Simplicity, personhood, and divinity

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Simplicity, personhood, and divinity"

Transcription

1 International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 41: , Kluwer Academic Publishers. Printed in the Netherlands. Simplicity, personhood, and divinity MARKWYNN Australian Catholic University, Brisbane, Australia 1. Introduction In contemporary philosophy of religion, it is customary to think of God as an individual person, who exists in time, and is related to things in the world not only as their cause but also in various respects as their effect.1 On the whole, this model has displaced the so-called 'classical' account, according to which God is pure being and therefore 'simple'. Two kinds of consideration lie behind this development. First of all, there is a philosophical concern regarding the internal consistency of the classical view. For instance, some commentators have urged that it makes no sense to suppose both that the world makes no difference to God and that God has knowledge of the world.2 A second kind of concern is more religious than philosophical in flavour. Here it is said that the classical view fails to provide for the inter-personal dimension of the believer's relation to God. Above all, this is because inter-personal relations, so it is said, require reciprocity: they demand that each party should be able to affect the other.3 In this paper, I shall consider the possibility of charting a sort of middle ground between these two approaches. I shall argue that certain features of the individualistic approach point us in the direction of the classical view, though they may not require the recapitulation of that view in full. More exactly, I shall argue that establishing the religious relevance of a God conceived individualistically will require some use of notions which are more commonly associated with the rival view. 2. The religious adequacy of the individualistic model I shall take Richard Swinburne's works The coherence of theism and The existence of God as a benchmark for my discussion of 'the' individualistic approach, although of course a great diversity of views may be brought under this general heading.4 The God depicted in these works endures through time, and changes over time, as he learns of new developments in the world. This reflects the fact that, in some cases, creaturely choices logi-

2 92 MARKWYNN cally precede God's knowledge of those choices.5 Moreover, this God acts in the world for reasons which are broadly (though not in all their detail) intelligible to human beings.6 Lastly, the God Swinburne portrays does not contain the reason for his own existence. In so far as his powers and knowledge are unbounded, such a God is more likely to exist than relatively complex things like you and me.7 In this sense, there is a connection between the divine nature and the divine existence. But this connection is probabilistic: while God's existence is more likely than that of other things, considered abstractly there is no necessity that God should exist.8 Writers in the classical tradition are likely to take exception to this picture on metaphysical grounds, arguing that an agent of this kind must be causally dependent. But I wish to examine the idea from another point of view, by considering its religious adequacy. The question I shall consider is this: why suppose that the God Swinburne describes is a fitting object of religious concern? I shall begin by offering, very briefly, a thought experiment which may appear to call into question the entitlement of a Swinburnean God to such regard. On Swinburne's account, God's existence is improbable.9 Granted this fact, we ought to attribute to such a God some of the following attitudes. First of all, such a God will surely feel gratitude for his existence, recognising the improbability of his existing, and that he has done nothing to earn it. In turn, if God views his own existence in these terms, then he will surely understand his creative activity as a matter of sharing with others the 'gift' of life which he has himself received. Such a God, we may think, will create in a spirit of wonder before the fact that anything at all exists, and in a spirit of gratitude for his own existence. Of course, this way of talking about God is strikingly anthropomorphic. However, the picture Swinburne presents seems to invite this sort of extrapolation. And in other contexts, Swinburne himself is willing to attribute to God forms of understanding which offer a close parallel with the mental lives of human beings.10 For some, the possibility of this sort of imaginative reconstruction of the mental life of a Swinburnean kind of God will constitute a reductio ad absurdum of his approach. In what follows I wish to consider how far this response is justified. Should anthropomorphism of this kind call into question the entitlement of Swinburne's God to be called divine? In particular, we might ask: if some such self-understanding can intelligibly and plausibly be attributed to the God Swinburne describes, does that in any way detract from his entitlement to receive worship? Our first recourse in addressing this question must be Swinburne's own account of the rationale for worship. He writes that to worship is:

3 SIMPLICITY, PERSONHOOD, AND DIVINITY 93 to show respect towards a person acknowledged as de facto and de jure lord of all. Such a person deserves a peculiar kind of respect for two reasons. Firstly, whatever our dependence on other beings, they depend on him. He is our ultimate benefactor, and has the right to be such. Secondly, he has incomparable greatness; if greatness deserves respect, he deserves a peculiar respect.11 Here the entitlement of God to receive worship is grounded in a similarity between human beings and God. More exactly, worship is said to be a limiting case of the sort of respect that we owe to other human beings, in so far as we depend upon them, and in so far as they have achieved greatness. This may suggest that the 'discovery' that Swinburne's God will view his existence in rather the way that we view ours need not after all undermine his entitlement to worship, since that entitlement rests from the start on the thought that there are certain similarities between human beings and God. However, some emphases in this passage do seem rather strained if we start from the thought that Swinburne's God will feel wonder before his own existence, and consider his activity as an expression of gratitude. In particular, we might suppose, such a God would not conceive his own relationship to other beings primarily, if at all, in terms of lordship, where lordship implies that others are beholden to you, on account of their dependence upon you. I shall try to substantiate this claim by exploring first of all the way in which a human being's gratitude before their own existence should condition their attitudes towards other people. Suppose we draw a distinction between basic and derived abilities. My ability to ride a bike is, clearly, a derivative ability: it is one I have acquired by the exercise of various other abilities, such as the ability to move various parts of my body. But, evidently, not all of my abilities can be of this derivative kind. In particular, since I am not self-caused, the most fundamental of my abilities, those which are bound up with my very existence, cannot derive from my own activity. Even if we suppose that all the abilities I possess at present are derivative, my existence in the first place as an agent with the capacity to generate derivative abilities will need to be presupposed. This capacity must be basic. Granted that some of our abilities are basic, our capacity for activity is ultimately a 'given'. This suggests that whatever benefits we may have conferred upon others, our relation to them is never properly one of 'lordship'. While others may depend upon us, in engendering that dependence, we are ourselves dependent upon our initial endowment of basic abilities. In such a case, we may say, we are merely sharing with others the possibilities which

4 94 MARKWYNN were inherent in our initial endowment. And since this endowment was not of our own making, it seems inappropriate to make this sharing the basis of a relationship of subservience. This suggests that there is indeed a connection between recognising one's own dependence in gratitude and adopting a certain attitude towards other people. Of course, not all human beings have acknowledged the force of considerations of this kind. But the validity of such an association of ideas seems to recognised in, for instance, the traditional Christian teaching that human beings should relate to one another in humility. At least in part, this teaching seems to rest on the idea that since we are indebted ourselves, to a beneficent God, it would be a mark of ingratitude to consider our relations to people who in turn depend upon us in terms of power and domination.12 This teaching retains its relevance, I suggest, even if a person does not believe in God. For whether or not there is a God, it is clear that I cannot be the ground of my own existence. And so long as I am not the ground of my own existence, then I will have reason to consider my existence as a 'gift', to be received in gratitude and humility. Now by parity of argument, it is clear that Swinburne's God must also have certain powers which are basic. But if his existence, like ours, is ultimately a 'given', then surely his existence, like ours, is to be received in humility and gratitude. In turn, this suggests, to revert to the issue with which we began, that just as power and subordination are inappropriate ways of understanding inter-personal relations in the human case, so 'lordship' is not the most helpful category for understanding the relationship of Swinburne's God to other things. A further distinction is useful here. Clearly, the most basic powers of Swinburne's God are indeed a part of him. But he is not merely to be identified with these powers. For instance, on Swinburne's account, God's decision to create is free in the libertarian sense.13 It follows that God's knowledge of the world does not follow directly from his initial stock of basic powers. Hence we must distinguish between the basic reality which is ultimately presupposed in the activities of such a God and the particular pattern of world-dependent thoughts and world-sustaining activities which make up his reality more 'concretely'.14 So we might express the point that Swinburne's God will not conceive of his relation to other beings in terms of 'lordship' more precisely by saying that qua a mind with world-dependent thoughts, this God has reason not to understand his relationship to others in terms of subordination, in so far as his relation to his basic abilities is one of dependence. Granted all of this, is Swinburne's God properly considered as divine, or as worthy of worship? I shall suggest a fuller answer to this question shortly, but on the basis of this discussion, we might at least offer this

