailment principle is tempting is because it is true for a certain notion of can. Sometimes, when a person says that something can happen, she merely means that it is logically possible for the thing to happen. (E.g. The Earth could have been invaded by aliens in 1941, in which case World War II would have gone much differently. ) With respect to this notion of can, van Inwagen s entailment principle is certainly true. But this notion of can is not the relevant one for free will. The fact that Mount St. Helens could have erupted today does not help Mount St. Helens to have free will. In fact, I will argue that van Inwagen s entailment principle is false when can is interpreted in the sense relevant to free will. And what sense is that? In the Mount St. Helens example, the missing ingredient for free will is that even in our hypothetical scenario where Mount St. Helens erupted today, it still wasn t on purpose. The sense of can relevant to free will is an intention-oriented sense. To be more specific, I, like countless compatibilists before me, advocate the so-called conditional analysis of can : To say that an agent can do X means that if the agent formed the intention to do X, then she would do X. Notice that when an agent forms an intention to do X, even if X entails Y, the agent might not automatically form an intention to do Y. For example, you might form an intention to write down a prime p such that p 1 (mod 4) without forming the intention to write down a prime which is a sum of two squares, despite a theorem of Fermat that states that the two conditions are equivalent. This observation about intentions hopefully makes van Inwagen s entailment principle sound much less plausible. In particular, the instance of van Inwagen s entailment principle that appears in his main argument should now sound dubious and in serious need of justification. Clearly, the judge truly can raise his hand: if he were to form the intention to raise his hand, he would succeed (because of the laws of physics!) Can the judge alter circumstances before his birth? That depends on your model of counterfactual conditionals. But the point is that the relevant question What would happen if the judge formed the intention to alter circumstances before his birth? is completely different than the question of what would happen if the 3

judge formed the intention to raise his hand. Similarly with violating the laws of physics. In fact, van Inwagen s entailment principle is false in general. Here is a mundane counterexample. Imagine a linear algebra student who did not study enough for her test. She is asked to compute the inverse of a 6 6 matrix. She cannot compute the inverse. (Even if she formed the intention to invert the matrix, she still would not successfully do it.) But for each individual step of the Gauss-Jordan elimination algorithm, she can perform that individual step. (If she formed the intention to e.g. replace row 2 of the matrix with the sum of rows 1 and 2, she would easily do it.) She can perform each step of the algorithm, and performing all of the steps entails inverting the matrix, but she can t invert the matrix. For an even simpler counterexample, suppose the password for access to the United States nuclear weapons is 09384294. A Soviet spy wishes to gain access, but does not know the password. The spy cannot enter the correct password. (Even if she thinks, I shall enter the correct password, she still fails to enter the correct password.) But she can enter 09384294, and doing so entails entering the correct password. Thus, van Inwagen s argument for the incompatibility of free will and determinism is invalid. The point that van Inwagen seems to miss is that even if X and Y logically entail each other, determining the truth of S can do X requires consideration of one counterfactual world (the world where S thinks to herself I shall do X, ) whereas determining the truth of S can do Y requires consideration of a different counterfactual world (the world where S thinks to herself I shall do Y. ) I ll end by responding to van Inwagen s discussion of the conditional analysis. He correctly observes the potential threat posed by the conditional analysis to his argument: When his premises are reconsidered with the conditional analysis in mind, it might become clear that some premise is false. He considers one such premise (not the premise to which I objected) and argues that the conditional analysis leaves it unharmed, because either the premise is still true (it certainly still seems true), or else his argument in favor of the premise becomes an argument against the conditional analysis. He then says, The same dilemma confronts the conditionalist if he attempts to show, on the basis of the conditional analysis, that any of the other premisses of the argument is false. [2, page 227] I suppose that I do face that dilemma, but I believe I have overcome it. Indeed, his defense of his entailment principle is an argument against the conditional analysis. But it is an invalid argument against the conditional analysis, as I believe I have convincingly argued already. Have I saved compatibilism from van Inwagen s attack? It depends on what you mean. I do not pretend to have argued that free will and determinism are compatible; maybe van Inwagen s argument can be patched up. But, at least, I do believe that I have uncovered an unreasonable assumption of van Inwagen s about how the word can works. He wanted his assumptions to be basic and evident enough to be data that an 4

analysis of this concept must take account of, so that any analysis on which these claims did not come out true would be for that very reason defective. [2, page 216] On the conditional analysis, his entailment principle does not come out true. The conditional analysis may be defective, but not for that very reason. References [1] Van Inwagen, Peter. The incompatibility of free will and determinism. Philosophical studies 27.3 (1975): 185-199. [2] Pereboom, Derk. Free Will. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Pub., 1997. Print. 5