Moral Education or Social Institution?

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Moral Education or Social Institution?"

Transcription

1 Moral Education or Social Institution? (Kent State Graduate Conference, 2013) Abstract: On a plausible account of moral education the purpose of teaching ethics is to inculcate genuine moral virtues within persons. Moral education is for the sake of truly moral people, truly moral people have moral characters, and moral characters require genuine virtues; hence the need for a robust virtue ethics. This conception is under harsh attack, however, by a social psychological tradition and by many philosophers as well. Situationists recommend in place of moral education a program emphasizing the production of certain forms of socialization. Behaviors are all that are of concern. I suggest, however, that this taken as a sufficient account of morality is seriously lacking when moral education is at stake. A plausible apriori defense of the coherency of virtue ethics, and thus the proper conception of virtue, can be given such that genuine moral education is unaffected by situationist criticism. (word count: 3732) 1. Introduction By moral education I mean to promote the creation of genuinely moral people; anything less is to fall short of the ideal of a moral life. This plausibly implies that the most straightforward approach to moral education involves a form of robust virtue theory. Moral education is for the sake of truly moral people, truly moral people have moral characters, and moral characters require genuine virtues; hence the need for a robust virtue ethics. This conception is under attack by a social psychological tradition. The "situationist" approach, championed by Gilbert Harman, John Doris, and others, purports to demonstrate that genuine moral character is a fiction. 1 Behavior, it is claimed, results from situations not from persons and, as a result, any robust form of virtue theory is impossible. If this is the case then moral education is misguided or impossible. Situationists recommend in place of moral education a program emphasizing the production of certain forms of socialization. They propose to put in place a system of social institutions where persons can be coaxed into "moral behavior"; to focus on social institutions that bring about "social harmony" and "socialized" people. Importantly, moral behavior on this account has no place, or need, for genuine moral character. Behaviors are all that are of concern. Herein I am not concerned with the specific details of moral education, or of a program of socialization however that may go; rather, I am concerned with the possibility of moral education as opposed to socialization and shall keep the discussion at this level. I suggest that the situationist approach taken as sufficient is seriously lacking when moral education is at stake. An empirical approach is not enough. 2 This can be seen by presenting 1 As Julia Annas points out, Although it is never brought out into the open and discussed, some of the relevant literature here seems to be assuming that the scientific attitude of interpreting the behaviour of others has a kind of obvious and unquestionable authority, such that it does not matter that it fails to take into account sources of information such as the agent s own account of her actions. Annas, Virtue Ethics and Social Psychology. Apriori 2 (2003): 20-34, (23). 2 If for no better reason than that genuine moral education seems to be desperately needed and, truly, only possible if something like moral character is real. What is truly maddening about deflationisms, of all sorts but especially in this discussion, is that the philosophers who buy into deflated concepts take themselves as thereby excused from discussing facts about character and practical reasoning (facts demonstrated by 1 Page

2 several initial responses as to the mistaken characterization of virtue presented by situationists. These concerns give credence to and depend upon a further: that a plausible apriori defense of the coherency of virtue ethics, and thus the proper conception of virtue, can be given. I am defending a plausible account of virtue ethics from social psychology, so that a plausible account of moral education is found possible. If this is correct, then we can have robust virtue ethics and moral education rather than mere socialization. 2. Situationism Characterized Situationism arrives at a key claim concerning human behavior and character traits, since seemingly incidental or trivial features of situations disrupt allegedly stable character traits. As John Sabini and Maury Silver describe it, situationism holds that morally significant behavior is affected by the immediate situational features which: 1. are not in themselves of moral significance; 2. are not, prima facie, of great motivational significance; 3. are not well known either to laypeople or to the philosophical literature; 4, are numerous; and 5. do not form a coherent class from the point of view of folk psychology. 3 This suggests that, as Doris states,...behavior is contra the old saw about character and destiny extraordinarily sensitive to variation in circumstance. 4 Relatively minor situation manipulation can have a significant influence on a person s moral behavior and, contrary to expectations, a person will behave differently across contexts where the behavior should be consistent. 3. The Challenge It is important to understand what situationists understand by character. Doris gives the most helpful and complete criterion: globalism. Globalism is the claim that as traditionally understood character is an evaluatively integrated association of robust traits. By this Doris means that character must meet three criteria: (1) Consistency. Character and personality traits are reliably manifested in traitrelevant behavior across a diversity of trait-relevant eliciting conditions that may vary widely in their conduciveness to the manifestation of the trait in question. (2) Stability. Character and personality traits are reliably manifested in trait-relevant behaviors over iterated trials of similar trait-relevant eliciting conditions. (3) Evaluative integration. In a given character or personality the occurrence of a our perceived moral experience). This is particularly clear in the dialogue between Harman and Athanassoulis, where the latter gives demonstrable evidence that we have very good theories (namely, Aristotelian) of character and moral development. Harman simply responds by denying that there are character traits, simpliciter, with no discussion of Aristotelian theoretical points. Annas discusses this at Virtue Ethics and Social Psychology, 23. As she is apt to point out, this entire knee-jerk deference to science is simply begging the question. 3 John Sabini and Maury Silver, Lack of Character? Situationism Critiqued. Ethics 115 (2005) (545). 4 Doris, Lack of Character: Personality and Moral Behavior, 2. 2 Page

3 trait with a particular evaluative valence is probabilistically related to the occurrence of other traits with similar evaluative valences. 5 Notice that the key here is trait-relevant behavior, elicited by trait-relevant conditions. If there is character as traditionally understood, and needed by any strong theory of virtue, then we should expect empirical confirmation of intra-trait consistency, e.g. consistently cheating, or not, on tests, and inter-trait consistency, e.g. the honest person will also not steal and will keep their promises, be courageous, etc. The argument that Doris proposes can be summed up, then, as the following. 6 Robust-global character traits, commonly known as the virtues or vices, are taken to be an adequate normative account of human action; as such moral agents should demonstrate trait-relevant behavior in a wide variety of trait-relevant and eliciting situations. The empirical evidence demonstrates that for the most part agents do not display trait-relevant behavior across a wide variety of situations; rather, it shows highly local consistency. People simply do not seem to have globalist-like character. Thus, virtues robust character traits cannot give an adequate normative foundation for a theory of ethics Initial Responses Rather than directly attack the credibility of each experiment, or the interpretations given of their, as many already have done, I will offer several general responses intended to cut-across the research Aristotle, whom it is natural to think of in this connection, was well aware that situations could affect people s actions. Virtue ends up being a rare phenomenon, but that is 5 Ibid, 22. Doris claims that, Taken together, these theses construe personality as more or less coherent and integrated with reliable, relatively situation-resistant, behavioral implications. Ibid. 6 I borrow this formulation from Michael Winter and John Tauer, Virtue Theory and Social Psychology. The Journal of Value Inquiry 40 (2006): The situationists reject a globalist view of character traits. Human nature is not such that people can withstand situational pressures and behave consistently across situations. But, according to virtue ethics, morality is concerned with the cultivation of character traits with certain properties, i.e. virtues. The implication for virtue ethics is that such theories are empirically inadequate, given that they require global character traits. Virtues, according the situationists, just are global character traits indicating certain activity and, given the empirical evidence to the contrary, the theories are either false or lacking appropriate evidence. Since we are unable to consistently predict behavior, character traits are local, not global: they lack consistency and stability. That is, we can no longer talk of character as such or virtue as such (e.g. honest, truthful, etc.) but only local, specific traits and virtues (e.g. honest in his business dealings, truthful in her examination practices, etc.). Character is fragmented among highly specific and situation sensitive local traits, and hence Doris third criterion for globalism is not met. What is more, people are supposed to act from character; it is taken to be efficacious. Situations, though, not character, seem to be driving behavior. Hence, the explanatory role of character is taken away and character does not appear to be efficacious. If character is merely of the local variety, however, then a theory of ethics that focuses on robust character development and the normative dimension of character, such as classic virtue ethics, is defeated. But, if this last is true then the plausible case for moral education in terms of genuine character development within moral persons is lost. 8 For direct criticisms of the interpretation of the experiments, see the articles by Sreenivasan, Miller, Kamtekar, Sabini and Silver, and Athanassoulis. 3 Page