5 SIMPLICITY, PERSONHOOD, AND DIVINITY 95 response: not perhaps for the reasons that Swinburne gives. In particular, the relationship of lordship, in the sense we have considered, seems problematic, given the related facts that Swinburne's God should feel gratitude for his existence, that certain of his powers are basic, and that qua a mind who has knowledge of the world he is a dependent being. Significantly, these considerations do not seem to apply to the God of 'classical' theism. For instance, on the classical view, there is no question of God feeling wonder and gratitude before his own existence. For his essence and his existence will be conjoined necessarily (and not merely probabilistically).15 Moreover, on this account, the world makes no difference to God, and there is therefore no possibility of drawing a distinction between a core reality of basic powers and the actualisation of that reality in particular choices and activities. So there is no question on this approach of God qua individual mind with knowledge of the world exhibiting dependence upon God qua core reality. It is true that such a God will have certain powers which are basic. But given that the existence of these powers is guaranteed in the same way as the divine nature, and that they are indeed identical with that nature, then, again, the notions of gratitude and dependence will not have the same application here. So an attempt to spell out the sense in which the God of classical theism is entitled to respect and even to worship seems not to be vulnerable to the issues we have been considering. If these issues do indeed cast doubt on Swinburne's account of the rationale for worship, and if no persuasive account can be provided in its place, then the discussion so far could be taken as an argument, from the nature of worship, for something like the classical view. But before drawing such a conclusion, we need to think further about whether we can supply some other rationale for the worthiness of worship of Swinburne's God. 3. Developing the individualistic model We might begin by returning to the basic power which is presupposed in the activities of Swinburne's God. The question I want to consider is this: is this basic power a proper focus of worship? One reason for thinking it might be is that the basic power shares certain properties with the God of classical theism. Thus it is immaterial, and contains within itself all other possibilities, in so far as all other facts concerning reality ultimately depend upon it. Moreover, the power can be termed necessary in so far as Swinburne's God cannot lose his most fundamental powers (those which belong to him essentially).16 And by extension, if these fundamental powers are unchanging, and if they cannot be altered by other things, then the basic power may be considered immutable and impassible.

6 96 MARKWYNN In all of these respects, the character of the basic power clearly recalls the God of classical theism - immutability, impassibility and necessary existence are all, of course, characteristics of the 'simple' God of classical theism. By contrast, Swinburne's God qua individual mind thinking worlddependent thoughts is changing, passible, and contingent. This suggests that the God of classical theism and Swinburne's kind of God could in principle co-exist, assuming that the basic power which is presupposed in the activities of Swinburne's God can be given the further properties of the classical God (such as knowledge of the world). However, this possibility is unlikely to represent a happy compromise. Swinburne could hardly accept that the activities of his God depend upon the will of another, more fundamental reality. And proponents of the classical view will hardly agree that their God acts through a time-bound intermediary such as Swinburne's God. So despite the theoretical possibility that both kinds of agent might exist, we seem in practice to be driven to a choice between them. For the purposes of this paper, I shall simply assume that the classical account is not available at this point. Of course, on the classical view, the perfectly simple source of all other realities has knowledge of the world and will. Moreover, as the source of all other existents, this reality possesses the fullness of existence within itself - it is subsistent existence.17 By contrast, contemporary philosophers of religion tend to suppose that simplicity is not compatible with divine knowledge of the world. Such knowledge, they will say, implies that the world makes a difference to God, and that some distinction must therefore be drawn between God qua a mind with knowledge of a contingent world and God qua basic power (to put the point in my terms).18 They are likely moreover to suppose that the notion of subsistent existence, far from suggesting a rich concentration of possibilities for existence, is merely vacuous.19 If we may suppose that this critique is well-founded, then the basic power which is presupposed in the activities of Swinburne's God is unlikely to commend itself as a fitting object of religious reverence. For instance, on this supposition, the power will lack any knowledge of the world, even if knowledge of other kinds can be attributed to it. Understood in these terms, the power is more reminiscent of Aristotle's God than of the God specified in Christian theology, and seems no more likely to elicit a response of worship. So despite certain similarities between the basic power of Swinburne's God and the God of classical theism, it seems unlikely that this power can provide a satisfactory object of religious regard when deprived of the further assumptions which are characteristic of the classical scheme. So our question remains: if we adopt a basically Swinburnean ontology, is there any way of finding a proper focus for religious attitudes?

7 SIMPLICITY, PERSONHOOD, AND DIVINITY 97 Swinburne's God qua an individual with world-dependent knowledge is to be distinguished, I have suggested, from the basic power which is presupposed in his activities. Having considered the possible religious significance of Swinburne's God qua basic power, we might consider next whether any religious significance attaches to this God considered as an individual mind with knowledge of the world. I suggest that we can make some progress with this question by returning to the understanding of divinity which is evident in the writings of Aquinas. In the Summa Theologiae, Aquinas remarks that God created a great diversity of creatures so that the deficiencies of one kind of thing would be remedied by the characteristics of another. In this way, the divine nature could be bodied forth, in a fragmentary way, by the created order as a whole: God planned to create many distinct things, in order to share with them and reproduce in them his goodness. Because no one creature could do this, he produced many diverse creatures, so that what was lacking in one expression of his goodness could be made up by another; for the goodness which God has whole and together, creatures share in many different ways. And the whole universe shares and expresses that goodness better than any individual creature.20 This remark might suggest that if Thomas had been convinced that his doctrine of subsistent being was untenable, then he would have chosen the cosmos as a whole as the proper object of religious devotion, in preference to a Swinburnean kind of God. For the thought expressed here is that no individual thing (not even an individual of the kind described by Swinburne, we might suppose) can capture the nature of 'being' as fully as the totality of individuals. However, rather than pursuing this thought, I propose to keep to the main theme of our discussion by examining a further approach, one which will find a securer place for Swinburne's God. The passage from Thomas I have quoted implies that anything which is divine should body forth, in a unitary way, the nature of beings in general. (Of course, more generally, this is the implication of Thomas's teaching that God is pure being.) By this criterion, there is, it seems, some reason to consider Swinburne's God qua individual mind a proper recipient of religious regard. For if you want to know what 'being' is like in general, it is not enough to direct your attention to the basic power. More precisely, you need to look to the individual mind whose contingent intentions have fixed the general character and purpose of the world. Thus Swinburne's God contains the nature of being within himself in so far as his intentions and activities provide the primary 'channel' for the basic power, and thereby determine the fundamental tendencies of things in the world in general.21

