Free will and the necessity of the past

Similar documents
The Mind Argument and Libertarianism

How Necessary is the Past? Reply to Campbell MATTHEW H. SLATER

Philosophical Perspectives, 14, Action and Freedom, 2000 TRANSFER PRINCIPLES AND MORAL RESPONSIBILITY. Eleonore Stump Saint Louis University

POWERS, NECESSITY, AND DETERMINISM

Van Inwagen's modal argument for incompatibilism

SO-FAR INCOMPATIBILISM AND THE SO-FAR CONSEQUENCE ARGUMENT. Stephen HETHERINGTON University of New South Wales

Farewell to Direct Source Incompatibilism*

DENNETT ON THE BASIC ARGUMENT JOHN MARTIN FISCHER

Freedom and Determinism: A Framework

Free Will. Christian Wüthrich Metaphysics Fall 2012

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Free Will [The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy]

Some Unsound Arguments for Incompatibilism

In Defense of the Direct Argument for Incompatibilism

Compatibilism vs. incompatibilism, continued

MORAL RESPONSIBILITY, DETERMINISM, AND THE ABILITY TO DO OTHERWISE

A New Argument Against Compatibilism

The Incompatibility of Free Will and Naturalism

CRITICAL STUDY FISCHER ON MORAL RESPONSIBILITY

THE LUCK AND MIND ARGUMENTS

WHY PLANTINGA FAILS TO RECONCILE DIVINE FOREKNOWLEDGE

Foreknowledge, evil, and compatibility arguments

The Fall of the Mind Argument and Some Lessons about Freedom

What would be so bad about not having libertarian free will?

From Necessary Truth to Necessary Existence

Bad Luck Once Again. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Vol. LXXVII No. 3, November 2008 Ó 2008 International Phenomenological Society

The Problem of Freewill. Blatchford, Robert, Not Guilty

Free Will. Course packet

The Mystery of Free Will

Prompt: Explain van Inwagen s consequence argument. Describe what you think is the best response

Leeway vs. Sourcehood Conceptions of Free Will (for the Routledge Companion to Free Will)

Freedom and Determinism

THE FALL OF THE MIND ARGUMENT AND SOME LESSONS ABOUT FREEDOM

Truth and Freedom. Trenton Merricks. University of Virginia

Am I free? Free will vs. determinism

A Taxonomy of Free Will Positions

Free Agents as Cause

Daniel von Wachter Free Agents as Cause

Philosophical Perspectives, 14, Action and Freedom, 2000 FREE WILL REMAINS A MYSTERY. The Eighth Philosophical Perspectives Lecture

De Ethica. A Journal of Philosophical, Theological and Applied Ethics Vol. 1:3 (2014)

Predictability, Causation, and Free Will

Free Will Agnosticism i

An Alternate Possibility for the Compatibility of Divine. Foreknowledge and Free Will. Alex Cavender. Ringstad Paper Junior/Senior Division

It has been just over thirty years since the publication of An Essay on Free

Final Paper. May 13, 2015

The Consequence Argument

The Zygote Argument remixed

Merricks on the existence of human organisms

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

METAPHYSICS. The Problem of Free Will

Chapter Six Compatibilism: Mele, Alfred E. (2006). Free Will and Luck. Oxford University Press: Oxford.

Fatalism and Truth at a Time Chad Marxen

Truth and Molinism * Trenton Merricks. Molinism: The Contemporary Debate edited by Ken Perszyk. Oxford University Press, 2011.

Compatibilism and the Basic Argument

The Metaphysics of Perfect Beings, by Michael Almeida. New York: Routledge, Pp $105.00

Externalism and a priori knowledge of the world: Why privileged access is not the issue Maria Lasonen-Aarnio

Simplicity and Why the Universe Exists

A Compatibilist Account of the Epistemic Conditions on Rational Deliberation 1. Derk Pereboom, Cornell University

Freedom, Responsibility, and Frankfurt-style Cases

The Principle of Sufficient Reason and Free Will

Truth At a World for Modal Propositions

in defence of an argument for evans s principle 167

JASON S. MILLER CURRICULUM VITAE

MULTI-PEER DISAGREEMENT AND THE PREFACE PARADOX. Kenneth Boyce and Allan Hazlett

NON-MORAL EVIL AND THE FREE WILL DEFENSE

Molinism and divine prophecy of free actions

Fischer-Style Compatibilism

Timothy O'Connor, Persons & Causes: The Metaphysics of Free Will. Oxford & New York: Oxford University Press, Pp. Xv and 135. $35.