4 hardly surprising. 9 Rather than disconfirming virtue much of the social psychology experimentation confirms what virtue ethicists actually say: it takes effort, difficulty, and a lifetime for some traits to gain the right character. 10 Now, this can be seen as a retreat from the situationist s claim, and indeed it is; the situationist is simply too strong in her claims. This is hardly detrimental, despite the strong suggestion by Doris and Jesse Prinz that it is. 11 In effect, they charge that returning to a strongly Aristotelian virtue ethic, virtue that is hard to attain, is a theory that loses much of its interest. If the morality is out of reach for many then it is not a good guide to the moral life. However, they would have us ascertain beforehand what the good and moral life is and that is a mistaken methodology. It is no criticism of virtue theory that it is difficult for some people to be moral. We should not therefore complain that the theory is not attractive or of no interest. If the educational system of a nation is failing its students, such that every generation becomes increasingly less intelligent than the last, it is no criticism of a good teacher that she has higher standards so as to actually produce intelligent students. Indeed, we would think such a teacher virtuous. There are three ready responses to this reply. 12 The first is that this underestimates the challenge: what evidence is there for thinking that we are the sort of creatures capable of virtue, or acting from virtue? I shall return to this criticism later. Second, if virtue is rare and hard to achieve then the bar for morality is raised too high. Average persons will be held to the standard of some ideal actor. Such a criticism forgets the role of practical reasoning in virtue ethics. Once one realizes that virtue requires us to think about our actions, unify our behavior and judgments, and have good justifications, then an ideal naturally follows and ideals are difficult to attain. 13 Finally, the situationist can respond that the virtue theorist attains immunity from empirical critique by making their theory too modest. In so doing, however, the virtue theorist gives up empirical applicability, and thereby loses the power of an explanatory and predictive theory since the preponderance of subjects are not covered. This criticism misses the point. It would be absurd to say that the preponderance of subjects are virtuous. Rather the theory has an explanation why many or even most persons lack complete virtue while some may have more than others. Possessing virtue comes in degrees, being on the road as it were, and it simply turns out that many are vicious or incontinent. 9 Nafsika Athanassoulis makes the same point as I do when he says that, Virtue ethics presumably requires that moral behaviour, in the form of possessing virtuous character traits, is a possibility, rather than an actuality for the majority of people. Indeed the virtuous agent is often discussed as an ideal which we aim towards, but do not necessarily ever achieve. Athanassoulis, A Response to Harman: Virtue Ethics and Character Traits. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 100 (2000): , (217). 10 Miller, Social Psychology and Virtue Ethics, makes this point clearly. 11 Doris, Persons, Situations, and Virtue Ethics, 520. Prinz, The Normativity Challenge: Cultural Psychology Provides the Real Threat to Virtue Ethics, See Prinz, The Normativity Challenge: Cultural Psychology Provides the Real Threat to Virtue Ethics, , and Doris, Replies: Evidence and Sensibility, Just as one might think any student of physics compares her development in scientific knowledge against that of Einstein or Bohr. 4 Page

5 4.2 Virtue ethicists recognize that persons can and do act intentionally. Whether virtue is guiding behavior depends on two cognitive factors. First, the person must recognize or construe the situation in question as in some way germane or relevant to the virtue in question. Second, if the first holds, there may be other factors that weigh against or induce behavior contrary to the action generally in accordance with that virtue. 14 Testing for virtue takes more than merely observing external behavior, since the agent may have acted intentionally due to some overriding factor perceived in the situation. Situationists, in contrast, merely observe and encourage the outward behavior thinking mere behavior enough for moral action. This, however, misunderstands both virtue and the ability to act intentionally within various situations and entirely misconstrues the purpose of moral education. If moral education is merely the attempt to make behaviour-following automatons, then virtue is not needed fine; but it s most plausibly not. 4.3 This demonstrates that the notion of virtue that the situationists are critiquing is not the type of virtue defended by virtue ethicists. 15 Rather, Doris et alia have set up a radically unintellectual straw-man. Classical virtue, in the Aristotelian tradition, has always recognized that virtue is not merely a disposition to behave in certain ways, as if it were cloddish habit following, as Julia Annas so aptly puts it. 16 The possession of a virtue is to possess a certain disposition or state built up by and exercised by an agent s practical reasoning. Genuine dispositions of agents involve choice or decision, what Aristotle called a hexis proairetike. 17 They are intelligent. Acting virtuously is itself a choice and not a mere reflexive behavior, like a plant turning towards the stimulus of the sun. That the situationists have a faulty understanding of virtue, and hence of what good character brings about, is demonstrated rather vividly by Doris prosaic example of infidelity: Imagine that a colleague with whom you have had a long flirtation invites you to dinner... with the excuse that you are temporarily orphaned while your spouse is out of town... [Y]ou regard the infidelity that may result as a morally undesirable outcome... [Y]ou might think there is little cause for concern; you are, after all, a morally upright person... On the other hand, if you take the lessons of situationism to heart, you avoid dinner like the plague, because you know that you will not be able to predict your behavior in a problematic situation on the basis of your antecedent values... Relying on character once in the situation is a mistake, you agree; the way to achieve the ethically desirable result is to recognize that situational pressures may all too easily overwhelm character and avoid the dangerous situation See for a discussion of this Prinz, The Normativity Challenge: Cultural Psychology Provides the Real Threat to Virtue Ethics, Hence Annas, Situationists, then, have so misunderstood the classical or Aristotelian kind of virtue ethics that they are attacking, that they have been attacking the wrong target. Moreover, the alternative they recommend is already part of classical virtue ethics itself. Virtue Ethics and Social Psychology, Julia Annas, Comments on John Doris s Lack of Character. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research LXXI, no. 3 (2005): (737). 17 Annas, Virtue Ethics and Social Psychology, Doris, Persons, Situations, and Virtue Ethics, In a footnote (n 50, 526) Doris claims that situationism does not deny that people may consistently avow their values, only that there is doubt to the 5 Page

6 Only the situationist, he thinks, is intelligent enough to avoid dinner. Clearly this mistakes the purpose and function of virtue. The genuinely virtuous person has precisely the correct understanding of the situation and, as such, follows Doris recommendation to avoid the dinner. No one should rely on the force of habit alone, least of all a classical virtue theorist. Hence, when Nafsika Athanassoulis responds to Harman that in the classical tradition there is an understanding of moral growth, and degrees of good character, he makes a vital point. 19 Aristotle made the distinction between six types of character such that we may observe the same outward behavior by different people who nevertheless possess different characters. The virtuous and continent look the same but affectively, and perhaps also intellectually, they differ. Likewise for the vicious and the incontinent. And so when experiments give descriptions of outward behavior they do not thereby also give descriptions of interior character or lack thereof. This explains why the same person, further, can act one way and contrariwise to expectations in another situation: virtue involves struggle, and for the incontinent struggle is their middle name. Even the continent character, which knows what is right and generally has many of the right affections, can fail if the situation brings temptation or difficulty. Contrary to Doris claims, virtue ethicists in the Aristotelian tradition have never assumed that one can read a virtuous character off of another s outward behavior or even patterns of action. That was why Aristotle famously suggests that we call no man happy until dead. 20 One must take into considerations their reasons for action, as they describe them and as they can be inferred from action. 21 This will naturally lead to an understanding of moral expertise 22 where expertise is by definition and in practice highly sensitive to situational conditions, because the expert has understanding and practical effect that even consistent values bring about consistent behavioral patterns. Once again, however, this is only so if one antecedently presupposes a Humean understanding of practical rationality; that is, to beg the question against the Aristotelian. 19 Athanassoulis, A Response to Harman: Virtue Ethics and Character Traits, Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, pp [1100a a22]. 21 See Rachana Kamtekar s discussion of traits and virtues at Situationism and Virtue Ethics on the Content of Our Character. Ethics 114 (2004): ( ). Kamtekar discusses Doris example of Oskar Schindler, whom Doris holds as an example of fragmented virtue (not evaluatively integrated, see Doris, Lack of Character, 59, 115). Oskar Schindler had guts, but so did many other womanizers and war profiteers; this is not surprising. What is surprising is the claim that this demonstrates fragmented character other than a merely incontinent one. Schindler very much lacked the virtue of temperance, although he exhibited great acts of courage (and so could reasonably be considered continent in that regard). 22 Annas has a very good analogy for ethical expertise (virtue) compared to a skill or technical expertise. As she says, We are all familiar with the point that there are expert mechanics, plumbers and so on. What makes them experts, rather than learners, is that they understand what they do. They do not mechanically follow the rule-book, but approach each new challenge in a way informed by long practice, but sensitive to the particular demands of the situation, and ready to respond in creative ways to unfamiliar challenges. We want our practical experts to have learned from experience and practice, but we do not expect them to have developed a routinized habit that produces predictable outcomes whatever the nature of the individual challenges; if we find that our plumber of mechanic does have such a routinized habit, we realize that she is not an expert, since she lacks understanding of what she is doing. (and so we go to another.) Annas, Virtue Ethics and Social Psychology, Page

