Kant on the Notion of Being İlhan İnan

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Kant on the Notion of Being İlhan İnan"

Transcription

1 Kant on the Notion of Being İlhan İnan Bogazici University, Department of Philosophy In his Critique of Pure Reason Kant attempts to refute Descartes' Ontological Argument for the existence of God by claiming that "'being' is not a real predicate". In this essay I wish to explore what Kant means by this, what arguments he gives in support of it, and whether by this claim Kant anticipates the Frege/Russell view that existence is a secondorder concept. 1 I An important heritage that remains from The Linguistic Turn is the Existential Quantifier. Frege and Russell independently came to the same conclusion that existence is not an ordinary concept that ascribes a property to a particular object. Frege analyzes existence as a second level concept ; a proposition in the form "F exists", according to Frege, should be analyzed as "There is at least one object that falls under the concept F". Similarly a negative existential claim in the form "F does not exist" turns out to subscribe to the concept of F being empty. 2 In a similar vein, Russell takes existence to be a property of a "propositional function 3 which comes close to, and perhaps is the same as Frege's "concept" (which Frege defines as functions from objects to truth values). For both philosophers an existential claim makes no reference to an object, which allows them to solve the time honored Riddle of non-being. For instance if the sentence "God exists" makes reference to God, then the same should be expected of its negation "God does not exist", which in effect would lead to a contradiction. Therefore in both of those sentences, there is no reference to God, on the Frege/Russell view, but only a reference to the concept God; the first says the concept is not empty and the latter says that it is. Today perhaps there is no philosopher who denies that this is at least one good use of the existence predicate.

2 A commonly held view among historians is that Frege and Russell were the pioneers of the view that existence is a second-order concept ascribing a property to a concept rather than an object. Did Kant anticipate this view in his Critique of Pure Reason which was published more than a century before Frege and Russell had published their work? 4 Let us then proceed to the section of the Critique where Kant takes up this issue, which predominantly is concentrated in A599-B627 in the Ideal of Pure Reason. Here Kant's main purpose is not to explore what existence is but rather to demonstrate what goes wrong in the ontological arguments given for the existence of God. Though Kant only makes reference to Descartes, it seems clear that he has in mind the earlier versions due to Anselm and others. The Cartesian version of the argument (given in the fifth Meditation) briefly runs as follows: "God by definition has all perfections; existence is perfection, therefore God exists". Such arguments, according to Kant, wrongly presuppose that " being is a real predicate". Before we go into Kant's arguments, it is vital that we try to clarify the crucial notions of "being" [Sein] and "predicate" [praedikat]. II In the English translations of the Critique, the term "Sein" is, in general, translated as "being" especially in the section we are considering. It seems clear that the term "being" as it occurs in certain utterances of English means "object" or "thing", as for instance in the sentence "Humans are rational beings". If this is the sense we attach to the term in Kant's major claim "'being' is not a real predicate", we would get "An object is not a real predicate" which would be far from what Kant meant by this claim. Rather "Sein" should be taken, in this context as "existence", which I believe is the common interpretation. So in what follows I will put aside the term "being", and use "existence" in the discussion. On the other hand what is more problematic is the term "predicate" [praedikat] which I believe is used ambiguously by Kant. In certain contexts Kant seems to be using the term

3 to mean property or attribute, yet in other contexts he uses the term to refer to a syntactic/logical part of a sentence. For instance Kant makes a distinction between "real" and "logical" predicates, where he defines the former as a predicate that "does not enlarge the concept of the subject", and the latter as one that does. Now it seems to me that we cannot take the term "predicate" to mean property here, or else we would end up saying that there are two types of properties, real ones and logical ones. This would be inconsistent with Kant's claim that the same predicate can occur as a logical one in one sentential context and a real one in another. He says: Anything one likes can serve as a logical predicate, even the subject can be predicated of itself. Clearly this indicates that whether a predicate is a logical one or a real one is to be determined in terms of the sentential context in which it occurs. It would be wrong, for instance, to ask "is 'red' a logical or a real predicate?" independent of a sentential context. In the sentence "apples are red" it appears as a real predicate, whereas in the sentence "all red things are red" its latter occurrence is a logical one. Nonetheless redness is a property after all. In all of this discussion then, the term "predicate" should be taken not to mean property, but rather a syntactic unit of a sentence, namely the part that remains when the subject term and the copula are deleted from that sentence. On the other hand there are other passages where it could make a lot more sense to take the term "predicate" to mean property. So in what follows, I will use the term "predicate" in the syntactic sense, and in those sections in which I interpret Kant to mean property by this term, I will prefer to simply use the term "property". Here are then two possible disambiguations of Kant's major claim that "existence is not a real predicate". Existence is not a real property. "Existence" is not a real predicate. The former claim makes no mention of terms of a language, whereas the latter is a metalinguistic claim about the English language. Now which one did Kant have in mind? Was he trying to make a syntactic/semantic claim about the use of "Sein" in the German language, or was he making a substantial philosophical and therefore a metaphysical claim? I am not sure as to how to answer this question, and it seems that Kant's text is of

4 not great help. However intuition has it that it is the former that would seem to reflect the philosophical significance of the issue. So that is the interpretation I will prefer. III The idea that what goes wrong in Descartes Ontological Argument is a misuse of the concept of existence was in fact stated by Gassendi before Kant: Existence is a perfection neither in God nor anything else; it is rather in the absence of which there is no perfection...hence neither is existence held to exist in a thing in the way that perfections do, nor if the thing lacks existence is it said to be imperfect (or deprived of perfection), so much as to be nothing. (Haldane and Ross, 1931:186) Similarly Hume also had noted that existence is not an ordinary concept that applies to an object: The idea of existence...is the very same with what we conceive to be existent. To reflect on anything simply, and to reflect on it as existent, are nothing different from each other. That idea [i.e. of existence], when conjoined with the idea of any object, makes no addition to it. (Hume, 1960: 60-67) Both philosophers seem to have anticipated Kant's thesis. In fact as we shall see one of the arguments Kant gives in support of his thesis (which I call the Epistemological Argument ) is quite close to and perhaps the same as Hume s. However as we go through his other arguments it will become clear that Kant goes well beyond both Hume and Gassendi in his discussion of the matter. I will now try to isolate three separate but inter-related arguments that I believe are inherent in Kant s discussion of his main thesis that existence is not a real property. As it is well known, the discussion is packed into a passage between paragraphs A 592/B 619 and A 603/ B 631, especially A 599/ B 627 in the Ideal of Pure Reason. None of them are explicitly stated in the text, at least not in the way I will reconstruct them. As I do so, I will provide my interpretation of certain key terms used by Kant in his text, though, some of them will no doubt be controversial. At most what I could claim is that

