A Compatibilist Account of Free Will and Moral Responsibility

Similar documents
This handout follows the handout on Determinism. You should read that handout first.

Moral Psychology

Chapter Six Compatibilism: Mele, Alfred E. (2006). Free Will and Luck. Oxford University Press: Oxford.

Harry Frankfurt Freedom of the Will and the Concept of a Person

Final Paper. May 13, 2015

Compatibilism vs. incompatibilism, continued

MANIPULATION AND INDEPENDENCE 1

FRANKFURT-TYPE EXAMPLES FLICKERS AND THE GUIDANCE CONTROL

Libertarian Free Will and Chance

An Argument for Moral Nihilism

Note: This is the penultimate draft of an article the final and definitive version of which is

Am I free? Free will vs. determinism

Defending Hard Incompatibilism Again

Compatibilist Objections to Prepunishment

DOES STRONG COMPATIBILISM SURVIVE FRANKFURT COUNTER-EXAMPLES?

METAPHYSICS. The Problem of Free Will

SUPPORT MATERIAL FOR 'DETERMINISM AND FREE WILL ' (UNIT 2 TOPIC 5)

The Problem of Freewill. Blatchford, Robert, Not Guilty

A Coherent and Comprehensible Interpretation of Saul Smilansky s Dualism

Kane is Not Able: A Reply to Vicens Self-Forming Actions and Conflicts of Intention

Think by Simon Blackburn. Chapter 3d Free Will

The Mystery of Libertarianism

In his pithy pamphlet Free Will, Sam Harris. Defining free will away EDDY NAHMIAS ISN T ASKING FOR THE IMPOSSIBLE. reviews/harris

The Zygote Argument remixed

Hard Determinism, Humeanism, and Virtue Ethics

Free Will: Do We Have It?

Free Will as an Open Scientific Problem

POWERS, NECESSITY, AND DETERMINISM

The Mystery of Free Will

Fischer-Style Compatibilism

Philosophical Perspectives, 14, Action and Freedom, 2000 TRANSFER PRINCIPLES AND MORAL RESPONSIBILITY. Eleonore Stump Saint Louis University

Think by Simon Blackburn. Chapter 3e Free Will

Philosophy 203 History of Modern Western Philosophy. Russell Marcus Hamilton College Spring 2014

Free Will. Course packet

Reflection on what was said about coercion above might suggest an alternative to PAP:

The Cosmological Argument

If God brought about the Big Bang, did he do that before the Big Bang?

Predictability, Causation, and Free Will

Bad Luck Once Again. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Vol. LXXVII No. 3, November 2008 Ó 2008 International Phenomenological Society

Sensitivity to Reasons and Actual Sequences * Carolina Sartorio (University of Arizona)

Journal of Cognition and Neuroethics

A Framework of Responsibility and Absolution

Hard incompatibilism and the participant attitude

An Alternate Possibility for the Compatibility of Divine. Foreknowledge and Free Will. Alex Cavender. Ringstad Paper Junior/Senior Division

Causation and Free Will

ALTERNATIVE POSSIBILITIES AND THE FREE WILL DEFENCE

Free Will [The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy]

Freedom, Responsibility, and Frankfurt-style Cases

THE SENSE OF FREEDOM 1. Dana K. Nelkin. I. Introduction. abandon even in the face of powerful arguments that this sense is illusory.

Can Rationality Be Naturalistically Explained? Jeffrey Dunn. Abstract: Dan Chiappe and John Vervaeke (1997) conclude their article, Fodor,

Hence, you and your choices are a product of God's creation Psychological State. Stephen E. Schmid

Can Libertarianism or Compatibilism Capture Aquinas' View on the Will?

Mitigating Soft Compatibilism

I will briefly summarize each of the 11 chapters and then offer a few critical comments.