7 rationality. 23 I shall have more to say on the topic of character types below. 4.4 One way to arrive at the requisite global character traits has been suggested by Christian Miller and is rather intuitive. 24 Essentially, one gets global character traits from local character traits. Given that no one denies our having local character traits, which are predictable and consistent given a limited range of specific situations, all we need is good moral education. That is, teach people to take what they already recognize as the right manifestation of a character trait in specific local situations and apply that to other situations, using their moral imagination. If situational factors seem to lead to dramatic differences in behavior, chalk it up to an inadequate moral education. If accomplished, then indeed there will be global character traits with consistency and predictability as much predictability as one can sensibly expect from rational agents acting for reasons. 25 This is why proper habituation from an early age is required, and that means proper moral education rather than socialization It is clear that there are two general problems with the situationist view of morality and the attack on virtue ethics. These were highlighted by the two general responses given: they have misconstrued character traits and they have misconstrued virtue. The first general response 23 This is why Aristotle says at 1107a1 that, Virtue, then, is a state that decides, consisting in a mean, the mean relative to us, which is defined by reference to reason, that is to say, to the reason by reference to which the prudent person would define it. Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, 25. Emphasis added. 24 Miller, Social Psychology and Virtue Ethics, One can see here a meeting of the Situationist halfway: giving them their cross-situational consistency and predictability (mitigated predictability) while retaining efficacious global traits in a way similar enough to how they understand them. Thus, Miller gives us a formulation (at 387) of what by all accounts seems to be a (modest) necessary condition for global trait acquisition (and, further, attribution). This he calls a minimal subset of a character trait, such that: (MS) For any dispositional global character trait T and agent A, a set is the minimal subset of T just in case it is the least membered set of T-counterfactuals of the form: If A were in the relevant T-eliciting circumstances C n, then A would attempt to perform the appropriate T-sortal act. Such that, other things being equal, A has T only if each member of the set is true of A. Sreenivasan points in the same direction with his two lessons that a theory of virtue can learn from situationsim (Sreenivasan, Errors about Errors: Virtue Theory and Trait Attribution, 66). Now, it is absolutely crucial to remember that, given virtuous agents are not machines and, hence, act for reasons taken to be appropriate for the circumstance at hand, it is not merely a matter of mechanical disposition that an agent A being in some T-eliciting circumstance will act in the relevant T-sortal way (as Miller puts it). Rather, it is highly probable, or expected that they will act in that way (especially if the eliciting circumstance is part of the minimal subset). It remains the case that the agent may choose to not perform the relevant T-sortal act due to special considerations of the situation C (especially if the eliciting circumstance is not in the minimal subset). One can see, then, that many people may not be able to live up to the special considerations of some difficult circumstances (such as being in a Milgram study or a Good Samaritan experiment). If such is the case, however, it is no reason to deny them a global trait of the appropriate sort; rather, recognize that their moral education lacked the ability to discriminate such situations properly (or some such explanation). 26 Thus Aristotle was quite correct when at 1095b5-10 of the Nicomachean Ethics he says, That is why we need to have been brought up in fine habits if we are to be adequate students of fine and just things... For we begin from the belief that something is true; if this is apparent enough to us, we can begin without also knowing why it is true. Someone who is well brought up has the beginnings, or can easily acquire them. Someone who neither has them nor can acquire them should listen to Hesiod: He who grasps everything himself is best of all; he is noble also who listens to one who has spoken well; but he who neither grasps it himself nor takes to heart what he hears from another is a useless man. 7 Page

8 was to demonstrate that situationists directly misunderstand character traits, and thus indirectly virtue: they ascribe too much power to the situation given that they approach experiments with the false notion that character is merely an unreflective habit of stereotypical response to stimuli. 27 The second general response was to demonstrate that situationists directly misunderstand virtue, as it genuinely features in virtue ethics. For, the situationists seem to understand virtue as merely a habit, a disposition, to produce certain regular behaviors in certain situations. This, however, leaves out the fact that virtue ethicists claim that virtues are dispositions to act for reasons there must be reference to the agent s own reasons for acting. 28 This conception of virtue, the correct one, needs some defense. I shall now attempt to do so. 5. The Apriori Argument 5.1 Timothy and Lydia McGrew offer a response to naturalism in epistemology, and hence the attack on apriori epistemologists, by making a distinction between psychological data and psychological concepts. 29 I would like to extend that type of defense from epistemology to virtue ethics. Given this distinction an apriorist 30 can use psychological concepts without needing psychological data (i.e. experiments) to corroborate the theory. So, we distinguish virtue data from virtue concepts this allows for the right theory. In epistemology, the question asked is what sort of processes are beliefs based on, in ethics, on what sort of reasoning should behaviors be based on. If one considers Hilary Kornblith or Susan Haack, for example, the claim that epistemic matters are obviously empirical is taken as just that, obvious. But on close examination there is reason to worry about this characterization. Epistemologists make claims about basing beliefs off of others, or of perceptual experience ; but what are these claims? There are two options. On the one hand one might be referring to characteristics of general human cognition, and so empirical observation is needed to justify such a claim: it is referential. On the other hand, a concept can be used non-referentially: one takes as data the contents of one s own mind. In virtue ethics, we can see a correlation between, on the one hand, the claims of the situationist and on the other the claims of the classic Aristotelian. The former takes concepts to be referential and thus empirical, while the latter can take them to be non-referential concepts: virtue concepts rather than virtue data. The distinction between referential and non-referential is key for this distinction I am making between the empirical and the apriori. Consider Kripke s famous conclusion that water is H 2 O. In order to discover that water is related in a strong way to the chemical make-up H 2 O we already had to have some concepts about it, e.g. clear liquid stuff that fills lakes and ponds. In that case, however, it is conceivable that water is not H 2 O. The concept need not entail the 27 Annas, Virtue Ethics and Social Psychology, Julia Annas, Virtue Ethics. In The Oxford Handbook of Ethical Theory, David Copp editor. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006, (519). 29 McGrew, Timothy and Lydia McGrew. Psychology For Armchair Philosophers. Idealistic Studies 10, no. 3 (1998): That is, armchair philosophers such as the McGrews and myself. 8 Page

