PHI 1700: Global Ethics

Similar documents
PHI 1700: Global Ethics

Part I Of the Propriety of Action. Consisting of Three Sections Section I Of the Sense of Propriety Chap. I Of Sympathy I.I.1

Adam Smith and the Limits of Empiricism

Is It Morally Wrong to Have Children?

CHAPTER 13: UNDERSTANDING PERSUASIVE. What is persuasion: process of influencing people s belief, attitude, values or behavior.

Take Home Exam #1. PHI 1700: Global Ethics Prof. Lauren R. Alpert

Human Nature & Human Diversity: Sex, Love & Parenting; Morality, Religion & Race. Course Description

EXERCISES, QUESTIONS, AND ACTIVITIES My Answers

KANTIAN ETHICS (Dan Gaskill)

CONTEMPORARY MORAL PROBLEMS LECTURE 14 CAPITAL PUNISHMENT PART 2

PHI 1500: Major Issues in Philosophy

PHI 1500: Major Issues in Philosophy

Challenges to Traditional Morality

learning objectives the establishment Psychology 2200

Are Humans Always Selfish? OR Is Altruism Possible?

Philosophical Ethics. Consequentialism Deontology (Virtue Ethics)

Hume s Law Violated? Rik Peels. The Journal of Value Inquiry ISSN J Value Inquiry DOI /s

Against Individual Responsibility (Sinnott-Armstrong)

PHI 1700: Global Ethics

Radicalization and extremism: What makes ordinary people end up in extreme situations?

Morally Adaptive or Morally Maladaptive: A Look at Compassion, Mercy, and Bravery

Take Home Exam #2. PHI 1700: Global Ethics Prof. Lauren R. Alpert

Self-Evidence and A Priori Moral Knowledge

Socratic and Platonic Ethics

What Makes Someone s Life Go Best from Reasons and Persons by Derek Parfit (1984)

Marriage. Embryonic Stem-Cell Research

AN OUTLINE OF CRITICAL THINKING

I Have A Dream. New Far East Book Six Lesson Four 黃昭瑞. Judy Huang 台南女中

The Moral Relevance of the Past (Hanna)

Take Home Exam #1. PHI 1700: Global Ethics Prof. Lauren R. Alpert

Take Home Exam #1. PHI 1500: Major Issues in Philosophy Prof. Lauren R. Alpert

The Place of Empathy A Sermon by the Rev. Dr. Stephanie May First Parish in Wayland May 21, 2017

PHI 1700: Global Ethics

Phil 108, August 10, 2010 Punishment

PHI 1700: Global Ethics

THEMES: PROMPT: RESPONSE:

Climate change and you: consequences, intentions and consistency. Climate change is a many-sided problem. It s a scientific problem, because what

Going beyond good and evil

Ethical Relativism 1. Ethical Relativism: Ethical Relativism: subjective objective ethical nihilism Ice cream is good subjective

(i) Morality is a system; and (ii) It is a system comprised of moral rules and principles.

Utilitarianism: For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), pp Reprinted in Moral Luck (CUP, 1981).

Section 1 of chapter 1 of The Moral Sense advances the thesis that we have a

Investigating Nature Course Survey Spring 2010 (2104) Rankings Pre Post (1-5) (mean) (mean)

Pihlström, Sami Johannes.

A Case against Subjectivism: A Reply to Sobel

Is Adam Smith s Impartial Spectator Selfless?

SUPPOSITIONAL REASONING AND PERCEPTUAL JUSTIFICATION

Chapter 2. Moral Reasoning. Chapter Overview. Learning Objectives. Teaching Suggestions

THE WHAT, WHY & HOW OF FORGIVENESS When We Need to Forgive Ourselves & Others. By Haidee Lease

HEART WORM What Does God Do with a Self-Righteous Heart? Text: Luke 15:1-32

What God Could Have Made

Empathy, Concern, and Understanding in The Theory of Moral Sentiments. I. Introduction

The Discount Rate of Well-Being

Summary of Kant s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals

BELIEF POLICIES, by Paul Helm. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, Pp. xiii and 226. $54.95 (Cloth).

Chapter 12: Areas of knowledge Ethics (p. 363)

I m sure we would agree our experience tells us that it s not easy for anger be used constructively. Recycling Anger John 2:12-17, James 1:19-22

that the only way a belief can be justified is if it is based on sufficient evidence. However,

Personal & Organizational Spiritual Leadership. (c) IISL 1

Reasons for Belief Session 1 I Struggle With Doubt. Is That OK?

