CONVENTIONALISM AND NORMATIVITY

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "CONVENTIONALISM AND NORMATIVITY"

Transcription

1 1 CONVENTIONALISM AND NORMATIVITY TORBEN SPAAK We have seen (in Section 3) that Hart objects to Austin s command theory of law, that it cannot account for the normativity of law, and that what is missing in Austin s theory is the idea of a rule. We have also seen that, on Hart s analysis, the foundation of the normativity of law is to be found in the rule of recognition, which is a judicial customary rule, that is, a social rule. As Hart sees it, the rule of recognition qualifies as a social rule because it satisfies the criteria in his general theory of social rules, sometimes referred to as the practice theory of rules (see, e.g., Raz 1990, 50-8). Under this theory, there is a social rule, R, in a community, S, if, and only if, the members of S (i) display a certain pattern of behavior that corresponds to R (the external aspect) and also (ii) hold that they ought to act in this particular way (the internal aspect). And since it is clear from Hart s account (1961, 112) that legal officials must view the rule of recognition as a common standard of correct judicial decision, and not as something which each judge obeys merely for his part only, we may with Hart (1994, 255) describe the rule of recognition as a conventional rule. As we have seen (in Section 2), Hart appears to operate with the conception of social normativity, according to which a standard is a social norm if and in so far as it is socially upheld as a binding standard and the society involved exerts pressure on people to whom the standard applies to conform to it. But we have also said that the conception or grade of normativity that is most interesting in this context is not social, but justified (or authoritative) normativity. However, some authors, who appear to have something like justified normativity in mind, have argued that if we can only refine Hart s practice theory of rules, we may be

2 2 able to account for the normativity of law. Gerald Postema (1982, 167), for example, proposes to shift the focus of the [conventionalist] doctrine away from the regularities of behavior and attitude which Hart believes constitute the rule of recognition to the strategic context, the context of practical reasoning, in which such regularities take on normative significance. On his analysis, a regularity, R, in the behavior of persons in a population, P, in a recurring situation, S, is a convention if, and only if, in any instance of S (1) it is common knowledge in P (a) that there is in P general conformity to R; (b) that most members of P expect most other members of P to conform to R; (c) that almost every member of P prefers that any individual conform rather than not conform to some regularity of behavior in S, given general conformity to that regularity; and (d) that almost every member of P prefers general conformity to some regularity rather than general non-conformity; and (2) that part of the reason why most members of P conform to R in S is that (1a)-(1d) obtains. 1 As Postema sees it (ibid., 182), a person who fails to do his part in such a conventionally defined joint effort acts unfairly, and this means that at least in some cases he may have an obligation to conform to the convention. Postema maintains (ibid., 194), that coordination is fundamental to law and that no legal system is conceivable without substantial coordination elements at its foundation. To defend his claim, he introduces a distinction between (i) first-, (ii) second-, and (iii) third-level coordination in law (ibid., ) and argues (ibid., 183) that there are significant secondand third-level coordination problems in a community living under law... [that it] is legitimate to describe social interaction (and the structure of practical reasoning) within the 1 One may well wonder whether (1c) adds anything important to (1d). If the members of the community prefer general conformity to some regularity, R, to general non-conformity, as (1d) has it, must they not also prefer, on pain of contradiction, that any individual conform rather than not conform to some regularity of behavior in S, given general conformity to that regularity, as (1c) has it?

3 3 context of law as a set of complex and persisting coordination problems. His idea, then, is that legal thinking typically aims at coordinating the actions of officials and lay persons. As he puts it (ibid., 187), law-identifying, law-applying, and law-interpreting activities of both officials and lay persons essentially involve a complex form of social interaction having the structure of a coordination problem or, rather, of an interrelated, continuous series or overlapping network of coordination problems. Having pointed out (i) that law aims to regulate the behavior of agents that respond to reasons, (ii) that law is a common public standard for behavior, (iii) that, generally speaking, the use of rules presupposes a fixed background context of interpretation and application, and (iv) that the authoritative law-identifying, law-interpreting, and law-applying activities of judges tend to shape the practical import of legal rules in a special way, Postema concludes that the understanding of law and legal requirements by officials and citizens are interdependent to an important degree in the sense that the understanding of the law on the part of the citizens depends on the expectations and understanding of the law on the part of the legal officials, and, conversely, that the understanding of law on the part of the officials depends on the understanding and expectations on the part of the citizens and, indeed, that all the elements of strategic interaction can be found in the relation between citizens and judges: Law can direct action to its ends only if its rules are integrated into the practical reasoning of those subject to the rules, and communication is an interactive process in which the understanding of each party depends on the expectations and understanding of the other. Authoritative interpretation and application of the law can to some extent take the lead there is, therefore, a significant asymmetry in the strategic relations between subjects and officials but it cannot depart substantially from the background practice of interpretation and remain an intelligible enterprise (or at least not one with the distinctive characteristics of law). (Ibid )

4 4 He then argues that we have reason to view the rule of recognition as precisely such a conventional rule aiming at coordinating the behavior of officials and citizens that may give rise to an obligation (or a duty): On this view, conventional judicial duties are genuine duties, not just forms of behavior which people may believe to be obligatory. Because they rest on an important (albeit limited) concern for fairness, they belong to a species of moral duty. (Ibid., Footnote omitted.) The important thing about the rule of recognition, on this analysis, Postema points out in conclusion, is not the underlying reasons for accepting it, but the fact of acceptance itself. The normative force of the rule of recognition, he explains,... depends simply on the fact that the rule succeeds in the task of coordinating law-identifying and law-applying activities of officials and lay persons. It provides a common way of acting on a large number of occasions, where often it is more important that there be a common way of acting than that it be the right, just, or otherwise best way. Judges need not believe, nor need it be true, that the existing rule of recognition is the ideally best such rule. They may believe, and have good arguments to show, that some other rule would be better, more just, or the like. But as long as the existing rule succeeds, and alternative rules cannot promise success, and as long as achieving coordination is at least minimally desirable, the existing rule will continue to generate (prima facie) obligations on the part of officials to conform to it. (Ibid., ) I find plausible Postema s claim that the rule of recognition is a coordination convention in the somewhat loose sense explained. It seems right to me to hold that the understanding of the law on the part of the citizens depends on the expectations and understanding of the law on the part of judges and other legal officials, and that the understanding of the law on the part of judges and other legal officials depends on the understanding of the law on the part of the citizens. I am not, however, convinced by Postema s claim that this means that law is essentially normative in the sense of justified normativity, that is, in the sense that judges and