9 empirical matter; we can conceive of water without conceiving of the underlying structure. H 2 O is referential; water is not necessarily referential and, hence, can be non-referential. In that case, then, we possess psychological concepts without psychological data. But in that case, we can make valid arguments, and have valid concepts, of subjects containing experiential concepts (e.g. wet, liquid, cold, etc.) without referring to anything in need of empirical verification. 31 If we can do this in epistemology with our concepts concerning beliefs and perception, we can do likewise with our moral concepts. 32 For the sake of the correct moral theory what matters is the concept of virtue. 5.2 As such we can see that Aristotle s characterization of the moral field, as divided between six character states, uses psychological concepts that do not require appeal to psychological data for corroboration, even though such corroboration is available. 33 These concepts form a core of the theory and can be understood apriori. They may be informed by experience, but we can understand the theory and, hence, moral behavior, independent of empirical verification. This does not deny that they are unable to be corroborated. The virtuous person, through the process of living their life, and also in dialogue with the wise and the many, understands that the best life to live is of a certain sort and further understands why they acted the way they did in any given situation. This is what possessing practical rationality allows. Hence, it is no criticism or demonstration of virtue ethics to be false to point to empirical data demonstrating that many or most people fail to act in certain ways. Virtue ethics need not base its concepts off of the empirical data; they are apriori in the strong sense of being derived from theoretical deduction and then applied to practical affairs. We know what virtue is before we experiment, we know what the virtuous person is like before we experiment, and we know that virtue as truly described by virtue theorists is attainable at the very least because the situationists have not been finding data that is contradictory since they have been working with the wrong concepts. The apriori conception of virtue is what gives us the content of virtue theory, such that to leave aside its conclusions is to attack the wrong theory. Situationism has attacked the wrong understanding of virtue and thus has not threatened the possibility of genuine virtuous character. Where the empirical meets the apriori in ethics is not to set the boundary of the apriori, not to deduce our notions of virtue, but rather to demonstrate that there is a connection of the actual to the possible. This is why historical examples of virtuous character are pertinent: they connect the empirical to the apriori conception of virtue, vindicating but not determining it. Having the correct apriori account of virtue, then, sets the boundary of the empirical and this is paramount for proper 31 Timothy and Lydia McGrew. Psychology For Armchair Philosophers, One might wonder what the connection to the external world is at all. But, as the McGrew s state, From an a priorist point of view, the question of whether human beings, including the epistemologist, actually think or reason in a certain way is neither distinctively epistemological nor relevant to epistemic standards themselves. It is the knowing subject as conceived at a given time about whom the a priorist is asking epistemic questions, I do not hold that this is the only characterization of the moral field possible or even the correct one. I simply state it due to historical importance and plausibility. 9 Page

10 moral education: educators need to be making the correct assumptions about virtue, but that requires the correct theory. Only with the correct theory is correct practice intelligible, and hence only with the correct theory is moral education possible. 5.3 There is at least one lingering concern with the above. The question can still be asked whether the apriori argument actually fits the actual world. Consider two types of moral agents: Man A and Man S, where the first is man according to virtue theory and the latter is unable to have the right sort of character needed for real virtue. The apriori argument does not tell us which we have, Man A or Man S. I take it, in response, that the jury is out as to whether we really should believe we have Man S as opposed to Man A. Given that we have strong reason to think there are virtuous characters, from reflection but also from myriads of historical, cultural, and literary examples, the onus is on the demonstration of Man S. Given that any demonstration of Man S is going to need the use of certain psychological concepts I feel entirely free to simply doubt the correctness of those findings Conclusion Four points have been made throughout this paper. First, the situationist s behavioral approach to moral education leaves out the importance of practical reasoning, the cornerstone of moral inquiry, and hence is inadequate. They would have one merely possess automatic, and rigid, habits. Second, if one is to give up practical reasoning from moral education there had better be compelling reasons, such as the impossibility of practical reason; these are found lacking in situationist criticism. Third, this demonstrates that situationism lacks needed attention of the internal, rational, aspects of moral action; but this is needed for moral education. Finally, the evidence that virtue itself is impossible or unneeded is lacking, as historical examples can easily establish. The apriori argument for these points demonstrates what the proper relation between theory and practice can be, and hence what proper moral education can be. An emphasis on social situations in order to bring about moral behavior presupposes already a conception of virtue and of the ends of moral education. In that case, the apriori boundaries of a theory of virtue must be set, aided by reflection on the empirical data. This is to link the correct theory to evidence of possible practice. The latter, however, cannot be determined without presupposition of the former. Given this it is plausible to say that the most promising case for moral education, a robust form of virtue ethics, is safely immune from social psychology. 34 I realize that this is to put me squarely at the mercy of the empiricist-rationalist debate. I take it that the rationalist is the winner, and I take that as a theoretical primitive needed for my argument. 10 Page

11 Bibliography Annas, Julia. Virtue Ethics and Social Psychology. Apriori 2 (2003): Annas, Julia. Comments on John Doris s Lack of Character. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research LXXI, no. 3 (2005): Annas, Julia. Virtue Ethics. In The Oxford Handbook of Ethical Theory, David Copp editor. Oxford: Oxford University Press, Annas, Julia. Intelligent Virtue. Oxford: Oxford University Press, Aristotle. Nicomachean Ethics. Translated by Terence Irwin, Second Edition. Indianapolis, Indiana: Hackett Publishing Company, Inc., Arjoon, Surendra. Reconciling Situational Social Psychology With Virtue Ethics. International Journal of Management Reviews 10, no. 3 (2008): Athanassoulis, Nafsika. A Response to Harman: Virtue Ethics and Character Traits. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 100 (2000): Darley, John M. and C. Daniel Batson. From Jerusalem to Jericho: A Study of Situational and Dispositional Variables in Helping Behavior. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 27, no. 1 (1973): Doris, John. Persons, Situations, and Virtue Ethics. Nous 32, no. 4 (1998): Doris, John. Lack of Character: Personality and Moral Behavior. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, Doris, John. Replies: Evidence and Sensibility. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research LXXI, no. 3 (2005): Doris, John and Steven Stitch. Moral Psychology: Empirical Approaches. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Edward N. Zalta (ed.), (2006). URL=< Geach, Peter. The Virtues. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, Harman, Gilbert. Moral Philosophy Meets Social Psychology. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 99 (1999): Harman, Gilbert. The Nonexistence of Character Traits. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 100 (2000): Harman, Gilbert. No Character of Personality. Business Ethics Quarterly 13, no. 1 (2003): Harman, Gilbert. Skepticism About Character Traits. Journal of Ethics 13 (2009): Hartshorne, Hugh and M. A. May. Studies in the Nature of Character, vol. 1, The Nature of Deceit. New York: MacMillan, Isen, Alice M. and Paula Levine. Effects of Feeling Good on Helping: Cookies and Kindness. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 21 (1972): Isen, Alice M. et al. Duration of the Effect of Good Mood on Helping: Footprints on the Sands of Time. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 34 (1976): Page

12 Kamtekar, Rachana. Situationism and Virtue Ethics on the Content of Our Character. Ethics 114 (2004): McGrew, Timothy and Lydia McGrew. Psychology For Armchair Philosophers. Idealistic Studies 10, no. 3 (1998): Merritt, Maria. Virtue Ethics and Situationist Personality Psychology. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 3 (2000): Milgram, Stanley. Behavioral Study of Obedience. In Moral Psychology: Historical and Contemporary Readings, edited by Thomas Nadelhoffer et al. West Sussex, United Kingdom: Wiley-Blackwell, Miller, Christian. Social Psychology and Virtue Ethics. The Journal of Ethics 7 (2003): Ross, Lee and Richard E. Nisbett. The Person and the Situation. In Moral Psychology: Historical and Contemporary Readings, edited by Thomas Nadelhoffer et al. West Sussex, United Kingdom: Wiley-Blackwell, Prinz, Jesse. The Normativity Challenge: Cultural Psychology Provides the Real Threat to Virtue Ethics. Journal of Ethics 13 (2009): Sabini, John and Maury Silver. Lack of Character? Situationism Critiqued. Ethics 115 (2005) Sreenivasan, Gopal. Errors about Errors: Virtue Theory and Trait Attribution. Mind 111 (2002): Sreenivasan, Gopal. Disunity of Virtue. The Journal of Ethics 13 (2009): Upton, Candace L. Virtue Ethics and Moral Psychology: The Situationism Debate. The Journal of Ethics 13 (2009): Winter, Michael and John Tauer. Virtue Theory and Social Psychology. The Journal of Value Inquiry 40 (2006): Page

Virtuous act, virtuous dispositions

Virtuous act, virtuous dispositions virtuous act, virtuous dispositions 69 Virtuous act, virtuous dispositions Thomas Hurka Everyday moral thought uses the concepts of virtue and vice at two different levels. At what I will call a global

More information

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006 In Defense of Radical Empiricism Joseph Benjamin Riegel A thesis submitted to the faculty of the University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of

More information

A solution to the problem of hijacked experience

A solution to the problem of hijacked experience A solution to the problem of hijacked experience Jill is not sure what Jack s current mood is, but she fears that he is angry with her. Then Jack steps into the room. Jill gets a good look at his face.