The Pedagogical Approach to Teaching the Holocaust

Précis of Empiricism and Experience. Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh

IN DEFENSE OF AN ANIMAL S RIGHT TO LIFE. Aaron Simmons. A Dissertation

John Locke. An Essay Concerning Human Understanding

The Value of the Life of Reason ( ) Alonzo Fyfe

Peter Singer, Famine, Affluence, and Morality

Comment on Michael Slote: Moral Sentimentalism. Thomas Schramme

CLASSICS IN THE HISTORY OF LIBERTY

Florida State University Libraries

Making Decisions on Behalf of Others: Who or What Do I Select as a Guide? A Dilemma: - My boss. - The shareholders. - Other stakeholders

Ethical Theory for Catholic Professionals

Short Answers: Answer the following questions in one paragraph (each is worth 5 points).

A Framework for Thinking Ethically

Utilitarianism pp

INJUSTICE ARGUMENT ESSAY

Multilateral Retributivism: Justifying Change Richard R. Eva

THE ROAD TO HELL by Alastair Norcross 1. Introduction: The Doctrine of the Double Effect.

Resistance and Transformation: Taking Politics Public Unitarian Coastal Fellowship April 30, 2017 Rev. Sally B. White 1

That which renders beings capable of moral government, is their having a moral nature, and

Defining good and evil.

Early Modern Moral Philosophy. Lecture 5: Hume

CHRISTIANITY AND THE NATURE OF SCIENCE J.P. MORELAND

I m sure your new roommates are totally normal people, and you have nothing to worry about unlike the fellow in the Tell-tale heart.

Compatibilist Objections to Prepunishment

Hume's Representation Argument Against Rationalism 1 by Geoffrey Sayre-McCord University of North Carolina/Chapel Hill

Psychological Egoism, Hedonism and Ethical Egoism

TRY TO FORGET THIS. By Mike Sanker. Does a world without crisis exist within the bounds of our reality? Is there a less

24.03: Good Food 2/15/17

World Hunger and Poverty

The Quintessence of a Christian

ON THE INCOMPATIBILITY BETWEEN ARISTOTLE S AND KANT S IMPERATIVES TO TREAT A MAN NOT AS A MEANS BUT AS AN END-IN- HIMSELF

factors in Bentham's hedonic calculus.

Looking for Justice? Isaiah 51:5. The text for this sermon, the theme of which is, Looking for Justice?, is

Interest-Relativity and Testimony Jeremy Fantl, University of Calgary

The Critical Mind is A Questioning Mind

The main reason we should forgive is because Jesus mandates it.

Darwinian Morality. Why aren t t all the atheists raping and pillaging? Ron Garret (Erann( Gat) September 2004

Notes on Moore and Parker, Chapter 12: Moral, Legal and Aesthetic Reasoning

SOCIAL PHILOSOPHY from the BEGINNING 1/05

Transcription:

PHI 1700: Global Ethics Session 5 September 13 th, 2018 Metaethics: Rationalism vs. Sentimentalism 1

Today s topic is an enduring question in moral psychology: Do we make moral judgments using our reason, or our emotions? Adam Smith (1723-1790, Scotland) endorses a view about moral decision-making called sentimentalism,» according to which our emotions (especially sympathy) guide us in judging actions as right or wrong. In contrast, rationalism is the view that moral judgments are (or should be) based on reasoning. We will look at Smith s defense of sentimentalism, and then consider a more recent debate about the role of empathy in morality. Interestingly, both sentimentalists & rationalists have suggested that empathy might do more harm than good for our moral decision-making. 2

Smith begins: How[ever] selfish man may be supposed [to be], there are evidently some principles in his nature, which interest him in the fortune of others, and render their happiness necessary to him, though he derives nothing from it except the pleasure of seeing it. Of this kind is pity or compassion, the emotion which we feel from the misery of others, when we either see it or are made to [envision] it in a very lively manner. video (from Up!): bit.ly/1pr1ydq That we often derive sorrow from the sorrow of others, is a matter of fact too obvious to require any instances to prove it; for this sentiment, like all the other original passions of human nature, is by no means confined to the virtuous and humane [type of person], though they perhaps may feel it with the most exquisite sensibility. The greatest ruffian, the most hardened violator of the laws of society, is not altogether without it. (4) 3