5 5 citizens alike have a moral obligation (or duty) to obey the law at the most, it might mean that judges and other legal officials have such an obligation. 2 Indeed, I am not convinced that benefitting from a cooperative enterprise yields an obligation even in the best of circumstances (on this, see Nozick 1974, 90-5; Simmons, 1979, chap. 5). In any case, I doubt whether almost all citizens take part voluntarily in such an enterprise. Even anarchists who refuse to vote may to some extent be parties to such a coordinative enterprise, in the sense that they will have certain expectations and a certain understanding of the law of the land, which will depend to some extent on the expectations and understanding of the law on the part of judges and other legal officials. And it seems farfetched to maintain that they acquire an obligation to obey the law by virtue of being more or less forced to predict the lawinterpreting and law-applying activities of judges and other legal officials. Andrei Marmor (2010), who speaks about the rules of recognition in the plural, shares Hart s (and Postema s) view that these rules are conventional rules, and he also appears to share Kelsen s and Olivecrona s and Postema s view of what normativity is, namely something like justified normativity. He maintains, however, that the rules of recognition are best understood as constitutive as distinguished from coordinative conventions, and that this means that the normativity of law can only be conditional upon a wish on the part of the subjects of law to play the legal game. Marmor lays down the following three individually necessary and jointly sufficient conditions for the existence of a conventional rule: 2 To be sure, Postema mentions only officials in the quotation above. His general discussion of coordination at the foundation of law suggests, however, that he thinks that anyone who takes part in a cooperative enterprise acquires an obligation to obey the rules involved in the cooperation.

6 6 (i) There is a group of people, P, whose members normally follow the rules of recognition, RR, in circumstances, C. (ii) There is a set of reasons, A, for the members of P to follow RR. (iii) There is at least one other potential set of rules, SR, such that if the members of P had actually followed SR instead of RR in C, then A would have been sufficient for the members of P to do so. We see that, on Marmor s analysis, a rule, R 1, is a conventional rule if, and only if, (i) the members of a group of people follow R 1, (ii) they have reasons, A, to follow R 1, and (iii) A would also have been sufficient for them to follow another, similar rule, R 2. Condition (i) makes it clear that the members of the group must normally, usually, or on the whole, follow the rule. This simply means that not every member must on every occasion follow the rule. Condition (ii), as I understand it, means that the members of the group do not have to follow the rule because of the reasons, A, or, indeed, be aware of A at all. As Raz (1990, 178) might put it, while they must conform to the rule, they need not comply with it. And condition (iii) makes it clear that conventions are arbitrary, in the sense that a different rule than the one at hand might have fulfilled the function equally well. What is important is that there is a rule, not its specific content. Marmor notes (2010, 150) that some authors have objected to the view that the rules of recognition are conventional, that it is difficult to see how a mere convention could give rise to an obligation. He cites an article by Leslie Green (1996, 1697), in which the author says that the view (Hart s view) that the rule of recognition is a mere convention continues to sit uneasily with any notion of obligation. And he (Marmor) takes the gist of Green s

7 7 objection to concern the above-mentioned arbitrariness of conventions (ibid., 151), if the rules of recognition are arbitrary in the requisite sense, how can we explain the fact that they are supposed to obligate judges and other legal officials to follow them? His answer to this question suggests that he considers the objection to be well founded, arguing as he does that we have to make a distinction between the legal obligation to follow the rules of recognition and the moral obligation, if there is one, to follow these rules: The rules of recognition, like the rules of chess, determine what the practice is. They constitute the rules of the game, so to speak. Like other constitutive rules, they have a dual function: they both determine what constitutes the practice, and prescribe modes of conduct within it. The legal obligation to follow the rules of recognition is just like the chess players obligation, say, to move the bishop diagonally. Both are prescribed by the rules of the game. What such rules cannot prescribe, however, is an ought about playing the game to begin with. As I noted elsewhere, the normativity of constitutive conventions is always conditional. Conventional practices create reasons for action only if the relevant agent has a reason to participate in the practice to begin with. And that is true of the law as well. If there is an ought to play the game, so to speak, then this ought cannot be expected to come from the rules of recognition. The obligation to play by the rules, that is, to follow the law, if there is one, must come from moral and political considerations. The reasons to obey the law cannot be derived from the norms that determine what the law is. (Ibid., 152. Footnote omitted.) Marmor s view that the rules of recognition are constitutive conventions makes good sense to me, though I am not convinced that this means that they cannot also and, indeed, primarily fulfil a coordinative function. Marmor offers three distinct arguments in support of the claim that the rules of recognition, conceived as constitutive conventions, cannot also be coordination conventions. Specifically, he objects (ibid., 153-4) that the view that the rules of recognition are coordination conventions (i) misses the point that the rules of recognition constitute what law is, (ii) is not easy to reconcile with the political importance of these rules,

8 8 and (iii) that it blurs the distinction between the question of what law is and the question of what counts as law in a particular legal order. I am not, however, convinced by his argumentation. Let me explain why. Marmor argues, on the first count, that coordinative conventions do not usually have a constitutive function, that we cannot even begin to coordinate the actions of judges if we do not already see them as judges, that it is the rule of recognition that makes them judges, and that this means that that the rule of recognition cannot be a coordination convention (ibid., 153). But this argument is hardly air-tight. To begin with, although coordination conventions do not usually fulfil a constitutive function, this does not mean that they never fulfil a constitutive function, still less that they cannot fulfil such a function. Although Marmor is right to say that the much-cited problem of which side of the road to drive on clearly precedes and is independent of the convention that solves it, this hardly shows that there cannot be other conventions that fulfil a constitutive function by virtue of fulfilling a coordination function. Moreover, the idea that it is the rules of recognition that make a person a judge ( constitute a judge ) is problematic, given that, on Hart s analysis, it is the behavior of judges (together with a certain attitude, known as the internal point of view) that make up or constitute the rules of recognition. More specifically, in order to have the rules of recognition, we need to have judges, in order to have judges, we need to have rules of adjudication, and in order to have rules of adjudication, we need to have the rule of recognition. As far as I can see, we have here a vicious circle (on this, see MacCormick 1981, 108-9), and this in turn means that it cannot be the case, on Hart s theory, that it is the rule of recognition that turns a person into a judge. Hence if Marmor wishes to argue that the rules of recognition are constitutive conventions, he needs to explain just how the rule of recognition constitutes judges.