Free will & divine foreknowledge

Is Incompatibilism Intuitive?

Dumitrescu Bogdan Andrei - The incompatibility of analytic statements with Quine s universal revisability

Free Will as an Open Scientific Problem

How (not) to attack the luck argument

A Priori Skepticism and the KK Thesis

McDowell and the New Evil Genius

I will briefly summarize each of the 11 chapters and then offer a few critical comments.

Free Will and Theism. Connections, Contingencies, and Concerns. edited by Kevin Timpe and Daniel Speak

This is a collection of fourteen previously unpublished papers on the fit

Journal of Cognition and Neuroethics

THE ASSIMILATION ARGUMENT AND THE ROLLBACK ARGUMENT

Note: This is the penultimate draft of an article the final and definitive version of which is

IS GOD "SIGNIFICANTLY FREE?''

moral absolutism agents moral responsibility

Pre-publication version: DO NOT CITE HUMEAN COMPATIBILISM. Helen Beebee &Alfred R. Mele, Mind, 111 (2 2):

The principle of sufficient reason and necessitarianism

5 A Modal Version of the

Surveying Freedom: Folk Intuitions about Free Will and Moral Responsibility

Moore s paradoxes, Evans s principle and self-knowledge

Common Sense, Strict Incompatibilism, and Free Will

DANCY ON ACTING FOR THE RIGHT REASON

Empty Names and Two-Valued Positive Free Logic

First published Mon Apr 26, 2004; substantive revision Mon Oct 5, 2009

Walter Terence Stace. Soft Determinism

Philosophy of Religion 21: (1987).,, 9 Nijhoff Publishers, Dordrecht - Printed in the Nethenanas

Locke On Liberty And Necessity

Chapter 7. The Direct Argument for Incompatibilism

Humean Compatibilism Helen Beebee and Alfred Mele

Phil Notes #27: For Determinism (Blanshard)

The Metaphysics of Freedom

David E. Alexander and Daniel Johnson, eds. Calvinism and the Problem of Evil.

Transcription:

free will and the necessity of the past 105 Free will and the necessity of the past Joseph Keim Campbell 1. Introduction In An Essay on Free Will (1983), Peter van Inwagen offers three arguments for incompatibilism, the view that the free will thesis is incompatible with the thesis of determinism. All are formal versions of the Consequence Argument (1983: 56). If determinism is true, then our acts are the consequences of the laws of nature and events in the remote past. But it is not up to us what went on before we were born, and neither is it up to us what the laws of nature are. Therefore, the consequences of these things are not up to us. (1983: 16) I critique the Third Argument (1983: 93 105; 1989: 223 24; 2000: 2 10). My criticism centers on premiss (4), which claims that the past is necessary in some sense: (4) NP 0. Np stands for p and no one has, or ever had, any choice about whether p (1983: 93; 1989: 224). 1 P 0 is a proposition that expresses the state of the world at some instant in the remote past, before there were any 1 An interesting counterexample by McKay and Johnson (1996) has led van Inwagen to revise his definition of Np (2000: 2 10). This is irrelevant to the topics discussed in this paper, so I use van Inwagen s original formulation. Analysis 67.2, April 2007, pp. 105 11. Joseph Keim Campbell Blackwell Publishing Ltd.Oxford, UK and Malden, USAANALAnalysis0003-26382007 Blackwell Publishing Ltd.April 200767210511Original ArticlesJoseph Keim Campbell FREE WILL AND THE NECESSITY OF THE PAST