More information

Skepticism and Internalism

Skepticism and Internalism Skepticism and Internalism John Greco Abstract: This paper explores a familiar skeptical problematic and considers some strategies for responding to it. Section 1 reconstructs and disambiguates the skeptical

More information

Utilitarianism: For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), pp Reprinted in Moral Luck (CUP, 1981).

Utilitarianism: For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), pp Reprinted in Moral Luck (CUP, 1981). Draft of 3-21- 13 PHIL 202: Core Ethics; Winter 2013 Core Sequence in the History of Ethics, 2011-2013 IV: 19 th and 20 th Century Moral Philosophy David O. Brink Handout #14: Williams, Internalism, and

More information

Self-Evidence and A Priori Moral Knowledge

Self-Evidence and A Priori Moral Knowledge Self-Evidence and A Priori Moral Knowledge Colorado State University BIBLID [0873-626X (2012) 33; pp. 459-467] Abstract According to rationalists about moral knowledge, some moral truths are knowable a

More information

Virtue Ethics without Character Traits

Virtue Ethics without Character Traits Virtue Ethics without Character Traits Gilbert Harman Princeton University August 18, 1999 Presumed parts of normative moral philosophy Normative moral philosophy is often thought to be concerned with

More information

Can A Priori Justified Belief Be Extended Through Deduction? It is often assumed that if one deduces some proposition p from some premises

Can A Priori Justified Belief Be Extended Through Deduction? It is often assumed that if one deduces some proposition p from some premises Can A Priori Justified Belief Be Extended Through Deduction? Introduction It is often assumed that if one deduces some proposition p from some premises which one knows a priori, in a series of individually

More information

KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST. Arnon Keren

KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST. Arnon Keren Abstracta SPECIAL ISSUE VI, pp. 33 46, 2012 KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST Arnon Keren Epistemologists of testimony widely agree on the fact that our reliance on other people's testimony is extensive. However,

More information

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism? Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism? Author: Terence Rajivan Edward, University of Manchester. Abstract. In the sixth chapter of The View from Nowhere, Thomas Nagel attempts to identify a form of idealism.

More information

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory Western University Scholarship@Western 2015 Undergraduate Awards The Undergraduate Awards 2015 Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory David Hakim Western University, davidhakim266@gmail.com

More information

3. Knowledge and Justification

3. Knowledge and Justification THE PROBLEMS OF KNOWLEDGE 11 3. Knowledge and Justification We have been discussing the role of skeptical arguments in epistemology and have already made some progress in thinking about reasoning and belief.

More information

Realism and instrumentalism

Realism and instrumentalism Published in H. Pashler (Ed.) The Encyclopedia of the Mind (2013), Thousand Oaks, CA: SAGE Publications, pp. 633 636 doi:10.4135/9781452257044 mark.sprevak@ed.ac.uk Realism and instrumentalism Mark Sprevak

More information

Belief Ownership without Authorship: Agent Reliabilism s Unlucky Gambit against Reflective Luck Benjamin Bayer September 1 st, 2014

Belief Ownership without Authorship: Agent Reliabilism s Unlucky Gambit against Reflective Luck Benjamin Bayer September 1 st, 2014 Belief Ownership without Authorship: Agent Reliabilism s Unlucky Gambit against Reflective Luck Benjamin Bayer September 1 st, 2014 Abstract: This paper examines a persuasive attempt to defend reliabilist

More information

Are There Reasons to Be Rational?

Are There Reasons to Be Rational? Are There Reasons to Be Rational? Olav Gjelsvik, University of Oslo The thesis. Among people writing about rationality, few people are more rational than Wlodek Rabinowicz. But are there reasons for being

More information

Moral requirements are still not rational requirements

Moral requirements are still not rational requirements ANALYSIS 59.3 JULY 1999 Moral requirements are still not rational requirements Paul Noordhof According to Michael Smith, the Rationalist makes the following conceptual claim. If it is right for agents

More information

Introduction to Cognitivism; Motivational Externalism; Naturalist Cognitivism

Introduction to Cognitivism; Motivational Externalism; Naturalist Cognitivism Introduction to Cognitivism; Motivational Externalism; Naturalist Cognitivism Felix Pinkert 103 Ethics: Metaethics, University of Oxford, Hilary Term 2015 Cognitivism, Non-cognitivism, and the Humean Argument

More information

Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000)

Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000) Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000) One of the advantages traditionally claimed for direct realist theories of perception over indirect realist theories is that the

More information

On Searle on Human Rights, Again! J. Angelo Corlett, San Diego State University

On Searle on Human Rights, Again! J. Angelo Corlett, San Diego State University On Searle on Human Rights, Again! J. Angelo Corlett, San Diego State University With regard to my article Searle on Human Rights (Corlett 2016), I have been accused of misunderstanding John Searle s conception

More information

Reasons With Rationalism After All MICHAEL SMITH

Reasons With Rationalism After All MICHAEL SMITH book symposium 521 Bratman, M.E. Forthcoming a. Intention, belief, practical, theoretical. In Spheres of Reason: New Essays on the Philosophy of Normativity, ed. Simon Robertson. Oxford: Oxford University

More information

Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Introduction

Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Introduction 24 Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Abstract: In this paper, I address Linda Zagzebski s analysis of the relation between moral testimony and understanding arguing that Aquinas

More information

Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords

Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords ISBN 9780198802693 Title The Value of Rationality Author(s) Ralph Wedgwood Book abstract Book keywords Rationality is a central concept for epistemology,

More information

ALTERNATIVE SELF-DEFEAT ARGUMENTS: A REPLY TO MIZRAHI

ALTERNATIVE SELF-DEFEAT ARGUMENTS: A REPLY TO MIZRAHI ALTERNATIVE SELF-DEFEAT ARGUMENTS: A REPLY TO MIZRAHI Michael HUEMER ABSTRACT: I address Moti Mizrahi s objections to my use of the Self-Defeat Argument for Phenomenal Conservatism (PC). Mizrahi contends

More information

Varieties of Apriority

Varieties of Apriority S E V E N T H E X C U R S U S Varieties of Apriority T he notions of a priori knowledge and justification play a central role in this work. There are many ways in which one can understand the a priori,

More information

The stated objective of Gloria Origgi s paper Epistemic Injustice and Epistemic Trust is:

The stated objective of Gloria Origgi s paper Epistemic Injustice and Epistemic Trust is: Trust and the Assessment of Credibility Paul Faulkner, University of Sheffield Faulkner, Paul. 2012. Trust and the Assessment of Credibility. Epistemic failings can be ethical failings. This insight is

More information

In essence, Swinburne's argument is as follows:

In essence, Swinburne's argument is as follows: 9 [nt J Phil Re115:49-56 (1984). Martinus Nijhoff Publishers, The Hague. Printed in the Netherlands. NATURAL EVIL AND THE FREE WILL DEFENSE PAUL K. MOSER Loyola University of Chicago Recently Richard Swinburne

More information

Practical Wisdom and Politics

Practical Wisdom and Politics Practical Wisdom and Politics In discussing Book I in subunit 1.6, you learned that the Ethics specifically addresses the close relationship between ethical inquiry and politics. At the outset, Aristotle

More information

Deontological Perspectivism: A Reply to Lockie Hamid Vahid, Institute for Research in Fundamental Sciences, Tehran

Deontological Perspectivism: A Reply to Lockie Hamid Vahid, Institute for Research in Fundamental Sciences, Tehran Deontological Perspectivism: A Reply to Lockie Hamid Vahid, Institute for Research in Fundamental Sciences, Tehran Abstract In his (2015) paper, Robert Lockie seeks to add a contextualized, relativist

More information

INTUITION AND CONSCIOUS REASONING

INTUITION AND CONSCIOUS REASONING The Philosophical Quarterly Vol. 63, No. 253 October 2013 ISSN 0031-8094 doi: 10.1111/1467-9213.12071 INTUITION AND CONSCIOUS REASONING BY OLE KOKSVIK This paper argues that, contrary to common opinion,

More information

Craig on the Experience of Tense

Craig on the Experience of Tense Craig on the Experience of Tense In his recent book, The Tensed Theory of Time: A Critical Examination, 1 William Lane Craig offers several criticisms of my views on our experience of time. The purpose

More information

Introductory Kant Seminar Lecture

Introductory Kant Seminar Lecture Introductory Kant Seminar Lecture Intentionality It is not unusual to begin a discussion of Kant with a brief review of some history of philosophy. What is perhaps less usual is to start with a review

More information

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. The Physical World Author(s): Barry Stroud Source: Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, New Series, Vol. 87 (1986-1987), pp. 263-277 Published by: Blackwell Publishing on behalf of The Aristotelian

More information

Projection in Hume. P J E Kail. St. Peter s College, Oxford.