Williamson, Knowledge and its Limits Seminar Fall 2006 Sherri Roush Chapter 8 Skepticism

Free Will, Alternative Possibilities, and Responsibility: An Empirical Investigation 1

David Hume. Walter Terence Stace. Soft Determinism. Dan Dennett

HABERMAS ON COMPATIBILISM AND ONTOLOGICAL MONISM Some problems

PHLA Freedom and Determinism II

Some proposals for understanding narrow content

Why Frankfurt-Style Cases Don t Help (Much) Neil Levy

Free Will Theodicies for Theological Determinists

Journal of Philosophy, Inc.

Truth and Molinism * Trenton Merricks. Molinism: The Contemporary Debate edited by Ken Perszyk. Oxford University Press, 2011.

What God Could Have Made

Alfred Mele s Modest. Hard Determinism Compatibilism. Libertarianism. Soft Determinism. Hard Incompatibilism. Semicompatibilism.

Manipulation and Hard Compatibilism

Walter Terence Stace. Soft Determinism

Agency Implies Weakness of Will

Wright on response-dependence and self-knowledge

Chapter 5: Freedom and Determinism

Why Pereboom's Four-Case Manipulation Argument is Manipulative

Incompatibilism (1) Anti Free Will Arguments

Causation and Freedom * over whether the mysterious relation of agent- causation is possible, the literature

BUDAPEST UNIVERSITY OF TECHNOLOGY AND ECONOMICS

Am I free? Freedom vs. Fate

Chapter 5: Freedom and Determinism

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Kane on. FREE WILL and DETERMINISM

16 Free Will Requires Determinism

Does Theism Imply Determinism? Questions about Hard Determinism. Objections to Hard Determinism, I. Objections to Hard Determinism, II

THE ASSIMILATION ARGUMENT AND THE ROLLBACK ARGUMENT

Prompt: Explain van Inwagen s consequence argument. Describe what you think is the best response

Think by Simon Blackburn. Chapter 3b Free Will

EXERCISES, QUESTIONS, AND ACTIVITIES

2 FREE CHOICE The heretical thesis of Hobbes is the orthodox position today. So much is this the case that most of the contemporary literature

Action, responsibility and the ability to do otherwise

CRUCIAL TOPICS IN THE DEBATE ABOUT THE EXISTENCE OF EXTERNAL REASONS

Vihvelin on Frankfurt-Style Cases and the Actual- Sequence View

The Problem of Divine Foreknowledge and Human Freedom

Free Will, Genuine Alternatives and Predictability

Hard Determinism, Moral Responsibility and Free Will

Manipulators and Moral Standing

To appear in Metaphysics: Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 82, Cambridge University Press, 2018.

AN ACTUAL-SEQUENCE THEORY OF PROMOTION

Is Klein an infinitist about doxastic justification?

ON PROMOTING THE DEAD CERTAIN: A REPLY TO BEHRENDS, DIPAOLO AND SHARADIN

Free Agents as Cause

The Consequence Argument

Transcription:

A Compatibilist Account of Free Will and Moral Responsibility If Frankfurt is right, he has shown that moral responsibility is compatible with the denial of PAP, but he hasn t yet given us a detailed account of free will. When and how are we free, even if determinism is true? In his follow-up article, he attempts to supply answers. 1. Defining Terms: First, some terms: First-Order Desire: This is simply a desire to do something. Frankfurt expresses this as A wants to X (where X is an action). Note that first-order desires can be effective (meaning that they move you to act) or non-effective (meaning that they DON T move you to act). For instance, I had an effective desire to do a lecture on Frankfurt. I also have a desire to eat an entire bag of Reese s cups, but this desire has (so far) been non-effective. They can also compete. I have a desire both to take a trip to Hawaii and Alaska. If I end up going to Hawaii, it is that desire that ends up being effective. Will: When I have an effective first-order desire, this is my will. I will myself to do something, and I do it. He writes, To identify an agent s will is either to identify the desire (or desires) by which he is motivated in some action he performs, or to identify the desire (or desires) by which he will or would be motivated when or if he acts. An agent s will, then, is identical with one or more of his first-order desires. But the notion of the will, as I am employing it, is not coextensive with the notion of first-order desires. Rather, it is the notion of an effective desire one that moves (or will or would move) a person all the way to action. (8) Second-Order Desire: This is a desire ABOUT one s (first-order) desires. We can express this as A wants to want to X (where X is an action). Note that my second-order desires can be either for effective or non-effective first-order desires. For instance, I want to want to exercise more and I want to want this in a way that will be effective (i.e., where I will actually exercise). But, Frankfurt points out that it doesn t HAVE to be this way. He describes a situation where a psychologist is studying the effects of addiction. He wishes he could get inside the head of the addict. In that sense he wants to want to take drugs. But, he doesn t actually want this in a way that it would be effective. He wants to have the desire for drugs so that he can better understand the addict but he doesn t actually want to follow through and take drugs. 1