8 98 MARKWYNN So there is a sense in which in relating ourselves to Swinburne's God, considered as an individual mind, we relate ourselves to being in general and, we might say, to the basic drive towards goodness and community which is evident in things in general. On this basis, we may say that to be related to the personal God Swinburne describes is indeed to be related to what is divine. But again this God is not so much the 'lord' of all; his role is rather one of 'focussing' or 'channelling' the basic power, the core reality which is presupposed in his own activity and thereby in the activity of all other things. And in turn, his goodness is not simply intrinsic (by contrast with Thomas's God, who is subsistent existence), but is determined by reference to the quality of his effects - for it is these effects which fix the character of 'being' in general. In so far as the tendencies of things are indeed value-promoting, to that degree we have good reason to think of the channel of the basic power as divine. This understanding of the basis for ascriptions of divinity lends itself easily to the thought that individual things within the world may also have a claim to divinity, not by virtue of focussing the basic tendencies of existence, but by providing in themselves a paradigmatic expression of those basic tendencies.22 More exactly, if we suppose, following the Christian tradition, that the basic purpose and tendency of the world has to do with the creation of community or love, then we might infer that only a consciously relational being could play such a role in full. If such a being were to express unreservedly (and proleptically) the communitarian character of the world, then we would have reason to consider it divine. Notice that this reason would be of the same general character as our reason for thinking Swinburne's God divine, for it would have to do with the capacity of an individual thing to represent the nature and goodness of being in general. But in this case, the individual's significance would relate to its role as an expression of this goodness, rather than as a channel for it.23 Clearly, these thoughts could be developed in an incarnational direction. But this would take us away from the basic issue before us - whether a Swinburnean kind of ontology is rich enough to sustain religious attitudes. In brief, the answer which is beginning to emerge is 'yes', but not perhaps for the reason which Swinburne gives. Swinburne's God has reason to be considered divine not as lord of the world, but rather as the channel which establishes the basic patterns of the world's development, and in this sense discloses the nature of being. In concluding this section, it may be helpful to note how the proposal I have developed is affected if we abandon Swinburne's libertarianism, while keeping the remainder of his system. If we forgo the idea that God and creatures have libertarian freedom, and suppose that the divine activity follows directly from the divine essence, and that the activity of creatures follows

9 SIMPLICITY, PERSONHOOD, AND DIVINITY 99 directly from the divine activity, then on the account I have given, there is no obstacle to the thought that the basic power is divine without qualification. For in such a case, the basic power will fix the nature of being in all its detail. Notice also that in such a case we can consistently attribute to the basic power a knowledge of the world, since there will be a precise correspondence between the world and the power from which it deterministically derives. This position is, clearly, closer to the classical ideal than the one I have described above, though it still makes no reference to the idea of subsistent being. However, once we re-introduce divine (or creaturely) libertarian freedom, then the distinction between God qua core reality and God qua mind with knowledge of the world will re-emerge. In this case, the nature of being in general will not be fully expressed by the core reality. So in such a case, on the view I have expounded, the core reality will not have a claim to divinity considered simply in itself. 4. The proposal in context In concluding, I would like to clarify the approach I have outlined by comparing it with three others - firstly, with Swinburne's (once more), then with the classical account, and then with Charles Hartshorne's. Turning to Swinburne first, the approach I have followed has taken for granted Swinburne's ontology, and tried to see on what basis we might commend religious attitudes towards certain of the entities picked out within that ontology. So my concern has not been with epistemological issues (why think there is a God of the kind Swinburne describes?), but rather with a conceptual issue - why think that the reality Swinburne describes is properly the focus of religious attitudes? My account, unlike Swinburne's, rests on a distinction between God qua basic power and God qua individual having knowledge of the world. In brief, I have argued that this distinction is necessary if we are to see what attitude a Swinburnean God would take towards his own existence, and if we are to see how this self-understanding would shape his way of relating to things in the world. More exactly, I have argued that qua individual mind, Swinburne's God has reason to consider himself not as 'lord of all' but rather as the channel, even the 'servant', of the basic endowment presupposed in his activities, and that Swinburne's rationale for worship therefore fails. However, such a God remains worthy of worship not so much qua basic power, but rather as the channel of that power, for in this role he sums up the basic tendencies of existence. There may appear to be a tension here in the thought that Swinburne's God should consider himself a servant, in the sense indicated, while still being a proper object of worship. But this suggestion presents a paradox

10 100 MARKWYNN only while we persist in connecting the ideas of worship and of power or dominion. On the account I have given, it is the ability of Swinburne's God to represent the character of existence in general which establishes his divinity, and therefore his worthiness of worship. His refusal to consider himself as 'lord' in the sense of master in no way compromises a claim to divinity which rests on these grounds. Of course, we are free to keep the notion of 'lordship' in relation to such a God, but in that case the notion will need to undergo a transformation of sense, and will need to be purged of any association with domination.24 To the extent that this account succeeds in making Swinburne's ontology appear religiously relevant, it amounts to a defence of that scheme over against the classical approach. But at the same time, it brings out at various points the significance of the classical proposal. It does this in particular by suggesting that understanding the religious significance of Swinburne's God depends upon making a distinction between this God qua an individual mind and qua the indeterminate and 'simple' power which is presupposed in the existence of everything else. Granted that Swinburne's God qua individual mind will acknowledge his dependence upon this basic power, there is a clear concession here to the thought that no individual thing, considered merely as such, can provide a proper anchor for religious devotion. Instead, Swinburne's personal God provides a proper focus for religious devotion by virtue of serving the basic power which is presupposed in his own existence, and thereby in the existence of all other things. At the same time, it is this personal God, and not the basic power, which is divine in the fullest sense, in so far as he sums up the nature of being in general. This understanding of the basis for ascriptions of divinity represents, of course, a further acknowledgment of the value of the classical tradition. The question which remains, one I have skirted around for present purposes, is whether the classical account of the status of the basic power carries conviction. In turn, that will depend on what we make of the classical approach to a variety of topics, including divine knowledge, the nature of personhood, and the relation between a cause and its effects. For instance, if we adopt the classical understanding of divine knowledge, then we should be able to dispense with the distinction between core reality and actualisation of that reality. If moreover we adopt the classical view of personhood, then the proper focus of religious devotion will be a reality which is at once simple and personal. Lastly, the account I have offered may suggest certain parallels with Hartshorne's well-known distinction between the abstract and concrete poles of the divine nature.25 In particular, these notions recall respectively the idea of God as basic power and as individual mind with knowledge of the world. However, Hartshorne treats the abstract pole of the divine nature

11 SIMPLICITY, PERSONHOOD, AND DIVINITY 101 as merely a simplification of the fullness of the divine reality. On his view, this simplification may have a certain point philosophically, but is devoid of any religious significance.26 By contrast, on the account I have given, reference to the basic power is required for an appreciation of the self-understanding of a Swinburnean (or Hartshornean) God, and is therefore essential for understanding the basis of any religious response to this reality. The account I have given is consistent with various Hartshornean moves concerning the superiority of change over changelessness, and so on, but does not require them. It identifies divinity in the first instance not by reference to some such theory of the nature of perfection, but by reference to the idea that a thing is divine in so far as it discloses the nature of being. Such an approach is, clearly, closer in spirit to the Thomistic account in its understanding of the rationale for ascriptions of divinity. 5. Conclusions In this discussion, I have tried to identify some of the ways in which God conceived individualistically, in the way Swinburne indicates, may prove to be a proper focus of religious attitudes. The discussion suggests that Swinburne's own way of justifying the idea that such an agent is worthy of worship may not carry conviction. In place of this account, I have suggested that a personal God of the kind he describes is worthy of worship as the summation of the basic tendencies of existence, and not as the world's master. The idea of simplicity retains a place here in so far as this view rests upon the thought that a personal God should consider himself as the humble servant of the basic, 'simple' reality presupposed in his own activities. It has a place moreover in so far as the divinity of Swinburne's God rests on his ability to represent in a unitary way the nature of being in general. It would be possible, I think, to argue for an approach of this general kind on rather different grounds. For instance, there seem to be christological as well as broadly pastoral reasons for favouring such an account over the view that it is God's dominion over the world which establishes the appropriateness of religious attitudes. However, I hope the case I have made can stand independently of such supporting considerations. Notes 1. Of course, it will also be said that there is a distinction between creaturely and divine passibility in so far as God's being affected always depends upon the divine consent. See for instance Marcel Sarot, God, passibility and corporeality (Kampen: Kok Pharos, 1992), pp