Projection in Hume. P J E Kail. St. Peter s College, Oxford. Projection in Hume P J E Kail St. Peter s College, Oxford Peter.kail@spc.ox.ac.uk A while ago now (2007) I published my Projection and Realism in Hume s Philosophy (Oxford University Press henceforth abbreviated

More information

On Some Alleged Consequences Of The Hartle-Hawking Cosmology. In [3], Quentin Smith claims that the Hartle-Hawking cosmology is inconsistent with

On Some Alleged Consequences Of The Hartle-Hawking Cosmology. In [3], Quentin Smith claims that the Hartle-Hawking cosmology is inconsistent with On Some Alleged Consequences Of The Hartle-Hawking Cosmology In [3], Quentin Smith claims that the Hartle-Hawking cosmology is inconsistent with classical theism in a way which redounds to the discredit

More information

Philosophy Epistemology. Topic 3 - Skepticism

Philosophy Epistemology. Topic 3 - Skepticism Michael Huemer on Skepticism Philosophy 3340 - Epistemology Topic 3 - Skepticism Chapter II. The Lure of Radical Skepticism 1. Mike Huemer defines radical skepticism as follows: Philosophical skeptics

More information

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View Chapter 98 Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View Lars Leeten Universität Hildesheim Practical thinking is a tricky business. Its aim will never be fulfilled unless influence on practical

More information

Phil Aristotle. Instructor: Jason Sheley

Phil Aristotle. Instructor: Jason Sheley Phil 290 - Aristotle Instructor: Jason Sheley To sum up the method 1) Human beings are naturally curious. 2) We need a place to begin our inquiry. 3) The best place to start is with commonly held beliefs.

More information

THE FREGE-GEACH PROBLEM AND KALDERON S MORAL FICTIONALISM. Matti Eklund Cornell University

THE FREGE-GEACH PROBLEM AND KALDERON S MORAL FICTIONALISM. Matti Eklund Cornell University THE FREGE-GEACH PROBLEM AND KALDERON S MORAL FICTIONALISM Matti Eklund Cornell University [me72@cornell.edu] Penultimate draft. Final version forthcoming in Philosophical Quarterly I. INTRODUCTION In his

More information

Lost in Transmission: Testimonial Justification and Practical Reason

Lost in Transmission: Testimonial Justification and Practical Reason Lost in Transmission: Testimonial Justification and Practical Reason Andrew Peet and Eli Pitcovski Abstract Transmission views of testimony hold that the epistemic state of a speaker can, in some robust

More information

Construing Character: Virtue as a Cognitive- Affective Processing System

Construing Character: Virtue as a Cognitive- Affective Processing System City University of New York (CUNY) CUNY Academic Works Dissertations, Theses, and Capstone Projects Graduate Center 6-3-2016 Construing Character: Virtue as a Cognitive- Affective Processing System Denise

More information

Epistemic Normativity for Naturalists

Epistemic Normativity for Naturalists Epistemic Normativity for Naturalists 1. Naturalized epistemology and the normativity objection Can science help us understand what knowledge is and what makes a belief justified? Some say no because epistemic

More information

Quine s Naturalized Epistemology, Epistemic Normativity and the. Gettier Problem

Quine s Naturalized Epistemology, Epistemic Normativity and the. Gettier Problem Quine s Naturalized Epistemology, Epistemic Normativity and the Gettier Problem Dr. Qilin Li (liqilin@gmail.com; liqilin@pku.edu.cn) The Department of Philosophy, Peking University Beiijing, P. R. China

More information

A primer of major ethical theories

A primer of major ethical theories Chapter 1 A primer of major ethical theories Our topic in this course is privacy. Hence we want to understand (i) what privacy is and also (ii) why we value it and how this value is reflected in our norms

More information

- 1 - Outline of NICOMACHEAN ETHICS, Book I Book I--Dialectical discussion leading to Aristotle's definition of happiness: activity in accordance

- 1 - Outline of NICOMACHEAN ETHICS, Book I Book I--Dialectical discussion leading to Aristotle's definition of happiness: activity in accordance - 1 - Outline of NICOMACHEAN ETHICS, Book I Book I--Dialectical discussion leading to Aristotle's definition of happiness: activity in accordance with virtue or excellence (arete) in a complete life Chapter

More information

Huemer s Problem of Memory Knowledge

Huemer s Problem of Memory Knowledge Huemer s Problem of Memory Knowledge ABSTRACT: When S seems to remember that P, what kind of justification does S have for believing that P? In "The Problem of Memory Knowledge." Michael Huemer offers

More information

From the Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy

From the Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy From the Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy Epistemology Peter D. Klein Philosophical Concept Epistemology is one of the core areas of philosophy. It is concerned with the nature, sources and limits

More information

Coordination Problems

Coordination Problems Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Vol. LXXXI No. 2, September 2010 Ó 2010 Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, LLC Coordination Problems scott soames

More information

Small Stakes Give You the Blues: The Skeptical Costs of Pragmatic Encroachment

Small Stakes Give You the Blues: The Skeptical Costs of Pragmatic Encroachment Small Stakes Give You the Blues: The Skeptical Costs of Pragmatic Encroachment Clayton Littlejohn King s College London Department of Philosophy Strand Campus London, England United Kingdom of Great Britain

More information

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea. Book reviews World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Naturalism, by Michael C. Rea. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2004, viii + 245 pp., $24.95. This is a splendid book. Its ideas are bold and

More information

THE SENSE OF FREEDOM 1. Dana K. Nelkin. I. Introduction. abandon even in the face of powerful arguments that this sense is illusory.

THE SENSE OF FREEDOM 1. Dana K. Nelkin. I. Introduction. abandon even in the face of powerful arguments that this sense is illusory. THE SENSE OF FREEDOM 1 Dana K. Nelkin I. Introduction We appear to have an inescapable sense that we are free, a sense that we cannot abandon even in the face of powerful arguments that this sense is illusory.

More information

Philosophical Perspectives, 16, Language and Mind, 2002 THE AIM OF BELIEF 1. Ralph Wedgwood Merton College, Oxford

Philosophical Perspectives, 16, Language and Mind, 2002 THE AIM OF BELIEF 1. Ralph Wedgwood Merton College, Oxford Philosophical Perspectives, 16, Language and Mind, 2002 THE AIM OF BELIEF 1 Ralph Wedgwood Merton College, Oxford 0. Introduction It is often claimed that beliefs aim at the truth. Indeed, this claim has

More information

On the Nature of Intellectual Vice. Brent Madison, United Arab Emirates University, Al-Ain, UAE

On the Nature of Intellectual Vice. Brent Madison, United Arab Emirates University, Al-Ain, UAE http://social-epistemology.com ISSN: 2471-9560 On the Nature of Intellectual Vice Brent Madison, United Arab Emirates University, Al-Ain, UAE Madison, Brent. On the Nature of Intellectual Vice. Social

More information

proper construal of Davidson s principle of rationality will show the objection to be misguided. Andrew Wong Washington University, St.

proper construal of Davidson s principle of rationality will show the objection to be misguided. Andrew Wong Washington University, St. Do e s An o m a l o u s Mo n i s m Hav e Explanatory Force? Andrew Wong Washington University, St. Louis The aim of this paper is to support Donald Davidson s Anomalous Monism 1 as an account of law-governed

More information

Reading the Nichomachean Ethics

Reading the Nichomachean Ethics 1 Reading the Nichomachean Ethics Book I: Chapter 1: Good as the aim of action Every art, applied science, systematic investigation, action and choice aims at some good: either an activity, or a product

More information

Moral Twin Earth: The Intuitive Argument. Terence Horgan and Mark Timmons have recently published a series of articles where they