9 9 Marmor argues on the second count that since the rules of recognition are often politically important and it is difficult to see how coordination conventions which are necessarily arbitrary can be politically important, the rules of recognition cannot be coordination conventions. And he rightly points out that it matters to us who makes the law (politicians, judges, private parties, etc.) and infers that this means that the question of who makes the law cannot be a matter of coordination. But while it seems reasonable to assume that matters of pure coordination cannot be politically important there is, as I have said, the possibility that the rules of recognition may be both constitutive and coordinative in the sense explained above. Marmor argues, on the third count, that the view under consideration makes it unclear just how the rules of recognition relate to the concept of law. He maintains, as we have seen, that it is typically the case that we have independently of the relevant convention the concept of the activity that the convention is meant to coordinate, and that this follows from the point of having a coordination convention in the first place, namely that there is an activity that needs coordination (that is, a coordination problem that needs to be solved). As he puts it (ibid., 154), without the social conventions that constitute ways of making law and recognising it as such, it is difficult to imagine what kind of concept of law we could possibly have. But this particular argument appears to be aimed only at the view that it is in the nature of law to fulfil a coordinating function and not at the view that the rules of recognition are coordination conventions or at the view that the rules of recognition are both coordination conventions and constitutive conventions. For these are different ideas. One may certainly hold that the rules of recognition are coordination conventions without having to maintain that the basic function (or purpose) of law is to coordinate human behaviour. Moreover, just as a duty-imposing norm can also be a competence norm (or, if you will, a power-conferring norm), on the grounds that it confers competence on the members of a class of persons, A, by

10 10 virtue of imposing a duty on the members of another class of persons, B, to act in accordance with, say, the norms issued or the decisions made by the members of A (on this, see Spaak 1994, 171-3; 2003a, 94-7), a coordination convention can also be a constitutive convention, on the grounds that it imposes a duty on the members of B (assuming, of course, that it can impose a duty) to act in accordance with, say, the norms issued or the decisions made by the members of A. Let us, however, suppose, for the sake of argument, that Marmor is right that the rules of recognition are constitutive conventions and nothing more. My objection will then be that Marmor s claim that the normativity of law is, and can only be, conditional upon the existence of valid moral reasons to play the game of law is not a very novel claim. For it seems to be in substance, if not in form, more or less the same as Kelsen s view put forward by Kelsen already in 1925 (Kelsen 1993[1925], 251) and repeated in his later books (see, e.g., Kelsen 1960; 1992; 1999) that the normativity of law can only be conditional upon the presupposition of the basic norm, or, if you prefer, seen from a point of view of someone who adopts the basic norm. Marmor s introduction of the idea of a constitutive convention is, to be sure, an important contribution to the debate, but it does not add much to the substance of Kelsen s claim as regards the central question of whether the normativity of law is conditional or non-conditional. Interestingly, Marmor objects that not much is explained by the presupposition of the basic norm (2010, 146): Instead of telling us something about the foundations of the basic norm, Kelsen simply invites us to stop asking. But this objection misses the mark. First, why would a presupposition need a foundation? Since Kelsen makes it clear that the theory of the basic norm provides no more than a conditional foundation of the normativity of law, why accuse him of failing to provide a non-conditional foundation? Secondly, as we have seen, whereas Kelsen appears to be offering a belief-based, not a validity-based, explanation of

11 11 legal normativity (see Section 7, Marmor clearly has in mind a validity-based explanation. And, as I have said, while it is difficult to see how a presupposition on the part of, say, judges or legal scholars could explain the normativity of law, conceived as an essential property of law, it is not difficult to see how such a presupposition (even if implicit) could explain the use of normative language on the part of those who make the presupposition. Kelsen may thus have succeeded in answering his own question, even if he did not succeed in answering Marmor s question. I agree, however, with (what I take to be) Marmor s view, that Marmor s question is more interesting. One might also be tempted to object that Marmor s second existence-condition for conventional rules, which does not require that the members of the relevant group of persons be aware of the set of reasons, A, for the members of the group to follow the rule, that the connection between the beliefs or attitudes of the people in question and the relevant pattern of behavior will be rather weak. As far as I can tell, the usual assumption in the literature on conventions is instead that the members of the relevant group of people must have a belief or an expectation about or an attitude to something, such as a pattern of behavior or some other type of entity. Thus Hart (1961; 1994), Lyons (1969, chaps. 1-2), Postema (1982, 176), and Lagerspetz (1995, chap. 1) all take this view. On Lagerspetz s account (1995, chap. 1), for example, a social rule, R, exists if the members of the relevant group of people (1a) believe that R exists and (1b) believe that the others in the group believe that R exists, and (2) act accordingly, that is, speak of R as existing and, if occasion arises, treat R as existing, at least partly because they have the beliefs (1a) and (1b). 3 3 Note that the account lays down sufficient, but not necessary, conditions for the existence of conventional facts. The reason, Lagerspetz explains (1995, 19), is that there may be some rules that are not generally followed by large parts of the population, perhaps because they are not known to the population, but which nevertheless may be said to exist in the sense that they are part of a system of rules that satisfies the conditions laid down in the account.

12 12 Marmor does not explain why he chooses to formulate condition (ii) the way he does. But one may assume that he has in mind objections to David Lewis s account of convention, such as the one put forward by Tyler Burge in his article On Knowledge and Convention (1971). Burge s central objection (ibid., 254-5) to Lewis s account according to which there is common knowledge in the relevant group of people that the relevant conditions hold is that it takes too little note of the extent of the unconscious element in many conventions and the possibility of their being essentially misconceived or misvalued. Burge objects, in particular, that the members of the community need not know that there are alternatives to the convention in question. He considers the case of an isolated community in which the inhabitants speak a certain language and have no idea that there are other languages, and that they might equally well have spoken one of those other languages, since they believe perhaps for religious reasons that their own language is the only language there is and can be (ibid., 250). Nevertheless, Burge says, we would not hesitate to say that their language is conventional. I shall, however, have to leave it an open question whether Burge s objection is well founded.

University of Southern California Law School

University of Southern California Law School University of Southern California Law School Legal Studies Working Paper Series Year 2006 Paper 10 How Law is Like Chess Andrei Marmor This working paper is hosted by The Berkeley Electronic Press (bepress)

More information

* Dalhousie Law School, LL.B. anticipated Interpretation and Legal Theory. Andrei Marmor Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992, 193 pp.