Second-Order Volition: When I have a second-order desire to have a firstorder desire that is EFFECTIVE, this is my (second-order) volition. THESE are the things that separate us as importantly different from other animals: Now it is having second-order volitions, and not having second-order desires generally, that I regard as essential to being a person. (10) One more technical term: Persons: Persons are beings who have second-order volitions. Note also that being a person requires being RATIONAL. In order to have secondorder volitions, you need to be capable of rationally reflecting upon yourself and your desires. We are peculiar in that we can sort of step back and take a bird s eye view of our desires, and wish for some of them to be effective. You don t just WANT to study hard, you look down at that desire and APPROVE of it. You WANT to WANT to study hard and in a way that will actually result in ACTION (i.e., actual studying). Animals don t seem to have this capacity. Frankfurt calls them wantons. These are any creatures that lack second-order volitions. The essential characteristic of a wanton is that he does not care about his will. His desires move him to do certain things, without its being true of him either that he wants to be moved by those desires or that he prefers to be moved by other desires. (11) 2. Frankfurt s Proposal: Only persons have free will, Frankfurt says. And therefore, (since moral responsibility requires free will) they are the ONLY sorts of creatures that are capable of being morally responsible for their actions. Only persons are what we d call moral agents, deserving of praise and blame. Putting all of this together, Frankfurt makes the following claims: 1. A is morally responsible for doing X if and only if A does X freely. 2. A does X of her own free will (i.e., she freely does X) if and only if doing X meets the following criteria: (i) A has a desire to X (ii) A reflects on whether the desire to X is a desire by which she wants to be motivated (iii) A answers yes ; i.e., she reflectively endorses/identifies with the desire to X (iv) The desire to X moves A to perform action, X 2

Thus, It is in securing the conformity of his will to his second-order volitions, then, that a person exercises freedom of the will. And it is in the discrepancy between his will and his second-order volitions that a person does not have this freedom (15) 3. Applications: Frankfurt s proposal seems to get things right in a number of the cases that we have looked at. For instance: Drug Addicts and Kleptomaniacs: Imagine a drug addict who both wants a drug (because of the addiction) and doesn t want it (because it is bad for her, or whatever). If she wishes she DIDN T want the drug, but takes it anyway, she is not acting freely because she isn t able to bring her will (i.e., her effective first-order desire) in line with her second-order volition (simply put, she is not free to have the will that she wants to have). Note that, in theory, an addict might not have any second-order volitions about their addiction. They might not reflect or care one way or another which firstorder desire wins out. Such an addict is merely a wanton addict. Such addicts have freedom of action i.e., they want something and nothing stops them from DOING it but they do not have freedom of the WILL. This is because they are not in control of WHICH desires move them to action. Note that there might also be willing addicts. Agents who WANT to be addicted. What Frankfurt says about this is dizzyingly confusing. I discuss it at the end. Similarly, kleptomaniacs who have an uncontrollable desire to steal, but wish that they could stop, are not in control of their actions. They are not acting freely. But, that seems intuitive. Both the unwilling addict and the unwilling kleptomaniac deserve HELP, not BLAME. Jones on Election Day: Recall Jones on Election Day. Even though Jones could not do otherwise, Jones still acts FREELY so long as the neurosurgeon does not intervene. Jones has a first-order desire to vote for Trump, and Jones IDENTIFIES with this desire, or reflectively APPROVES of it, so his vote is a free one. However, if he wants to will to vote for Clinton, and the neurosurgeon intervenes to compel him to vote for Trump instead, he is NOT voting freely. For his will (i.e., his effective first-order desire to vote for Trump) is not in line with his volition (i.e., his second-order desire to will to vote for Clinton). 3