12 102 MARKWYNN 2. See, for instance, William Alston, 'Hartshorne and Aquinas: A via media' in Divine nature and human language: Essays in philosophical theology (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1989), pp Contrast Summa Theologiae 1 13, art See, for instance, Grace Jantzen's God's world's, God's body (Philadelphia: Westminster Press, 1984), pp Oxford: Clarendon Press, revised edition, 1993, and Oxford: Clarendon Press, revised edition, 1991, respectively. 5. These choices are free in the libertarian sense. Of course, some commentators have sought to break the link between libertarian freedom and divine passibility, for instance by reference to the idea of middle knowledge, but this is not Swinburne's approach. See The coherence of theism, pp For a summary of Swinburne's approach here, see The existence of God (1991),. p Swinburne talks of God's * simplicity' in this connection, but clearly the term is not intended to carry all of the associations which it bears for writers in the classical tradition. 8. However, granted God's existence at one time, t\, his existence at later times is logically necessary. See The coherence of theism (1993), p For the relative probability of God and other things, see The existence of God (1991), p A discussion of certain tensions in Swinburne's association of 'simplicity' and probability can be found in my paper 'Some reflections on Richard Swinburne's argument from design', Religious Studies 29 (1993): Indeed, it is improbable that anything at all should exist. See The existence of God (1991), p. 106, and pp See again Note 6 above. 11. The coherence of theism (1993), p See, for instance, the Gospel of Matthew, 18: Swinburne thinks that God will do anything which he has overriding reason to do, since he is 'perfectly free': The coherence of theism (1993), pp But on his account, God does not have overriding reason to create: The existence of God (1991), pp 'Concretely' here is used in Hartshorne's sense, to which I shall return in Section This is to say that the Ontological Argument works in principle, even if we cannot grasp its soundness in practice. This seems to be Aquinas 's view: Summa Theologiae, 12, art See again The coherence of theism (1993), p See Aquinas, Summa Theologiae, 14, art Even commentators sympathetic to Thomas have granted this sort or point. See, tor instance, Gerard Hughes, The nature of God (London: Routledge, 1995), pp See, for instance, Anthony Kenny's remark that 'the notion of pure being is as empty as the notion of pure life or pure history': Aquinas (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1980), p I 47, art. 1, in T. McDermott (ed.), Summa Theologiae: A concise translation (Westminster: Christian Classics), p We might add: such a God provides a more obvious focus of religious respect than the cosmos in general, in so far as it is not a conglomeration of individuals, but a genuine unity, and the source of whatever unity can be ascribed to the cosmos. For this sort of reason, I doubt whether Aquinas would in fact have followed a pantheistic approach in the circumstances I have just described. 22. This thought could be elaborated in the way William Alston indicates when he treats goodness as a particularistic rather than a platonic predicate. See 'Some suggestions for divine command theorists', in Op. cit. (1989), pp

13 SIMPLICITY, PERSONHOOD, AND DIVINITY Of course, the act of focussing the basic tendencies of existence could itself provide a paradigmatic expression of those tendencies. 24. Of course, this is what Christians have done in speaking of Jesus as servant and as lord. Perhaps Swinburne was thinking of lordship in this sense in the passage I cited earlier. If so, his reference to the connection between lordship and dependence obscured his meaning, at least for this reader. It is true that on the view I have expounded, it is the dependence of things upon Swinburne's God which allows him to represent the nature of being in general; but on Swinburne's account, the significance of dependence relates rather to the idea that creatures owe respect to God as their benefactor. Compare Aquinas on the nature of God's lordship, Summa Theologiae, 113, art See, for instance, Creative synthesis and philosophic method (London: SCM, 1970), p See 'The God of religion and the God of philosophy', in Talk of God (London: Royal Institute of Philosophy, 1969), pp Address for correspondence: Professor Mark Wynn, Network of Philosophy, Australian Catholic University, McAuley Campus, 53 Prospect Road, Brisbane, Qld 4053, Australia Phone: ; Fax: ; m.wynn@mcauley.acu.edu.au

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism? Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism? Author: Terence Rajivan Edward, University of Manchester. Abstract. In the sixth chapter of The View from Nowhere, Thomas Nagel attempts to identify a form of idealism.

More information

THE MORAL ARGUMENT. Peter van Inwagen. Introduction, James Petrik

THE MORAL ARGUMENT. Peter van Inwagen. Introduction, James Petrik THE MORAL ARGUMENT Peter van Inwagen Introduction, James Petrik THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHICAL DISCUSSIONS of human freedom is closely intertwined with the history of philosophical discussions of moral responsibility.

More information

Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Introduction

Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Introduction 24 Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Abstract: In this paper, I address Linda Zagzebski s analysis of the relation between moral testimony and understanding arguing that Aquinas

More information

1/12. The A Paralogisms

1/12. The A Paralogisms 1/12 The A Paralogisms The character of the Paralogisms is described early in the chapter. Kant describes them as being syllogisms which contain no empirical premises and states that in them we conclude

More information

What We Are: Our Metaphysical Nature & Moral Implications

What We Are: Our Metaphysical Nature & Moral Implications What We Are: Our Metaphysical Nature & Moral Implications Julia Lei Western University ABSTRACT An account of our metaphysical nature provides an answer to the question of what are we? One such account

More information

5 A Modal Version of the

5 A Modal Version of the 5 A Modal Version of the Ontological Argument E. J. L O W E Moreland, J. P.; Sweis, Khaldoun A.; Meister, Chad V., Jul 01, 2013, Debating Christian Theism The original version of the ontological argument

More information

Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible?

Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible? Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible? Anders Kraal ABSTRACT: Since the 1960s an increasing number of philosophers have endorsed the thesis that there can be no such thing as

More information

The Quality of Mercy is Not Strained: Justice and Mercy in Proslogion 9-11

The Quality of Mercy is Not Strained: Justice and Mercy in Proslogion 9-11 The Quality of Mercy is Not Strained: Justice and Mercy in Proslogion 9-11 Michael Vendsel Tarrant County College Abstract: In Proslogion 9-11 Anselm discusses the relationship between mercy and justice.

More information

Summary of Kant s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals

Summary of Kant s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals Summary of Kant s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals Version 1.1 Richard Baron 2 October 2016 1 Contents 1 Introduction 3 1.1 Availability and licence............ 3 2 Definitions of key terms 4 3

More information

The Christian God Part I: Metaphysics

The Christian God Part I: Metaphysics The Christian God In The Christian God, Richard Swinburne examines basic metaphysical categories[1]. Only when that task is done does he turn to an analysis of divine properties, the divine nature, and

More information

Deontological Perspectivism: A Reply to Lockie Hamid Vahid, Institute for Research in Fundamental Sciences, Tehran

Deontological Perspectivism: A Reply to Lockie Hamid Vahid, Institute for Research in Fundamental Sciences, Tehran Deontological Perspectivism: A Reply to Lockie Hamid Vahid, Institute for Research in Fundamental Sciences, Tehran Abstract In his (2015) paper, Robert Lockie seeks to add a contextualized, relativist

More information

THE POSSIBILITY OF AN ALL-KNOWING GOD

THE POSSIBILITY OF AN ALL-KNOWING GOD THE POSSIBILITY OF AN ALL-KNOWING GOD The Possibility of an All-Knowing God Jonathan L. Kvanvig Assistant Professor of Philosophy Texas A & M University Palgrave Macmillan Jonathan L. Kvanvig, 1986 Softcover