* Dalhousie Law School, LL.B. anticipated Interpretation and Legal Theory. Andrei Marmor Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992, 193 pp. 330 Interpretation and Legal Theory Andrei Marmor Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992, 193 pp. Reviewed by Lawrence E. Thacker* Interpretation may be defined roughly as the process of determining the meaning

More information

Does law have to be effective in order for it to be valid?

Does law have to be effective in order for it to be valid? University of Birmingham Birmingham Law School Jurisprudence 2007-08 Assessed Essay (Second Round) Does law have to be effective in order for it to be valid? It is important to consider the terms valid

More information

Law and Authority. An unjust law is not a law

Law and Authority. An unjust law is not a law Law and Authority An unjust law is not a law The statement an unjust law is not a law is often treated as a summary of how natural law theorists approach the question of whether a law is valid or not.

More information

THE CONCEPT OF OWNERSHIP by Lars Bergström

THE CONCEPT OF OWNERSHIP by Lars Bergström From: Who Owns Our Genes?, Proceedings of an international conference, October 1999, Tallin, Estonia, The Nordic Committee on Bioethics, 2000. THE CONCEPT OF OWNERSHIP by Lars Bergström I shall be mainly

More information

HART ON THE INTERNAL ASPECT OF RULES

HART ON THE INTERNAL ASPECT OF RULES HART ON THE INTERNAL ASPECT OF RULES John D. Hodson Introduction, Polycarp Ikuenobe THE CONTEMPORARY AMERICAN PHILOSOPHER John Hodson, examines what H. L. A. Hart means by the notion of internal aspect

More information

HART ON SOCIAL RULES AND THE FOUNDATIONS OF LAW: LIBERATING THE INTERNAL POINT OF VIEW

HART ON SOCIAL RULES AND THE FOUNDATIONS OF LAW: LIBERATING THE INTERNAL POINT OF VIEW HART ON SOCIAL RULES AND THE FOUNDATIONS OF LAW: LIBERATING THE INTERNAL POINT OF VIEW Stephen Perry* INTRODUCTION The internal point of view is a crucial element in H.L.A. Hart s theory of law. Hart first

More information

Law Based on Accepted Authority

Law Based on Accepted Authority William & Mary Law Review Volume 23 Issue 3 Article 6 Law Based on Accepted Authority Michael A. Payne Repository Citation Michael A. Payne, Law Based on Accepted Authority, 23 Wm. & Mary L. Rev. 501 (1982),

More information

Andrei Marmor: Social Conventions

Andrei Marmor: Social Conventions Reviews Andrei Marmor: Social Conventions Princeton University Press, Princeton, 2009, xii + 186 pp. A few decades ago, only isolated groups of philosophers counted the phenomenon of normativity as one

More information

Some proposals for understanding narrow content

Some proposals for understanding narrow content Some proposals for understanding narrow content February 3, 2004 1 What should we require of explanations of narrow content?......... 1 2 Narrow psychology as whatever is shared by intrinsic duplicates......

More information

University of Southern California Law School

University of Southern California Law School University of Southern California Law School Legal Studies Working Paper Series Year 2010 Paper 66 The Dilemma of Authority Andrei Marmor amarmor@law.usc.edu This working paper is hosted by The Berkeley

More information

Follow links for Class Use and other Permissions. For more information send to:

Follow links for Class Use and other Permissions. For more information send  to: COPYRIGHT NOTICE: Andrei Marmor: Social Conventions is published by Princeton University Press and copyrighted, 2009, by Princeton University Press. All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reproduced

More information

Positivism A Model Of For System Of Rules

Positivism A Model Of For System Of Rules Positivism A Model Of For System Of Rules Positivism is a model of and for a system of rules, and its central notion of a single fundamental test for law forces us to miss the important standards that

More information

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori PHIL 83104 November 2, 2011 Both Boghossian and Harman address themselves to the question of whether our a priori knowledge can be explained in

More information

Dworkin on the Rufie of Recognition

Dworkin on the Rufie of Recognition Dworkin on the Rufie of Recognition NANCY SNOW University of Notre Dame In the "Model of Rules I," Ronald Dworkin criticizes legal positivism, especially as articulated in the work of H. L. A. Hart, and

More information

Duns Scotus on Divine Illumination

Duns Scotus on Divine Illumination MP_C13.qxd 11/23/06 2:29 AM Page 110 13 Duns Scotus on Divine Illumination [Article IV. Concerning Henry s Conclusion] In the fourth article I argue against the conclusion of [Henry s] view as follows:

More information

Toward a Jurisprudential Theory of International Law: Directions for Future Thought

Toward a Jurisprudential Theory of International Law: Directions for Future Thought Loyola Marymount University and Loyola Law School Digital Commons at Loyola Marymount University and Loyola Law School Loyola of Los Angeles International and Comparative Law Review Law Reviews 1-1-1979

More information

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism Mathais Sarrazin J.L. Mackie s Error Theory postulates that all normative claims are false. It does this based upon his denial of moral

More information

SANDEL ON RELIGION IN THE PUBLIC SQUARE

SANDEL ON RELIGION IN THE PUBLIC SQUARE SANDEL ON RELIGION IN THE PUBLIC SQUARE Hugh Baxter For Boston University School of Law s Conference on Michael Sandel s Justice October 14, 2010 In the final chapter of Justice, Sandel calls for a new

More information

FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. by Immanuel Kant

FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. by Immanuel Kant FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS SECOND SECTION by Immanuel Kant TRANSITION FROM POPULAR MORAL PHILOSOPHY TO THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS... This principle, that humanity and generally every

More information

Wright on response-dependence and self-knowledge

Wright on response-dependence and self-knowledge Wright on response-dependence and self-knowledge March 23, 2004 1 Response-dependent and response-independent concepts........... 1 1.1 The intuitive distinction......................... 1 1.2 Basic equations

More information

Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly *

Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly * Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly * Ralph Wedgwood 1 Two views of practical reason Suppose that you are faced with several different options (that is, several ways in which you might act in a

More information

McCLOSKEY ON RATIONAL ENDS: The Dilemma of Intuitionism

McCLOSKEY ON RATIONAL ENDS: The Dilemma of Intuitionism 48 McCLOSKEY ON RATIONAL ENDS: The Dilemma of Intuitionism T om R egan In his book, Meta-Ethics and Normative Ethics,* Professor H. J. McCloskey sets forth an argument which he thinks shows that we know,

More information

KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST. Arnon Keren

KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST. Arnon Keren Abstracta SPECIAL ISSUE VI, pp. 33 46, 2012 KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST Arnon Keren Epistemologists of testimony widely agree on the fact that our reliance on other people's testimony is extensive. However,

More information

-- The search text of this PDF is generated from uncorrected OCR text.