106 joseph keim campbell human beings (1989: 224). According to (4), no one has, or ever had, any choice about whether a proposition about the remote past is true. There are two distinct, though related, lines of support for premiss (4): argument (a) and argument (b). (a) NP 0 because P 0 is a true proposition about the past and no one can change the past (1983: 92); (b) NP 0 because P 0 is a true proposition about the remote past, before there were any human beings (1989: 224). Loosely speaking, argument (a) suggests that premiss (4) is true because of the pastness of P 0 while argument (b) suggests that premiss (4) is true because of its remoteness. I show that argument (a) is invalid ( 2). A response to this criticism is offered: the move to argument (b). I note that if premiss (4) is supported by argument (b), then the Third Argument does not establish incompatibilism, for having a remote past is not an essential feature of deterministic worlds ( 3). After extending these considerations to van Inwagen s First Argument (1975; 1983: 68 78), I close with some brief comments about the significance of these results ( 4). 2. The necessity of the past According to the free will thesis, some person has or had a choice about whether a true proposition is true. 2 The thesis of determinism is the conjunction of these two claims: For every instant of time, there is a proposition that expresses the state of the world at that instant; If p and q are any propositions that express the state of the world at some instants, then the conjunction of p with the laws of nature entails q. (1983: 65) In the Third Argument, van Inwagen constructs a modal operator, N, such that, Np stands for p and no one has, or ever had, any choice about whether p (1983: 93). He claims that according to the logic of this operator the following inference rules are valid: (α) From p deduce Np, 2 Van Inwagen adopts the traditional view of free will, which holds that a person has free will only if he has alternative possibilities of action (1983: 8). However, nothing I say in this paper presupposes the traditional view of free will. The phrase S has a choice about whether p is consistent with other accounts of free will, as well. One may hold, for instance, that S has a choice about whether p iff S is the source of the fact that p.

free will and the necessity of the past 107 where p stands for p is broadly logically necessary, and (β) From N(p q) and Np deduce Nq (1983: 94). P 0 is a proposition that expresses the state of the world at some time in the remote past, L is the conjunction of the laws of nature, and P is any true proposition (1983: 94 96). Here is van Inwagen s Third Argument (1983: 94 95; cf. 1989: 224, 2000: 2). (1) ((P 0 & L) P) df. determinism (2) (P 0 (L P)) from (1) by exportation (3) N(P 0 (L P)) from (2) by (α) (4) NP 0 premiss (5) N(L P) from (3), (4) by (β) (6) NL premiss (7) NP from (5), (6) by (β) The conclusion is that no one has, or ever had, any choice about whether any true proposition is true. Thus, the argument seems to prove incompatibilism: the free will thesis is incompatible with the thesis of determinism. In support of premisses (4) and (6) van Inwagen writes: I do not see how anyone can reject NP 0 or NL. My reasons are essentially those that I gave in support of MAA and MAB in the Second Argument and in support of premisses (5) and (6) of the First Formal Argument (1983: 96). Earlier, when discussing the Second Argument (1983: 78 93), he writes: MAA may be regarded as a statement of the familiar principle that no one can change the past (1983: 92). In support of premiss (4), van Inwagen is appealing to argument (a) from 1. (a) NP 0 because P 0 is a true proposition about the past and no one can change the past. If argument (a) supports premiss (4), it should equally support a similar claim about any true proposition about the past. However, the fact that no one can change the past is irrelevant to whether anyone ever had a choice about whether some true proposition about the past is true. To see why, consider the following example. Drunk Driver: Smith begins drinking at t 1 and a few hours later he gets in his car and drives home down a dark road in the middle of the night. At t 2 he is driving well over the speed limit and he is so drunk that both his vision and his reaction time are greatly impaired. A moment later, at t 3, he strikes and kills Jones who is walking in a crosswalk. (cf. van Inwagen 1989: 236)