More information

Man and the Presence of Evil in Christian and Platonic Doctrine by Philip Sherrard

Man and the Presence of Evil in Christian and Platonic Doctrine by Philip Sherrard Man and the Presence of Evil in Christian and Platonic Doctrine by Philip Sherrard Source: Studies in Comparative Religion, Vol. 2, No.1. World Wisdom, Inc. www.studiesincomparativereligion.com OF the

More information

Time travel and the open future

Time travel and the open future Time travel and the open future University of Queensland Abstract I argue that the thesis that time travel is logically possible, is inconsistent with the necessary truth of any of the usual open future-objective

More information

Divine Omniscience and Experience

Divine Omniscience and Experience Ars Disputandi Volume 3 (2003) ISSN: 15665399 Yujin Nagasawa AUSTRALIAN NATIONAL UNIVERSITY, AUSTRALIA Divine Omniscience and Experience A Reply to Alter Abstract According to one antitheist argument,

More information

Who or what is God?, asks John Hick (Hick 2009). A theist might answer: God is an infinite person, or at least an

Who or what is God?, asks John Hick (Hick 2009). A theist might answer: God is an infinite person, or at least an John Hick on whether God could be an infinite person Daniel Howard-Snyder Western Washington University Abstract: "Who or what is God?," asks John Hick. A theist might answer: God is an infinite person,

More information

WHAT DOES KRIPKE MEAN BY A PRIORI?

WHAT DOES KRIPKE MEAN BY A PRIORI? Diametros nr 28 (czerwiec 2011): 1-7 WHAT DOES KRIPKE MEAN BY A PRIORI? Pierre Baumann In Naming and Necessity (1980), Kripke stressed the importance of distinguishing three different pairs of notions:

More information

Rule-Following and the Ontology of the Mind Abstract The problem of rule-following

Rule-Following and the Ontology of the Mind Abstract The problem of rule-following Rule-Following and the Ontology of the Mind Michael Esfeld (published in Uwe Meixner and Peter Simons (eds.): Metaphysics in the Post-Metaphysical Age. Papers of the 22nd International Wittgenstein Symposium.

More information

Ibn Sina on Substances and Accidents

Ibn Sina on Substances and Accidents Ibn Sina on Substances and Accidents ERWIN TEGTMEIER, MANNHEIM There was a vivid and influential dialogue of Western philosophy with Ibn Sina in the Middle Ages; but there can be also a fruitful dialogue

More information

The CopernicanRevolution

The CopernicanRevolution Immanuel Kant: The Copernican Revolution The CopernicanRevolution Immanuel Kant (1724-1804) The Critique of Pure Reason (1781) is Kant s best known work. In this monumental work, he begins a Copernican-like

More information

David E. Alexander and Daniel Johnson, eds. Calvinism and the Problem of Evil.

David E. Alexander and Daniel Johnson, eds. Calvinism and the Problem of Evil. David E. Alexander and Daniel Johnson, eds. Calvinism and the Problem of Evil. Eugene, OR: Wipf and Stock Publishers, 2016. 318 pp. $62.00 (hbk); $37.00 (paper). Walters State Community College As David

More information

SIMPLICITY AND ASEITY. Jeffrey E. Brower. There is a traditional theistic doctrine, known as the doctrine of divine simplicity,

SIMPLICITY AND ASEITY. Jeffrey E. Brower. There is a traditional theistic doctrine, known as the doctrine of divine simplicity, SIMPLICITY AND ASEITY Jeffrey E. Brower There is a traditional theistic doctrine, known as the doctrine of divine simplicity, according to which God is an absolutely simple being, completely devoid of

More information

SWINBURNE ON THE EUTHYPHRO DILEMMA. CAN SUPERVENIENCE SAVE HIM?

SWINBURNE ON THE EUTHYPHRO DILEMMA. CAN SUPERVENIENCE SAVE HIM? 17 SWINBURNE ON THE EUTHYPHRO DILEMMA. CAN SUPERVENIENCE SAVE HIM? SIMINI RAHIMI Heythrop College, University of London Abstract. Modern philosophers normally either reject the divine command theory of

More information

On A New Cosmological Argument

On A New Cosmological Argument On A New Cosmological Argument Richard Gale and Alexander Pruss A New Cosmological Argument, Religious Studies 35, 1999, pp.461 76 present a cosmological argument which they claim is an improvement over

More information

The Five Ways of St. Thomas in proving the existence of

The Five Ways of St. Thomas in proving the existence of The Language of Analogy in the Five Ways of St. Thomas Aquinas Moses Aaron T. Angeles, Ph.D. San Beda College The Five Ways of St. Thomas in proving the existence of God is, needless to say, a most important

More information

Molinism and divine prophecy of free actions

Molinism and divine prophecy of free actions Molinism and divine prophecy of free actions GRAHAM OPPY School of Philosophical, Historical and International Studies, Monash University, Clayton Campus, Wellington Road, Clayton VIC 3800 AUSTRALIA Graham.Oppy@monash.edu

More information

Simplicity and Why the Universe Exists

Simplicity and Why the Universe Exists Simplicity and Why the Universe Exists QUENTIN SMITH I If big bang cosmology is true, then the universe began to exist about 15 billion years ago with a 'big bang', an explosion of matter, energy and space

More information

220 CBITICAII NOTICES:

220 CBITICAII NOTICES: 220 CBITICAII NOTICES: The Idea of Immortality. The Gifford Lectures delivered in the University of Edinburgh in the year 1922. By A. SBTH PBINGLE-PATTISON, LL.D., D.C.L., Fellow of the British Academy,

More information

HUME, CAUSATION AND TWO ARGUMENTS CONCERNING GOD

HUME, CAUSATION AND TWO ARGUMENTS CONCERNING GOD HUME, CAUSATION AND TWO ARGUMENTS CONCERNING GOD JASON MEGILL Carroll College Abstract. In Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion, Hume (1779/1993) appeals to his account of causation (among other things)

More information

the notion of modal personhood. I begin with a challenge to Kagan s assumptions about the metaphysics of identity and modality.

the notion of modal personhood. I begin with a challenge to Kagan s assumptions about the metaphysics of identity and modality. On Modal Personism Shelly Kagan s essay on speciesism has the virtues characteristic of his work in general: insight, originality, clarity, cleverness, wit, intuitive plausibility, argumentative rigor,

More information

God, Natural Evil and the Best Possible World

God, Natural Evil and the Best Possible World God, Natural Evil and the Best Possible World Peter Vardy The debate about whether or not this is the Best Possible World (BPW) is usually centred on the question of evil - in other words how can this

More information

How Do We Know Anything about Mathematics? - A Defence of Platonism

How Do We Know Anything about Mathematics? - A Defence of Platonism How Do We Know Anything about Mathematics? - A Defence of Platonism Majda Trobok University of Rijeka original scientific paper UDK: 141.131 1:51 510.21 ABSTRACT In this paper I will try to say something

More information

FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. by Immanuel Kant

FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. by Immanuel Kant FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS SECOND SECTION by Immanuel Kant TRANSITION FROM POPULAR MORAL PHILOSOPHY TO THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS... This principle, that humanity and generally every

More information

The Trinity and the Enhypostasia

The Trinity and the Enhypostasia 0 The Trinity and the Enhypostasia CYRIL C. RICHARDSON NE learns from one's critics; and I should like in this article to address myself to a fundamental point which has been raised by critics (both the

More information

Duns Scotus on Divine Illumination

Duns Scotus on Divine Illumination MP_C13.qxd 11/23/06 2:29 AM Page 110 13 Duns Scotus on Divine Illumination [Article IV. Concerning Henry s Conclusion] In the fourth article I argue against the conclusion of [Henry s] view as follows:

More information

Aquinas s Third Way Keith Burgess-Jackson 24 September 2017

Aquinas s Third Way Keith Burgess-Jackson 24 September 2017 Aquinas s Third Way Keith Burgess-Jackson 24 September 2017 Cosmology, a branch of astronomy (or astrophysics), is The study of the origin and structure of the universe. 1 Thus, a thing is cosmological

More information

Thought is Being or Thought and Being? Feuerbach and his Criticism of Hegel's Absolute Idealism by Martin Jenkins

Thought is Being or Thought and Being? Feuerbach and his Criticism of Hegel's Absolute Idealism by Martin Jenkins Thought is Being or Thought and Being? Feuerbach and his Criticism of Hegel's Absolute Idealism by Martin Jenkins Although he was once an ardent follower of the Philosophy of GWF Hegel, Ludwig Feuerbach

More information

II. In what way does the Unmoved Mover cause what it causes?

II. In what way does the Unmoved Mover cause what it causes? CAUSATION, ami the UNMOVED KAREN BELL University of Kansas MOTION MOVER I In Aristotle's Metaphysics, Book XII, Chapters 6 and 7, the Unmoved Mover is said to be an eternal, entirely actual substance which

More information

Self-Evidence in Finnis Natural Law Theory: A Reply to Sayers

Self-Evidence in Finnis Natural Law Theory: A Reply to Sayers Self-Evidence in Finnis Natural Law Theory: A Reply to Sayers IRENE O CONNELL* Introduction In Volume 23 (1998) of the Australian Journal of Legal Philosophy Mark Sayers1 sets out some objections to aspects

More information

THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE

THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE Diametros nr 29 (wrzesień 2011): 80-92 THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE Karol Polcyn 1. PRELIMINARIES Chalmers articulates his argument in terms of two-dimensional

More information

WHAT ARISTOTLE TAUGHT

WHAT ARISTOTLE TAUGHT WHAT ARISTOTLE TAUGHT Aristotle was, perhaps, the greatest original thinker who ever lived. Historian H J A Sire has put the issue well: All other thinkers have begun with a theory and sought to fit reality

More information

Bertrand Russell Proper Names, Adjectives and Verbs 1

Bertrand Russell Proper Names, Adjectives and Verbs 1 Bertrand Russell Proper Names, Adjectives and Verbs 1 Analysis 46 Philosophical grammar can shed light on philosophical questions. Grammatical differences can be used as a source of discovery and a guide

More information

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg 1 In Search of the Ontological Argument Richard Oxenberg Abstract We can attend to the logic of Anselm's ontological argument, and amuse ourselves for a few hours unraveling its convoluted word-play, or

More information

Wright on response-dependence and self-knowledge

Wright on response-dependence and self-knowledge Wright on response-dependence and self-knowledge March 23, 2004 1 Response-dependent and response-independent concepts........... 1 1.1 The intuitive distinction......................... 1 1.2 Basic equations

More information

AQUINAS S METAPHYSICS OF MODALITY: A REPLY TO LEFTOW

AQUINAS S METAPHYSICS OF MODALITY: A REPLY TO LEFTOW Jeffrey E. Brower AQUINAS S METAPHYSICS OF MODALITY: A REPLY TO LEFTOW Brian Leftow sets out to provide us with an account of Aquinas s metaphysics of modality. 1 Drawing on some important recent work,

More information

Conditions of Fundamental Metaphysics: A critique of Jorge Gracia's proposal

Conditions of Fundamental Metaphysics: A critique of Jorge Gracia's proposal University of Windsor Scholarship at UWindsor Critical Reflections Essays of Significance & Critical Reflections 2016 Mar 12th, 1:30 PM - 2:00 PM Conditions of Fundamental Metaphysics: A critique of Jorge

More information

Note: This is the penultimate draft of an article the final and definitive version of which is

Note: This is the penultimate draft of an article the final and definitive version of which is The Flicker of Freedom: A Reply to Stump Note: This is the penultimate draft of an article the final and definitive version of which is scheduled to appear in an upcoming issue The Journal of Ethics. That

More information

Can Christianity be Reduced to Morality? Ted Di Maria, Philosophy, Gonzaga University Gonzaga Socratic Club, April 18, 2008

Can Christianity be Reduced to Morality? Ted Di Maria, Philosophy, Gonzaga University Gonzaga Socratic Club, April 18, 2008 Can Christianity be Reduced to Morality? Ted Di Maria, Philosophy, Gonzaga University Gonzaga Socratic Club, April 18, 2008 As one of the world s great religions, Christianity has been one of the supreme

More information

Causing People to Exist and Saving People s Lives Jeff McMahan

Causing People to Exist and Saving People s Lives Jeff McMahan Causing People to Exist and Saving People s Lives Jeff McMahan 1 Possible People Suppose that whatever one does a new person will come into existence. But one can determine who this person will be by either

More information

William Ockham on Universals

William Ockham on Universals MP_C07.qxd 11/17/06 5:28 PM Page 71 7 William Ockham on Universals Ockham s First Theory: A Universal is a Fictum One can plausibly say that a universal is not a real thing inherent in a subject [habens

More information

From Necessary Truth to Necessary Existence

From Necessary Truth to Necessary Existence Prequel for Section 4.2 of Defending the Correspondence Theory Published by PJP VII, 1 From Necessary Truth to Necessary Existence Abstract I introduce new details in an argument for necessarily existing

More information

- 1 - Outline of NICOMACHEAN ETHICS, Book I Book I--Dialectical discussion leading to Aristotle's definition of happiness: activity in accordance

- 1 - Outline of NICOMACHEAN ETHICS, Book I Book I--Dialectical discussion leading to Aristotle's definition of happiness: activity in accordance - 1 - Outline of NICOMACHEAN ETHICS, Book I Book I--Dialectical discussion leading to Aristotle's definition of happiness: activity in accordance with virtue or excellence (arete) in a complete life Chapter

More information

1 Hans Jonas, The Imperative of Responsibility: In Search of an Ethics for the Technological Age (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984), 1-10.

1 Hans Jonas, The Imperative of Responsibility: In Search of an Ethics for the Technological Age (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984), 1-10. Introduction This book seeks to provide a metaethical analysis of the responsibility ethics of two of its prominent defenders: H. Richard Niebuhr and Emmanuel Levinas. In any ethical writings, some use

More information

SUPPORT MATERIAL FOR 'DETERMINISM AND FREE WILL ' (UNIT 2 TOPIC 5)

SUPPORT MATERIAL FOR 'DETERMINISM AND FREE WILL ' (UNIT 2 TOPIC 5) SUPPORT MATERIAL FOR 'DETERMINISM AND FREE WILL ' (UNIT 2 TOPIC 5) Introduction We often say things like 'I couldn't resist buying those trainers'. In saying this, we presumably mean that the desire to

More information

REVIEW. St. Thomas Aquinas. By RALPH MCINERNY. The University of Notre Dame Press 1982 (reprint of Twayne Publishers 1977). Pp $5.95.