5 these are the most plausible ways I could think of to reconstruct these arguments in the spirit of Kant s philosophy. 5 a. The Epistemological Argument The first argument one could extract from Kant s discussion of the topic is epistemological in its nature. Though I think that it is one of the main arguments that Kant has in mind in support of his claim, he never explicitly states it. The argument runs like this: One extends his knowledge of a certain object by learning that it has a property that he did not know earlier. Learning that a certain object exists does not extend one s knowledge of that object. Therefore, existence is not a real property. Though I think that this is one of the central arguments Kant had at the back of his mind, his discussion does not contain any reference to extension of one s knowledge or some such epistemic notion. Rather his discussion seems to be, at least on the surface, more semantic regarding the deep grammar of the term existence. The crucial paragraph A599/B 627 starts off with the following line: Being is obviously not a real predicate, i.e. a concept of something that could add to the concept of a thing, and then a few sentences later he says that when Now if I take the subject (God) and say God is, then I add no new predicate to the concept of God In the next paragraph we have the same idea expressed a bit differently: Thus when I think a thing, through whichever and however many predicates I like (even in its thoroughgoing determination 6 ), not the least bit gets added to the thing when I posit in addition that this thing is. (A600/B628) And again a few sentences later he says: Even if I think in a thing every reality except one, then the missing reality does not get added when I say the thing exists... (A600/B628) In all these passages Kant makes use of a key term: adding to the concept of a thing. Similarly in various other passages Kant frequently uses the notion of the

6 expansion of a concept as well. Now did Kant sincerely subscribe to the view that concepts are these unusual entities that can expand and shrink like balloons? I believe not, for such terms ought to be taken in a metaphorical sense that refer to an mental epistemic process. For instance when Kant says that in a synthetic judgment in the subject/predicate form, the concept of the predicate enlarges the concept of the subject, it is clear that he wishes to refer to a mental phenomenon. So the enlargement of a concept is not an event that takes place in the abstract world of concepts, but rather it is what the mind does in making a synthetic judgement, namely it is through the enlargement of the concept of the subject that we extend our knowledge of the object (referred to by the subject term). Now a predicate used in a judgment that has this function is called by Kant a real predicate, the determination, as well as a determining predicate. 7 These phrases may at times not be used by Kant as synonyms, but as far as our topic is concerned they seem to add up to the same thing. In fact Kant does seem to be using them interchangeably in A596/B 624: the illusion consisting in the confusion of a logical predicate with a real one (i.e. the determination of a thing)..." and at the end of the same paragraph he says: the determination is a predicate, which goes beyond the concept of the subject and enlarges it. Now a real or determining predicate on Kant s view is a predicate that enlarges, or adds something to, the concept of the subject. In that sense a real predicate is, or denotes, a genuine property. A predicate that does not do this is called a (merely) logical predicate. From this we should not conclude that the class of predicates nicely divide up into real ones and merely logical ones, for as I said earlier Kant points out any predicate may be used as a logical one in a sentence. Having said this however, existence can never be used as a real predicate for Kant, as I read him. The main claim then is that existence is not a predicate that enlarges our concept of the subject, and I take that to imply that our knowledge of a thing does not increase when we learn that it exists. Here we run into a difficulty though. If existence is not a real predicate, then we should expect it to be a logical one given that a third category is not suggested by Kant. So assuming that existence is merely a logical predicate, and that an existential judgment does not extend our knowledge of the object in question, we may be forced to claim that all existential judgments are analytic. Note that the other example given by Kant of an

7 occurrence of a logical predicate is a sentence in which the subject is predicated of itself, a typical analytic judgment. Clearly Kant holds that existential statements are synthetic. In fact before the main discussion starts, Kant introduces this as the main puzzle to be solved. I ask you: is the proposition, This or that thing exists, an analytic or a synthetic proposition? If it is the former, then with existence you add nothing to your thought of the thing if you concede, on the contrary, as in all fairness you must, that every existential proposition is synthetic, then how would you assert that the predicate of existence may not be cancelled without a contradiction? (A598) So what Kant has to show is that unlike other predicates that are used in the logical mode, existence is a peculiar logical predicate such that when we use it in a statement we get a synthetic judgment that is in fact informative. The Epistemic Argument then should be taken not to imply that existential judgments can not extend our knowledge, but rather the extension of our knowledge is not about the object but rather something else. In other words learning that a exists does not extend our knowledge of a but it does extend our knowledge nonetheless. 8 In any case what exactly is Kant s solution to this puzzle, and even if he has one is not clear. Though as I will suggest there are certain vague passages in which Kant hints at a solution that is in the spirit of the Frege/Russell view. But before we get to that we should first look at the other two arguments Kant gives for his main thesis. b. The Conceptual Argument The second argument is purely semantic in its nature, and here we are asked to compare what may seem to be different concepts to notice that they are all one and the same. Again this argument is not stated explicitly either, and here is how it may be reconstructed: Take any concept of an object, say God, and then add existence to it, i.e. existent- God. You will notice that the two concepts will not differ in any respect. Again

8 take the initial concept, God for instance, and this time subtract existence form it, i.e. non-existent God. Again you will notice that you have not ended up with a different concept. If existence had been a real property, these concepts would have been different, and given that they are not, existence is not a real property. Now an extraction of this argument is not as easy as the first one, for it involves his notoriously difficult passage concerning his example of the hundred dollars, which includes the surprising claim that a hundred actual dollars do not contain the least bit more than a hundred possible ones. Interestingly in this crucial sentence, from which I have derived this argument, the notion of existence does not appear. Rather there is the distinction between the actual and the possible. Yet in other passages we get the distinction between the real and the merely possible. It seems that the notions of the real and the actual are used interchangeably; but what is more problematic is whether they are also used synonymously with the notion of the existent. Now elsewhere Kant does distinguish these terms, especially within his discussion of how ideas may be schematized. 9 Judging that something exists does not imply that the concept of the subject can be schematized, as in the case of God, but judging that it is actual does have that implication. This need not concern us here, for a hundred dollars is no doubt schematizable. In any case, under this interpretation whatever is real and actual is existent, but not vice versa. So at least we could take the above sentence concerning the hundred dollars, even if it is not synonymous with it, to imply the following: the concepts of existent-hundred dollars and non-existent hundred dollars have the same content.(here I have taken possible to be a shorthand for the merely possible, which is supported by the discussion in the text.) This of course is an implausible claim at first blush, for it seems clear that the two concepts cannot be substitutable for one another (salva veritate) in every sentential context. Kant is aware of the fact that his remark may be misunderstood, as he later says in the same paragraph that in my financial condition there is more with a hundred actual dollars than with the mere concept of them (i.e. their possibility.) Here Kant is distinguishing between the concept and the object that falls under the concept, and saying that what improves his financial condition is not the concept but rather the object (the actual money) that falls under the concept. If so how

9 can we make sense of the initial remark then? How could merely possible dollars have the same content as actual hundred dollars? On the surface these simply are inconsistent claims. There is a more charitable reading though: The concepts of existent-hundred dollars, and non-existent hundred dollars both include the concept of hundred dollars, nothing more and nothing less. The reason why our financial condition is improved by hundred real dollars rather than possible ones, is not because the two concepts are different, but rather in one case the money is actual (object) in the other case it isn t (the possible, i.e. the mere concept.) 10 On the surface this argument is not at all convincing, for anyone who has a prior conviction that existence is in fact a real property would not be persuaded by this argument. All that Kant says here is that the concepts of existent-hundred dollars and non-existent hundred dollars both contain the property of hundred dollars which his opponent need not disagree with. Clearly just because the two concepts have one common element does not in any way show that they are identical. Philosophers who hold that there are non-existent objects could react by saying that a hundred actual dollars have the property of existence, whereas hundred possible ones do not. 11 As we shall see now the third argument is given in support of the same claim by this time going further than the second one. So I think that the Conceptual Argument is an argument in transition, and is not intended to be conclusive. It is in the third argument that Kant offers a new piece of reason to convince us that these concepts are the same. Note that this argument is vital for Kant s thesis: given that existence is not a real property that enlarges or shrinks the concept of the subject, God, existent-god, nonexistent God should all be the one and the same concept, and obviously this is valid for all concepts not just for the concept of God. c. Different-objects Argument Here then is my reconstruction of the third argument: If the concept of F and existent-f had been different, they would have been the concepts of different things. But then when I entertain the concept of F in my