Animals: Frankfurt s view nicely explains our intuition that animals do not have free will. Lacking second-order volitions, they are merely wantons. They are not blameworthy for their actions. If a lion mauls someone, we do not say What a morally terrible lion! That lion had a moral obligation not to maul that person. Toddlers, the Cognitively Impaired, Etc.: Note that, for the same reasons that animals are not free, neither are human CHILDREN free (at least, toddlers aren t). This may seem counter-intuitive, but consider a 2-year-old child who pushes someone down some stairs. Are they morally blameworthy? Typically, we do not hold them responsible. Sometimes, we speak of the age of accountability. On Freedom vs. Determinism: In light of the Jones Election Day case, it is apparent that Frankfurt s view of free will is compatible with determinism. Whether or not you are able to do otherwise is irrelevant to free will. Consider Jones, when he votes WITHOUT be interfered with by the neurosurgeon. It is true of him that, he is not only free to do what he wants to do; he is also free to want what he wants to want. It seems to me that he has, in that case, all the freedom it is possible to desire or to conceive. (17) 4. Objections: Here are some problems with Frankfurt s proposal: (a) Whims: We often act on a whim. When we do so, we simply act on a (first-order) desire without reflecting on it or forming any second-order desires regarding it. But, then, this is a problem: If I find you annoying, and get a sudden urge to punch you in the face, and I do so, apparently I am not morally responsible for my action. Hey! I can say, I just did it without reflecting on it first. I m not responsible for that. Reply #1: Perhaps one does not need to ACTUALLY engage in criteria (i) (iv) in order to be morally responsible, but it just needs to be the case that one WOULD endorse their action (i.e., have a second-order desire to have the first-order desire). Rebuttal: But, it s very likely the case that I WOULDN T endorse my action of punching you in the face, had I taken the time to reflect on it. So, in that case, I STILL am not responsible for that action. (?) [We didn t cover this reply in class] Reply #2: In claim 1, we could remove the only if, so that it instead says, P is morally responsible for doing x if P does x freely. In philosophyspeak, the suggestion is that freedom is a SUFFICIENT condition for moral responsibility, but not a NECESSARY condition for it; i.e., maybe we could weaken Frankfurt s proposal to say that you re definitely responsible for actions that you perform freely, but maybe SOMETIMES you can be responsible even for actions that you do NOT perform freely. 4