REVIEW. St. Thomas Aquinas. By RALPH MCINERNY. The University of Notre Dame Press 1982 (reprint of Twayne Publishers 1977). Pp $5.95. REVIEW St. Thomas Aquinas. By RALPH MCINERNY. The University of Notre Dame Press 1982 (reprint of Twayne Publishers 1977). Pp. 172. $5.95. McInerny has succeeded at a demanding task: he has written a compact

More information

THE PROBLEM OF PERSONAL IDENTITY

THE PROBLEM OF PERSONAL IDENTITY THE PROBLEM OF PERSONAL IDENTITY There is no single problem of personal identity, but rather a wide range of loosely connected questions. Who am I? What is it to be a person? What does it take for a person

More information

What God Could Have Made

What God Could Have Made 1 What God Could Have Made By Heimir Geirsson and Michael Losonsky I. Introduction Atheists have argued that if there is a God who is omnipotent, omniscient and omnibenevolent, then God would have made

More information

Horwich and the Liar

Horwich and the Liar Horwich and the Liar Sergi Oms Sardans Logos, University of Barcelona 1 Horwich defends an epistemic account of vagueness according to which vague predicates have sharp boundaries which we are not capable

More information

UC Berkeley UC Berkeley Previously Published Works

UC Berkeley UC Berkeley Previously Published Works UC Berkeley UC Berkeley Previously Published Works Title Disaggregating Structures as an Agenda for Critical Realism: A Reply to McAnulla Permalink https://escholarship.org/uc/item/4k27s891 Journal British

More information

12. A Theistic Argument against Platonism (and in Support of Truthmakers and Divine Simplicity)

12. A Theistic Argument against Platonism (and in Support of Truthmakers and Divine Simplicity) Dean W. Zimmerman / Oxford Studies in Metaphysics - Volume 2 12-Zimmerman-chap12 Page Proof page 357 19.10.2005 2:50pm 12. A Theistic Argument against Platonism (and in Support of Truthmakers and Divine

More information

Are There Reasons to Be Rational?

Are There Reasons to Be Rational? Are There Reasons to Be Rational? Olav Gjelsvik, University of Oslo The thesis. Among people writing about rationality, few people are more rational than Wlodek Rabinowicz. But are there reasons for being

More information

CONVENTIONALISM AND NORMATIVITY

CONVENTIONALISM AND NORMATIVITY 1 CONVENTIONALISM AND NORMATIVITY TORBEN SPAAK We have seen (in Section 3) that Hart objects to Austin s command theory of law, that it cannot account for the normativity of law, and that what is missing

More information

There might be nothing: the subtraction argument improved

There might be nothing: the subtraction argument improved ANALYSIS 57.3 JULY 1997 There might be nothing: the subtraction argument improved Gonzalo Rodriguez-Pereyra 1. The nihilist thesis that it is metaphysically possible that there is nothing, in the sense

More information

Wisdom in Aristotle and Aquinas From Metaphysics to Mysticism Edmond Eh University of Saint Joseph, Macau

Wisdom in Aristotle and Aquinas From Metaphysics to Mysticism Edmond Eh University of Saint Joseph, Macau Volume 12, No 2, Fall 2017 ISSN 1932-1066 Wisdom in Aristotle and Aquinas From Metaphysics to Mysticism Edmond Eh University of Saint Joseph, Macau edmond_eh@usj.edu.mo Abstract: This essay contains an

More information

Positivism A Model Of For System Of Rules

Positivism A Model Of For System Of Rules Positivism A Model Of For System Of Rules Positivism is a model of and for a system of rules, and its central notion of a single fundamental test for law forces us to miss the important standards that

More information

DIVINE FREEDOM AND FREE WILL DEFENSES

DIVINE FREEDOM AND FREE WILL DEFENSES This is a pre-publication copy, please do not cite. The final paper is forthcoming in The Heythrop Journal (DOI: 10.1111/heyj.12075), but the Early View version is available now. DIVINE FREEDOM AND FREE

More information

From Transcendental Logic to Transcendental Deduction

From Transcendental Logic to Transcendental Deduction From Transcendental Logic to Transcendental Deduction Let me see if I can say a few things to re-cap our first discussion of the Transcendental Logic, and help you get a foothold for what follows. Kant

More information

Review of Aristotle on Knowledge and Learning: The Posterior Analytics by David Bronstein

Review of Aristotle on Knowledge and Learning: The Posterior Analytics by David Bronstein Marquette University e-publications@marquette Philosophy Faculty Research and Publications Philosophy, Department of 4-1-2017 Review of Aristotle on Knowledge and Learning: The Posterior Analytics by David

More information

The Sea-Fight Tomorrow by Aristotle

The Sea-Fight Tomorrow by Aristotle The Sea-Fight Tomorrow by Aristotle Aristotle, Antiquities Project About the author.... Aristotle (384-322) studied for twenty years at Plato s Academy in Athens. Following Plato s death, Aristotle left

More information

Externalism and a priori knowledge of the world: Why privileged access is not the issue Maria Lasonen-Aarnio

Externalism and a priori knowledge of the world: Why privileged access is not the issue Maria Lasonen-Aarnio Externalism and a priori knowledge of the world: Why privileged access is not the issue Maria Lasonen-Aarnio This is the pre-peer reviewed version of the following article: Lasonen-Aarnio, M. (2006), Externalism

More information

UNIVERSITY OF MALTA THE MATRICULATION EXAMINATION ADVANCED LEVEL

UNIVERSITY OF MALTA THE MATRICULATION EXAMINATION ADVANCED LEVEL UNIVERSITY OF MALTA THE MATRICULATION EXAMINATION ADVANCED LEVEL PHILOSOPHY MAY 2017 EXAMINERS REPORT ADVANCED PHILOSOPHY MAY 2017 SESSION EXAMINERS REPORT Part 1: Statistical Information Table 1 shows

More information

BOOK REVIEW: Gideon Yaffee, Manifest Activity: Thomas Reid s Theory of Action

BOOK REVIEW: Gideon Yaffee, Manifest Activity: Thomas Reid s Theory of Action University of Nebraska - Lincoln DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln Faculty Publications - Department of Philosophy Philosophy, Department of 2005 BOOK REVIEW: Gideon Yaffee, Manifest Activity:

More information

The Divine Nature. from Summa Theologiae (Part I, Questions 3-11) by Thomas Aquinas (~1265 AD) translated by Brian J.

The Divine Nature. from Summa Theologiae (Part I, Questions 3-11) by Thomas Aquinas (~1265 AD) translated by Brian J. The Divine Nature from Summa Theologiae (Part I, Questions 3-11) by Thomas Aquinas (~1265 AD) translated by Brian J. Shanley (2006) Question 3. Divine Simplicity Once it is grasped that something exists,

More information

The cosmological argument (continued)

The cosmological argument (continued) The cosmological argument (continued) Remember that last time we arrived at the following interpretation of Aquinas second way: Aquinas 2nd way 1. At least one thing has been caused to come into existence.

More information

Chapter Six. Aristotle s Theory of Causation and the Ideas of Potentiality and Actuality

Chapter Six. Aristotle s Theory of Causation and the Ideas of Potentiality and Actuality Chapter Six Aristotle s Theory of Causation and the Ideas of Potentiality and Actuality Key Words: Form and matter, potentiality and actuality, teleological, change, evolution. Formal cause, material cause,

More information

IS GOD "SIGNIFICANTLY FREE?''