Moral Twin Earth: The Intuitive Argument. Terence Horgan and Mark Timmons have recently published a series of articles where they Moral Twin Earth: The Intuitive Argument Terence Horgan and Mark Timmons have recently published a series of articles where they attack the new moral realism as developed by Richard Boyd. 1 The new moral

More information

Epistemic Contextualism as a Theory of Primary Speaker Meaning

Epistemic Contextualism as a Theory of Primary Speaker Meaning Epistemic Contextualism as a Theory of Primary Speaker Meaning Gilbert Harman, Princeton University June 30, 2006 Jason Stanley s Knowledge and Practical Interests is a brilliant book, combining insights

More information

EXTERNALISM AND THE CONTENT OF MORAL MOTIVATION

EXTERNALISM AND THE CONTENT OF MORAL MOTIVATION EXTERNALISM AND THE CONTENT OF MORAL MOTIVATION Caj Strandberg Department of Philosophy, Lund University and Gothenburg University Caj.Strandberg@fil.lu.se ABSTRACT: Michael Smith raises in his fetishist

More information

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 4: Skepticism. Part 1: The Scope of Skepticism and Two Main Types of Skeptical Argument

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 4: Skepticism. Part 1: The Scope of Skepticism and Two Main Types of Skeptical Argument 1. The Scope of Skepticism Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 4: Skepticism Part 1: The Scope of Skepticism and Two Main Types of Skeptical Argument The scope of skeptical challenges can vary in a number

More information

THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE

THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE Diametros nr 29 (wrzesień 2011): 80-92 THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE Karol Polcyn 1. PRELIMINARIES Chalmers articulates his argument in terms of two-dimensional

More information

Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible?

Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible? Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible? Anders Kraal ABSTRACT: Since the 1960s an increasing number of philosophers have endorsed the thesis that there can be no such thing as

More information

Book Reviews 309 science, in the broadest sense of the word is a complex achievement, which depends on a number of different activities: devising theo

Book Reviews 309 science, in the broadest sense of the word is a complex achievement, which depends on a number of different activities: devising theo Book Reviews 309 science, in the broadest sense of the word is a complex achievement, which depends on a number of different activities: devising theories, testing them experimentally, inventing and making

More information

Andrea Westlund, in Selflessness and Responsibility for Self, argues

Andrea Westlund, in Selflessness and Responsibility for Self, argues Aporia vol. 28 no. 2 2018 Phenomenology of Autonomy in Westlund and Wheelis Andrea Westlund, in Selflessness and Responsibility for Self, argues that for one to be autonomous or responsible for self one

More information

Chapter 18 David Hume: Theory of Knowledge

Chapter 18 David Hume: Theory of Knowledge Key Words Chapter 18 David Hume: Theory of Knowledge Empiricism, skepticism, personal identity, necessary connection, causal connection, induction, impressions, ideas. DAVID HUME (1711-76) is one of the

More information

Two Kinds of Moral Relativism

Two Kinds of Moral Relativism p. 1 Two Kinds of Moral Relativism JOHN J. TILLEY INDIANA UNIVERSITY PURDUE UNIVERSITY INDIANAPOLIS jtilley@iupui.edu [Final draft of a paper that appeared in the Journal of Value Inquiry 29(2) (1995):

More information

British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 62 (2011), doi: /bjps/axr026

British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 62 (2011), doi: /bjps/axr026 British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 62 (2011), 899-907 doi:10.1093/bjps/axr026 URL: Please cite published version only. REVIEW

More information

Externalism and a priori knowledge of the world: Why privileged access is not the issue Maria Lasonen-Aarnio

Externalism and a priori knowledge of the world: Why privileged access is not the issue Maria Lasonen-Aarnio Externalism and a priori knowledge of the world: Why privileged access is not the issue Maria Lasonen-Aarnio This is the pre-peer reviewed version of the following article: Lasonen-Aarnio, M. (2006), Externalism

More information

Scientific Progress, Verisimilitude, and Evidence

Scientific Progress, Verisimilitude, and Evidence L&PS Logic and Philosophy of Science Vol. IX, No. 1, 2011, pp. 561-567 Scientific Progress, Verisimilitude, and Evidence Luca Tambolo Department of Philosophy, University of Trieste e-mail: l_tambolo@hotmail.com

More information

CRUCIAL TOPICS IN THE DEBATE ABOUT THE EXISTENCE OF EXTERNAL REASONS

CRUCIAL TOPICS IN THE DEBATE ABOUT THE EXISTENCE OF EXTERNAL REASONS CRUCIAL TOPICS IN THE DEBATE ABOUT THE EXISTENCE OF EXTERNAL REASONS By MARANATHA JOY HAYES A THESIS PRESENTED TO THE GRADUATE SCHOOL OF THE UNIVERSITY OF FLORIDA IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS

More information

Korsgaard and Non-Sentient Life ABSTRACT

Korsgaard and Non-Sentient Life ABSTRACT 74 Between the Species Korsgaard and Non-Sentient Life ABSTRACT Christine Korsgaard argues for the moral status of animals and our obligations to them. She grounds this obligation on the notion that we

More information

WHAT DOES KRIPKE MEAN BY A PRIORI?

WHAT DOES KRIPKE MEAN BY A PRIORI? Diametros nr 28 (czerwiec 2011): 1-7 WHAT DOES KRIPKE MEAN BY A PRIORI? Pierre Baumann In Naming and Necessity (1980), Kripke stressed the importance of distinguishing three different pairs of notions:

More information

Conditions of Fundamental Metaphysics: A critique of Jorge Gracia's proposal

Conditions of Fundamental Metaphysics: A critique of Jorge Gracia's proposal University of Windsor Scholarship at UWindsor Critical Reflections Essays of Significance & Critical Reflections 2016 Mar 12th, 1:30 PM - 2:00 PM Conditions of Fundamental Metaphysics: A critique of Jorge

More information

Vol. II, No. 5, Reason, Truth and History, 127. LARS BERGSTRÖM

Vol. II, No. 5, Reason, Truth and History, 127. LARS BERGSTRÖM Croatian Journal of Philosophy Vol. II, No. 5, 2002 L. Bergström, Putnam on the Fact-Value Dichotomy 1 Putnam on the Fact-Value Dichotomy LARS BERGSTRÖM Stockholm University In Reason, Truth and History

More information

what makes reasons sufficient?

what makes reasons sufficient? Mark Schroeder University of Southern California August 2, 2010 what makes reasons sufficient? This paper addresses the question: what makes reasons sufficient? and offers the answer, being at least as

More information

IN DEFENCE OF CLOSURE

IN DEFENCE OF CLOSURE IN DEFENCE OF CLOSURE IN DEFENCE OF CLOSURE By RICHARD FELDMAN Closure principles for epistemic justification hold that one is justified in believing the logical consequences, perhaps of a specified sort,

More information

5 A Modal Version of the

5 A Modal Version of the 5 A Modal Version of the Ontological Argument E. J. L O W E Moreland, J. P.; Sweis, Khaldoun A.; Meister, Chad V., Jul 01, 2013, Debating Christian Theism The original version of the ontological argument

More information

Luck, Rationality, and Explanation: A Reply to Elga s Lucky to Be Rational. Joshua Schechter. Brown University

Luck, Rationality, and Explanation: A Reply to Elga s Lucky to Be Rational. Joshua Schechter. Brown University Luck, Rationality, and Explanation: A Reply to Elga s Lucky to Be Rational Joshua Schechter Brown University I Introduction What is the epistemic significance of discovering that one of your beliefs depends

More information

Edinburgh Research Explorer

Edinburgh Research Explorer Edinburgh Research Explorer Re-evaluating the Epistemic Situationist Challenge to Virtue Epistemology Citation for published version: Pritchard, D 2014, Re-evaluating the Epistemic Situationist Challenge

More information

STEWART COHEN AND THE CONTEXTUALIST THEORY OF JUSTIFICATION

STEWART COHEN AND THE CONTEXTUALIST THEORY OF JUSTIFICATION FILOZOFIA Roč. 66, 2011, č. 4 STEWART COHEN AND THE CONTEXTUALIST THEORY OF JUSTIFICATION AHMAD REZA HEMMATI MOGHADDAM, Institute for Research in Fundamental Sciences (IPM), School of Analytic Philosophy,