10 mind it would be impossible to find its object; for any such object would not fall under the concept F, but rather the concept of existent-f. Given that entertaining a concept and then finding its object is possible, the concept of F and existent-f must be identical. If so, then existence does not add anything to a concept, and thus it is not a real property. Again Kant makes use of the same example about the hundred dollars in this argument as well. We are to assume, for a reductio, that hundred actual dollars and hundred possible dollars are different concepts and then conclude that "...in case the former contained more than the latter, my concept would not express the entire object and thus would not be a suitable concept of it." (A599/B627) In the next paragraph the same idea is put differently: "For otherwise what would exist would not be the same as what I had thought in my concept, but more than that, and I could not say that the very object of my concept exits." (A600/B628) Here I take it that the concept of hundred actual dollars even if not synonymous with it to imply or contain the concept of existent hundred dollars. On the other hand the term possible seems to be used by Kant in some epistemic sense, which is that if a concept is possible then its object can be given in intuition, in Kant's terms. This I believe has the implication that merely entertaining a possible concept in the mind, has the implication that the entertainer of the concept does not know the object that falls under it. Let us now run the argument by making use of a simple example. Suppose I am curious about whether there is anyone in the audience who has never read Kant. In order to be curious about such an issue I need to form the concept of people in the audience who have never read Kant. To find out the answer, I could go around asking each person in the audience whether he or she has ever read Kant. Now as a result of my inquiry it would seem that I would find out the extension set of the concept. But that extension set would be that of the concept of existing people in the audience who have never read Kant as well. But if we assume that existence is a real property, then the two concepts would not be identical. If so, then their extensions should also differ. Therefore the extension I find would not be the extension of my original concept.

11 Now a crucial premise of the argument is the following: If two concepts are not identical, then their extensions would also not be identical. This, at first blush seems obviously false: Suppose, for instance, I take the concept of the youngest person in the audience and add the property of being male to it and get the concept of the youngest male in the audience; it may turn out that the two concepts are co-extensional if it happens to be the case that the youngest person in the audience is a male. So it seems that Kant wrongly presupposes here that if two concepts are different than their extensions should also differ. There is however a more charitable reading of the argument which need not presuppose this fallacious principle. Going back to the earlier example, doing an inquiry with respect to the concept of people in the audience who have never read Kant would be exactly the same as what we would do with respect to the concept we get by deleting existence form it. After all it sounds ridiculous to go up to someone in the audience and ask "do you exist, and if so have you read Kant?" Things would have been different if instead of adding existence I had added, say the property of being male to the first concept. Even if it turns out that the only people who have never read Kant in the audience are all male, making my two concepts co-extensional, the inquiry I would have to make would differ. So there is something peculiar about existence, namely, when it is added to a concept, there is a sense in which it does not expand the original concept. Therefore we are to conclude that possible hundred dollars is the same concept as existing hundred dollars, which in effect shows that existence is not a real property. IV There are of course various ways in which one may object to these arguments. It is highly unlikely that anyone who holds that there are merely possible objects would be convinced by them. There is however a greater problem for Kant. If existence is not a real property, then it does not expand or add anything to the concept of the subject. But this is an essential feature of analytic judgments. In the Introduction to the Critique he explicitly says that "analytical judgments...do not add anything to the concept of the subject". We would then have to conclude that existential judgments are also analytic, but Kant

12 obviously would not be happy with this implication for he holds that "as in all fairness you must" concede that every existential proposition is synthetic. (A598/B627) So what then accounts for the synthetic character of existential judgments? The reason why the concept of the predicate does not expand the concept of the subject in an analytic judgment is because the latter is already included in the former. For instance our concept of body already has in it the concept of being extended, which is what makes our judgment that all bodies are extended analytic. Now this does not hold for existential judgments. The judgment that trees exist is not true in virtue of the fact that the concept of tree already includes the concept of existence. So there is this kind of asymmetry between analytic and existential judgments; though they share the feature that the concept of the predicate does not expand the concept of the subject, only in analytic judgments will it be correct to say that the concept of the predicate is already included in the concept of the subject. Kant then has to give a different kind of account concerning the synthetic character of existential judgments. 12 But interestingly Kant does not even address the issue, so we need to read between the lines. Here is a passage in which there is a hint towards a solution: Now if I take the subject (God) together with all his predicates...and say God is, or there is a God, then I add no new predicate to the concept of God, but only posit the subject in itself with all its predicates, and indeed posit the object in relation to my concept. (A599/B627) 13 This is as close as Kant gets to the Frege/Russell view. Had he taken a further step, he could have said that existence is not a property of objects but rather a property of concepts, and conclude that when we judge that God exist, we judge that the concept of God has an object. This would have provided him the means to give an account of the synthetic character and thus the informativeness of existential judgments. However it seems clear to me that Kant never reached this conclusion explicitly. This is made evident by a footnote added to the second edition where he comments on Descartes' Cogito:...here existence is not yet a category, which is not related to an indeterminately given object, but rather to an object of which one has a concept, and about which one wants to know whether or not it is posited outside this concept. (B423)

13 Interestingly, after a lengthy discussion attempting to show that existence is not a real property that applies to objects, Kant seems to be saying here that existence does apply to objects in this peculiar way. If for instance I am curious about whether God exists, following this line of reasoning, I should say that what I wish to know is whether God (the object) is posited outside my concept of God. But that would make my curiosity de re, implying that existence does apply to objects. This confusion, I believe, stems from the fact that Kant never reached the idea that there may be certain predicates, and hence certain properties that apply to concepts rather than objects. Nonetheless it seems that he did come very close to the Frege/Russell view; but had he explicitly endorsed it, his slogan would not have been "'being' is not a real predicate", but rather "'being' is a special kind of predicate that applies to concepts and not objects." 1 This essay is an expanded version of a talk I gave at the International Kant Symposium organized by the Philosophy Department of Mugla University marking the two hundredth anniversary of Kant's death. I would like to thank the audience for their comments, especially Paul Guyer and Manfred Baum. I have greatly benefited from my discussions I had with Lucas Thorpe on an earlier draft. 2 See Frege (1960), especially 46ff. Frege's analysis of existence seems to involve circularity. When we analyze "F exists" as, "There is something that falls under the concept F", we appeal to existence in the analysis. In order to overcome this apparent circularity, one could say that the proper Fregean analysis of "F exists" ought to be "F is not an empty concept", where we take the concept of emptiness as being primitive, or at least one that is not analyzed further into something involving existence. 3 See Russell (1914). It seems that Russell takes the discussion further than Frege and claims that in the sentence "God exists" the term "God" cannot be a proper name. This is in fact a logical implication of Frege's view as well, though to my knowledge it was never stated explicitly by Frege. 4 A common view among historians is that it was Frege and Russell who first came up with the idea that existence is a quantifier that is a second-order concept. As I will argue, the origins of this view can be found in certain parts of the Critique of Pure Reason, whose significance I believe has been greatly ignored. An important exception is Forgie (2000), who argues that Kant clearly defended the view that existence is a second-order concept. As I will try to show, on my view Kant never clearly stated this. In his discussion Forgie takes the textual evidence for this claim mainly from the Beweisgrund (1763) which was published before the Critique, though in my talk I only took up the relevant parts of the Critique. Nonetheless it also seems to me that Forgie reads too much into what Kant says in the Beweisgrund as well; or else Kant would not have stated his main thesis as "'being' is not a real predicate". I will come back to this at the end of my essay. 5 I received no substantial reaction to my re-construction of these arguments form Kant scholars such as P. Guyer, M. Baum, and L. Thorpe. I take this to be a good sign that my interpretation is in the right track. 6 I take the "full determination" of an object to mean the concept of the object that includes all the properties of that object. 7 The determination of an object is achieved by collecting the properties of the object in a concept of it. That is why a logical predicate does not add anything to the determination of the object. 8 Perhaps Kant could have appealed to the de re/de dicto distinction that was available to him at the time, and claim that existential judgments are not de re but rather de dicto. 9 I owe this point to Lucas Thorpe. 13