-- The search text of this PDF is generated from uncorrected OCR text. Citation: 21 Isr. L. Rev. 113 1986 Content downloaded/printed from HeinOnline (http://heinonline.org) Sun Jan 11 12:34:09 2015 -- Your use of this HeinOnline PDF indicates your acceptance of HeinOnline's

More information

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism? Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism? Author: Terence Rajivan Edward, University of Manchester. Abstract. In the sixth chapter of The View from Nowhere, Thomas Nagel attempts to identify a form of idealism.

More information

PHILOSOPHY 4360/5360 METAPHYSICS. Methods that Metaphysicians Use

PHILOSOPHY 4360/5360 METAPHYSICS. Methods that Metaphysicians Use PHILOSOPHY 4360/5360 METAPHYSICS Methods that Metaphysicians Use Method 1: The appeal to what one can imagine where imagining some state of affairs involves forming a vivid image of that state of affairs.

More information

Gilbert. Margaret. Scientists Are People Too: Comment on Andersen. Social Epistemology Review and Reply Collective 6, no. 5 (2017):

Gilbert. Margaret. Scientists Are People Too: Comment on Andersen. Social Epistemology Review and Reply Collective 6, no. 5 (2017): http://social-epistemology.com ISSN: 2471-9560 Scientists Are People Too: Comment on Andersen Margaret Gilbert, University of California, Irvine Gilbert. Margaret. Scientists Are People Too: Comment on

More information

Legal Positivism: Still Descriptive and Morally Neutral

Legal Positivism: Still Descriptive and Morally Neutral Cornell University Law School Scholarship@Cornell Law: A Digital Repository Cornell Law Faculty Publications Faculty Scholarship Winter 2006 Legal Positivism: Still Descriptive and Morally Neutral Andrei

More information

CRUCIAL TOPICS IN THE DEBATE ABOUT THE EXISTENCE OF EXTERNAL REASONS

CRUCIAL TOPICS IN THE DEBATE ABOUT THE EXISTENCE OF EXTERNAL REASONS CRUCIAL TOPICS IN THE DEBATE ABOUT THE EXISTENCE OF EXTERNAL REASONS By MARANATHA JOY HAYES A THESIS PRESENTED TO THE GRADUATE SCHOOL OF THE UNIVERSITY OF FLORIDA IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS

More information

Are There Reasons to Be Rational?

Are There Reasons to Be Rational? Are There Reasons to Be Rational? Olav Gjelsvik, University of Oslo The thesis. Among people writing about rationality, few people are more rational than Wlodek Rabinowicz. But are there reasons for being

More information

Philosophy of Law: Reply to Critics

Philosophy of Law: Reply to Critics Cornell University Law School Scholarship@Cornell Law: A Digital Repository Cornell Law Faculty Publications Faculty Scholarship 2014 Philosophy of Law: Reply to Critics Andrei Marmor Cornell University,

More information

Reply to Kit Fine. Theodore Sider July 19, 2013

Reply to Kit Fine. Theodore Sider July 19, 2013 Reply to Kit Fine Theodore Sider July 19, 2013 Kit Fine s paper raises important and difficult issues about my approach to the metaphysics of fundamentality. In chapters 7 and 8 I examined certain subtle

More information

Legal positivism represents a view about the nature of law. It states that

Legal positivism represents a view about the nature of law. It states that Legal Positivism A N I NTRODUCTION Polycarp Ikuenobe Legal positivism represents a view about the nature of law. It states that there is no necessary or conceptual connection between law and morality and

More information

Utilitarianism: For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), pp Reprinted in Moral Luck (CUP, 1981).

Utilitarianism: For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), pp Reprinted in Moral Luck (CUP, 1981). Draft of 3-21- 13 PHIL 202: Core Ethics; Winter 2013 Core Sequence in the History of Ethics, 2011-2013 IV: 19 th and 20 th Century Moral Philosophy David O. Brink Handout #14: Williams, Internalism, and

More information

Stout s teleological theory of action

Stout s teleological theory of action Stout s teleological theory of action Jeff Speaks November 26, 2004 1 The possibility of externalist explanations of action................ 2 1.1 The distinction between externalist and internalist explanations

More information

LEGAL STUDIES RESEARCH PAPER SERIES

LEGAL STUDIES RESEARCH PAPER SERIES Legal Positivism: Still Descriptive and Morally Neutral (forthcoming in the OXFORD JOURNAL OF LEGAL STUDIES) Andrei Marmor USC Legal Studies Research Paper No. 05-16 LEGAL STUDIES RESEARCH PAPER SERIES

More information

Kant and his Successors

Kant and his Successors Kant and his Successors G. J. Mattey Winter, 2011 / Philosophy 151 The Sorry State of Metaphysics Kant s Critique of Pure Reason (1781) was an attempt to put metaphysics on a scientific basis. Metaphysics

More information

Positivism and Conventionalism

Positivism and Conventionalism Osgoode Hall Law School of York University Osgoode Digital Commons Articles & Book Chapters Faculty Scholarship 1999 Positivism and Conventionalism Leslie Green Osgoode Hall Law School of York University

More information

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View Chapter 98 Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View Lars Leeten Universität Hildesheim Practical thinking is a tricky business. Its aim will never be fulfilled unless influence on practical

More information

HAVE WE REASON TO DO AS RATIONALITY REQUIRES? A COMMENT ON RAZ

HAVE WE REASON TO DO AS RATIONALITY REQUIRES? A COMMENT ON RAZ HAVE WE REASON TO DO AS RATIONALITY REQUIRES? A COMMENT ON RAZ BY JOHN BROOME JOURNAL OF ETHICS & SOCIAL PHILOSOPHY SYMPOSIUM I DECEMBER 2005 URL: WWW.JESP.ORG COPYRIGHT JOHN BROOME 2005 HAVE WE REASON

More information

Is and Ought Distinction in Legal Philosophy

Is and Ought Distinction in Legal Philosophy I Is and Ought Distinction in Legal Philosophy Wojciech Załuski The University of Krakow, Krakow, Poland Introduction The controversy over Is and Ought distinction appears in legal philosophy in two different