108 joseph keim campbell Suppose that Smith later argues that, given his drunken state and the speed at which he was traveling at t 2, he had no choice about whether he killed Jones at t 3. Smith is correct that he had no choice at t 2 about whether he killed Jones at t 3 but this does not mean that he had no choice about whether he killed Jones at t 3. Prior to t 2, for instance, Smith apparently had several choices available to him, e.g. whether or not to drink, whether or not to drive, etc. (cf. Taylor and Cahn 1965; Lehrer and Taylor 1965; and Lehrer 1990: 243). Argument (a) rests on an invalid inference rule. Let Pp stand for p is a true proposition about the past. Here is the rule: (χ) From Pp deduce Np. Suppose that no one can change the past. Thus, from Pp it follows that no one has any choice about whether p. Nonetheless, it does not follow from Pp that no one ever had any choice about whether p. Consider again our example, Drunk Driver. Let P 2 be a proposition about the entire state of the world at t 2 and let P 3 be the proposition that Smith kills Jones at t 3. Smith argues as follows. NP 2 N(P 2 P 3 ) Therefore, NP 3 Suppose Smith claims that the first premiss is true by appeal to rule (χ) and the fact that no one can change the past. Though this may establish that Smith has no choice about whether P 2, the mere pastness of P 2 is irrelevant to whether Smith ever had a choice about whether P 2. Inference rule (χ) is invalid and so is argument (a). 3. The necessity of the remote past The proponent of the Third Argument has an easy response. P 0 is a proposition about the remote past, a time prior to the existence of human beings. Though Smith had a choice about whether P 3, neither he nor anyone else ever had any choice about whether P 0. Accordingly, premiss (4) is supported by argument (b) from 1 rather than argument (a). (b) NP 0 because P 0 is a true proposition about the remote past. The proponent of the Third Argument might argue that since P 0 describes the state of the world at a time prior to the existence of any human beings, no one has, or ever had, any choice about whether P 0. No one was around back then to have had such a choice. It is not the pastness of our past that gives it its necessity, according to argument (b). Rather it is the remoteness of some of our past the

free will and the necessity of the past 109 fact that our past continues back to a time prior to our existence. If determinism is a threat to our free will, it is so only because there are true propositions about the remote past. If this is the case, though, then the Third Argument cannot provide a general argument for incompatibilism. That there is a remote past is a contingent truth about the actual world, one that is not essential to the thesis of determinism. Consider, for instance, the possible world W. Suppose that W is a determined world such that some adult person exists at every instant. Thus, W has no remote past. At its first moment of existence lived Adam, an adult person with all the knowledge, powers, and abilities necessary for moral responsibility. Shortly after Adam comes Eve, and the rest is history. 3 For each of the propositions that comprise W, someone is such that he has, or had, a choice about whether that proposition is true at least there is no reason to doubt this claim. The Third Argument is not a general argument for incompatibilism. At most, the Third Argument proves the weaker claim that persons cannot have free will in determined worlds with a remote past. In response, one might offer another version of the Consequent Argument: the First Argument (1975; 1983: 68 78). In the First Argument, P 0 is a proposition that expresses the state of the world at some time prior to the birth of some arbitrary person, J, who happens not to raise his hand at some time t. The conclusion is that if determinism is true, J could not have raised his hand at t. The First Argument does not assume that there is a remote past, so it seems immune to my criticism. The First Argument does assume that every person has a remote individual past, that is, that for each person there is an earlier time when that person failed to exist. Adam is such that he has no remote individual past. There is no true proposition about the way that W was prior to Adam s existence, for there is no way that W was prior to his existence. Since W is, by hypothesis, a determined world, the First Argument is not a general argument for incompatibilism either. 4. Concluding remarks 4 How significant are my results? Van Inwagen distinguishes between the Traditional Problem and the Compatibility Problem (1983: 2). The first deals with whether or not the free will thesis and the thesis of determin- 3 Jason Turner noted that I might have supposed a world in which time was circular. 4 Thanks to Eddy Nahamias and the Analysis referee for raising issues that led to the addition of this final section.