14 10 After reading an earlier draft Uygar Abaci put this rather neatly: "With real hundred dollars you can buy a lot of stuff, but with merely possible ones you can only do philosophy." 11 I have in mind especially A. Meinong (1914), T. Parsons (1979), and N. Salmon (1987). Despite the fact that these philosophers differ sharply in what they say about existence, it seems they share the common view that there are merely possible, therefore non-existent objects. So it follows from their view that at least one understanding of the existence makes it a first order property that could be attributed to objects. However unlike Meinong, both Parsons and Salmon also allow for another notion of "existence" as expressing a second-order concept. On the other hand Parsons and Salmon disagree on how to individuate possible entities. 12 Everitt (2004) after clearly stating the problem claims that Kant falls into a contradiction and has no solution to offer. 13 We come across a similar passage in the "Beweisgrund": "If I say, 'God is an existing thing', it appears that I express the relation of a predicate to a subject. But there is an incorrectness in this expression. Expressed exactly, it should say: something existing is God, that is, those predicates that we designate collectively by the expression 'God' belong to an existing thing." As it can be noticed both here and in the quote in the main text, the circularity problem (see note 2) crops up, that is Kant has to appeal to the notion of "existence" in analyzing it. References: Kant, I., (1999) (first published in 1781) Critique of Pure Reason, Editors: P. Guyer, A.W. Wood, Cambridge University Press. Forgie, W., (2000) Kant and Frege: Existence as a Second-Level Property, Kantien Studien, Band 91. Frege, G., (1962) The Foundation of Arithmetic, tr. J.L. Austin, New York: Harper. Haldane & Ross, (1931) The Philosophical Writings of Descartes, London: Cambridge. Everitt, N. (2004) The Non-existence of God, London: Cambridge. Hume, D. (1960) (first published in 1888) A Treatise Concerning Human Nature, ed. L.A. Selby-Bigge, Oxford: Clarendon Press. Meinong, A. (1960) (first published in 1914) The Theory of Objects, Realism and the Background of Phenomenology, ed. R. Chisholm, New York: The Free Press. Russell, B., (1918) The Philosophy of Logical Atomism, The Monist. Parsons, T. (1979) Referring to Nonexistent Objects, Theory and Decision s , Kluwer. Salmon, N. (1987) Existence, Philosophical Perspectives 1. 14

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW DISCUSSION NOTE BY CAMPBELL BROWN JOURNAL OF ETHICS & SOCIAL PHILOSOPHY DISCUSSION NOTE MAY 2015 URL: WWW.JESP.ORG COPYRIGHT CAMPBELL BROWN 2015 Two Versions of Hume s Law MORAL CONCLUSIONS CANNOT VALIDLY

More information

PHILOSOPHICAL PROBLEMS & THE ANALYSIS OF LANGUAGE

PHILOSOPHICAL PROBLEMS & THE ANALYSIS OF LANGUAGE PHILOSOPHICAL PROBLEMS & THE ANALYSIS OF LANGUAGE Now, it is a defect of [natural] languages that expressions are possible within them, which, in their grammatical form, seemingly determined to designate

More information

Russell: On Denoting

Russell: On Denoting Russell: On Denoting DENOTING PHRASES Russell includes all kinds of quantified subject phrases ( a man, every man, some man etc.) but his main interest is in definite descriptions: the present King of

More information

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism? Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism? Author: Terence Rajivan Edward, University of Manchester. Abstract. In the sixth chapter of The View from Nowhere, Thomas Nagel attempts to identify a form of idealism.

More information

(1) a phrase may be denoting, and yet not denote anything e.g. the present King of France

(1) a phrase may be denoting, and yet not denote anything e.g. the present King of France Main Goals: Phil/Ling 375: Meaning and Mind [Handout #14] Bertrand Russell: On Denoting/Descriptions Professor JeeLoo Liu 1. To show that both Frege s and Meinong s theories are inadequate. 2. To defend

More information

From Necessary Truth to Necessary Existence

From Necessary Truth to Necessary Existence Prequel for Section 4.2 of Defending the Correspondence Theory Published by PJP VII, 1 From Necessary Truth to Necessary Existence Abstract I introduce new details in an argument for necessarily existing

More information

Skepticism and Internalism

Skepticism and Internalism Skepticism and Internalism John Greco Abstract: This paper explores a familiar skeptical problematic and considers some strategies for responding to it. Section 1 reconstructs and disambiguates the skeptical

More information

Ayer and Quine on the a priori

Ayer and Quine on the a priori Ayer and Quine on the a priori November 23, 2004 1 The problem of a priori knowledge Ayer s book is a defense of a thoroughgoing empiricism, not only about what is required for a belief to be justified

More information

1/5. The Critique of Theology

1/5. The Critique of Theology 1/5 The Critique of Theology The argument of the Transcendental Dialectic has demonstrated that there is no science of rational psychology and that the province of any rational cosmology is strictly limited.

More information

Rule-Following and the Ontology of the Mind Abstract The problem of rule-following

Rule-Following and the Ontology of the Mind Abstract The problem of rule-following Rule-Following and the Ontology of the Mind Michael Esfeld (published in Uwe Meixner and Peter Simons (eds.): Metaphysics in the Post-Metaphysical Age. Papers of the 22nd International Wittgenstein Symposium.

More information

Coordination Problems

Coordination Problems Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Vol. LXXXI No. 2, September 2010 Ó 2010 Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, LLC Coordination Problems scott soames

More information

Class 2 - The Ontological Argument

Class 2 - The Ontological Argument Philosophy 208: The Language Revolution Fall 2011 Hamilton College Russell Marcus Class 2 - The Ontological Argument I. Why the Ontological Argument Soon we will start on the language revolution proper.