More information

Gale on a Pragmatic Argument for Religious Belief

Gale on a Pragmatic Argument for Religious Belief Volume 6, Number 1 Gale on a Pragmatic Argument for Religious Belief by Philip L. Quinn Abstract: This paper is a study of a pragmatic argument for belief in the existence of God constructed and criticized

More information

Reply to Robert Koons

Reply to Robert Koons 632 Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic Volume 35, Number 4, Fall 1994 Reply to Robert Koons ANIL GUPTA and NUEL BELNAP We are grateful to Professor Robert Koons for his excellent, and generous, review

More information

Philosophical reflection about what we call knowledge has a natural starting point in the

Philosophical reflection about what we call knowledge has a natural starting point in the INTRODUCTION Originally published in: Peter Baumann, Epistemic Contextualism. A Defense, Oxford: Oxford University Press 2016, 1-5. https://global.oup.com/academic/product/epistemic-contextualism-9780198754312?cc=us&lang=en&#

More information

Let s Bite the Bullet on Deontological Epistemic Justification: A Response to Robert Lockie 1 Rik Peels, Vrije Universiteit Amsterdam.

Let s Bite the Bullet on Deontological Epistemic Justification: A Response to Robert Lockie 1 Rik Peels, Vrije Universiteit Amsterdam. Let s Bite the Bullet on Deontological Epistemic Justification: A Response to Robert Lockie 1 Rik Peels, Vrije Universiteit Amsterdam Abstract In his paper, Robert Lockie points out that adherents of the

More information

Introduction Naturalized virtue epistemology

Introduction Naturalized virtue epistemology chapter 1 Introduction Naturalized virtue epistemology 1 Virtue epistemology: metaphysical and normative Th is volume aims to launch a powerful and largely unexplored position in epistemology: naturalized

More information

Explanatory Indispensability and Deliberative Indispensability: Against Enoch s Analogy Alex Worsnip University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill

Explanatory Indispensability and Deliberative Indispensability: Against Enoch s Analogy Alex Worsnip University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill Explanatory Indispensability and Deliberative Indispensability: Against Enoch s Analogy Alex Worsnip University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill Forthcoming in Thought please cite published version In

More information

Skepticism is True. Abraham Meidan

Skepticism is True. Abraham Meidan Skepticism is True Abraham Meidan Skepticism is True Copyright 2004 Abraham Meidan All rights reserved. Universal Publishers Boca Raton, Florida USA 2004 ISBN: 1-58112-504-6 www.universal-publishers.com

More information

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology. Topic 6: Theories of Justification: Foundationalism versus Coherentism. Part 2: Susan Haack s Foundherentist Approach

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology. Topic 6: Theories of Justification: Foundationalism versus Coherentism. Part 2: Susan Haack s Foundherentist Approach Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 6: Theories of Justification: Foundationalism versus Coherentism Part 2: Susan Haack s Foundherentist Approach Susan Haack, "A Foundherentist Theory of Empirical Justification"

More information

HAS DAVID HOWDEN VINDICATED RICHARD VON MISES S DEFINITION OF PROBABILITY?

HAS DAVID HOWDEN VINDICATED RICHARD VON MISES S DEFINITION OF PROBABILITY? LIBERTARIAN PAPERS VOL. 1, ART. NO. 44 (2009) HAS DAVID HOWDEN VINDICATED RICHARD VON MISES S DEFINITION OF PROBABILITY? MARK R. CROVELLI * Introduction IN MY RECENT ARTICLE on these pages entitled On

More information

The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel s Idealism

The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel s Idealism The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel s Idealism What is a great mistake? Nietzsche once said that a great error is worth more than a multitude of trivial truths. A truly great mistake

More information

Why Is Epistemic Evaluation Prescriptive?

Why Is Epistemic Evaluation Prescriptive? Why Is Epistemic Evaluation Prescriptive? Kate Nolfi UNC Chapel Hill (Forthcoming in Inquiry, Special Issue on the Nature of Belief, edited by Susanna Siegel) Abstract Epistemic evaluation is often appropriately

More information

Philosophers in Jesuit Education Eastern APA Meetings, December 2011 Discussion Starter. Karen Stohr Georgetown University

Philosophers in Jesuit Education Eastern APA Meetings, December 2011 Discussion Starter. Karen Stohr Georgetown University Philosophers in Jesuit Education Eastern APA Meetings, December 2011 Discussion Starter Karen Stohr Georgetown University Ethics begins with the obvious fact that we are morally flawed creatures and that

More information

THE MORAL ARGUMENT. Peter van Inwagen. Introduction, James Petrik

THE MORAL ARGUMENT. Peter van Inwagen. Introduction, James Petrik THE MORAL ARGUMENT Peter van Inwagen Introduction, James Petrik THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHICAL DISCUSSIONS of human freedom is closely intertwined with the history of philosophical discussions of moral responsibility.

More information

Wittgenstein on the Fallacy of the Argument from Pretence. Abstract

Wittgenstein on the Fallacy of the Argument from Pretence. Abstract Wittgenstein on the Fallacy of the Argument from Pretence Edoardo Zamuner Abstract This paper is concerned with the answer Wittgenstein gives to a specific version of the sceptical problem of other minds.

More information

RECENT WORK THE MINIMAL DEFINITION AND METHODOLOGY OF COMPARATIVE PHILOSOPHY: A REPORT FROM A CONFERENCE STEPHEN C. ANGLE

RECENT WORK THE MINIMAL DEFINITION AND METHODOLOGY OF COMPARATIVE PHILOSOPHY: A REPORT FROM A CONFERENCE STEPHEN C. ANGLE Comparative Philosophy Volume 1, No. 1 (2010): 106-110 Open Access / ISSN 2151-6014 www.comparativephilosophy.org RECENT WORK THE MINIMAL DEFINITION AND METHODOLOGY OF COMPARATIVE PHILOSOPHY: A REPORT

More information

Markie, Speckles, and Classical Foundationalism

Markie, Speckles, and Classical Foundationalism Markie, Speckles, and Classical Foundationalism In Classical Foundationalism and Speckled Hens Peter Markie presents a thoughtful and important criticism of my attempts to defend a traditional version

More information

CONVENTIONALISM AND NORMATIVITY

CONVENTIONALISM AND NORMATIVITY 1 CONVENTIONALISM AND NORMATIVITY TORBEN SPAAK We have seen (in Section 3) that Hart objects to Austin s command theory of law, that it cannot account for the normativity of law, and that what is missing

More information

Does Deduction really rest on a more secure epistemological footing than Induction?

Does Deduction really rest on a more secure epistemological footing than Induction? Does Deduction really rest on a more secure epistemological footing than Induction? We argue that, if deduction is taken to at least include classical logic (CL, henceforth), justifying CL - and thus deduction

More information

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction Kent State University BIBLID [0873-626X (2014) 39; pp. 139-145] Abstract The causal theory of reference (CTR) provides a well-articulated and widely-accepted account

More information

In Defense of Culpable Ignorance

In Defense of Culpable Ignorance It is common in everyday situations and interactions to hold people responsible for things they didn t know but which they ought to have known. For example, if a friend were to jump off the roof of a house

More information

Annas, Julia. (2007) Virtue Ethics and the Charge of Egoism. In P. Bloomfield (ed.), Morality and Self-Interest. (New York: Oxford University Press).

Annas, Julia. (2007) Virtue Ethics and the Charge of Egoism. In P. Bloomfield (ed.), Morality and Self-Interest. (New York: Oxford University Press). Annas, Julia. (2007) Virtue Ethics and the Charge of Egoism. In P. Bloomfield (ed.), Morality and Self-Interest. (New York: Oxford University Press). We care about being generous, courageous, and fair.

More information

The Positive Argument for Constructive Empiricism and Inference to the Best

The Positive Argument for Constructive Empiricism and Inference to the Best The Positive Argument for Constructive Empiricism and Inference to the Best Explanation Moti Mizrahi Florida Institute of Technology motimizra@gmail.com Abstract: In this paper, I argue that the positive

More information