Last week I introduced you to this question about moral psychology: Are moral judgments innate or learned? Moral empiricists believe that we learn how to judge right & wrong actions, either by imitating others or through explicit training. Moral nativists believe that we have inborn, instinctual mechanisms for judging right & wrong actions. rationalist empiricist Ø By saying that pity/compassion is part of human nature, Smith is endorsing nativism.» So not only does he believe that emotions are central to emotional decision-making (sentimentalism), sentimentalist he believes that those emotions are common to all human beings and do not require any training (nativism). nativist (In contrast, someone could be a sentimentalist but also an empiricist, who believes that the emotions we use in moral decision-making are learned or trained.) 4

Smith continues: [Since] we have no immediate experience of what other men feel, we can form no idea of the manner in which they are affected, [except] by conceiving what we ourselves should feel in the like situation. Though our brother is on the rack [i.e., in great distress], as long as we ourselves are at ease, our senses will never inform us of what he suffers. it is by the imagination only that we can form any [idea] of what are [another person s] sensations. Smith is describing a view that contemporary psychologists call simulation theory: We gain understanding of how other people feel by going through a mental simulation of what we would feel in their situation. 5

Smith elaborates on how this simulation works: By the imagination we place ourselves in his situation,! we conceive ourselves enduring all the same torments, we enter as it were into his body, & become in some measure the same person with him, & thence form some idea of his sensations, & even feel something which, though weaker in degree, is not altogether unlike them. His agonies, when we have thus adopted & made them our own, begin at last to affect us, & then we tremble & shuffle at the thought of what he feels.» For [just] as to be in pain or distress or any kind excites the most excessive sorrow, to imagine that we are in [pain or distress] excites some degree of the same emotion (4-5) 6

According to Smith, the most important emotion we use to make ethical decisions is sympathy or fellow-feeling, though in today s parlance, we d call this empathy. Empathy involves feeling with another person by sharing their emotions; many sentimentalists believe this helps us do the right thing for others, by giving us insight into what we should do to bring them joy, & what we should avoid doing to spare them pain. E.g., our ability to imaginatively feel another person s pain allows us to recognize that it is wrong to hurt them or to let them suffer. Our ability to imagine someone s joy from being relieved of financial stress allows us to judge that it is right to give to charity. 7

How is empathy for others supposed to prompt ethical actions? Smith says the very appearances of grief & joy [in other people] inspire us with some degree of the like emotions, because they suggest to us the general idea of some good or bad fortune that has befallen the person in whom we observe them [which] creates some concern for the person who has met with it. but he emphasizes that empathy does not arise so much from the [observation] of [another person s emotion], [but rather] from that of the situation which excites [that emotion]. One reason he gives to defend this conclusion is that we can feel for people who aren t actually feeling emotions themselves, like when we feel bad for a madman who laughs & sings perhaps, and is altogether insensible of his own misery» video: bit.ly/2ny3gdd 8

So, Smith s sentimentalist outlook on moral decision-making is that we determine what s right or wrong by imagining what emotions we would feel if we were in another person s shoes. Hence, Smith believes that making a decision about an ethical question (like Is it OK to punch Nazis? ) is not a matter of rational investigation, (so we don t need to think through the reasons why it is or isn t ok) but rather is the result of examining the emotions that arise when we imagine ourselves in the relevant situation(s). How would you feel if you were the person punching? How would you feel if you were the person being punched? Is this a good method for determining! whether punching Nazis is right or wrong? 9

Smith is convinced that empathy reliably leads to ethical behavior but this view has recently come under fire. Psychologist Paul Bloom (1963 present, USA) explains (in The Baby in the Well ) how common it is to enthusiastically champion an increase in empathy as a cure for humanity s ills. (3) A lack of empathy is often suggested as the basis for immoral actions (e.g., torture of prisoners of war, partisan bickering, cyberbullying, school shootings, etc.) Bloom will defend the surprising view that this enthusiasm [for empathy] may be misplaced, Ø because we re often at our best! when we re smart enough not to rely on it. (3) He ll explain that empathy needs to be counterbalanced with reason, because empathy is short-sighted, parochial, narrow-minded, & innumerate 10

Bloom explains that empathy motivates us to volunteer and donate in response to newsworthy, flashy events 11

However, our empathy is comparatively lacking for ongoing conflicts, which may have more severe effects or a much greater number of victims. Ø For moral issues that do not have specific, visible victims, empathy is not engaged, & we are less likely to take action to help. Ø For this reason, Bloom criticizes empathy as narrow-minded. 12