More information

What is the Frege/Russell Analysis of Quantification? Scott Soames

What is the Frege/Russell Analysis of Quantification? Scott Soames What is the Frege/Russell Analysis of Quantification? Scott Soames The Frege-Russell analysis of quantification was a fundamental advance in semantics and philosophical logic. Abstracting away from details

More information

1/12. The A Paralogisms

1/12. The A Paralogisms 1/12 The A Paralogisms The character of the Paralogisms is described early in the chapter. Kant describes them as being syllogisms which contain no empirical premises and states that in them we conclude

More information

Understanding Belief Reports. David Braun. In this paper, I defend a well-known theory of belief reports from an important objection.

Understanding Belief Reports. David Braun. In this paper, I defend a well-known theory of belief reports from an important objection. Appeared in Philosophical Review 105 (1998), pp. 555-595. Understanding Belief Reports David Braun In this paper, I defend a well-known theory of belief reports from an important objection. The theory

More information

Empty Names and Two-Valued Positive Free Logic

Empty Names and Two-Valued Positive Free Logic Empty Names and Two-Valued Positive Free Logic 1 Introduction Zahra Ahmadianhosseini In order to tackle the problem of handling empty names in logic, Andrew Bacon (2013) takes on an approach based on positive

More information

Curiosity and Ignorance

Curiosity and Ignorance Croatian Journal of Philosophy Vol. XVI, No. 48, 2016 Curiosity and Ignorance ILHAN INAN Department of Philosophy, Boğaziçi University, Istanbul, Turkey Though ignorance is rarely a bliss, awareness of

More information

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory Western University Scholarship@Western 2015 Undergraduate Awards The Undergraduate Awards 2015 Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory David Hakim Western University, davidhakim266@gmail.com

More information

Definite Descriptions and the Argument from Inference

Definite Descriptions and the Argument from Inference Philosophia (2014) 42:1099 1109 DOI 10.1007/s11406-014-9519-9 Definite Descriptions and the Argument from Inference Wojciech Rostworowski Received: 20 November 2013 / Revised: 29 January 2014 / Accepted:

More information

This is a longer version of the review that appeared in Philosophical Quarterly Vol. 47 (1997)

This is a longer version of the review that appeared in Philosophical Quarterly Vol. 47 (1997) This is a longer version of the review that appeared in Philosophical Quarterly Vol. 47 (1997) Frege by Anthony Kenny (Penguin, 1995. Pp. xi + 223) Frege s Theory of Sense and Reference by Wolfgang Carl

More information

Bertrand Russell Proper Names, Adjectives and Verbs 1

Bertrand Russell Proper Names, Adjectives and Verbs 1 Bertrand Russell Proper Names, Adjectives and Verbs 1 Analysis 46 Philosophical grammar can shed light on philosophical questions. Grammatical differences can be used as a source of discovery and a guide

More information

A Problem for a Direct-Reference Theory of Belief Reports. Stephen Schiffer New York University

A Problem for a Direct-Reference Theory of Belief Reports. Stephen Schiffer New York University A Problem for a Direct-Reference Theory of Belief Reports Stephen Schiffer New York University The direct-reference theory of belief reports to which I allude is the one held by such theorists as Nathan

More information

Quine on the analytic/synthetic distinction

Quine on the analytic/synthetic distinction Quine on the analytic/synthetic distinction Jeff Speaks March 14, 2005 1 Analyticity and synonymy.............................. 1 2 Synonymy and definition ( 2)............................ 2 3 Synonymy

More information

Class #3 - Meinong and Mill

Class #3 - Meinong and Mill Philosophy 308: The Language Revolution Fall 2014 Hamilton College Russell Marcus Class #3 - Meinong and Mill 1. Meinongian Subsistence The work of the Moderns on language shows us a problem arising in

More information

ILLOCUTIONARY ORIGINS OF FAMILIAR LOGICAL OPERATORS

ILLOCUTIONARY ORIGINS OF FAMILIAR LOGICAL OPERATORS ILLOCUTIONARY ORIGINS OF FAMILIAR LOGICAL OPERATORS 1. ACTS OF USING LANGUAGE Illocutionary logic is the logic of speech acts, or language acts. Systems of illocutionary logic have both an ontological,

More information

Early Russell on Philosophical Grammar

Early Russell on Philosophical Grammar Early Russell on Philosophical Grammar G. J. Mattey Fall, 2005 / Philosophy 156 Philosophical Grammar The study of grammar, in my opinion, is capable of throwing far more light on philosophical questions

More information

Leibniz, Principles, and Truth 1

Leibniz, Principles, and Truth 1 Leibniz, Principles, and Truth 1 Leibniz was a man of principles. 2 Throughout his writings, one finds repeated assertions that his view is developed according to certain fundamental principles. Attempting

More information

15. Russell on definite descriptions

15. Russell on definite descriptions 15. Russell on definite descriptions Martín Abreu Zavaleta July 30, 2015 Russell was another top logician and philosopher of his time. Like Frege, Russell got interested in denotational expressions as

More information

Theories of propositions

Theories of propositions Theories of propositions phil 93515 Jeff Speaks January 16, 2007 1 Commitment to propositions.......................... 1 2 A Fregean theory of reference.......................... 2 3 Three theories of

More information

Philosophy 203 History of Modern Western Philosophy. Russell Marcus Hamilton College Spring 2011

Philosophy 203 History of Modern Western Philosophy. Russell Marcus Hamilton College Spring 2011 Philosophy 203 History of Modern Western Philosophy Russell Marcus Hamilton College Spring 2011 Class 28 - May 5 First Antinomy On the Ontological Argument Marcus, Modern Philosophy, Slide 1 Business P

More information

[3.] Bertrand Russell. 1

[3.] Bertrand Russell. 1 [3.] Bertrand Russell. 1 [3.1.] Biographical Background. 1872: born in the city of Trellech, in the county of Monmouthshire, now part of Wales 2 One of his grandfathers was Lord John Russell, who twice

More information

Chadwick Prize Winner: Christian Michel THE LIAR PARADOX OUTSIDE-IN

Chadwick Prize Winner: Christian Michel THE LIAR PARADOX OUTSIDE-IN Chadwick Prize Winner: Christian Michel THE LIAR PARADOX OUTSIDE-IN To classify sentences like This proposition is false as having no truth value or as nonpropositions is generally considered as being

More information

Epistemic Contextualism as a Theory of Primary Speaker Meaning

Epistemic Contextualism as a Theory of Primary Speaker Meaning Epistemic Contextualism as a Theory of Primary Speaker Meaning Gilbert Harman, Princeton University June 30, 2006 Jason Stanley s Knowledge and Practical Interests is a brilliant book, combining insights

More information

Does Deduction really rest on a more secure epistemological footing than Induction?