Rebuttal: But, he doesn t say this. Also, this significantly weakens Frankfurt s view, and now we no longer have a full account of when one is morally responsible for one s actions and when one is not. The question would still remain unanswered, So, then, what makes me responsible for my punching you!!? Reply #3: When you act on a whim perhaps you don t question it because you DO identify with it. The only time that you would question a first-order desire is when it doesn t seem to cohere or mesh well with your other desires. When acting on a whim, there isn t any reason to engage in deliberation first. So, perhaps criterion (iii) is just automatically met in the case of acting on a whim. Frankfurt writes, We may suggest that volitions of the second order must be formed deliberately and that a person characteristically struggles to ensure that they are satisfied. But the conformity of a person s will to his higher-order volitions may be far more thoughtless and spontaneous than this. Some people are naturally moved by kindness whey they want to be kind, and by nastiness when they want to be nasty, without any explicit forethought and without any need for energetic self-control. The enjoyment of freedom comes easily to some. (17) In short, maybe the reflective endorsement can be either explicit OR implicit. [What do you think? Is this a good defense of Frankfurt?] (b) Weakness of the Will: Perhaps the drug addict is not morally responsible for taking more of the drug if he wishes that he DIDN T want the drug, but has a weakness of will where he cannot overcome the strength of that first-order desire. But, Frankfurt s thesis would entail that we are NEVER morally responsible for having weakness of will. Imagine that you are tempted to cheat on your significant other. You do so. You reflect on the desire to cheat, and do NOT endorse it or identify with it. And yet, you find yourself doing it anyway. You suffered from weakness of the will. On Frankfurt s view, you would not be morally blameworthy for such an action. Reply: Disidentification with one s will is not MERELY thinking, I shouldn t be doing this or this is not the right course of action. For Frankfurt, the struggle must be within the will itself. In other words, you must WILL the opposite of what you re doing. In the addict s case, the addict TRIES not to take the drug, or STRUGGLES against the urge, but fails. This is importantly different from the adulterer who thinks, I know this is wrong, but what the hell. Here goes nothing! Rebuttal: Yet, surely some adulterers (or murderers, thieves, etc. fill in the blank here with any seemingly blameworthy action) actually TRY to resist the urge to act wrongly, and fail. So, Frankfurt s view still seems to entail that a pretty significant number of wrongdoers aren t blameworthy. 5

(c) Manipulation: Frankfurt claims to explain how one is free in manipulation cases such as Election Day. In that case, if the neurosurgeon were to press the button to control Jones s brain and force his vote, it would NOT count as free on Frankfurt s view because, even though he has a FIRST ORDER desire to vote for Trump, he has a second-order desire NOT to want to vote for Trump. Since Jones doesn t IDENTIFY with his action, his action is not free. But, has Frankfurt just moved the problem back one level? What if the neurosurgeon s chip controls not only first-order desires but SECOND-order desires as well? In that case, Jones would be freely voting for Trump EVEN IF he is only doing so because the neurosurgeon has pushed the button to force him into doing so. That seems mistaken. Reply #1: Perhaps we could appeal to THIRD-order desires? Rebuttal: But, then we could just propose a case where the neurosurgeon manipulates those too. One could appeal, of course, to FOURTH-order desires But, we are off on an infinite regress. Reply #2: Perhaps we should expand the discussion to not merely include desire, but a whole range of things, including also values, beliefs, and so on. A free action would then be one that conforms to one s second-order desires, AND values, AND beliefs, etc. Rebuttal: But, then we could just propose a manipulation case where the neurosurgeon manipulates THOSE TOO! Reply: Perhaps we could add that, in addition to those things, it has to be the case that: If the agent knew the TRUTH about the SOURCE of those internal attitudes, s/he would STILL identify with them? Rebuttal: But, we can t ever know these things for sure. So We can t ever know for sure whether we are morally responsible for our actions? On Willing Addicts: Imagine that an addict reflects on her addiction and APPROVES of it (i.e., her will IS in line with her second-order volition). Confusingly, Frankfurt says that this willing addict is still NOT free. WTF? His reason seems to be that a criterion (v) is added. Something like, (v) A s will to X is (at least partially) CAUSED by her (second-order) reflection about which (effective first-order) desires she wants to have. He writes, Suppose that a person has done what he wanted to do, that he did it because he wanted to do it, and that the will by which he was moved when he did it was his will BECAUSE it was the will he wanted. (19) If the addict s effective desire for the drug is not caused by any kind of second-order reflection or endorsement, but, rather, by the addiction, then she is not free. (But, if it IS partially caused by the second-order reflection, then it IS free??) Let s ignore this 6