According to Bloom, the key to engaging empathy is what has been called the identifiable victim effect. Ø The visibility & specificity of a victim vastly increases how much people empathize with the victim (measured by how willing they are to help): Empathy for an identifiable victim does spur ethical action but it can do so at the expense of action on behalf of other deserving causes. Ø Not all moral causes can induce empathy, so we can t rely on empathy to inspire us to come to the aid of all people who we should be concerned about helping. 13

Bloom adds that empathy is not proportional to the severity of suffering: This is the basis of his critique that empathy is innumerate: it is not attuned to the quantity of suffering experienced by those we empathize with. We don t necessarily feel worse for those who are worse off, or when more people are suffering. 14

An example of how empathy s innumeracy comes into play: the donations made to disease research & treatment funds are disproportionate to the mortality rates of those diseases, so people are not giving in ways that could save the most lives; they are probably giving to fight diseases that have touched them or their loved ones personally, or ones they ve heard of in the media (e.g. ALS, because of the Ice Bucket Challenge) 15

Bloom s concerns about empathy have to do with an area of moral philosophy called distributive justice: the fair allocation of goods & resources within society. According to Bloom,» One plausible principle of distributive justice is that our efforts to help others should be distributed to those in need according to how much they are suffering. If we want to obey this principle, we need to be aware of how empathy can lead us astray (because it s insensitive to how much people are suffering). In order to make sure that we actually dole out our volunteering hours, charity, tax dollars, and so forth in a sensible way, we need to use our reasoning to figure out how much each cause/victim should get, not our emotions, which lead us to distribute goods unjustly. 16

Another problem with empathy is that it can be weaponized in opposition to others. Typically, political disputes involve a disagreement over whom we should empathize with. Liberals argue for gun control, for example, by focusing on the victims of gun violence; conservatives point to the unarmed victims of crime, defenseless against the savagery of others, Bloom explains. For both parties in this debate, the argumentative strategy is often to stoke empathy for particular victims to advance one s agenda. Empathy does not necessarily promote tolerance or concern for the welfare of all kinds of people. Ø Hence, empathy is parochial: it favors people close to us geographically, demographically, or ideologically. 17

[E]mpathy can [also] pull us in the wrong direction because outrage that comes from adopting the perspective of a victim can drive an appetite for retribution [revenge, payback ] But the appetite for retribution is typically indifferent to long-term consequences. 18

There s a larger pattern here, says Bloom. Sensible policies often have benefits that are merely statistical but victims who have names & stories. Consider global climate change: Opponents of restrictions on CO 2 emissions are flush with identifiable victims all those who will be harmed by increased costs, by business closures.» The millions of people who at some unspecified future date will suffer the consequences of our current inaction are, by contrast, pale statistical abstraction. Ø The worry, then, is that empathetic concern for the visible victims of emissions restrictions may overtake our reason-based concern for people far away from us, future generations of humans, or animals. Ø Too often, our concern for specific individuals today means neglecting crises that will harm countless people in the future. 19

Bloom s conclusion is that moral action requires more than just empathy: our concern for specific individuals can blind us to the wrongness of actions that have no (immediately) identifiable victim, like tax evasion or environmental pollution. but also sometimes requires us to disregard our empathetic impulses: E.g., we ought to recognize that eight deaths are worse than one, even if you know the name of the one; [and] the threat posed by climate change warrants the sacrifices entailed by efforts to ameliorate it. Ø A reasoned, even counter-empathetic analysis of moral obligation & likely consequences is a better guide to planning for the future than the gut wrench of empathy. This claim makes Bloom a rationalist, who believes moral decision-making ought to be guided by reason. 20

Philosopher Jesse Prinz summarizes the downsides of empathy: [it s] not a key player in some core respects of moral reasoning, such as thinking about inequality, the environment, or cases where large groups of people are threatened. not a great motivator: studies show that when we feel another s pain, we tend to do little about it. biased: it increased when those in need are salient, similar to ourselves, and close by. easily manipulated, leading us to give preferential treatment to those who may not deserve it. Prinz concludes (similarly to Bloom) that in making policy, we would be better off ignoring empathy. The crucial question is not whose suffering touches us most but who needs us most. 21

Prinz believes attending to injustice is a better route to moral action: Ø Injustice provokes anger,! which motivates us to act to change immoral policies. Prinz believes that emotions are essential for moral decision-making & action; Ø but empathy is neither the only, nor the best emotion to use. 22