Does Deduction really rest on a more secure epistemological footing than Induction? Does Deduction really rest on a more secure epistemological footing than Induction? We argue that, if deduction is taken to at least include classical logic (CL, henceforth), justifying CL - and thus deduction

More information

From Transcendental Logic to Transcendental Deduction

From Transcendental Logic to Transcendental Deduction From Transcendental Logic to Transcendental Deduction Let me see if I can say a few things to re-cap our first discussion of the Transcendental Logic, and help you get a foothold for what follows. Kant

More information

Cognitive Significance, Attitude Ascriptions, and Ways of Believing Propositions. David Braun. University of Rochester

Cognitive Significance, Attitude Ascriptions, and Ways of Believing Propositions. David Braun. University of Rochester Cognitive Significance, Attitude Ascriptions, and Ways of Believing Propositions by David Braun University of Rochester Presented at the Pacific APA in San Francisco on March 31, 2001 1. Naive Russellianism

More information

The Ontological Argument

The Ontological Argument The Ontological Argument Arguments for God s Existence One of the classic questions of philosophy and philosophical argument is: s there a God? Of course there are and have been many different definitions

More information

Varieties of Apriority

Varieties of Apriority S E V E N T H E X C U R S U S Varieties of Apriority T he notions of a priori knowledge and justification play a central role in this work. There are many ways in which one can understand the a priori,

More information

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras Module - 28 Lecture - 28 Linguistic turn in British philosophy

More information

Remarks on a Foundationalist Theory of Truth. Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh

Remarks on a Foundationalist Theory of Truth. Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh For Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Remarks on a Foundationalist Theory of Truth Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh I Tim Maudlin s Truth and Paradox offers a theory of truth that arises from

More information

Russell on Descriptions

Russell on Descriptions Russell on Descriptions Bertrand Russell s analysis of descriptions is certainly one of the most famous (perhaps the most famous) theories in philosophy not just philosophy of language over the last century.

More information

Wright on response-dependence and self-knowledge

Wright on response-dependence and self-knowledge Wright on response-dependence and self-knowledge March 23, 2004 1 Response-dependent and response-independent concepts........... 1 1.1 The intuitive distinction......................... 1 1.2 Basic equations

More information

Why the Traditional Conceptions of Propositions can t be Correct

Why the Traditional Conceptions of Propositions can t be Correct Why the Traditional Conceptions of Propositions can t be Correct By Scott Soames USC School of Philosophy Chapter 3 New Thinking about Propositions By Jeff King, Scott Soames, Jeff Speaks Oxford University

More information

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori PHIL 83104 November 2, 2011 Both Boghossian and Harman address themselves to the question of whether our a priori knowledge can be explained in

More information

Millian responses to Frege s puzzle

Millian responses to Frege s puzzle Millian responses to Frege s puzzle phil 93914 Jeff Speaks February 28, 2008 1 Two kinds of Millian................................. 1 2 Conciliatory Millianism............................... 2 2.1 Hidden

More information

OSSA Conference Archive OSSA 3

OSSA Conference Archive OSSA 3 University of Windsor Scholarship at UWindsor OSSA Conference Archive OSSA 3 May 15th, 9:00 AM - May 17th, 5:00 PM Commentary on Schwed Lawrence Powers Follow this and additional works at: https://scholar.uwindsor.ca/ossaarchive

More information

1/10. The Fourth Paralogism and the Refutation of Idealism

1/10. The Fourth Paralogism and the Refutation of Idealism 1/10 The Fourth Paralogism and the Refutation of Idealism The Fourth Paralogism is quite different from the three that preceded it because, although it is treated as a part of rational psychology, it main

More information

Copyright 2015 by KAD International All rights reserved. Published in the Ghana

Copyright 2015 by KAD International All rights reserved. Published in the Ghana Copyright 2015 by KAD International All rights reserved. Published in the Ghana http://kadint.net/our-journal.html The Problem of the Truth of the Counterfactual Conditionals in the Context of Modal Realism

More information

Faults and Mathematical Disagreement

Faults and Mathematical Disagreement 45 Faults and Mathematical Disagreement María Ponte ILCLI. University of the Basque Country mariaponteazca@gmail.com Abstract: My aim in this paper is to analyse the notion of mathematical disagreements

More information

Ayer s linguistic theory of the a priori

Ayer s linguistic theory of the a priori Ayer s linguistic theory of the a priori phil 43904 Jeff Speaks December 4, 2007 1 The problem of a priori knowledge....................... 1 2 Necessity and the a priori............................ 2

More information

PHILOSOPHY OF LOGIC AND LANGUAGE OVERVIEW FREGE JONNY MCINTOSH 1. FREGE'S CONCEPTION OF LOGIC

PHILOSOPHY OF LOGIC AND LANGUAGE OVERVIEW FREGE JONNY MCINTOSH 1. FREGE'S CONCEPTION OF LOGIC PHILOSOPHY OF LOGIC AND LANGUAGE JONNY MCINTOSH 1. FREGE'S CONCEPTION OF LOGIC OVERVIEW These lectures cover material for paper 108, Philosophy of Logic and Language. They will focus on issues in philosophy

More information

Todays programme. Background of the TLP. Some problems in TLP. Frege Russell. Saying and showing. Sense and nonsense Logic The limits of language

Todays programme. Background of the TLP. Some problems in TLP. Frege Russell. Saying and showing. Sense and nonsense Logic The limits of language Todays programme Background of the TLP Frege Russell Some problems in TLP Saying and showing Sense and nonsense Logic The limits of language 1 TLP, preface How far my efforts agree with those of other

More information

PHILOSOPHY 4360/5360 METAPHYSICS. Methods that Metaphysicians Use

PHILOSOPHY 4360/5360 METAPHYSICS. Methods that Metaphysicians Use PHILOSOPHY 4360/5360 METAPHYSICS Methods that Metaphysicians Use Method 1: The appeal to what one can imagine where imagining some state of affairs involves forming a vivid image of that state of affairs.

More information

Logic -type questions

Logic -type questions Logic -type questions [For use in the Philosophy Test and the Philosophy section of the MLAT] One of the questions on a test may take the form of a logic exercise, starting with the definition of a key

More information

The Referential and the Attributive : Two Distinctions for the Price of One İlhan İnan

The Referential and the Attributive : Two Distinctions for the Price of One İlhan İnan The Referential and the Attributive : Two Distinctions for the Price of One İlhan İnan ABSTRACT There are two sorts of singular terms for which we have difficulty applying Donnellan s referential/attributive

More information

Action in Special Contexts

Action in Special Contexts Part III Action in Special Contexts c36.indd 283 c36.indd 284 36 Rationality john broome Rationality as a Property and Rationality as a Source of Requirements The word rationality often refers to a property

More information

The Representation of Logical Form: A Dilemma

The Representation of Logical Form: A Dilemma The Representation of Logical Form: A Dilemma Benjamin Ferguson 1 Introduction Throughout the Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus and especially in the 2.17 s and 4.1 s Wittgenstein asserts that propositions

More information

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. Tractatus 6.3751 Author(s): Edwin B. Allaire Source: Analysis, Vol. 19, No. 5 (Apr., 1959), pp. 100-105 Published by: Oxford University Press on behalf of The Analysis Committee Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/3326898

More information

Phil 435: Philosophy of Language. [Handout 7] W. V. Quine, Quantifiers and Propositional Attitudes (1956)

Phil 435: Philosophy of Language. [Handout 7] W. V. Quine, Quantifiers and Propositional Attitudes (1956) Quine & Kripke 1 Phil 435: Philosophy of Language [Handout 7] Quine & Kripke Reporting Beliefs Professor JeeLoo Liu W. V. Quine, Quantifiers and Propositional Attitudes (1956) * The problem: The logical

More information

Review Tutorial (A Whirlwind Tour of Metaphysics, Epistemology and Philosophy of Religion)

Review Tutorial (A Whirlwind Tour of Metaphysics, Epistemology and Philosophy of Religion) Review Tutorial (A Whirlwind Tour of Metaphysics, Epistemology and Philosophy of Religion) Arguably, the main task of philosophy is to seek the truth. We seek genuine knowledge. This is why epistemology

More information

Russell on Denoting. G. J. Mattey. Fall, 2005 / Philosophy 156. The concept any finite number is not odd, nor is it even.