More information

Comment on Martha Nussbaum s Purified Patriotism

Comment on Martha Nussbaum s Purified Patriotism Comment on Martha Nussbaum s Purified Patriotism Patriotism is generally thought to require a special attachment to the particular: to one s own country and to one s fellow citizens. It is therefore thought

More information

Kelsen's Pure Theory of Law

Kelsen's Pure Theory of Law The Catholic Lawyer Volume 26 Number 2 Volume 26, Spring 1981, Number 2 Article 4 September 2017 Kelsen's Pure Theory of Law Henry Cohen Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarship.law.stjohns.edu/tcl

More information

IS THERE VALUE IN KEEPING A PROMISE? A Response to Joseph Raz. Crescente Molina

IS THERE VALUE IN KEEPING A PROMISE? A Response to Joseph Raz. Crescente Molina Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy Vol. 15, No. 1 April 2019 https://doi.org/10.26556/jesp.v15i1.616 2019 Author IS THERE VALUE IN KEEPING A PROMISE? A Response to Joseph Raz Crescente Molina S ome

More information

The Conflict Between Authority and Autonomy from Robert Wolff, In Defense of Anarchism (1970)

The Conflict Between Authority and Autonomy from Robert Wolff, In Defense of Anarchism (1970) The Conflict Between Authority and Autonomy from Robert Wolff, In Defense of Anarchism (1970) 1. The Concept of Authority Politics is the exercise of the power of the state, or the attempt to influence

More information

The ontology of human rights and obligations

The ontology of human rights and obligations The ontology of human rights and obligations Åsa Burman Department of Philosophy, Stockholm University asa.burman@philosophy.su.se If we are going to make sense of the notion of rights we have to answer

More information

Who or what is God?, asks John Hick (Hick 2009). A theist might answer: God is an infinite person, or at least an

Who or what is God?, asks John Hick (Hick 2009). A theist might answer: God is an infinite person, or at least an John Hick on whether God could be an infinite person Daniel Howard-Snyder Western Washington University Abstract: "Who or what is God?," asks John Hick. A theist might answer: God is an infinite person,

More information

Ethics Handout 19 Bernard Williams, The Idea of Equality. A normative conclusion: Therefore we should treat men as equals.

Ethics Handout 19 Bernard Williams, The Idea of Equality. A normative conclusion: Therefore we should treat men as equals. 24.231 Ethics Handout 19 Bernard Williams, The Idea of Equality A descriptive claim: All men are equal. A normative conclusion: Therefore we should treat men as equals. I. What should we make of the descriptive

More information

Rawls, rationality, and responsibility: Why we should not treat our endowments as morally arbitrary

Rawls, rationality, and responsibility: Why we should not treat our endowments as morally arbitrary Rawls, rationality, and responsibility: Why we should not treat our endowments as morally arbitrary OLIVER DUROSE Abstract John Rawls is primarily known for providing his own argument for how political

More information

Obligation and Mutual Respect

Obligation and Mutual Respect Yale Law Journal Volume 95 Issue 2 Yale Law Journal Article 10 1985 Obligation and Mutual Respect John Martin Fischer Follow this and additional works at: http://digitalcommons.law.yale.edu/ylj Recommended

More information

Rethinking Legal Positivism. Jules L. Coleman Yale University. Introduction

Rethinking Legal Positivism. Jules L. Coleman Yale University. Introduction Dear Participants in the USC Workshop The following is a 'drafty' paper -- a term I use intentionally to convey a double meaning: it outlines a large research project and provides the outlines of a full

More information

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006 In Defense of Radical Empiricism Joseph Benjamin Riegel A thesis submitted to the faculty of the University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of

More information

Rawls s veil of ignorance excludes all knowledge of likelihoods regarding the social

Rawls s veil of ignorance excludes all knowledge of likelihoods regarding the social Rawls s veil of ignorance excludes all knowledge of likelihoods regarding the social position one ends up occupying, while John Harsanyi s version of the veil tells contractors that they are equally likely

More information

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy Res Cogitans Volume 5 Issue 1 Article 20 6-4-2014 Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy Kevin Harriman Lewis & Clark College Follow this and additional works at: http://commons.pacificu.edu/rescogitans

More information

The CopernicanRevolution

The CopernicanRevolution Immanuel Kant: The Copernican Revolution The CopernicanRevolution Immanuel Kant (1724-1804) The Critique of Pure Reason (1781) is Kant s best known work. In this monumental work, he begins a Copernican-like

More information

Ayer and Quine on the a priori

Ayer and Quine on the a priori Ayer and Quine on the a priori November 23, 2004 1 The problem of a priori knowledge Ayer s book is a defense of a thoroughgoing empiricism, not only about what is required for a belief to be justified

More information

Logic and the Absolute: Platonic and Christian Views

Logic and the Absolute: Platonic and Christian Views Logic and the Absolute: Platonic and Christian Views by Philip Sherrard Studies in Comparative Religion, Vol. 7, No. 2. (Spring 1973) World Wisdom, Inc. www.studiesincomparativereligion.com ONE of the

More information

On legal things to do: external and internal legal reasons Comments on Brian Bix s Hart, Kelsen and legal normativity

On legal things to do: external and internal legal reasons Comments on Brian Bix s Hart, Kelsen and legal normativity Revus Journal for Constitutional Theory and Philosophy of Law / Revija za ustavno teorijo in filozofijo prava in print 2018 (- Already online -) On legal things to do: external and internal legal reasons

More information

5 A Modal Version of the

5 A Modal Version of the 5 A Modal Version of the Ontological Argument E. J. L O W E Moreland, J. P.; Sweis, Khaldoun A.; Meister, Chad V., Jul 01, 2013, Debating Christian Theism The original version of the ontological argument

More information

INTRODUCTION TO THINKING AT THE EDGE. By Eugene T. Gendlin, Ph.D.