IS GOD SIGNIFICANTLY FREE?'' IS GOD "SIGNIFICANTLY FREE?'' Wesley Morriston In an impressive series of books and articles, Alvin Plantinga has developed challenging new versions of two much discussed pieces of philosophical theology:

More information

Fr. Copleston vs. Bertrand Russell: The Famous 1948 BBC Radio Debate on the Existence of God

Fr. Copleston vs. Bertrand Russell: The Famous 1948 BBC Radio Debate on the Existence of God Fr. Copleston vs. Bertrand Russell: The Famous 1948 BBC Radio Debate on the Existence of God Father Frederick C. Copleston (Jesuit Catholic priest) versus Bertrand Russell (agnostic philosopher) Copleston:

More information

Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly *

Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly * Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly * Ralph Wedgwood 1 Two views of practical reason Suppose that you are faced with several different options (that is, several ways in which you might act in a

More information

William Hasker s discussion of the Thomistic doctrine of the soul

William Hasker s discussion of the Thomistic doctrine of the soul Response to William Hasker s The Dialectic of Soul and Body John Haldane I. William Hasker s discussion of the Thomistic doctrine of the soul does not engage directly with Aquinas s writings but draws

More information

Faith and Philosophy, April (2006), DE SE KNOWLEDGE AND THE POSSIBILITY OF AN OMNISCIENT BEING Stephan Torre

Faith and Philosophy, April (2006), DE SE KNOWLEDGE AND THE POSSIBILITY OF AN OMNISCIENT BEING Stephan Torre 1 Faith and Philosophy, April (2006), 191-200. Penultimate Draft DE SE KNOWLEDGE AND THE POSSIBILITY OF AN OMNISCIENT BEING Stephan Torre In this paper I examine an argument that has been made by Patrick

More information

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction Kent State University BIBLID [0873-626X (2014) 39; pp. 139-145] Abstract The causal theory of reference (CTR) provides a well-articulated and widely-accepted account

More information

Is God Good By Definition?

Is God Good By Definition? 1 Is God Good By Definition? by Graham Oppy As a matter of historical fact, most philosophers and theologians who have defended traditional theistic views have been moral realists. Some divine command

More information

PHILOSOPHY 4360/5360 METAPHYSICS. Methods that Metaphysicians Use

PHILOSOPHY 4360/5360 METAPHYSICS. Methods that Metaphysicians Use PHILOSOPHY 4360/5360 METAPHYSICS Methods that Metaphysicians Use Method 1: The appeal to what one can imagine where imagining some state of affairs involves forming a vivid image of that state of affairs.

More information

A New Argument Against Compatibilism

A New Argument Against Compatibilism Norwegian University of Life Sciences School of Economics and Business A New Argument Against Compatibilism Stephen Mumford and Rani Lill Anjum Working Papers No. 2/ 2014 ISSN: 2464-1561 A New Argument

More information

TEMPORAL NECESSITY AND LOGICAL FATALISM. by Joseph Diekemper

TEMPORAL NECESSITY AND LOGICAL FATALISM. by Joseph Diekemper TEMPORAL NECESSITY AND LOGICAL FATALISM by Joseph Diekemper ABSTRACT I begin by briefly mentioning two different logical fatalistic argument types: one from temporal necessity, and one from antecedent

More information

The Names of God. from Summa Theologiae (Part I, Questions 12-13) by Thomas Aquinas (~1265 AD) translated by Brian Shanley (2006)

The Names of God. from Summa Theologiae (Part I, Questions 12-13) by Thomas Aquinas (~1265 AD) translated by Brian Shanley (2006) The Names of God from Summa Theologiae (Part I, Questions 12-13) by Thomas Aquinas (~1265 AD) translated by Brian Shanley (2006) For with respect to God, it is more apparent to us what God is not, rather

More information

Aquinas, Maritain, and the Metaphysical Foundation of Practical Reason

Aquinas, Maritain, and the Metaphysical Foundation of Practical Reason Aquinas, Maritain, and the Metaphysical Foundation of Practical Reason MatthewS~ Pugh For the past thirty-five years or so, much of the debate in Thomistic ethics has concerned the following question:

More information

PHENOMENALITY AND INTENTIONALITY WHICH EXPLAINS WHICH?: REPLY TO GERTLER

PHENOMENALITY AND INTENTIONALITY WHICH EXPLAINS WHICH?: REPLY TO GERTLER PHENOMENALITY AND INTENTIONALITY WHICH EXPLAINS WHICH?: REPLY TO GERTLER Department of Philosophy University of California, Riverside Riverside, CA 92521 U.S.A. siewert@ucr.edu Copyright (c) Charles Siewert

More information

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory Western University Scholarship@Western 2015 Undergraduate Awards The Undergraduate Awards 2015 Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory David Hakim Western University, davidhakim266@gmail.com

More information

Moral Objectivism. RUSSELL CORNETT University of Calgary

Moral Objectivism. RUSSELL CORNETT University of Calgary Moral Objectivism RUSSELL CORNETT University of Calgary The possibility, let alone the actuality, of an objective morality has intrigued philosophers for well over two millennia. Though much discussed,

More information

Pentecostals and Divine Impassibility: A Response to Daniel Castelo *

Pentecostals and Divine Impassibility: A Response to Daniel Castelo * Journal of Pentecostal Theology 20 (2011) 184 190 brill.nl/pent Pentecostals and Divine Impassibility: A Response to Daniel Castelo * Andrew K. Gabriel ** Horizon College and Seminary, 1303 Jackson Ave.,

More information

Ethical Consistency and the Logic of Ought

Ethical Consistency and the Logic of Ought Ethical Consistency and the Logic of Ought Mathieu Beirlaen Ghent University In Ethical Consistency, Bernard Williams vindicated the possibility of moral conflicts; he proposed to consistently allow for

More information

Chapter 18 David Hume: Theory of Knowledge

Chapter 18 David Hume: Theory of Knowledge Key Words Chapter 18 David Hume: Theory of Knowledge Empiricism, skepticism, personal identity, necessary connection, causal connection, induction, impressions, ideas. DAVID HUME (1711-76) is one of the

More information

Kant and his Successors

Kant and his Successors Kant and his Successors G. J. Mattey Winter, 2011 / Philosophy 151 The Sorry State of Metaphysics Kant s Critique of Pure Reason (1781) was an attempt to put metaphysics on a scientific basis. Metaphysics

More information

CHRISTIAN THEOLOGIANS /PHILOSOPHERS VIEW OF OMNISCIENCE AND HUMAN FREEDOM

CHRISTIAN THEOLOGIANS /PHILOSOPHERS VIEW OF OMNISCIENCE AND HUMAN FREEDOM Christian Theologians /Philosophers view of Omniscience and human freedom 1 Dr. Abdul Hafeez Fāzli Associate Professor, Department of Philosophy, University of the Punjab, Lahore 54590 PAKISTAN Word count:

More information

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy Res Cogitans Volume 5 Issue 1 Article 20 6-4-2014 Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy Kevin Harriman Lewis & Clark College Follow this and additional works at: http://commons.pacificu.edu/rescogitans

More information

In this paper I will critically discuss a theory known as conventionalism

In this paper I will critically discuss a theory known as conventionalism Aporia vol. 22 no. 2 2012 Combating Metric Conventionalism Matthew Macdonald In this paper I will critically discuss a theory known as conventionalism about the metric of time. Simply put, conventionalists

More information

KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST. Arnon Keren

KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST. Arnon Keren Abstracta SPECIAL ISSUE VI, pp. 33 46, 2012 KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST Arnon Keren Epistemologists of testimony widely agree on the fact that our reliance on other people's testimony is extensive. However,

More information

Ontological Justification: From Appearance to Reality Anna-Sofia Maurin (PhD 2002)

Ontological Justification: From Appearance to Reality Anna-Sofia Maurin (PhD 2002) Ontological Justification: From Appearance to Reality Anna-Sofia Maurin (PhD 2002) PROJECT SUMMARY The project aims to investigate the notion of justification in ontology. More specifically, one particular

More information

If God brought about the Big Bang, did he do that before the Big Bang?

If God brought about the Big Bang, did he do that before the Big Bang? If God brought about the Big Bang, did he do that before the Big Bang? Daniel von Wachter Email: daniel@abc.de replace abc by von-wachter http://von-wachter.de International Academy of Philosophy, Santiago

More information