Russell on Denoting. G. J. Mattey. Fall, 2005 / Philosophy 156. The concept any finite number is not odd, nor is it even. Russell on Denoting G. J. Mattey Fall, 2005 / Philosophy 156 Denoting in The Principles of Mathematics This notion [denoting] lies at the bottom (I think) of all theories of substance, of the subject-predicate

More information

Logic and Existence. Steve Kuhn Department of Philosophy Georgetown University

Logic and Existence. Steve Kuhn Department of Philosophy Georgetown University Logic and Existence Steve Kuhn Department of Philosophy Georgetown University Can existence be proved by analysis and logic? Are there merely possible objects? Is existence a predicate? Could there be

More information

In Reference and Definite Descriptions, Keith Donnellan makes a

In Reference and Definite Descriptions, Keith Donnellan makes a Aporia vol. 16 no. 1 2006 Donnellan s Distinction: Pragmatic or Semantic Importance? ALAN FEUERLEIN In Reference and Definite Descriptions, Keith Donnellan makes a distinction between attributive and referential

More information

Can logical consequence be deflated?

Can logical consequence be deflated? Can logical consequence be deflated? Michael De University of Utrecht Department of Philosophy Utrecht, Netherlands mikejde@gmail.com in Insolubles and Consequences : essays in honour of Stephen Read,

More information

Epistemic two-dimensionalism

Epistemic two-dimensionalism Epistemic two-dimensionalism phil 93507 Jeff Speaks December 1, 2009 1 Four puzzles.......................................... 1 2 Epistemic two-dimensionalism................................ 3 2.1 Two-dimensional

More information

Comments on Van Inwagen s Inside and Outside the Ontology Room. Trenton Merricks

Comments on Van Inwagen s Inside and Outside the Ontology Room. Trenton Merricks Comments on Van Inwagen s Inside and Outside the Ontology Room Trenton Merricks These comments were presented as part of an exchange with Peter van Inwagen in January of 2014 during the California Metaphysics

More information

Kripke s famous thesis that proper names are rigid designators is accepted by many and

Kripke s famous thesis that proper names are rigid designators is accepted by many and Rigid General Terms and Essential Predicates Ilhan Inan Published in Philosophical Studies, 140:213 228, 2008. Kripke s famous thesis that proper names are rigid designators is accepted by many and contested

More information

Resemblance Nominalism and counterparts

Resemblance Nominalism and counterparts ANAL63-3 4/15/2003 2:40 PM Page 221 Resemblance Nominalism and counterparts Alexander Bird 1. Introduction In his (2002) Gonzalo Rodriguez-Pereyra provides a powerful articulation of the claim that Resemblance

More information

1 John Hawthorne s terrific comments contain a specifically Talmudic contribution: his suggested alternative interpretation of Rashi s position. Let m

1 John Hawthorne s terrific comments contain a specifically Talmudic contribution: his suggested alternative interpretation of Rashi s position. Let m 1 John Hawthorne s terrific comments contain a specifically Talmudic contribution: his suggested alternative interpretation of Rashi s position. Let me begin by addressing that. There are three important

More information

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction Kent State University BIBLID [0873-626X (2014) 39; pp. 139-145] Abstract The causal theory of reference (CTR) provides a well-articulated and widely-accepted account

More information

Logical Mistakes, Logical Aliens, and the Laws of Kant's Pure General Logic Chicago February 21 st 2018 Tyke Nunez

Logical Mistakes, Logical Aliens, and the Laws of Kant's Pure General Logic Chicago February 21 st 2018 Tyke Nunez Logical Mistakes, Logical Aliens, and the Laws of Kant's Pure General Logic Chicago February 21 st 2018 Tyke Nunez 1 Introduction (1) Normativists: logic's laws are unconditional norms for how we ought

More information

Based on the translation by E. M. Edghill, with minor emendations by Daniel Kolak.

Based on the translation by E. M. Edghill, with minor emendations by Daniel Kolak. On Interpretation By Aristotle Based on the translation by E. M. Edghill, with minor emendations by Daniel Kolak. First we must define the terms 'noun' and 'verb', then the terms 'denial' and 'affirmation',

More information

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy Res Cogitans Volume 5 Issue 1 Article 20 6-4-2014 Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy Kevin Harriman Lewis & Clark College Follow this and additional works at: http://commons.pacificu.edu/rescogitans

More information

Overview. Is there a priori knowledge? No: Mill, Quine. Is there synthetic a priori knowledge? Yes: faculty of a priori intuition (Rationalism, Kant)

Overview. Is there a priori knowledge? No: Mill, Quine. Is there synthetic a priori knowledge? Yes: faculty of a priori intuition (Rationalism, Kant) Overview Is there a priori knowledge? Is there synthetic a priori knowledge? No: Mill, Quine Yes: faculty of a priori intuition (Rationalism, Kant) No: all a priori knowledge analytic (Ayer) No A Priori

More information

Who or what is God?, asks John Hick (Hick 2009). A theist might answer: God is an infinite person, or at least an

Who or what is God?, asks John Hick (Hick 2009). A theist might answer: God is an infinite person, or at least an John Hick on whether God could be an infinite person Daniel Howard-Snyder Western Washington University Abstract: "Who or what is God?," asks John Hick. A theist might answer: God is an infinite person,

More information

Comments on Truth at A World for Modal Propositions

Comments on Truth at A World for Modal Propositions Comments on Truth at A World for Modal Propositions Christopher Menzel Texas A&M University March 16, 2008 Since Arthur Prior first made us aware of the issue, a lot of philosophical thought has gone into

More information

Kripke on the distinctness of the mind from the body

Kripke on the distinctness of the mind from the body Kripke on the distinctness of the mind from the body Jeff Speaks April 13, 2005 At pp. 144 ff., Kripke turns his attention to the mind-body problem. The discussion here brings to bear many of the results

More information

What is the Nature of Logic? Judy Pelham Philosophy, York University, Canada July 16, 2013 Pan-Hellenic Logic Symposium Athens, Greece

What is the Nature of Logic? Judy Pelham Philosophy, York University, Canada July 16, 2013 Pan-Hellenic Logic Symposium Athens, Greece What is the Nature of Logic? Judy Pelham Philosophy, York University, Canada July 16, 2013 Pan-Hellenic Logic Symposium Athens, Greece Outline of this Talk 1. What is the nature of logic? Some history

More information

(1) A phrase may be denoting, and yet not denote anything; e.g., 'the present King of France'.