INTRODUCTION TO THINKING AT THE EDGE. By Eugene T. Gendlin, Ph.D. INTRODUCTION TO THINKING AT THE EDGE By Eugene T. Gendlin, Ph.D. "Thinking At the Edge" (in German: "Wo Noch Worte Fehlen") stems from my course called "Theory Construction" which I taught for many years

More information

Firth and Hill: Two Dispositional Ethical Theories. Margaret Chiovoloni. Chapel Hill 2006

Firth and Hill: Two Dispositional Ethical Theories. Margaret Chiovoloni. Chapel Hill 2006 Firth and Hill: Two Dispositional Ethical Theories Margaret Chiovoloni A thesis submitted to the faculty of the University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill in partial fulfillment of the requirements for

More information

Promises, Practices, and Reciprocity

Promises, Practices, and Reciprocity ! Recently, conventionalism about promise-keeping has been charged with making promising too impersonal. By conventionalism about promise-keeping, I mean the view that the moral demands involved in promising

More information

Chapter 2 Ethical Concepts and Ethical Theories: Establishing and Justifying a Moral System

Chapter 2 Ethical Concepts and Ethical Theories: Establishing and Justifying a Moral System Chapter 2 Ethical Concepts and Ethical Theories: Establishing and Justifying a Moral System Ethics and Morality Ethics: greek ethos, study of morality What is Morality? Morality: system of rules for guiding

More information

Hans Kelsen. 1. Kelsen s life ( )

Hans Kelsen. 1. Kelsen s life ( ) Hans Kelsen Interview at Kelsen Tours Ltd (The following exchange takes place at the office of a travel agent soon after a democratic government of a holiday island country has been ousted by a military

More information

Mark Greenberg, UCLA 1

Mark Greenberg, UCLA 1 THE STANDARD PICTURE AND ITS DISCONTENTS Mark Greenberg, UCLA 1 This paper is a rough and preliminary work in progress and is largely without citations. I would be grateful for comments of any sort. Please

More information

The Reasons of Trust

The Reasons of Trust This is an Accepted Manuscript of an article published in The Australasian Journal of Philosophy 86, no. 2 (June 2008): 213 36, available online: http://www.tandfonline.com/10.1080/00048400801886496. The

More information

A Case against Subjectivism: A Reply to Sobel

A Case against Subjectivism: A Reply to Sobel A Case against Subjectivism: A Reply to Sobel Abstract Subjectivists are committed to the claim that desires provide us with reasons for action. Derek Parfit argues that subjectivists cannot account for

More information

Etchemendy, Tarski, and Logical Consequence 1 Jared Bates, University of Missouri Southwest Philosophy Review 15 (1999):

Etchemendy, Tarski, and Logical Consequence 1 Jared Bates, University of Missouri Southwest Philosophy Review 15 (1999): Etchemendy, Tarski, and Logical Consequence 1 Jared Bates, University of Missouri Southwest Philosophy Review 15 (1999): 47 54. Abstract: John Etchemendy (1990) has argued that Tarski's definition of logical

More information

Direct Sterilization: An Intrinsically Evil Act - A Rejoinder to Fr. Keenan

Direct Sterilization: An Intrinsically Evil Act - A Rejoinder to Fr. Keenan The Linacre Quarterly Volume 68 Number 2 Article 4 May 2001 Direct Sterilization: An Intrinsically Evil Act - A Rejoinder to Fr. Keenan Lawrence J. Welch Follow this and additional works at: http://epublications.marquette.edu/lnq

More information

8 Internal and external reasons

8 Internal and external reasons ioo Rawls and Pascal's wager out how under-powered the supposed rational choice under ignorance is. Rawls' theory tries, in effect, to link politics with morality, and morality (or at least the relevant

More information

EUI Working Papers MWP 2007/15

EUI Working Papers MWP 2007/15 EUI Working Papers MWP 2007/15 Authority, Arbitration and the Claims of the Law Lars Vinx EUROPEAN UNIVERSITY INSTITUTE MAX WEBER PROGRAMME Authority, Arbitration and the Claims of the Law LARS VINX EUI

More information

the notion of modal personhood. I begin with a challenge to Kagan s assumptions about the metaphysics of identity and modality.

the notion of modal personhood. I begin with a challenge to Kagan s assumptions about the metaphysics of identity and modality. On Modal Personism Shelly Kagan s essay on speciesism has the virtues characteristic of his work in general: insight, originality, clarity, cleverness, wit, intuitive plausibility, argumentative rigor,

More information

Citation for the original published paper (version of record):

Citation for the original published paper (version of record): http://www.diva-portal.org Postprint This is the accepted version of a paper published in Utilitas. This paper has been peerreviewed but does not include the final publisher proof-corrections or journal

More information

THINKING ANIMALS AND EPISTEMOLOGY

THINKING ANIMALS AND EPISTEMOLOGY THINKING ANIMALS AND EPISTEMOLOGY by ANTHONY BRUECKNER AND CHRISTOPHER T. BUFORD Abstract: We consider one of Eric Olson s chief arguments for animalism about personal identity: the view that we are each

More information

New Aristotelianism, Routledge, 2012), in which he expanded upon

New Aristotelianism, Routledge, 2012), in which he expanded upon Powers, Essentialism and Agency: A Reply to Alexander Bird Ruth Porter Groff, Saint Louis University AUB Conference, April 28-29, 2016 1. Here s the backstory. A couple of years ago my friend Alexander

More information

Compromise and Toleration: Some Reflections I. Introduction

Compromise and Toleration: Some Reflections  I. Introduction Compromise and Toleration: Some Reflections Christian F. Rostbøll Paper for Årsmøde i Dansk Selskab for Statskundskab, 29-30 Oct. 2015. Kolding. (The following is not a finished paper but some preliminary

More information

LEGAL STUDIES RESEARCH PAPER SERIES

LEGAL STUDIES RESEARCH PAPER SERIES Truth in Law Andrei Marmor USC Legal Studies Research Paper No. 11-3 LEGAL STUDIES RESEARCH PAPER SERIES University of Southern California Law School Los Angeles, CA 90089-0071 Draft/ November, 2011 Truth

More information

Summary of Kant s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals

Summary of Kant s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals Summary of Kant s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals Version 1.1 Richard Baron 2 October 2016 1 Contents 1 Introduction 3 1.1 Availability and licence............ 3 2 Definitions of key terms 4 3

More information

Phil 114, April 24, 2007 until the end of semester Mill: Individual Liberty Against the Tyranny of the Majority

Phil 114, April 24, 2007 until the end of semester Mill: Individual Liberty Against the Tyranny of the Majority Phil 114, April 24, 2007 until the end of semester Mill: Individual Liberty Against the Tyranny of the Majority The aims of On Liberty The subject of the work is the nature and limits of the power which

More information

Hume's Is/Ought Problem. Ruse and Wilson. Moral Philosophy as Applied Science. Naturalistic Fallacy

Hume's Is/Ought Problem. Ruse and Wilson. Moral Philosophy as Applied Science. Naturalistic Fallacy Ruse and Wilson Hume's Is/Ought Problem Is ethics independent of humans or has human evolution shaped human behavior and beliefs about right and wrong? "In every system of morality, which I have hitherto

More information

In Epistemic Relativism, Mark Kalderon defends a view that has become

In Epistemic Relativism, Mark Kalderon defends a view that has become Aporia vol. 24 no. 1 2014 Incoherence in Epistemic Relativism I. Introduction In Epistemic Relativism, Mark Kalderon defends a view that has become increasingly popular across various academic disciplines.