110 joseph keim campbell ism are true. The second is concerned with whether or not the free will thesis is compatible with the thesis of determinism. Most philosophers believe that the Consequence Argument provides a compelling argument for incompatibilism, and a potential solution to the Compatibility Problem (cf. Warfield 2000: 167). Yet neither of the most popular versions of the argument the First and Third Arguments offer general reasons for endorsing incompatibilism. In the context of contemporary discussions of the Compatibility Problem, this is a rather startling and significant result. On the other hand, Ted Warfield (2000) has already proposed that the Consequence Argument offers a weaker conclusion than is needed, though for reasons very different from mine. According to Warfield, the conclusion of the Consequent Argument is a contingent claim: if determinism is true, then the free will thesis is false. What is needed is a stronger claim: necessarily if determinism is true, then the free will thesis is false. The incompatibilist may also argue for something strictly weaker than the proper incompatibilist conclusion : Necessarily, all deterministic worlds with C contain no freedom, where C is some contingent claim (Warfield 2000: 170). Following Warfield s last point, the principles of the Third Argument may be used to show that the thesis of determinism together with some other claim e.g., that every person has a remote individual past is inconsistent with the free will thesis. This Weaker Argument is immune to my criticism. 5 Two responses are worth mentioning. First, given only the Weaker Argument, we should judge that Adam is free in W but that Eve is not free. Yet it is hard to see how Adam and Eve differ in any important respects. Good arguments for incompatibilism are supposed to expose the tension between the thesis of determinism and the free will thesis. If the Weaker Argument is the best that the incompatibilist has to offer, it remains a mystery why it cannot show that Adam lacks free will in determined world W. Second, my results suggest that most philosophers have failed to identify the conclusion of the Consequence Argument. We thought it proved, or attempted to prove, incompatibilism but at most it proves something weaker. We should be careful not to draw hasty conclusions about the Weaker Argument, as well. Consider thesis C of the Weaker Argument: the thesis that, when conjoined with the thesis of determinism, entails that no one has free will. What is the full content of C? It might be that C, or some other proposition that entails C, is incompatible with the free will thesis independent of the thesis of 5 Randy Clarke and the Analysis referee offered versions of the Weaker Argument.

free will and the necessity of the past 111 determinism (Turner 2005; Nahamias 2006). Perhaps deterministic models help to expose our worries about free will but these worries persist whether or not determinism is true. It could even be the case that there is a necessarily true proposition that is incompatible with the free will thesis (Strawson 2004). Here the incompatibilist s victory is a mere technicality, so the compatibilist should be able to live with this result, too. 6 Washington State University Pullman, WA 99164-5130, USA josephc@wsu.edu References Lehrer, K. 1990. A possible worlds analysis of freedom. In Metamind. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Lehrer, K. and R. Taylor. 1965. Time, truth and modalities. Mind 74: 390 98. McKay, T. and D. Johnson. 1996. A reconsideration of an argument against compatibilism. Philosophical Topics 24: 113 22. Nahmias, E. 2006. Relocating the problem of free will. Unpublished; presented at the 2006 Inland Northwest Philosophy Conference. Strawson, G. 2004. Free will. In Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. E. Craig. London: Routledge. Taylor, R. and S. Cahn [under the pseudonym Diodorus Cronus ]. 1965. Time, truth and ability. Analysis 25: 137 41. Turner, J. 2005. The incompatibility of free will and naturalism. Available on-line: http://fas-philosophy.rutgers.edu/turner/papers/incompat.pdf van Inwagen, P. 1975. The incompatibility of free will and determinism. Philosophical Studies 27: 185 99. van Inwagen, P. 1983. An Essay on Free Will. Oxford: Clarendon Press. van Inwagen, P. 1989. When is the will free? Philosophical Perspectives 3: 399 422. Repr. in Agents, Causes, and Events, ed. T. O Connor. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1995. Page references are to this latter work. van Inwagen, P. 2000. Free will remains a mystery. Philosophical Perspectives 14: 1 19. Warfield, T. 2000. Causal determinism and human freedom are incompatible: a new argument for incompatibilism. Philosophical Perspectives 14: 167 80. 6 Thanks go to several folks who provided written comments on earlier drafts of this paper: Randy Clarke, Carl Ginet, Noa Latham, Eddy Nahmias, Jason Turner, Kadri Vihvelin, David Widerker, and an anonymous Analysis referee. A previous version of this paper was presented at the 2006 Northwest Philosophy Conference. Thanks especially to my commentator, Matthew Slater, as well as Latham, Michael Nelson and Ben Vilhauer for a helpful discussion. Finally, a special thanks to my fellow Moscow metaphysicians: Michael O Rourke, Slater, and Mitch Stokes.