Against Compatibilism 1. The Dilemma: Harry Frankfurt claims to have proposed a view of free will that is compatible with determinism (where agents lack the ability to do otherwise). But, Laura Ekstrom (a famous philosopher of free will right here at W&M!!) critiques this claim. Ekstrom identifies two strategies by which we might refute Frankfurt. Note that, in Election Day, Frankfurt does not specify whether determinism is true or not. But, either way, it seems that Frankfurt is mistaken. We stated Frankfurt s argument as follows (assume that we re talking about the version of Election Day where the neurosurgeon does NOT intervene): 1. In Election Day, Jones could not do otherwise. 2. In Election Day, Jones is responsible for his action. 3. Therefore, being responsible for one s action does not require the ability to do otherwise (i.e., PAP is false). Philosopher John Martin Fischer puts it this way: [There is] a dilemma: the Frankfurt-type stories presuppose either that causal determinism is true or that it is false. If the former, then the claim that the relevant agent is morally responsible is question-begging, and if the latter, then the claim that the agent lacks alternative possibilities is false. (My Way, 2006) Ekstrom argues for this dilemma, claiming that premise 1 is false if indeterminism is true, and premise 2 is false if determinism is true. 2. Indeterminism; P1 is false; Jones DOES have the ability to do otherwise: In Election Day, Frankfurt says, if Jones votes for Trump without the interference of the neurosurgeon, he DOES act freely even though he could not have done otherwise. But, as Frankfurt sets up the story, the neurosurgeon will only intervene if he observes Jones STARTING to form the intention to vote for the wrong candidate. Now, imagine that determinism is false, and that Jones COULD HAVE started to vote for Clinton, but he doesn t (and the neurosurgeon never intervenes). While it is true that he couldn t have done otherwise if we mean he couldn t have voted for anyone but Trump. But, in another sense, he DOES still seem to have alternate possibilities available to him. Namely, he can either (i) form the intention to vote for Trump, and then vote for Trump without intervention, or he can (ii) form the intention to vote for Clinton and then vote for Trump WITH intervention. But, then, Frankfurt has NOT refuted PAP. 7

In Ekstrom s version, Jones is deciding whether or not to kill someone (Smith). If he tries not to, Black will intervene and force Jones to do so anyway. She writes: still he could have tried to decide otherwise [meaning] he could have gone some way toward deciding not to kill Smith. After all, presumably Black s device is triggered by the occurrence of some event, an event that could be described as Jones s trying to decide, or beginning to decide, in an alternate way than as Black desires. And the presence of this indeterminacy or a flicker of freedom at this point shows that Jones s being morally responsible for his act does not conflict with the truth of P.A.P. (283) 3. Determinism; P2 is false; Jones is NOT morally responsible for his action: Ekstrom s preferred objection is this one. When we think about Election Day, we ARE inclined to feel that Jones is responsible for his action. But, we are probably smuggling in the idea that Jones COULD HAVE tried to decide to vote for Clinton (which, we have already shown, would not refute PAP). But, now really, vividly imagine that determinism is true, so that Jones COULD NOT HAVE even TRIED to decide to vote for Clinton. Is it still so obvious that he is responsible for his action? Ekstrom puts the worry beautifully (284-285): perhaps, we think that Jones committed his act freely, of his own accord, if he was not pushed into killing Smith by anything or anyone. And since, by hypothesis in this case, Black did not intervene, so that Black did not push Jones into killing Smith, we conclude that Jones committed his act freely and hence we conclude that Jones is morally responsible for killing Smith. But now, focus our attention on the fact that causal determinism might be true. If it is true, then past events together with the laws of nature are together sufficient for Jones's making the particular decision he makes. A perfect predictor a being with knowledge of all of the relevant facts about the past and of the laws of nature could tell us with certainty what Jones will decide, based on her knowledge of the past and the laws. So Jones's subjective perception of available options is irrelevant; in fact, the past pushes him into one particular decision state, the only state physically possible at the time, given the past and the laws of nature. Thus the incompatibilist argues that, if determinism is true, then Jones was, in fact, pushed into killing Smith: he was pushed by the past and the laws of nature to kill Smith, since the past and the laws being what they were causally necessitated Jones's action of killing Smith. Focusing on the fact that Jones was pushed by the past and the laws into making precisely the decision he made, makes clear that his responsibility is undermined, the incompatibilist argues. In the actual circumstances, given the truth of determinism, Jones could do no other than kill Smith. Hence, to hold that Jones killed Smith freely and so is morally 8