More information

Positivism, Natural Law, and Disestablishment: Some Questions Raised by MacCormick's Moralistic Amoralism

Positivism, Natural Law, and Disestablishment: Some Questions Raised by MacCormick's Moralistic Amoralism Valparaiso University Law Review Volume 20 Number 1 pp.55-60 Fall 1985 Positivism, Natural Law, and Disestablishment: Some Questions Raised by MacCormick's Moralistic Amoralism Joseph M. Boyle Jr. Recommended

More information

Against the Vagueness Argument TUOMAS E. TAHKO ABSTRACT

Against the Vagueness Argument TUOMAS E. TAHKO ABSTRACT Against the Vagueness Argument TUOMAS E. TAHKO ABSTRACT In this paper I offer a counterexample to the so called vagueness argument against restricted composition. This will be done in the lines of a recent

More information

proper construal of Davidson s principle of rationality will show the objection to be misguided. Andrew Wong Washington University, St.

proper construal of Davidson s principle of rationality will show the objection to be misguided. Andrew Wong Washington University, St. Do e s An o m a l o u s Mo n i s m Hav e Explanatory Force? Andrew Wong Washington University, St. Louis The aim of this paper is to support Donald Davidson s Anomalous Monism 1 as an account of law-governed

More information

Merricks on the existence of human organisms

Merricks on the existence of human organisms Merricks on the existence of human organisms Cian Dorr August 24, 2002 Merricks s Overdetermination Argument against the existence of baseballs depends essentially on the following premise: BB Whenever

More information

Loyola of Los Angeles Law Review

Loyola of Los Angeles Law Review Loyola Marymount University and Loyola Law School Digital Commons at Loyola Marymount University and Loyola Law School Loyola of Los Angeles Law Review Law Reviews 3-1-2007 Introduction Robin Bradley Kar

More information

Kelsen s Legal Monism and the Future of the European Constitution

Kelsen s Legal Monism and the Future of the European Constitution Kelsen s Legal Monism and the Future of the European Constitution Draft, August 2011 Lars Vinx Department of Philosophy Bilkent University vinx@bilkent.edu.tr In recent years, much of the debate on the

More information

Review of Constructive Empiricism: Epistemology and the Philosophy of Science

Review of Constructive Empiricism: Epistemology and the Philosophy of Science Review of Constructive Empiricism: Epistemology and the Philosophy of Science Constructive Empiricism (CE) quickly became famous for its immunity from the most devastating criticisms that brought down

More information

What conditions does Plato expect a good definition to meet? Is he right to impose them?

What conditions does Plato expect a good definition to meet? Is he right to impose them? What conditions does Plato expect a good definition to meet? Is he right to impose them? In this essay we will be discussing the conditions Plato requires a definition to meet in his dialogue Meno. We

More information

HANDBOOK (New or substantially modified material appears in boxes.)

HANDBOOK (New or substantially modified material appears in boxes.) 1 HANDBOOK (New or substantially modified material appears in boxes.) I. ARGUMENT RECOGNITION Important Concepts An argument is a unit of reasoning that attempts to prove that a certain idea is true by

More information

Strange bedfellows or Siamese twins? The search for the sacred in practical theology and psychology of religion

Strange bedfellows or Siamese twins? The search for the sacred in practical theology and psychology of religion Strange bedfellows or Siamese twins? The search for the sacred in practical theology and psychology of religion R.Ruard Ganzevoort A paper for the Symposium The relation between Psychology of Religion

More information

Legal Positivism: the Separation and Identification theses are true.

Legal Positivism: the Separation and Identification theses are true. PHL271 Handout 3: Hart on Legal Positivism 1 Legal Positivism Revisited HLA Hart was a highly sophisticated philosopher. His defence of legal positivism marked a watershed in 20 th Century philosophy of

More information

The view that all of our actions are done in self-interest is called psychological egoism.

The view that all of our actions are done in self-interest is called psychological egoism. Egoism For the last two classes, we have been discussing the question of whether any actions are really objectively right or wrong, independently of the standards of any person or group, and whether any

More information

KANT, MORAL DUTY AND THE DEMANDS OF PURE PRACTICAL REASON. The law is reason unaffected by desire.

KANT, MORAL DUTY AND THE DEMANDS OF PURE PRACTICAL REASON. The law is reason unaffected by desire. KANT, MORAL DUTY AND THE DEMANDS OF PURE PRACTICAL REASON The law is reason unaffected by desire. Aristotle, Politics Book III (1287a32) THE BIG IDEAS TO MASTER Kantian formalism Kantian constructivism

More information

THE FREEDOM OF THE WILL By Immanuel Kant From Critique of Pure Reason (1781)

THE FREEDOM OF THE WILL By Immanuel Kant From Critique of Pure Reason (1781) THE FREEDOM OF THE WILL By Immanuel Kant From Critique of Pure Reason (1781) From: A447/B475 A451/B479 Freedom independence of the laws of nature is certainly a deliverance from restraint, but it is also

More information

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg 1 In Search of the Ontological Argument Richard Oxenberg Abstract We can attend to the logic of Anselm's ontological argument, and amuse ourselves for a few hours unraveling its convoluted word-play, or

More information

The Philosophy of Education. An Introduction By: VV.AA., Richard BALEY (Ed.) London: Continuum

The Philosophy of Education. An Introduction By: VV.AA., Richard BALEY (Ed.) London: Continuum John TILLSON The Philosophy of Education. An Introduction By: VV.AA., Richard BALEY (Ed.) London: Continuum John TILLSON II Época, Nº 6 (2011):185-190 185 The Philosophy of Education. An Introduction 1.

More information

UNDERSTANDING FUNDAMENTAL SECONDARY RULES

UNDERSTANDING FUNDAMENTAL SECONDARY RULES UNDERSTANDING FUNDAMENTAL SECONDARY RULES UNDERSTANDING FUNDAMENTAL SECONDARY RULES AND THE INCLUSIVE/EXCLUSIVE LEGAL POSITIVISM DEBATE By HEATHER KUIPER, B.A., M.A. A Dissertation Submitted to the School

More information