(1) A phrase may be denoting, and yet not denote anything; e.g., 'the present King of France'. On Denoting By Russell Based on the 1903 article By a 'denoting phrase' I mean a phrase such as any one of the following: a man, some man, any man, every man, all men, the present King of England, the

More information

THE SEMANTIC REALISM OF STROUD S RESPONSE TO AUSTIN S ARGUMENT AGAINST SCEPTICISM

THE SEMANTIC REALISM OF STROUD S RESPONSE TO AUSTIN S ARGUMENT AGAINST SCEPTICISM SKÉPSIS, ISSN 1981-4194, ANO VII, Nº 14, 2016, p. 33-39. THE SEMANTIC REALISM OF STROUD S RESPONSE TO AUSTIN S ARGUMENT AGAINST SCEPTICISM ALEXANDRE N. MACHADO Universidade Federal do Paraná (UFPR) Email:

More information

Logical Foundations of Metaphysics

Logical Foundations of Metaphysics 1 Logical Foundations of Metaphysics IUC - Dubrovnik, Croatia 21-26 May 2007 Hume s Principle and Sortal Concepts Majda Trobok, trobok@ffri.hr 1. Introduction. In this talk I try to evaluate the neo-fregeans

More information

5 A Modal Version of the

5 A Modal Version of the 5 A Modal Version of the Ontological Argument E. J. L O W E Moreland, J. P.; Sweis, Khaldoun A.; Meister, Chad V., Jul 01, 2013, Debating Christian Theism The original version of the ontological argument

More information

Buck-Passers Negative Thesis

Buck-Passers Negative Thesis Mark Schroeder November 27, 2006 University of Southern California Buck-Passers Negative Thesis [B]eing valuable is not a property that provides us with reasons. Rather, to call something valuable is to

More information

WHAT DOES KRIPKE MEAN BY A PRIORI?

WHAT DOES KRIPKE MEAN BY A PRIORI? Diametros nr 28 (czerwiec 2011): 1-7 WHAT DOES KRIPKE MEAN BY A PRIORI? Pierre Baumann In Naming and Necessity (1980), Kripke stressed the importance of distinguishing three different pairs of notions:

More information

Philosophy of Mathematics Kant

Philosophy of Mathematics Kant Philosophy of Mathematics Kant Owen Griffiths oeg21@cam.ac.uk St John s College, Cambridge 20/10/15 Immanuel Kant Born in 1724 in Königsberg, Prussia. Enrolled at the University of Königsberg in 1740 and

More information

Kant On The A Priority of Space: A Critique Arjun Sawhney - The University of Toronto pp. 4-7

Kant On The A Priority of Space: A Critique Arjun Sawhney - The University of Toronto pp. 4-7 Issue 1 Spring 2016 Undergraduate Journal of Philosophy Kant On The A Priority of Space: A Critique Arjun Sawhney - The University of Toronto pp. 4-7 For details of submission dates and guidelines please

More information

Ethical non-naturalism

Ethical non-naturalism Michael Lacewing Ethical non-naturalism Ethical non-naturalism is usually understood as a form of cognitivist moral realism. So we first need to understand what cognitivism and moral realism is before

More information

S T A TE THE REFERENTIAL AND THE ATTRIBUTIVE : TWO DISTINCTIONS FOR THE PRICE OF ONE 1

S T A TE THE REFERENTIAL AND THE ATTRIBUTIVE : TWO DISTINCTIONS FOR THE PRICE OF ONE 1 S T A TE THE REFERENTIAL AND THE ATTRIBUTIVE : TWO DISTINCTIONS FOR THE PRICE OF ONE 1 İlhan İNAN There are two sorts of singular terms for which we have difficulty applying Donnellan s referential/attributive

More information

BOOK REVIEWS. Duke University. The Philosophical Review, Vol. XCVII, No. 1 (January 1988)

BOOK REVIEWS. Duke University. The Philosophical Review, Vol. XCVII, No. 1 (January 1988) manner that provokes the student into careful and critical thought on these issues, then this book certainly gets that job done. On the other hand, one likes to think (imagine or hope) that the very best

More information

Molnar on Truthmakers for Negative Truths

Molnar on Truthmakers for Negative Truths Molnar on Truthmakers for Negative Truths Nils Kürbis Dept of Philosophy, King s College London Penultimate draft, forthcoming in Metaphysica. The final publication is available at www.reference-global.com

More information

Class 33 - November 13 Philosophy Friday #6: Quine and Ontological Commitment Fisher 59-69; Quine, On What There Is

Class 33 - November 13 Philosophy Friday #6: Quine and Ontological Commitment Fisher 59-69; Quine, On What There Is Philosophy 240: Symbolic Logic Fall 2009 Mondays, Wednesdays, Fridays: 9am - 9:50am Hamilton College Russell Marcus rmarcus1@hamilton.edu I. The riddle of non-being Two basic philosophical questions are:

More information

A Liar Paradox. Richard G. Heck, Jr. Brown University

A Liar Paradox. Richard G. Heck, Jr. Brown University A Liar Paradox Richard G. Heck, Jr. Brown University It is widely supposed nowadays that, whatever the right theory of truth may be, it needs to satisfy a principle sometimes known as transparency : Any

More information

It doesn t take long in reading the Critique before we are faced with interpretive challenges. Consider the very first sentence in the A edition:

It doesn t take long in reading the Critique before we are faced with interpretive challenges. Consider the very first sentence in the A edition: The Preface(s) to the Critique of Pure Reason It doesn t take long in reading the Critique before we are faced with interpretive challenges. Consider the very first sentence in the A edition: Human reason

More information

Rationalism. A. He, like others at the time, was obsessed with questions of truth and doubt

Rationalism. A. He, like others at the time, was obsessed with questions of truth and doubt Rationalism I. Descartes (1596-1650) A. He, like others at the time, was obsessed with questions of truth and doubt 1. How could one be certain in the absence of religious guidance and trustworthy senses

More information

Introductory Kant Seminar Lecture

Introductory Kant Seminar Lecture Introductory Kant Seminar Lecture Intentionality It is not unusual to begin a discussion of Kant with a brief review of some history of philosophy. What is perhaps less usual is to start with a review

More information

MULTI-PEER DISAGREEMENT AND THE PREFACE PARADOX. Kenneth Boyce and Allan Hazlett

MULTI-PEER DISAGREEMENT AND THE PREFACE PARADOX. Kenneth Boyce and Allan Hazlett MULTI-PEER DISAGREEMENT AND THE PREFACE PARADOX Kenneth Boyce and Allan Hazlett Abstract The problem of multi-peer disagreement concerns the reasonable response to a situation in which you believe P1 Pn

More information

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras Module - 21 Lecture - 21 Kant Forms of sensibility Categories

More information

part one MACROSTRUCTURE Cambridge University Press X - A Theory of Argument Mark Vorobej Excerpt More information

part one MACROSTRUCTURE Cambridge University Press X - A Theory of Argument Mark Vorobej Excerpt More information part one MACROSTRUCTURE 1 Arguments 1.1 Authors and Audiences An argument is a social activity, the goal of which is interpersonal rational persuasion. More precisely, we ll say that an argument occurs

More information

Broad on Theological Arguments. I. The Ontological Argument

Broad on Theological Arguments. I. The Ontological Argument Broad on God Broad on Theological Arguments I. The Ontological Argument Sample Ontological Argument: Suppose that God is the most perfect or most excellent being. Consider two things: (1)An entity that

More information

Lecture 4. Before beginning the present lecture, I should give the solution to the homework problem

Lecture 4. Before beginning the present lecture, I should give the solution to the homework problem 1 Lecture 4 Before beginning the present lecture, I should give the solution to the homework problem posed in the last lecture: how, within the framework of coordinated content, might we define the notion

More information