responsible for killing him in the Frankfurt-type case begs the question against the incompatibilist. In fact, according to the incompatibilist, if determinism is true, Jones should not be judged as morally responsible for his decision and his act, given the pushing feature of determinism. Hence Jones does not have available alternatives for action in the Frankfurt case, if determinism is assumed to hold, yet Jones is not morally responsible, so P.A.P. is not defeated. Reply: The compatibilist will quickly point out that this is unfair. The push of determinism is importantly different from the push of Black, the neurosurgeon. If determinism is true, then the push is merely our own beliefs, desires, values and so on. But, don t we WANT these things to be the things that push us to action? On compatibilism + determinism, we simply act for reasons that we find compelling. This is not at all like being shoved by a stranger. Rebuttal: But, Ekstrom points out, whether the pusher is inside or outside of one s head, it is pushing nonetheless. For, if determinism is true, then my very beliefs, desires, reasons, values THEMSELVES have been determined since before my birth. Sure, Jones wants to vote for Trump (and he identifies with/approves of this desire), but all of that is just a product of the laws of nature! He could not have wanted anything else. So, what does it matter to freedom that I act according to my desires IF THOSE DESIRES THEMSELVES ARE DETERMINED? Pereboom s Four Case Argument: Derk Pereboom puts this last thought nicely (well, not really. His article is super complicated and boring, which is why I assigned Beebee s summary of it instead). Pereboom considers four cases, where in each of them, Professor Plum kills Ms. White: Plum1: Neuroscientists have controlled every aspect of Professor Plum s brain since birth, and they manipulate him with remote control to kill Ms. White. Clearly, Plum1 is not morally responsible for his action. How could he be? Everything he does is merely a product of the scientist s complete and utter control. Plum2: Neuroscientists do not control Professor Plum s brain moment to moment, but programmed his brain at birth to generate throughout his life the sorts of desires (first and second order) that result in him killing Ms. White. Plum2 doesn t seem to be responsible for his action either. For, his action is still the result of the scientist s mind control. The only difference is that, in Plum2, they input ALL of the orders at birth rather than inputting them moment to moment (as in Plum1). 9

Plum3: Rather than neuroscientists programming Professor Plum from birth, instead he is rigorously trained and conditioned by others from birth to behave and react to situations in very specific ways. These shape his character so thoroughly, and from such an early age, that he is unable to form the intention to question or go against his conditioning. One of the ways that he is conditioned to behave results in him killing Ms. White. The only difference between Plum2 and Plum3 is that, rather than neuroscientists programming his brain directly at birth, instead he is programmed by his rigorous training and conditioning at birth (and through childhood). Pereboom thinks this is irrelevant to moral responsibility, and so it is clear that Plum3 is not responsible for his action. Plum4: Determinism is true. Professor Plum is just a normal human being who, because of the initial conditions of his birth and genetics which shaped how he would behave and react to various situations, plus the circumstances that he found himself in (all of which were determined by the laws of nature long before his birth), he kills Ms. White. The only difference between Plum3 and Plum4 is that his behavioral conditioning was the result of the laws of the universe, rather than people. His programming was simply the laws of nature (such that his act was determined since the beginning of the universe), rather than the programming of other agents. But, Pereboom thinks this is irrelevant to moral responsibility. So, Plum4 is not morally responsible for his action. Conclusion: Pereboom s conclusion is that, contrary to what compatibilists say, we can NOT be free or morally responsible for our actions if determinism is true. In effect, he is saying that Jones manipulated into voting by the neurosurgeon is in the same situation as Jones living in a deterministic universe manipulated by no one. Neither are morally responsible for their actions. Pereboom is in agreement here that, when we assign moral responsibility to Jones, we are not imagining the fact of determinism vividly enough. Plum1 - Plum4 are designed to take us there in baby steps. 10